*?r*-Si 1 JJCSB LIBRAKY "), V - PRINCIPLES SOCIAL ECONOMICS INDUCTIVELY CONSIDERED AND PRACTICALLY APPLIED WITH CRITICISMS ON CURRENT THEORIES GEORGE GUNTON AUTHOR OF " WEALTH AND PROGRESS G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS NEW YORK LONDON 7 WBST TWBXTY-THIRD ST. 27 KING WILLIAM ST.. STRAND 1891 J0> RBAFJA. CALIF/ COPYRIGHT, 1891 BY GEORGE GUNTON ttbe Iknicfterbocher press, t*ew Elearotyped and Printed by G. P. Putnam's Sons \ - . TO MY WIFE WITHOUT WHOSE INSPIRATION AND AID THIS BOOK COULD NOT HAVE BEEN WRITTEN. PREFACE. IF there is one subject that should be more attractive the student and more inspiring to the citizen than an- other, it is that of social economics, because it deals directly and exclusively with the influences and conditions which control all human welfare. It is through a knowl- edge of the principles and laws of human economics that we are enabled to make nature contribute to man's comfort and luxury by substituting abundance for poverty, freedom for slavery, peace for war, intelligence and morality for ignorance and brutality ; in short, a civilization of democracy and culture for one of despotism and degradation. When- ever the science which should furnish the key to nature's bounties and the light to human progress becomes unattrac- tive to the student and repulsive to the average citizen, we may be assured that there is something fundamentally amiss with the conception and treatment of the subject. This is precisely the case with political economy to-day. Instead of being the beacon-light of industrial and social affairs, the source to which all may turn for safe instruction and hopeful guidance, it is the " dismal science " which students avoid, statesmen and capitalists disregard, citizens ignore, and laborers discredit. Why is a science so dreary and pessimistic, which by its very nature should be fasci- nating and hopeful ? The obvious answer is, that it fails to fulfill its function as a science of industrial welfare and social advancement. On nearly all fundamental questions affecting the production and distribution of wealth its doc- trines are both uncertain and inconsistent. The popular Vi PREFACE. theory of wages has been exploded by experience,' and the current doctrines of value, interest, and profit have for gen- erations been subjects of perplexing controversy between experts and sources of utter bewilderment to students. This is mainly due to the fact that the accepted theories belong to the hand-labor conditions of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, which have very little relation to the factory conditions of the nineteenth century. Nor should this be a matter of surprise, since it is entirely consistent with the law of industrial evolution. In its development society has assumed several distinct and essentially different industrial phases, which have each changed the economic structure of society, shifting the centre of industrial move- ment and the point of view of economic study. Under feudalism, for instance, the land-owning class was the centre of all social and industrial movement. Economic policy therefore was considered from the standpoint of a land-owning class. With the development of manufacture and trade however, came a radical change in economic relations. Serfs became wage receivers, and the cultivation of the land passed to tenant farmers, which change transferred the distribution of wealth from the domain of authority, to that of economic law. By this transition the social basis of industrial prosperity was broadened, and the centre of economic movement was shifted from the industries required to supply the needs of a small land-owning class to those required to supply the demands of a relatively large commercial class, whose interests were more varied and extensive. In proportion as new conditions developed, the narrow paternal policy which was adapted to the old regime became inimical to the welfare of the community, and a reconstruction of economic doctrine from a new point of view became necessary. The efforts of two centuries to supply this need culminated in the " Wealth of Nations," which really marks the advent of middle-class political economy, whose influence has practically moulded the economic thought of the present century. PREFACE. Vll For the same reason that under feudalism every thing was viewed from the standpoint of the land-owner, every thing was now considered from the standpoint of the manufac- turer and merchant, whose income was derived from trade. How to promote sales became the fundamental idea of what has been well named the " Commodities School " of political economy. To sell extensively necessitated pro- ducing cheaply. And since wages formed the greater part of the cost of production, it appeared from the " com- modities " point of view to be as necessary to obtain cheap labor as cheap raw material, and for the same reason. Consequently it became a cardinal doctrine of the '' Com- modities School " that large profits depend upon low wages. " It has been my endeavor to show throughout this work," says Ricardo, " that the ratio of profits can never be increased but by a fall in wages." In the days of hand labor and small factories, when the consumption of the upper and middle classes furnished a sufficient market for pro- ducts, this cheap-labor policy was successful in giving profits. But this very success led to the development of large factories, which were destined again to revolutionize the economic structure of society. For since these large enter- prises required a more extensive market for their success than any possible increase in the consumption of wealth by the upper and middle classes could furnish, the habitual demands of the masses for the first time necessarily became the foundation of industrial prosperity. Therefore it is in the needs of the masses that the economics of the future must be studied and statesmanship determined. To such a change of indu'strial relations Adam Smith and his followers were altogether oblivious ; their conception of industrial evolution was too limited to enable them to antici- pate it, and their purely " commodities " point of view pre- vented them from observing it. They saw the importance of the factory as a means of making wealth cheap, but they did not see the economic importance of making man dear. Having failed to recognize the laborer as the great factor in VI 11 PREFACE. a market whose consuming power must be increased, they continued to treat him only as a productive force in the factory, whose cost should be reduced, on the theory as Mill puts it, that " profits depend upon wages, rising as wages fall and falling as wages rise." Thus through an effort to apply erroneous ante-factory theories to factory conditions political economy has for three quarters of a century been made a gospel of cheap labor and an enemy of social advance. The growing incompetency of political economy to deal with modern conditions has begun to be recognized by in- ductive economists, and during the last twenty years an increasing departure from economic orthodoxy has been manifest among the younger economists of Europe and this country, which is now developing to the proportions of a new school. In breaking from the hard and narrow lines established by the doctrines of early English economists, the " New School " has already rendered an important service to economic sci- ence, by making respectable the re-discussion of the funda- mental principles governing industrial relations and political policy, in the light of modern knowledge. Thus far, however, its work has been critical rather than constructive. It has contributed far more to break up the old than to establish a new body of economic doctrine. Although the English theory of wages has been repudiated and the doctrine of laissez faire rejected by them, no ap- proximately adequate explanation of wage phenomena has been furnished, nor any affirmative principle of public policy suggested. In the following pages I have endeavored to discuss the principles of social economics from the nineteenth century point of view. If the facts of modern experience are to be the court of final appeal, the great fundamental fact to be recognized in our society is the democratic basis of industry, The factory system has made the use of natural forces (steam, electricity, etc.) necessary to successful industrial en- PREFACE. IX terprise. Nature is intensely democratic. She will only work cheaply when she is serving a large number. Kings and aristocracies may command the unpaid service of slaves, but natural forces will work efficiently only for the million. Millionaires could not travel by steam or communicate by electricity if millions of workmen did not use the same methods. In short, the success of all machine-using industries now primarily depends on the extent to which their products are consumed by the masses. Therefore the prosperity of the community in general and capitalists in particular depends upon increasing the wants and elevating the social life and character of the laboring classes. Considered from this standpoint, the whole subject of economics assumes a new and altogether more rational and humane aspect. It ceases to be a mere " science of wealth," subordinating producers to the product, and becomes a science of human welfare, making the social life of the producers the end to which the creation of commodities is the great means. In other words, it is transformed from a dismal science of pessimism and despair, which complacently sees the masses crowded to the verge of starvation, into a science of optimism and hope, which bears a message of prosperity and progress to the whole of humanity. Besides giving economic science a humane, hopeful aspect hitherto conspicuously wanting, this change in the point of view makes it integral, harmonious, and intelligible. Much that has been involved in confusion becomes simple and clear; much that has been mistakenly regarded as unjust and oppressive enough to warrant revolution, becomes obviously beneficent and progressive ; and much that has been dole- fully taught as axiomatic truth is seen to be manifest error. Moreover, when we change our point of view from com- modities to men, and make the laborer the initial point of observation, the questions of production and distribution become susceptible of discussion in terms intelligible to ordi- nary minds. We then find value or price assuming a human basis, and commodities are seen to be dear or cheap not as X PREFACE. they will exchange for more or less gold, but as they will exchange for more or less of labor, as economic equivalents- With this idea of value the theory of supply and demand of which Malthusianism and the wage-fund fallacy are a natural outcome, is incompatible. The ratio in which a given quan- tity of cloth or shoes is the economic equivalent of a day's labor can no more be determined by the mere fact of the quantity of cloth or the number of laborers, than can the moral quality of a robbery by the number of thieves. The only basis upon which two things can be economic equivalents of each other is the substantial equality of their cost of production. Upon no other principle can exchanges be economic, equitable, and mutually advantageous. The principle of cost, governed as it is by the cost of the dearest portion of the economic supply of any commodity, furnishes a keystone to the arch of economic science. It supplies the basis for a consistent body of economic doctrine capable of explaining the phenomena of wages, rent, interest, and profit upon one general principle of universal application namely, the law of economic price and its corollary, the law of economic surplus. Instead of a system of " commodity " economics which justifies human degradation as a means of cheapening wealth, we have a sys- tem of social economics, which shows that the most effective means of promoting the industrial welfare of society on a strictly equitable basis, must be sought in influences which develop the wants, and elevate the social life and character of the masses. Here then we have a sound, economic, and broad social basis for intelligent, humane, and progressive statesmanship, which shall promote individuality without incurring the follies of laissez faire, and utilize the educa- tional and protective functions of the state without incurring the dangers of paternalism. NEW YORK CITY, January, 1891. CONTENTS. PART I. THE PRINCIPLES OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. CHAPTER I. SOCIAL PROGRESS. FACE The law of progress the key to history ....... 3 The nature of progress . . ^ ....... 4 Progress defined and phenomena classified 5 Its tendency shown by the primitive condition of man .... 6 By the development of the family as a social unit ..... 7 By the rise of the feudal system ........ 8 By the growth of free towns and individual rights .... 9 By the development of the middle class and the factory system . . IO Industrial progress different from social and political . . . .n The source of individual freedom 12 Socializing effect of the wages system . . . . . . .13 Economic interdependence and social individuality a criterion of civilization, 14 CHAPTER II. THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. The elements in social progress 15 Natural order of social progress . . . . . . . .16 Industrial progress the basis of all progress 17 Comte's mistake 18 The intellect the servant of human wants ...... 19 Relation of egoism to altruism ........ 2O Law of social progress summarized ........ 21 Xll CONTENTS. CHAPTER III THE CAUSE OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. PAGE Human wants the cause of social evolution . . . . . .22 Effectual and non-effectual desires ........ 23 The social source of equity 24 Intelligence, justice, and virtue have same origin ..... 25 As human wants increase civilization advances . . . .26 CHAPTER IV. VERIFICATION OF THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. Progress accompanies large consumption of wealth by the masses . . 27 Small consumption in Oriental countries ....... 28 Under ancient Greece and Rome, few rich, many poor . . 29 Slavery preponderates 30 Why ancient philosophy long remained without effect . . . .31 Arrested progress cause of Rome's fall ....... 32 CHAPTER V. THE RISE AND SOCIAL POWER OF FREE CITIES AS VERIFYING THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROCESS. Barbarism supplanted by feudalism ........ 33 Concentration of the serfs in the towns ....... 34 The burgesses secure control of the towns by paying rent ... 35 Insurrection of the towns ......... 36 Transformation of towns into free cities 37 The cities were the homes of freedom 38 CHAPTER VI. THE FALL OF THE FREE CITIES AND ITS EFFECT UPON SOCIAL PROGRESS. Progress arrested by their fall ......... 39 Spain distracted by religious wars ........ 40 Premature development in Italy . . . . . . . .41 German freedom destroyed by imperial alliance ..... 42 French cities overcome by the barons ....... 43 In England the cities not suppressed ....... 44 Charters rendered inviolable ......... 45 Labor rents superseded by wages ........ 46 Feudalism abolished by expansion of freedom in the towns ... 47 Increased wealth of the middle class . 48 CONTENTS. XI 1! CHAPTER VII. THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS AS VERIFIED IN THE PROGRESS OF POLITICAL AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM. PAGE Political power of English Commons ....... 49 Religious and political liberty follow material development ... 50 Wicliff's Bible succeeds ; Hussite War a failure . . . . .51 Character of the Jacquerie and the Peasant War . . . .52 Social character of the Reformation 53 Protestantism due to the social power of middle class .... 54 Condition of the masses from the fifteenth to the eighteenth century . 55 The factory system. Industrial legislation ...... 56 Right to vote extended to the laboring classes 57 Superior industrial conditions of America . . . . . .58 Difference between French and American Revolutions .... 59 Industrial prosperity cause of our free institutions ..... 60 PART II. THE PRINCIPLES OF ECONOMIC PRODUCTION. CHAPTER I. WEALTH AND THE LAW OF ITS PRODUCTION. Mill's conflicting definitions of wealth ....... 63 Walker's definition ........... 64 Perry substitutes the word property .65 Essential characteristics of wealth 66 Wealth defined 67 Various views of production ......... 68 Theory of non-productive labor ........ 69 All useful labor productive .70 Differentiation of productive effort 71 Gratified desires complete the cycle of effort ...... 72 Land, labor, and natural forces the necessary factors in production . . 72 Land passive, man and nature active . . . . . 73 Nature and character of capital ........ 74 Economic use of the term capital ........ 75 Use of capital determined by increasing returns ..... 76 Mistaken praise of parsimony 77 Capital the effect not the cause of industrial prosperity .... 78 Capital arises from the hope of gain ....... 79 No use for capital in barbarism ........ 80 Social consumption the cause of economic production . . . . 81 XIV CONTENTS. PAGE Characteristic simplicity of physical wants ....... 82 Complexity of social wants 83 Nature responds liberally only to large demand ..... 84 New wants make large markets ........ 85 High wages lead to low prices 86 Two kinds of discoveries under ancient and modern civilizations . . 87 Why ancient civilizations were not self-sustaining ..... 88 Resume of laws of production ......... 89 CHAPTER II. ECONOMIC VALUE. Adam Smith's definition confusing ........ 90 Relation of value and utility . . . . . . . . .91 Definition of value 92 Price and value identical . . . . . . . . 93, 94 Value a relation between man and things ...... 95 Mistaken point of view 96 Error of Mill and Cairnes 97 Value is not the exchange ratio of things to things, but of things to man . 98 Effect of the new point of view 99 CHAPTER III. DEMAND AND SUPPLY NOT THE LAW OF ECONOMIC PRICES. Economic price not governed by demand and supply .... 100 Gregory King's law .......... 101 It applies to agricultural products ....... 102 Not to manufactured products . . . . . . . 103, 104 The theory does not fit the facts 105 Wages do not obey the law of supply and demand ..... 106 Economic price the exchange of equivalents ...... 167 Cost the basis of economic equivalence ....... 107 Testimony of McCulloch 108 Cairnes' error regarding supply and demand 109 Commodities do not create demand . . . . . . .no Demand the cause of supply . . . . . . . . .in Origin of price .......... 1 12 Initial point of supply . . . . . . . . . .113 Price phenomena originate in man . . . . . . . .114 CHAPTER IV. THE LAW OF ECONOMIC PRICES. Exchange ratio of wealth and service . ". . . . . .115 Meaning of economic law . . . . . . . . .116 CONTENTS. XV PAGE Laissez faire not scientific . . . . . . . . .117 Economic law defined . . . . . . . . .118 Maximum and minimum price, how determined ..... 120 Cost the point of economic equilibrium 121 All the factors in production must receive the equivalent of what they con- tribute ............ 122 The possibility of an economic surplus ....... 123 Equity of economic law 124 How cost of production affects price . . . . . . .125 Origin of economic profits . . . . . . . . .126 Their equitable basis .......... 127 Primary law of price .......... 128 Character of price variations 129 Prices in the same market tend to uniformity ...... 130 Statement of law of prices 131 Verification of the law of prices . ' . . . . . . . 132 Agricultural prices . . . . . . . . . . .133 Relation of quantity to price 134 All prices regulated by cost of dearest portion ...... 135 Quality of labor determines its cost 136 Variation in wages ........... 137 CHAPTER V. THE LAW OF THE COST OF PRODUCTION. Popular errors regarding cost of production 138 Simple phenomena misleading ......... 139 Ricardo's illustration . . . . . . . . . 140 Cost and quantity ........... 141 Brassey's experience in several countries ....... 142 High wages make cheap wealth ...... . . 143 Important relation of wages to machinery ...... 144 Use of capital, how determined ........ 145 Nature and function of capital ........ 146 Importance of large market ......... 147 Wages measure the laborer's consumption 148 The true law of prices . 149 CHAPTER VI. MONEY AND ITS ECONOMIC FUNCTION. Walker's definition of money . . . . . . . . .150 Money and wealth not identical 151 Money an evidence of credit . . . . . . . . .152 Definition of money .......... 153 XVI CONTENTS. PAGE Function of money 154 Evils of fluctuations in the value of money , . . . . .155 Of what should money be made ? 156 Essential attributes of money 157 It must have maximum value in minimum form . . . . .158 Claims of a tabular standard . . . . . . . . .159 Its difficulties ........... 160 Need of a scientific price-level 161 Depreciation of money . . . . . . . . . .162 Inadequacy of metallic money ........ 163 Basis of a paper currency . . . . . . . . .164 Necessity of gold and silver 165 Because universally acceptable 166 Proportion between property and credit money ..... 167 Herbert Spencer's view 168 Essentials of a sound monetary system ........ 169 How to regulate the quantity . . . . . . . . .170 Advantages of private enterprise . . . . . . . .171 Money should be- taken out of politics . . . . . . .172 PART III. THE PRINCIPLES OF ECONOMIC DISTRIBUTION. CHAPTER I. THE DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH. Distribution inseparable from production ...... 175 It is an economic transfer. Difference between consumption and pro- ductive use . . . . . . . . . . .176 Function of productive wealth . . . . . . . .177 Order of economic distribution ........ 178 Walker's inconsistency . 179 Walker's doctrine of " residual claimant " fallacious . . . 180,181 Historic order of distribution 182 Economic order wages, rent, interest, profit . . , . . .183 CHAPTER II. SOME RECENT THEORIES OF WAGES CONSIDERED. Woods theory of wages 184 Doctrine of final utility .185 Mistaken application of 186 Wages not uniform in all industries ....... 187 CONTENTS. XVI i Laborers' welfare depends on absolute not relative income . . . 188 Capital sometimes yields no interest . . . . . . .189 Wages not determined by rate of interest ...... 190 Nor must they be confounded with profit . . ' . . . 191 Uniformity in wages and prices ; diversity in profits .... 192 Prof. Clark's theory of wages ......... 193 He, like Marx, confounds the last increment with the dearest . 194, 195 Price-fixing increment not the same in manufacture as in agriculture . 196 Confounding wages with rent ......... 197 Price and surplusage 198 Defects of Prof. Clark's theory summarized . . . . . .199 CHAPTER III. THE LAW OF WAGES. Requisites of a sound theory 200 Definition of wages 201 Real and nominal wages .......... 202 Wages the economic price of labor ........ 203 Statement of law of wages 204 Wages determined by standard of living ....... 205 Prices of labor and of products move differently ..... 206 Dearest laborers fix price of labor ........ 207 Poorest capitalists fix price of commodities 208 Relation between wages and savings-bank deposits .... 209, 210 Difference in cost of living the source of savings . . . . .211 Agriculture unfavorable to savings 212 Foreign laborers save more because they cost less 213 Very highest-paid laborers strike ........ 214 Family income regulated by its cost 215 How the cost of living is determined 216 Remedy for low wages 217 CHAPTER IV. RENT, ITS ECONOMIC LAW AND CAUSE. The Ricardo- Walker definition of rent ....... 218 Amended definition .......... 219 Economic production as applied to land 220 The law of rent stated 221 Rent governed by the law of surplusage ....... 222 Walker's explanation of rent ......... 223 Fertility not cause of rent ......... 224 Rent has a social origin .......... 225 Relation of rent to prices ......... 226 XVI 11 CONTENTS. PAGB Economic basis of rent 227 Effect of population on prices 228 Effect of improved methods 229 Rent follows and leads the movement of wages ..... 230 Is rent a social tax ? . . . . . . . . .231 Difference in the economic order of using land and machinery . . . 232 Relation of rent to wages illustrated . 233 High wages cause of high rents ........ 234 Effect of abolishing rent .......... 235 ResumJ of the doctrine of rent ........ 236 CHAPTER V. THE LAW OF INTEREST. Interest related to capital as rent is to land 237 Walker's view considered ......... 238 Not consistent with facts ......... 239 No-interest capital common ......... 240 Economic movement of capital ........ 241 Economic movement of interest ........ 242 Improved methods constantly push capital towards the no-interest point . 243 True law of interest 244 The law illustrated 245 Surplus enlarged by increased production ...... 246 Entrepreneur's profit comes from surplus above rent and interest . . 247 The social character of interest 248 CHAPTER VI. THE LAW OF PROFIT. Orthodox errors the source of socialistic theories ..... 249 Employers' view of profit and wages ....... 250 Theories of Rodbertus and Marx . . . . . . . .251 Statement of Marx's theory of surplus value . . . . . .252 Misleading illustrations .......... 253 Fallacy of his theory demonstrated ........ 254 Relation of labor to value 255 Distribution of cost-items does not alter value 256 Cause of Marx's error 257 His mistaken assumptions . . . . . . . . . 258 Economic evolution of profit ......... 259 Equity of economic profit ......... 260 Surplus does not prove exploitation ........ 261 Ratio of product to profit and wages ...... 262, 263 Illustrated by cotton industry ......... 264 CONTENTS. xix FACE Mr. Giffen's view of wages and product 265 His error 266 Distribution of economic benefits ........ 267 Ratio of wages and profits to product 269 Defective modes of calculation ........ 270 They lead to false conclusions . . ... . . 271 Omitted data vitiate conclusions ........ 272 Salaries and depreciation of capital overlooked .... 273 Wages have increased relatively to net product ..... 274 Relative decrease of profits ......... 275 Correct mode of ascertaining economic condition of laborer . . . 276 Incompleteness of obtainable data ........ 277 Table showing ratio of wages to profits ....... 278 Nature of industrial tendencies ........ 279 PART IV. THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL STATESMANSHIP. CHAPTER I. LAISSEZ FAIRE AS A GUIDING PRINCIPLE IN PUBLIC POLICY. Origin of laissez-faire doctrine ........ 283 Adam Smith and the French Physiocrats ....... 284 Negative character of laissez faire- . . . . . . . .285 Its erroneous postulates . . . . . . . . . 286, 287 False views of competition . . . . . . . . . 288 Misuse of the term natural law ........ 289 Natural and human selection ......... 290 Survival of the unfittest .......... 291 Government essential to society 292 Character of economic competition . . . . . . . 293 The competing units must be approximately equal ..... 294 The necessity of opportunity .... ; .... 294 CHAPTER II. THE STATE J OR, THE NATURE AND FUNCTION OF GOVERNMENT. The state as distinguished from society ....... 295 No absolute rights in society ..... ... 296 All government is representative ........ 297 The state is the authoritative expression of the aggregate .... 298 Relation of the state to the individual . 299 XX CONTENTS. PAGE Social-organism theory of Plato, Hobbes, Rodbertus, Marx, and Spencer. 300 Spencer's claim that society is an organism, stated .... 301, 302 His fundamental propositions considered ...... 303 Radical distinction between society and an individual organism . . 304 Society is not an organic entity 305 Social evolution different from physical 306 Mr. Spencer logically supports socialism 307 Clark's attempt to apply this theory to economics ..... 308 His position analyzed .......... 309 The function of government . . . . . . . . .310 Importance of mutual dependence . 311 Controlling principle in statesmanship 312 Individual action preferable to state action . . . . . .313 Difficulty of determining their respective spheres .... 314, 315 Sphere of individual action 315 Sphere of state action 316, 317 Difference between protection and paternalism 318 State functions essentially protective and educational .... 319 CHAPTER III THE PRINCIPLE OF INTERNATIONAL TRADE. Necessity of national development 320 Society a means for individual advancement 321 The nation 322 Socializing tendency of manufacturing industries 323 Importance of their development 324 A large home market necessary 325 Superiority of home over foreign market ....... 326 Foreign markets and home wages ........ 327 A nation is rich by what it uses, not by what it sells .... 328 Test of economic cheapness . . 329, 330 False assumption of free-traders 331 Operation of free trade illustrated ....... 332, 333 Uneconomic competition ......... 334 Basis of economic competition . . 335 Popular fallacies regarding the nature of a tariff 336 The law of international competition . . . . . . 337 Weakness of the infant-industry theory ....... 338 Civilization depends upon protecting the higher against the lower . . 339 India, Ireland, and Russia ......... 340 England, America, and Continental countries ...... 341 Protection and home prices 34 2 Proper mode of testing a tariff ....'.... 343 Ultimate effect of a protective tariff on profits 344 CONTENTS. XX PAG Effect of protecting the higher wage-level 345 Illustrated by cotton industry 346 Led to improved methods of production ...... 347 Effect on the industrial development in America . . . . 348 Wages in non-protected industries ........ 349 Erroneous views regarding 350 Mr. Elaine's mistaken view . . . . . . . . -35* Has not outgrown the English theory of wages ..... 352 How protection affects wages ......... 353 Wages can only be raised by social forces 354 How to examine wages phenomena . . . . . . . -355 Industrial improvement affects all classes 356 Effect of protection upon other countries ..... 357, 358 How protection promotes the economic selection of industries . . -359 It leads to free trade 360 Its domestic application 361 CHAPTER IV. THE PRINCIPLES OF ECONOMIC TAXATION. Basis of equitable taxation . . . . . . . . . 362 It should come from surplus incomes ....... 363 The mobility of taxes . 364 Their relation to wages 365 How transferred from laborer to employer . . . . . . 366 How he pays them out of his surplus . . . . . . . 367 How his surplus is replenished from nature 368 Taxation like wages a form of consumption ...... 369 Economic importance of taxation exaggerated ...... 370 Taxes enable government to exercise its functions . . . . 371 How taxes should be levied, paid, and collected 372 Evils of direct taxation 373, 374 Property and incomes tax ......... 375 Advantages of indirect taxation ........ 376 Taxes should be levied upon real estate ....... 377 Equitable nature of a land tax ........ 378 Objections answered 379 No profits on taxes. Mill's error ........ 380 Taxation is public consumption of wealth 381 Henry George's delusion 381 CHAPTER V. BUSINESS DEPRESSIONS. How distinguished from famines ........ 383 Historical facts about depressions ........ 384 xxil CONTENTS. PAGE Inadequate causes assigned ......... 385 Low consumption the real cause ........ 386 Evils attending factory system ........ 387 Indications of arrested consumption . ... . . . . 388 Mistaken industrial policy . . . 389 Economists largely responsible for this 390 Sound economics would ..ead to their gradual extinction .... 391 Two points which should be realized by capitalists ..... 392 Increase consumption by raising wages ....... 393 Improve laborers' social condition ........ 394 Necessity of an industrial barometer 394 Idleness statistics should be frequently collected 396 CHAPTER VI. COMBINATION OF CAPITAL. Social alarm created by spinning-jenny 397 Modern opposition to trusts of similar nature 398 Relation of capital to consumption ........ 399 Combination of capital raises the plane of competition .... 400 Concentration of capital and competition ...... 401 Efficiency not number of competitors the criterion of competition . . 402 Economic incentive 403 Power of potential competition ........ 404 Mobility of capital diminishes as that of comsumable wealth increases . 405 Effect of no-profit capital ......... 406 Limit of concentration .......... 407 Purchasing power of wages and the concentration of capital . . . 408 Effects of trusts on prices 409 Standard Oil Trust 410,411 Its economy in utilizing waste . . . . . .412 Its economies extended to other countries -4*3 Trusts unlike corners . . . . . . . . . 414 CHAPTER VII. COMBINATION OF LABOR. Combination of labor accompanies that of capital . . . . . 415 Both have an economic function 4 10 Objections to trades-unions ......... 4*7 Concentration the keynote of all progress 4*8 False notions of individual freedom ...... . 4 J 9 One-sided economics 420 Impossibility of individual contracts - 4 21 Incompatible with industrial complexity ....... 4 22 CONTENTS, XX111 PAGE Economic nature of labor organizations 423 Strikes and corners 424 Social contact essential to progress .425 It develops intelligence and refines manners 426 Social effects of labor unions 427 Economic effect of labor unions 428 Their relation to hours of labor and wages ...... 429 They must be judged by their permanent effect 430 Gain and loss by strikes .......... 431 Unfair criticisms 432 Trades-unions are necessary institutions - . 433 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION. Character of social progress 434 Nature of production and of value ........ 436 Nature and order of distribution ...... 436 Duties of statesmanship 438 INDEX 443 INDEX TO " WEALTH AND PROGRESS " 449 PART L THE PRINCIPLES OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. PRINCIPLES OF SOCIAL ECONOMICS. CHAPTER I. SOCIAL PROGRESS. SECTION I. The Nature and Meaning of Social Progress. THE promotion of social progress may be regarded as the primary object of all human institutions. The wisdom or un- wisdom of any form of government, political and industrial policy, or moral code regardless of climate, country, or civiliza- tion depends upon whether or not it tends to promote the social progress of the people. When we can furnish an adequate explanation of the law of social progress we shall be in a position to explain why the march of civilization has been so marked and continuous in some countries and so retarded in others ; why nations once the most advanced are now greatly in the rear ; why the ancients made such progress in art and philosophy, while they lacked simple contrivances with which to procure the common comforts and decencies of daily life ; why general poverty, religious, social, and political despotism prevail in some countries, while comparative abundance with religious freedom and political democracy obtain in others. " The law of prog- ress," says Fiske, 1 " when discovered, will be found to be the law of history. The great fact to be explained is either the presence or the absence of progress, and when we have formu- lated the character of progress and the conditions essential to it, we have the key to the history of the stationary as well as of the progressive nations. When we are able to show why the latter "Cosmic Philosophy," vol. ii., pp. 195, 196. 3 4 THE KEY TO SOCIAL HISTORY, have advanced, the same general principle will enable us to show why the former have not advanced." Indeed, to explain the nature, law, and cause of social progress is not only to lay the foundation for the science of social economics, but it is also to furnish the key to social philosophy, and thereby to establish a rational basis for statesmanship and social reform. This in- volves, first of all, the consideration of what constitutes progress. Unless we understand what social progress is, there can be no intelligent consideration of the law and cause of its development, and hence no approximately correct science, either of economics or of government, is possible. Progress is commonly regarded as synonymous with improve- ment. This expression confounds the process with the product. It states what progress does rather than what it is. If asked what constitutes the progress of the plant, it would not be correct to say the flowers, buds, and foliage. Their condition correctly indicates the state of the plant's progress, but they no more con- stitute the progress than the apple constitutes the tree, or the barometer the storm. The progress of the plant consists of a series of changes that take place in its organization before the flower appears, and of which 'it is the result. So, too, of improve- ment. While progress usually implies a change for the better, the improvement is not the progress, but the result of it ; it is the change of form or condition which precedes and produces the improvement. Although all progress is simply change, all change is not necessarily progress. It may be retrogression. What then are the distinguishing characteristics of the changes which con- stitute progress ? Fortunately science has furnished the answer to this question, so far as physical development is concerned. The investigations of Linnaeus, Wolf, Goethe, Schelling, Von Baer, Darwin, and others have established the fact that the "growth or progress of organisms, both vegetable and animal, consists of a series of structural changes from a relatively simple to a relatively complex state of organization. For more than half a century this definition of progress has so completely stood the test of verification that it has become an accepted scientific truth, and now both plants and animals are classified in the scale of development according to the simplicity or complexity of their organization. DEFINITION OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. 5 If we examine the history of social institutions we shall find that this distinguishing characteristic of progress is equally true of society. Although the precise forms of the earliest phases of social life are difficult to determine, modern investigation has proved beyond question that society in its primitive stages was a homogeneous aggregate of human beings without industrial specialization or social or political individuality, and that all progress from that time to this has been a movement towards a greater complexity of life and definiteness of individual, social, and political functions. Progress in general, therefore, may be defined as a tendency to change from a relatively simple to a relatively complex organization. Although this movement from the simple to the complex is the distinguishing characteristic of all progress, the form it assumes in physical and social phenomena is very different. In all the phases of physical development the tendency is to produce a greater perfection, individuality, and freedom of the organism, the highest type of which is man. Society is not an individual organism, but an association of individual organisms. Social development, therefore, does not consist in organic differentiation, but in the differentiation of the social environment of individuals. In considering social advancement, therefore, we are concerned only with social phenomena ; that is to say, with the influences which affect the material, political, and moral condition of man in society ; nor are we called upon to deal with the origin of the elements in his social character, but only with the development of their expression. The phenomena of society may be classified as social and economic ; the former relates to man's political and ethical life, and the latter to his industrial efforts. In order to correctly understand progress in society, it will be necessary briefly to consider the historic tendency of these two phases separately. SECTION II. The Historic Tendency of Social Progress. Although the genesis of man is still an unsettled question, the fact that he once existed as a mere physical being scarcely superior to the lower animals is conclusively established. 1 1 The wild men in the interior of Borneo are described by Dalton as living : " absolutely in a state of nature, who neither cultivate the ground nor live in 6 THE JELLY-FISH PERIOD OF SOCIETY. Recent investigations have shown that primitive man was so devoid of social life and character as to neither cook his food nor build himself a hut to live in. In many instances the insti- tution of marriage was entirely unknown ; in others the conjugal ties were so slender that they existed only until the birth of the child. 1 The interminable struggle for life against the elements, wild beasts, and his fellows, made man's localization necessary, and brought him into social and personal relations that gradually assumed a more permanent or tribal character. This may properly be said to constitute the first stage of social existence the jelly-fish period of society. Here the social homogeneity was such that every thing was owned in common even wives and children. Authorities agree that " the primitive condition of man socially was one where every man and woman were regarded as equally married to one another," and "any woman who attempted to resist the marriage privileges claimed by any member of the tribe was liable to severe punishment. " * The child had no particular father or mother, but belonged to the tribe. 8 The struggle for existence being now between tribes, war was the chief occupation, and those who were most proficient and brave as warriors naturally became the most honored and influential leaders of the tribe. One of the chief characteristics of tribal warfare was that the will of the victor became the law of the vanquished. Accordingly, if the chief desired to take a huts, who neither eat rice nor salt, and who do not associate with each other, but rove about some woods like wild beasts ; the sexes meet in the jungle, or the man carries away a woman from some campong. When the children are old enough to shift for themselves, they separate neither one afterwards think- ing of the other. At night they sleep under some large trees, the branches of which hang low." Sir John Lubbock's " Origin of Civilization," pp. 5, 6 ; Ibid. , chapter iii. See also Lichtenstein's " Travels in South Africa," p. 137 ; " Expedition to Borneo," vol. ii., p. 10 ; Lubbock's " Prehistoric Times," pp. 563-5, 595, 596 ; Lyell's " Antiquity of Man,'' pp. 377-80 ; Sproat's " Scenes and Studies of Savage Life," p. 120 ; Dubois' " Description of the People of India," p. 3 ; " Transactions Ethnological Society," new series, vol. iii., p. 248. 1 Lubbock's "Origin of Civilization," pp. 53-57- See also Sir Edward Belcher's " Transactions Ethnological Society," vol. v., p. 45 ; Starke's " Primitive Family," pp. 82-84. 2 Lubbock's "Origin of Civilization," p. 67; Starke's "Primitive Family," p. 245 ; McLennan's " Primitive Marriages," pp. 229, 230. s Lubbock's " Origin of Civilization," p. 71. THE FAMILY THE SOCIAL UNIT. 7 woman from among his war captives, he could have the exclusive use and enjoyment of her as against any and all other members of the tribe. 1 This instituted a departure from tribal homoge- neity which naturally led first to a certain degree of personal domestic exclusiveness, then to individual marriages, and finally to the family group. Thus, through the gradual process of social differentiation and integration, society was slowly transformed from a simple homogeneous mass, in which the tribal aggregate was the only unit, into a relatively complex social organization with the family as the unit, possessing definite social functions, rights, and powers. It should be remembered, however, that this social individuation conferred no rights or powers upon the individual, but only upon the family. 3 Indeed, it is a universal law in society that the exercise of social rights extends only with the growth of the social unit. Hence, when the family became the unit, it acquired all the social rights and powers of the unit. But all rights absolutely stopped at this point. The individual members of the family acquired no more social recognition by this change than had been previously accorded to the individual members of the tribe. The family was recognized solely through its male head, whose power was absolute, even to life and death. With the settlement of the family came the necessity of culti- vating the lands. This led to the substitution of an agricultural for a pastoral life, and the right of private for public ownership in land and its products. 8 Another feature of this regime was the practice of enlarging the family by enforced or voluntary adoption ; those entering the family by this means were kinsmen ; a fiction that nothing, but "A war captive, however, was in a peculiar position ; the tribe had no rights to her ; her capturer might have killed her if he chose ; if he preferred to keep her alive he was at liberty to do so ; he did as he liked, and the tribe was no sufferer." Sir John Lubbock's "Origin of Civilization," p. 71 ; also McLen- nan's " Primitive Marriages," pp. 43, 44. 5 " At the outset, the peculiarities of law in its most ancient state lead us irresistibly to the conclusion that it took precisely the same view of the family group which is taken of individual men by the system of rights and duties now prevalent throughout Europe." Maine's " Ancient Law," p. 129. " But ancient law, it must again be repeated, knows next to nothing of Individuals. It is concerned not with Individuals, but with Families ; not with single human beings, but with groups." Ibid., p. 250. "Village Communities," p. 10. 3 Maine's " Early History of Institutions," pp. I, 2, 73-79. 8 THE PATRIARCHAL FAMILY. the absolute authority of the head of the family could have estab- lished. In this way the simple primitive family made up of blood relations, was expanded into the patriarchal family, held together by the tie of a mythical kinship. 1 Greater sacredness of, and protection to, life and property came with this higher state of organization, and " marriage by capture " gave place to marriage by purchase, transferring the selection of a wife from the muscu- lar authority of the savage suitor, to the civil authority of the parent. 2 These social relations continued theoretically until the Chris- tian era, and practically until the middle of the sixth century. From the time of the Twelve Tables, B.C., 450, to that of the Justinian Code, progress was very tardy, but tended tow- ards a further differentiation of the social polity in the direc- tion of substituting the individual for the family as the social unit. This movement, which is most distinctly indicated by the innovations made upon the domain of patria potestas (the authority of the father over the person and property of his de- scendants), though imperceptible during the latter four hundred years of the Republic, began to show itself in the early days of the Empire. If we pass from the ancient to the modern world, where social progress has been more marked, we shall find that its movement has been everywhere distinguished by the same general charac- teristics. During the savage struggle for imperial supremacy which covered the face of Europe for nearly four hundred years after the fall of the Western Empire, in which all permanent authority and recognized law were practically abolished, 3 the patri- archal system virtually disappeared and society reorganized into the feudal system. Social institutions then assumed a different as- pect. Instead of being composed of family groups, held together 1 We must look on the family as constantly enlarged by the adoption of strangers within its circle, and we must try to regafd the fiction of adoption as so closely simulating the reality of kinship that neither law nor opinion makes the slightest difference between a real and an adoptive connection." Maine's "Ancient Law," p. 128. See also "Early History of Institutions," p. 310; "Village Communities," p. 115 ; Lubbock's " Origin of Civilization." 'Maine's "Ancient Law," pp. 119-133 ; cf, Lubbock's "Origin of Civili- zation," p. 52 ; " Fiske's " Cosmic Philosophy," vol. ii., pp. 220, 221. * Guizot's " History of Civilization," pp. 6, 69 ; also Hallam's " History of the Middle Ages," vol. i., p. 92. SOCIAL CHARACTER OF FEUDALISM. 9 by a mythical kinship under parental despotism, subject to impe- rial absolutism, society consisted of manorial or baronial groups, held together by mutual dependence upon the land-owner, who, while giving nominal allegiance to the king, was practically inde- pendent of him. 1 The individual instead of the family was the social unit, and industrial interest instead of kinship was the cohesive principle in society 2 ; land, or wealth, instead of birth, became the basis of rank and authority. 8 No sooner had feudalism become the settled order of society than the process of further social differentiation set in. One of the earliest evidences of this was the localization of the serfs on the estates of the respective barons, and their division into classes as "hinds" and "artificers." By this division of labor the former became permanently ruralized, and the latter central- ized, into groups whose history is that of modern civilization. During the tenth century these groups grew into permanent towns and became the centres of trade and industry. As they increased in population and wealth they grew in social activity, intelligence, and power ; and hence became the permanent source of the further division of labor, the specialization of social and religious functions, and of personal and political rights. By the middle of the eleventh century we find the burghers asserting their right to the ownership of property, and forcibly resisting the efforts of the barons to despoil them. Early in the twelfth century the towns began to obtain the right of local self- government. During the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries the serf was differentiated from the lord's estate, and became an economic and social individual. The separation of political in- stitutions from the authority of the Church, and the power of Parliament over the Crown were also positively asserted during this period. 1 ' ' The kingdom was as a great fief, or rather as a bundle of fiefs, and the king little more than one of a number of feudal nobles, differing rather in dig- nity than in power from some of the rest." Hallam's " History of the Middle Ages," vol. i., p. 136. 2 " It was feudalism which for the first time linked personal duties, and by consequence personal rights, to the ownership of land." Maine's "Ancient Law," p. 102. 3 Hallam's " Middle Ages," vol. i., p. 88; also ibid., p. 122, and Guizot's " History of Civilization," p. 67. IO FREE CITIES AND THE MIDDLE CLASS. This was followed in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries by a general breaking up of the feudal system and a new formation of social institutions. Throughout Europe the political elements integrated into definite nations. 1 The gentry and interior no- bility, who were economically and socially segregated from their class, and the superior artisans who, by the growth of manufac- ture and trade in the Free Towns, had become " master artificers," formed a new social stratum the mercantile or middle class which henceforth became the enterprising and progressive ele- ment in society. With the rise of this class came a new era in civilization. Under its influence industrial, political, and reli- gious institutions were revolutionized. In this period the dis- covery of America and the passage to India by the Cape of Good Hope, and the use of the mariner's compass were consummated ; painting with oil and the manufacture of paper from linen were invented ; the right of private judgment in religion and the supremacy of parliamentary government were permanently estab- lished. From this came the use of steam, the invention of the spinning-jenny and the power-loom, and the establishment of the factory system, the railroad, steamship, and telegraph, with their natural accompaniments the daily press, cheap books, and popular education. As the outgrowth of these movements slavery has been abol- ished from Christendom and the principle of civil and religious freedom for the individual, without regard to caste, color, race, or sex, has been established in the most advanced countries, and is destined to be extended to the whole human race. Thus the universal tendency of progress in society is to in- crease the power, rights, and freedom of the individual, and diminish the arbitrary control of collective authority. SECTION III. Historic Tendency of Economic Progress. Upon the principle that all progress is governed by one general law, it is commonly supposed that progress must assume the same form in economics that it does in society and politics. Consequently, because social progress tends toward greater democracy of administration, it is held that industrial progress 1 Guizot's " History of Civilization," chap. xi. CHARACTER OF ECONOMIC PROGRESS. II must be in the direction of the public administration of industry. A little reflection will show this to be a mistake. Although industrial progress has a tendency toward greater specialization, the form it assumes differs from that in social and political institutions, as much as progress in the latter differs from that in physical phenomena. The essential difference between political and industrial insti- tutions is that the utility of the former consists in their harmoni- ous adaptation to the social habits and character of the people, whereas the utility of industrial institutions consists in their economic efficiency their capacity of furnishing wealth cheaply. Since social institutions will necessarily more completely reflect the desire and character of the people in proportion as the masses participate in their construction, it follows that progress in society is a tendency towards democracy of administration of political and social affairs. With economics the case is different. No advantage can accrue to the laborer or the community by any change of industrial institutions which does not enable the la- borer to obtain more wealth for a day's work. Whether industry is conducted on the democratic town-meeting plan, or by a few private individuals, cannot possibly affect the welfare of the com- munity, except as it promotes that end. Unless democracy of industrial administration would cheapen wealth, it would be a burden upon the community, without any compensating advan- tage, since it would involve the care of management without any beneficial result. A brief survey of the history of industrial progress will show that the increasing efficiency of productive methods, and hence the improvement of the means of getting a living, has two characteristics. One is the division and concentration of labor power, the other is the increase and social diffusion of political power. The former tends to specialize and limit the laborer's economic function, the latter tends to generalize and extend his social function. Thus, as the laborer's industrial individuality diminishes, the influence of his social and political individuality increases. Primitive industry, like primitive society, was very simple and homogeneous. Every one performed practically all kinds of labor with equal proficiency. Progress from that point to the 12 MISTAKEN NOTIONS ABOUT FREEDOM. present has been a continuous tendency toward a greater divi- sion, and specialization of labor and concentration of capital. The tendency of this movement has ever been to differentiate productive force into numerous portions, integrating the laborer and machinery upon special branches, every one of which is dependent not only upon the action of the others, but upon the united action of the whole. Thus industrial differentiation, in- stead of increasing, tends to diminish the economic individuality of the laborer. It is because of this tendency to make the laborer an almost automatic part of a highly complex productive ma- chine, that the present industrial system is regarded as inimical to his social freedom. Those who take this view, and they are very numerous, lay great stress upon the fact that the laborer is an employe. To them the very stipulation of income means limita- tion of freedom. Of all the objections urged against the wages system, this is probably the most universal, and is regarded as the most fundamental. They think the only conditions under which social freedom is possible, is where the laborers employ themselves. The fallacy in this position arises from a miscon- ception of the idea of freedom. Freedom is not a mere theoretic form, but a sturdy fact. It does not consist in the formal per- mission, but in the actual power, to go or to do. Nothing can give social and political freedom but wealth ; the freedom that wealth affords does not depend upon whether the laborer works for himself or for another, but it depends entirely upon how much wealth he receives. There is no power in nature, society, or government that can make a poor man free. Poverty is social weakness ; it is the source of slavery, and the background of despotism. Social well-being consists not so much in doing, as in having. In proportion as man's energies are expended in obtaining a living, the possibilities of his social, intellectual, and moral life and de- velopment 'are restricted. In order, then, to maximize man's social individuality, it is necessary to minimize the expenditure of his physical energy. This is precisely what the division of labor, the concentration of capital, and the development of the factory system promote. The de-individualization of the laborer as a producer promotes his social advancement in many ways. In the first place, it makes INFLUENCE OF THE WAGES SYSTEM. 13 the wages or stipulated-income system necessary. In proportion as the income of any class becomes stipulated, it becomes less contingent. To the extent that this occurs, material subsistence becomes more certain, which is the first step toward social and intellectual development. So long as the laborer's living is uncertain, he is in a more or less constant state of anxiety and suspense, which tends to make progress in the higher phases of social life impossible. Another beneficial feature of this tendency is that it concentrates the laborers, and specializes their occupations. By this means they are not only forced into closer and more frequent intercourse with each other, but it also increases their mutual interdependence. The material condition of the masses cannot be improved, nor can their political freedom or social character be developed, by any thing which does not increase the economic interdepend- ence of the people, and weld them together in social classes. In proportion as this process of social differentiation increases, interests and sympathies broaden, altruism is developed, and the welfare of all becomes identical with that of each. Nothing so surely aids social advancement as that which makes it necessary for millions to rise together. No industrial system, no civiliza- tion, no religion even is worth sustaining which only saves a few. Another feature of the wages system is the tendency to promote more constant employment. There is no fact more conclusively established in the history of industrial progress than that the concentration of capital in fixed plants and large enterprises makes a marked increase in the permanence of employment. As industrial establishments increase in size, constant employ- ment of capital becomes necessary. The loss involved in the short stoppage of a large factory will soon be more than equal to the profit of a year's business. Whatever increases permanence in the use of capital necessarily increases the constancy of employment. Thus, as the factory methods develop, the capi- talist has to pay the penalty for enforced idleness through loss or bankruptcy ; and hence permanent employment becomes one of the features of the industrial expertness of capitalistic manage- ment. Under the individual or self-employing regime this was not the case. When the hand weaver failed to sell his cloth or make a living, he could starve, beg, go to jail, or die, as the case 14 ECONOMIC PROGRESS DEFINED. might be. His poverty involved nobody else, while under the wages system the great capitalist, nay, the whole community, is involved with the enforced idleness of the laborer. Accordingly, the world over, we find that permanence of employment increases and enforced idleness diminishes where the wages system is most developed and capital most concen- trated. This is clearly shown by the currents of emigration. People always leave those localities and countries where employ- ment is the most precarious and least remunerative, and move towards those where it is most permanent and best rewarded. Hence the tendency of emigration is always from those coun- tries where the wages system and factory methods are least developed, to those where they are most highly developed. It is from China, Bohemia, Austria, Italy, Germany, and Ireland, towards England and America, that laborers emigrate, and not from England or America to Continental Europe and Asia. The industrial system, which tends to socialize the laborer, in- crease the economic interdependence of the capitalist, consumer, and workman, and make the material well-being of the masses the basis of business success, necessarily possesses all the possi- bilities of an ever-advancing civilization. Progress in politics and society, therefore, may be defined as the tendency to increase the sovereignty of the individual and diminish the arbitrary authority of the state by establishing greater democracy of administration. In economics k may be defined as the tendency to centralize industrial administration and responsibility, de-individualize the laborer as a producer and socialize the results in better and cheaper products. CHAPTER II. THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. SECTION I. The Elements of Social Progress. IN the preceding chapter two facts were established. First, that social progress is the movement of society toward the reali- zation of the highest material, intellectual, and moral possibilities in human life ; i.e., toward the plane of greater human well- being. Second, that this progressive movement consists in a series of changes from a relatively simple to a relatively complex state of social organization. We now come to the consideration of the law by which this movement takes place ; that is to say, the order in which the different phases of social phenomena are developed. These may be grouped under three general heads, as the material, the intellectual, and the moral. The material element in social progress is not merely that which relates to man's physical necessities, but every thing that relates to his wants and desires, of whatever kind, the gratification of which involves the production of wealth. These will be found to in- clude, not only the necessities for food and shelter, but those for education, art, travel, intellectual and moral culture, and even religion. In fact, there are no desires of which man is capa- ble whose gratification does not directly or indirectly necessitate the production of wealth. The material element in social progress, therefore, includes every thing which relates to the gratification of human wants, desires, and aspirations. The intel- lectual element is that which relates to man's capacity to acquire and apply knowledge ; it is the analyzing, reasoning, judging, and directing element. Morality simply relates to the quality of is 1 6 THE ORDER OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. human conduct. We designate conduct as moral or immoral according as it directly or indirectly tends to promote or retard social well-being or human happiness. While these phenomena are distinct in their character they are inseparable in their relation ; hence no differentiation can result in permanent integration and specialization which does not find expression in all these phases of social life. 1 If the development of any one of these elements should be promoted at the expense of the rest, it must necessarily fail of its function because not one of them can permanently exist without the sustaining influence of the others. The increased production and accumulation of wealth, for example, could not continue without the increase of intelligence to devise the means necessary to produce it, and a corresponding advance in the social integrity to sustain it. A general advancement of intelligence is impossible without the relative elimination of poverty and vice ; and no considerable advance in ethics can take place without a previous increase in material well-being. SECTION II. The Natural Order of Social Progress. Although the various elements of social development are in- separably connected with, and constantly act and react upon each other, one of them must necessarily sustain the initiative relation to the others, or no movement could take place. Which of these occupies that position ? The answer to this question must explain the relative position these elements occupy in the scale of development and the historic order of their appearance, both of which are indicated by their functional relations. Morality, being the quality of conduct, necessarily arises from motives, decisions, and actions, and hence must be a resultant of the other elements. Morality is the fruit and not the root ; it is the objective point towards which progress tends, and conse- quently is the last to be developed. 8 The intellect, as already explained, is the reasoning, analyzing, judging faculty ; its func- tion consists exclusively in adapting means to an end. It occupies the position of servant and guide to the other faculties. ' ' The progress of society is not moral progress, or intellectual progress, or material progress ; but it is the combination of all the three." Fiske's " Cosmic Philosophy," vol. ii., p. 245. * Ward's "Dynamic Sociology," vol. i., p. 216. MATERIAL PROGRESS THE FIRST. 1? Human activities are never exerted except for the gratification of some desire, want, sympathy, sentiment, or ambition arising in the feelings. Intellectual or physical effort put forth without some motive or desire would be senseless. 1 Of necessity, there- fore, the material element in social progress is first in the scale of development and supplies the motive which calls the intellect into activity. All the inventions and discoveries in manufacture, science, and literature, all the doctrines of economics, ethics, politics, and religion have been produced by the intellect in its effort to gratify the desires. These efforts have been perpetuated or abandoned in proportion as they were found, by experience, to be favorable or unfavorable to human well-being. Clearly, therefore, the natural order of the various elements in social development is : the material, the intellectual, the moral ; the material being the basis or motor force, the intellectual the means, and the moral the result." Although the fact that progress of society has always been in the ascending order from the material to the moral has been generally recognized as a matter of history, it has been almost uniformly ignored as a principle in social philosophy. There appears to have been an undefined apprehension that to permanently regard the material as the preponderating element in human progress is to belittle the influence exercised by the intellect upon the advance of civilization. This is a mistake. The danger of inverting the order of its operation is what is most likely to occur. It is precisely at this point that some of the most fatal errors have "entered the popular theories. The best writers agree that in the early stages of social growth the material element is first in order and influence, but seeing that the mate- rial conditions and moral character advance more rapidly as the 1 Comte's "Positive Philosophy," pp. 384-50x3. 8 " The same may be said of all the so-called virtues honesty, benevolence, justice, etc. These qualities are the result of his civilization. His moral nature has sprung from his rational faculties, and may be traced back to its origin in sympathy : at first confined to his immediate companions or offspring ; thence gradually extended to embrace his own clan ; then his particular tribe, race, or country ; then, to a limited degree, the whole human race ; and lastly, as exhibiting the highest type, and quite rare even among the most civilized, made to comprehend the lower brute creation in one beneficent scheme of morals." Ward's " Dynamic Sociology," vol. i., p. 461. 2 1 8 COMTE'S MISTAKE. intellect develops, they appear to assume that the order of prog- ress changes and the intellectual instead of the material element becomes the dominating influence in social progress. Even Comte says : " If our affective faculties were subordinated to the intellectual, all idea of improving the social organism would be senseless. . . . For our affective faculties must preponderate, not only to rouse the reason from its natural lethargy, but to give a permanent aim and direction to its activity, without which it would be ever lost in vague, abstract speculation." ' After having thus affirmed the truth of the ascending order, he says : " This is the natural order . . . whereas the reverse is the rational one and that which gains upon the other in proportion as the intellect assumes a larger share in the human evolution." 2 Thus, according to Comte, upon the dawn of the human intellect, the natural order became irrational. Buckle, Draper, and Guizot all take practically the same position. Though they do not go through the same course of reasoning that M. Comte does, they act upon the same conclusions. They all admit that material conditions must precede intellectual and moral development, and then insist that the intellect is the source of human progress. 5 For the assumption that the order of evolution is thus reversed by the accession of the intellect there is no warrant either in rea- son or fact. That the material element in progress is greatly accelerated by the reflex action of the intellect, and the intellec- tual by the moral, and that progress is greatly enhanced thereby, is unquestionable. But that in no way implies any change in the law of social movement. The fact that the intellect fills a much larger sphere in human life than it once did, does not tend to show that it has in any way changed its relative position. The differ- ence in the activities of man in modern civilized society and those of his savage ancestors simply represents the difference in the quality and quantity of his desires. The intellect, by the very nature of its function, is not a propelling, but a guiding element. It is the servant and not the master of human wants. 1 "Positive Philosophy," p. 500. American edition. 3 Ibid., pp. 685, 636. 3 Buckle's " History of Civilization," vol. i., pp. 30, 31 ; cf. also pp. 242 and 509 ; Draper's " Intellectual Development of Europe," p. 591 ; Guizot's " History of Civilization," pp. 66, 84, 85, and 230. THE INTELLECT OBEYS THE WANTS. 19 The operation of this principle is clearly illustrated in the social effect of the discovery of the mariner's compass, the art of print- ing, the use of gunpowder, etc. It was not until some consider- able portion of mankind desired the products of other nations that navigation became necessary and the mariner's compass could be of service to man, while gunpowder and printing, having been invented before the desire for them was developed, had to wait thousands of years before they could exercise any influence upon civilization. 1 Although our acquisitions in sci- ence, art, labor-saving inventions, etc., are the work of the intellect, it is only when those achievements minister to human wants that its activities tend to promote human progress. It is true, however, that the influence of a new acquisition by the intellect seldom fully expands itself in the satisfaction of the wants to which it directly relates, but it frequently exercises a reflex influence, the tendency of which is to again increase the desire and consequently still further stimulate its own activity. For example, the art of printing not only increased the number of books sufficiently to supply those who had already acquired a positive desire for reading, but it so cheapened them as to put them within the reach of a large class to whom such a luxury had previously been impossible, thereby greatly increasing the desire for, as well as the possibilities of, obtaining knowledge. Again, when the power-loom and the spinning-jenny were invented, they not only enabled the manufacturers to supply the increasing demand for cotton cloth, but they so reduced its price that it could become an article of common use among the masses. This fact naturally soon gave rise to such desires for other and superior fabrics that the result was to ultimately revolutionize the industrial system of all Europe. It is therefore not true that the natural order of social evolu- tion is changed by the development of the intellect. To whatever extent the sphere and activities of the intellect may be increased, its relative position and function must, by the very nature of its constitution, remain the same. A similar error prevails in regard to the position of ethics in social progress. Because personal morality, commercial integ- rity, industrial equity, and social harmony are seen to increase 1 See Part II., chapter i. 2O ERRORS REGARDING ALTRUISM. as the altruistic feelings advance in society, it is held that altruism and egoism are essentially antagonistic to each other. Egoism is a term usually employed as relating to self, and altruism as relating to others ; hence all actions and feelings are regarded as egoistic in proportion as they tend to promote the welfare of self to the exclusion of others ; and conversely they are altruistic in pro- portion as they tend to promote the well-being of others to the exclusion of self. From this position it has been consistently inferred that self- interest is inimical to the well-being of society. The natural effect of such a conclusion is to create an aversion to all indus- trial institutions in which this principle is recognized and to stimulate the demand for a reconstruction of society on a so- called altruistic basis. This reasoning involves a misconception of the terms egoism and altruism and their logical relation to each other. It is a radical error to regard altruism as anti- egoistic, or even non-egoistic, in its influence. To injure or ignore the well-being of self is to destroy the first essential con- dition for promoting the welfare of others. We can only be helpful to others in proportion as we are well provided for our- selves. 1 The poor, the weak, and the inferior are always a burden rather than a help to their friends. Egoism may be defined as relating to the welfare of self ; and altruism as relating to the welfare of self and others. The basis of true altruism is successful egoism. Altruism differs from egoism, not in being opposed, or even indifferent to, the interests of self, but only in embracing the interests of others besides self-. Thus all real altruism is highly egoistic, though all egoism is not altruistic. All conduct may be called relatively altruistic accord- ing as it benefits more than one, and relatively egoistic as it benefits less than all. It is a mistake, therefore, to conclude that altruistic conduct in society can be increased only as the princi- ple of self-interest is diminished. There is, moreover, unconscious and conscious altruism. The 1 " The acts required for continued self-preservation, including the enjoyment of benefits achieved by such acts, are the first requisites to universal welfare. Unless each duly cares for himself his care for all others is ended by death ; and if each thus dies there remains no other to be cared for. This permanent supremacy of egoism over altruism, made manifest by contemplating existing life, is further made manifest by contemplating life in the course of evolution." Spencer, " Data of Ethics," pp. 187, 188. THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. 21 former is altruistic conduct prompted by egoistic motives ; the latter is that inspired by altruistic motives. In the progress of society unconscious altruism precedes and tends to develop con- scious altruism. Much the larger portion of the altruistic con- duct in the world to-day is of the unconscious class. The great improvements in manufacture and commerce that have put so many luxuries and refinements within the reach of the average citizen have, for the most part, been created by egoistic motives. It is because the industrial policy of the employing class has been dominated too much by the idea of benefiting self to the exclu- sion of others that it has received so many disastrous checks. We shall hereafter see that industrial depressions, bankruptcies, enforced idleness, and their accompanying evils, are the economic penalty for ignoring the interests of others in the efforts to bene- fit self. Those who are excluded from the benefits we enjoy become a menace to our well-being and a hindrance to our prog- ress ; and conversely, the more completely the welfare of others becomes identical with our own the more is our own increased. Altruism, then, is not opposed to egoism ; it is simply a higher phase of it. Obviously, altruism the highest form of ethical conduct is the consequence of broadening the egoistic activities of the material and intellectual elements, and hence is necessa- rily last in the order of development. We are therefore war- ranted in concluding that the progress of society toward greater complexity of organization, in which the necessity of physical effort is diminished, intellectual power and personal freedom increased, and moral character elevated, is always in the ascend- ing order from the material to the intellectual and moral ; the material being the basis, the intellectual the means, and the moral qualities the result. What then are the influences by which exclusive egoism is transformed into all inclusive altruism, and savagery is converted into civilization ? To answer this question is to explain the cause of social progress and will be the subject of the next chapter. CHAPTER III. THE CAUSE OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. IT is not enough to known what progress is, or even to know the law of progress ; but the cause of progress must also be under- stood before a true system of social philosophy can be established. We have seen : (i) that social progress consists in changes of man's social polity, or institutions, and not in his physical organ- ism ; (2) that while all progress is change, only those changes are progressive which tend to further social differentiation ; (3) that while there can be no social progress without differentiation, only that differentiation is progressive which results in new inte- grations and greater complexity of social relations. What then is the force which produces the changes that result in integrating differentiation ? If we examine the history of social institutions from their simplest beginnings, or trace them from their most complex stages back to the earliest times, we shall find that every change in the polity of society whether in- tellectual, political, moral, or religious has been brought about by man's conscious effort to adapt social institutions to his own needs and desires. Social institutions are established by man exclusively for men. It may be said that the changes in social institutions are the work of the human intellect ; that, where man's social wants are the most numerous his physical and intel- lectual activities are the most varied and all phases of social institutions are the most highly differentiated. In the last analysis the proximate cause of social progress is human wants. In the first place, it will be observed that all desires, of what- ever character, are simply states of feeling, the distinguishing characteristics of which are pleasure and pain. In proportion as 22 DESIRE THE CAUSE OF EFFORT. 23 pleasure exceeds pain in human experience happiness prevails and life becomes attractive and desirable ; and conversely, as pain exceeds pleasure misery prevails and life becomes undesirable. These antithetical states are completely represented in the terms, want and satisfaction. Want is pain ; satisfaction is pleasure ; and the extent to which the latter exceeds the former is the true measure of happiness. To increase the proportion of pleasure to pain, therefore, is the primary purpose of all human effort and the immediate cause of social differentiation. Although all effort is exerted for the gratification of some desire, there are many desires that fail to call forth sufficient effort for their satisfaction. Effectual desires are those which incite the necessary activity for their gratification ; those which fail to call out such effort are in- effectual. Only effectual desires cause progress. Why are some desires effectual and others ineffectual ? it may be asked. Upon what principle is effort expended for the satisfaction of some wants and not for others ? A moment's consideration will show that this is all determined by the relative degree of pain and pleasure involved. Hence, the gratification of any given desire must finally turn upon the choice between a relatively painful want and a relatively painful effort, the decision always being in favor of the minimum pain. If this be true, it follows that human wants are not only the cause of social progress, but that advance- ment toward a higher plane of happiness can only take place on the egoistic principle of obtaining the maximum pleasure for the minimum pain. It thus appears that self-interest in man is not an evil element, as we have been taught to consider it, but that the principle of egoism affords the basis of, and inspiration to, social develop- ment. Man in his most primitive state was exclusively egoistic in his desires and in his conduct. Altruism was not visible in any thing that he did. Having no social or physical interest in his fellow-man, there was no more economic or ethical reason, why he should not steal from, or even kill and eat, him, than that the lion should not devour the lamb. As his wants became more numerous the efforts to satisfy them became more burdensome, and the contest between want and effort began. The want must remain ungratified or a means of gratifying it less painful than the want itself must be devised. This 24 THE ORIGIN OF EQUITY. could only be accomplished by inventing labor-saving con- trivances ; and invention is exclusively the function of the mind. The greater the demand for this mental activity the more rapidly are the intellectual faculties developed, and the more easily are wants gratified. It was precisely upon this principle that the crude tomahawk, bow and arrow, and canoe were first employed, and the division of labor became a necessity. With the division and specialization of labor, exchange of products became indis- pensable to the gratification of wants, and some degree of inter- course having been established, a beginning of confidence became inevitable. As the wants of men increased, and they became more dependent upon each other for the means of satisfying them, they naturally became more settled and social in their mode of life, and as soon as the crudest form of association be- came necessary, altruistic conduct began. The fact that asso- ciation arose from self-interest made it indispensable that the advantages should be mutual to some extent. Thus from purely egoistic motives it became absolutely necessary that the efforts to benefit self should be so directed as to confer some benefit upon others. Through this closer social contact wants became still more varied and efforts more specialized ; intellectual activity in- creased and individuality gcew more pronounced. When, from these influences, exclusive family relations, with the permanent care of offspring, developed, and the private ownership of prop- erty became customary, it was obvious that one of two things must occur, either the security of life and property must be increased, or these complex social relations must be abandoned ; otherwise the danger to life and property would neutralize all the new advantages. Thus a certain degree of morality became in- dispensable to self-interest, and the murder, theft, and treachery which a more simple life induced, having proved injurious to all and permanently beneficial to none, were pronounced capital offences. The more closely we consider history in this light, the more clearly it appears that the same principle applies to the whole moral code. Just as fast as the quality of an action becomes uniformly recognized it is designated moral or immoral, and passes from the sphere of conscious expediency to that of moral principle. DEVELOPMENT OF MORALITY. 2$ In this way virtue tends to perpetuate itself, while vice or immorality tends to its own elimination. The object of intel- lectual activity being to serve the desire for happiness, it is neces- sarily employed in devising means for eliminating the painful without reducing the pleasurable experiences, and it is only as this eliminating process takes place that new social integrations become permanent and the best results of progress are secured. This principle applies to all phases of human conduct. All the improvements in medicines, ethics, politics, and economics are the direct results of this eliminating process. It may be urged that the altruism, or morality, thus evolved from egoistic motives, is only of the unconscious kind, and is very different from the conscious altruistic feeling which we recognize in the highest moral characters. If we pursue the enquiry a little further we shall see that volitional altruism is but a higher phase of the unconscious expedient. The same principle which leads men to repeat the conduct that produces beneficial results, also leads them to have a common interest in, admiration for, and sympathy with, those identified with such beneficial efforts. It should be remembered, however, that social progress is not a simple, direct movement, but a resultant of the action and reaction of a variety of social currents, and that with each suc- cessive increase in the social complexity the influences affecting their differentiation become more subtle and involved. The increasingly frequent personal intercourse which inevitably arises from more complex social relations, and the greater identity of interests, naturally tends to promote a greater reciprocation of sympathetic feelings. It is a universal principle in sociology that the more frequently we repeat acts which command our own and others' approval, the more they tend to become habitual and automatic ; and in proportion as any conduct tends to become an unconscious part of daily life, it forms a fixed element of social character. Accordingly, in the most advanced countries, where the wants and desires of the people are the most numerous *and their industrial and social relations the most complex, we find the greatest degree of honor, virtue, integrity, fair dealing, general honesty, and public and private justice ; in short, the highest phase of moral conduct. To such an extent is this true that con- tracts, sometimes covering millions of dollars, are daily made 26 NEW WANTS THE CAUSE OF PROGRESS. between parties in New York, London, Paris, etc., who never saw each other. Should either party violate such obligation, the law which expresses the moral character in the respective countries would enforce its fulfilment, and the civilized world even sanctions warfare when nations violate their treaties with each other. The transfer of conduct from a basis of conscious utility to that of moral principle is but another step in social evolution ; the essential difference being direct and indirect experience. When we act upon the abstract principle of right and wrong we are simply basing our conduct upon generalizations drawn from the repeated experiences of others. We accept it as a dogmatic principle only because its expediency has been pre- viously demonstrated. Nor is this all. The influences which are thus elevating indi- vidual egoism into moral principle are also simultaneously tending to expand and intensify sympathetic, altruistic feeling. In pro- portion as the influence of man's egoism becomes indirect, and that of his altruism direct, he becomes more sensitive to the feelings of others and less absorbed in his own ; so that, instead of regarding the misery of others with indifference, as formerly, a comparatively slight unhappiness becomes the source of great pain to him, and often the incentive to his highest action. Hence we see that, whereas man could once kill and feed upon his fellows, to-day the advanced races regard injury to another as equal to harm inflicted upon themselves. Viewing the subject in all its phases, we see that in every direction the increase of egoistic wants is the real source of social progress. It develops the activity of the intellect ; this in turn differentiates the social environment ; engrafts virtue into char- acter ; transforms conscious egoism and unconscious altruism into unconscious egoism and conscious altruism ; elevates utility into morality, and makes moral principle, instead of individual interest, the basis of social conduct. Thus, as man's intellect is called into activity by the differentiation of his desires, so is his moral character developed by the differentiation of his interests. CHAPTER IV. THE VERIFICATION OF THE LAW OF SOCIAL PROGRESS. ACCORDING to the theory of social progress presented in the preceding chapters the development of man's social wants, and the consequent increase in the general consumption of wealth, is the necessary precursor of social, intellectual, and moral advance- ment. If this doctrine is correct we may always expect to find the highest state of civilization, and the most complete social, political, and religious freedom, in those countries where the material well-being of the masses is the most marked and con- tinuous. And conversely, wherever the development of social wants have been the most restricted, we may equally expect to find the greatest intellectual and moral stagnation, and social, political, and religious despotism. The operation of this law is as universal as the human race. History is replete with the evidence that social, political, and re- ligious freedom is everywhere large or limited, the intellectual and moral character high or low, in proportion as the general consumption of wealth by the masses is great or small. The his- tory of India and China, for instance, reveals to us peoples whose simple habits of life induce very few wants, and those chiefly of a physical character which are easily supplied. Their food consists chiefly of rice, ragi, or millet, with a little seasoning. Their houses are mainly fragile huts which may keep out the rays of the sun, but seldom afford much protection against wind and rain. The furniture and clothing of the common people are equally simple and meagre, being confined to the limited uses which a rice-diet and a ten-cent-a-day social life make necessary. 27 28 INDIA, CHINA, AND EGYPT. Although the political institutions of the two countries are in many respects essentially different, the economic and social con- ditions of the people are practically the same. What law and caste has done towards stereotyping the industrial and social degradation of the laboring classes in Hindostan, custom has just as firmly established in China. The natural result of these con- ditions is the arrest of material and social progress in those countries. If we can accept the testimony of modern travellers, the people of India and China are in substantially the same state of mental and moral degradation that they were in nearly three thousand years ago. 1 In Egypt the industrial and social systems were very similar to those in India and China, and their influence upon civilization was substantially the same. Dates composed the staple food of the common people. The poverty of the masses in ancient Egypt may be inferred from the fact that the children of the lower classes went entirely naked, and that to bring up a child to maturity did not cost more than twenty drachmas, or thirteen shillings of English money,* i.e., about three dollars and a quarter. The social and political servitude of the lower classes is shown by the fact that they were prohibited by law and custom from owning land, participating in public affairs, or even choosing their own occupation.* So far as data are obtainable, a similar set of facts present 1 ' ' The nations of Europe have very little idea of the actual condition of the inhabitants of Hindostan. They are more wretchedly poor than we have any notion of." "Transactions of Asiatic Society," vol. i. t p. 482. "From the earliest period to which our knowledge of India extends, an immense majority of the people, pinched by the most galling poverty, . . . crouching before their superiors in abject submission, and only fit either to be made slaves them- selves or to be led to battle to make slaves of others." Buckle's " History of Civilization," vol. i., p. 53. " It is remarkable how little the people of Asiatic countries have to do in the revolution of their governments. They are never guided by any great and common impulse of feeling, and take no part in events the most interesting and important to their country and their own posterity." " Journal of Asiatic Society," vol. i., p. 250. See also Alison's " History of Europe," vol. x., pp. 419, 420. ' Buckle's " History of Civilization," vol. i., p. 63. 1 " If any artisan meddled with political affairs, or engaged in any other em- ployment than the one in which he had been brought up, a severe punishment was inflicted upon him." Wilkinson's " Ancient Egyptians," vol. ii., pp. 8, 9. GREECE AND ROME. 2Q themselves in the much-lauded early civilization of South Ameri- ca. The leading features of the industrial and social system in ancient Mexico and Peru were similar to those of China, India, and Egypt ; and consequently their influences upon human progress were substantially the same. What rice was to the in- habitants of India and China, and dates to those of Egypt, maize and bananas were to the people of Mexico and Peru. Here too, poverty, ignorance, and servitude, with all their attendant evils, were the direful lot of the laboring classes. 1 The history of ancient Rome and Greece presents a similar picture, although the setting is somewhat different. These two countries differed from each other in some respects ; their cli- mate, religion, political institutions and literature were unlike those of India, China, Egypt, and early America in many im- portant particulars ; but in one fundamental respect they were all substantially the same namely, the material and social con- dition of the people. The great mass of the people in Greece and Rome were miser- ably poor and the very few were enormously rich. Despite the progress of art, philosophy, and jurisprudence, the social con- tempt in which the industrial classes were held by their superiors was as intense as that exhibited by the ruling classes of Asia, Africa, and America. Slavery was so thoroughly rooted in the social system of Greece that it was not only sustained by those who had a mer- cenary interest in the traffic, but the philosophers before whose wisdom we of the nineteenth century are asked to bow defended it as being in accordance with natural law. Xenophon, a disciple of Socrates, in expressing his contempt for the laboring classes, declared : " The manual arts are infamous and unworthy of a citizen." Even Plato introduced slaves into his ideal republic. Nor did the scientific mind of Aristotle emancipate him from the iniquitous idea. Speaking of laborers, he says : " These indi- 1 " They (the masses) had nothing that deserved to be called property. They could follow no craft, could arrange no labor, no amusement, but such as was specially provided by law. They could not change their residence or dress without a license from the government. They could not even exercise the free- dom which is conceded to the most abject in other countries that of selecting their own wives." Prescott's "History of Peru," vol. i., p. 159. See also Draper's " Intellectual Development of Europe," p. 461. 3., the same " in all other employments," the reverse is everywhere the case. In all fairly well established industries where any appreciable amount of capital is employed, interest or profit varies from zero up. In farming and every branch of manufacture there are to be found some who are barely holding their own and keeping their capital intact. There are many who for years together receive no interest for the use of their capital, and frequently some who continue to employ it at a net loss, while others in the same business and often in the some locality receive five, ten, and sometimes twenty per cent, profit. It is exactly at this no-interest point that the price of the product is determined 4 ; and every time this price-fixing point is lowered by the use of improved methods of production, these no-interest producers are compelled to produce at a loss or leave the business. This is the only means by which the price of commodities is permanently reduced. It is in this process of pushing the price below the plane of the no-interest producer that 1 This point he makes clear by saying : " But the charges for insurance and for renewals, or wear and tear, are not strictly charges for the use of capital, but simply a provision to preserve its amount unimpaired. . . . Disregarding, therefore, all items of cost of employing auxiliary capital except interest, the law of wages assumes this form : The interest on capital and the price of labor, in all employments, are fixed by the rates paid for their use in those of their actual employments in which they are used indifferently" etc. Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. iii., No. I, pp. 71, 72. 8 Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. iii., No. I, p. 68. 1 Ibid., p. 86. 4 Part II., chapter iv., section iii. 190 WAGES UNLIKE INTEREST. small concerns are constantly being " crowded out of business by large ones ' ; and this tendency increases as the use of capital and specialization of industry develops and civilization advances. Since, in all well established industries subject to free competi- tion, there is capital employed which receives a liberal return as interest or profits, and in the same industries capital is employed for the use of which no interest whatever is paid, it is manifestly incorrect to say : " The same prices . . . are also paid for equal amounts of labor and capital in whatever other employments they may be engaged in." Nor is the second affirmation any more consistent with the facts. If it were true that the rate of wages is determined by, or only equal to, the rate of interest, the rate of wages could never exceed the amount paid for the use of the capital representing an equal amount of productive force. According to this hypothesis, wherever the capital is employed without interest the laborer must also work without wages. It is unnecessary to say that such a state of things is nowhere to be found in the industrial world, not even under slavery. In every industry we can find capital em- ployed without interest, but in no industry can we find labor working without wages. Since capital is frequently used without interest, and labor never used without wages, it is manifestly incorrect to say the rate of wages is determined by or equal to the rate of interest ; and since both the rate of wages and interest vary in different industries, and vary in different localities in the same industry, it cannot possibly be true that " the same prices as are paid in these cases for labor and for the use of capital are also paid for them in all their other employments." The only really important point in Mr. Wood's argument is the recognition of the fact that capital can only be successfully em- ployed when it is cheaper than labor as a means of production, a fact hitherto generally overlooked. Since social progress chiefly depends upon increasing the quantity and reducing the cost of wealth, and this in turn depends upon the use of capital in production, a correct understanding of the law governing the economic use of capital is of the utmost 1 Cf. chapter iv. ; also author's article, Political Science Quarterly, vol. iii., No. 3, pp. 385-408. CONFOUNDING WAGES WITH PROFITS. . 19! importance to economic science. As already explained, 1 that which undersells always succeeds, and that which succeeds establishes the methods by which its success is accomplished j consequently, the principle upon which capital can be successfully employed in production is its relative cheapness as a productive factor. The fact that " as between two methods of obtaining the same result, cheapness is the sole guide," is clear to Mr. Wood, but its economic significance he has evidently failed to recognize. Like the orthodox economists, he sees that the use of capital is the only means of permanently cheapening wealth. And he further sees what they did not, namely : that capital can only be em- ployed when it furnishes productive force cheaper than labor ; but the principle upon which capital becomes cheaper than labor he appears to be no nearer understanding than was Adam Smith, Gregory King, or Thomas Munn. The chief difficulty with Dr. Wood is that he fails to distinguish between the economic character of labor and capital and consequently confounds the price of labor with interest or profit which are fundamentally different. The price of labor, like that of all necessary factors in production, is determined by its own cost and not by interest, nor any thing relating to capital. The use of capital depends upon the cost of labor in two ways its cost as a factor in production, and its expensiveness as an element in consumption. While capital can never be employed unless it can work cheaper than labor, it can only do so when it is accompanied by new employment creat- ing conditions which nothing but an enlarged general consumption and higher wages can supply. Moreover, a general rate of wages and profits in all industries, such as Wood struggles to explain, is nowhere to be found. The rate of wages tends to uniformity only within specific industrial groups. In such countries as India and China and to some extent in Russia and Austria, among purely agricultural producers, there is the nearest approximation to a general rate of wages, because there industrial differentiation is at the minimum. But in proportion as the division of labor and the complexity of industrial and social relations increase, a general rate of wages becomes impossible, because distinctive industrial groups bring different rates of wages into existence. 1 Part II., chapter i. 192 . NO UNIFORMITY OF PROFITS. For example, the wages of spinners, weavers, carpenters, masons, tailors, etc., will tend to a uniform rate for each industry in the same market or locality, but that uniformity does not extend throughout the country. Accordingly, we find that the wages for the same occupation in New York City are very much higher than in rural districts and country villages, for the obvious reason that the cost of supplying the labor-power is greater in the former than in the latter places. Therefore while wages and prices always tend to a uniformity, it is a uniformity for the same quality in the same market. But even this is in no sense true of profits ; on the contrary, all the force of self-interest and economic law tend to make profits move in the opposite direction. The reason for this is very simple. Profits being the net surplus after all costs are paid, it is because prices tend to a uniformity that a variation in the cost makes profits possible, and therefore the greater the variation in the cost of production per unit of product, the greater the variation in the profits. And conversely the more uniform the cost of production per unit, the more uniform and the smaller the maximum amount of profit. Instead of profits tending towards a uniformity, they tend towards diversity, varying from zero up, in proportion as the complexity in productive methods and variety in the cost per unit increases. SECTION II. Professor Clark's Theory. In a recent monograph ' Professor Clark presents a theory of wages which, if not new, has some new features in it. The fun- damental point in this theory is, that the price of all factors in production is determined by what the last and no-rent increment can produce, which when applied to labor is, that the general rate of wages is determined by what the laborer could produce " empty-handed " or with such land and tools as can be had for nothing. As a theory of wages this is essentially the doctrine of Henry 1 A paper on the " Possibility of a Scientific Law of Wages," read before the Third Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association, in Philadelphia, December 27, 1888. " Publications American Economic Association," vol. iv., No. I. CLARK'S THEORY STATED. 193 George, which we have shown to be contrary to all experience. 1 Mr. Clark, however, seems to think the fallacies which we exposed in the theory of Mr. George are not due to the principle of the doctrine, but result from a too restricted application of it. Instead of limiting the theory to no-rent land, as George does, he extends it to no-rent instruments in all departments of the social working-field.* This theory affirms : (i) that there is a no-rent point at which every productive factor is employed ; (2) that this marginal or no-rent place is where the price of using all productive instruments is determined ; (3) that this price-fixing portion of the supply is always the last increment that is brought into use hence, "the men who fix the standard of wages are in the rear rank, not in the front " ; (4) that the wages of the last or price-fixing increment depend upon the proportion between the number of laborers and the amount of capital employed ; and consequently, that wages can only be advanced in proportion as capital increases faster than labor. 1. Is it correct to say that there is a no-rent point in the use of all productive factors ? Something depends here upon what is meant by the phrase " no-rent." If by rent he means the cost of maintaining the instrument unimpaired, then the statement is manifestly incorrect. In this sense a permanent no-rent use of any productive factor is impossible, since its wear and tear would soon cause its total destruction. If, however, by rent he means that which the owner obtains in addition to maintaining its pro- ductive efficiency unimpaired, the statement is unexceptionable. Regarding rent in the sense of net surplus, there is unquestion- ably a no-rent point at which every productive factor, including labor, is employed.' 2. Whether or not it is correct to say that the price of using the productive instruments is determined at the no-rent (no-sur- plus) point, depends upon the sense in which the word " price " is used. If by the price of using productive instruments is meant the expense of maintaining their productive efficiency, which 1 " Wealth and Progress," Part II., chap, i., sec. iii. * " The true margin of cultivation more accurately that of utilization is not wholly nor chiefly an agricultural thing ; it extends throughout the indus- trial system. . . . There is a margin of utilization in cotton spinning, in iron-smelting, in shop-keeping." Pp. 44, 45. 3 Part III., chapter iii. 194 HE COMMITS THE SAME ERROR AS MARX. constitutes a necessary part of the cost of production, and is paid by the consumer in the price of the product, there can be no exception to the statement. But if by the price of using produc- tive instruments is meant the rent of land, and the profit or interest of capital, or the savings of labor, in short, surplus incomes none of which enters the cost of production, then the statement would be manifestly incorrect. Instead of these being determined at the price of no-rent use, they are always deter- mined by variations from it. 1 It would indeed be a contradiction in terms to say surplus incomes are determined by no-surplus uses. 3. The third proposition will be found to be much less satis- factory. In affirming that the last increment added to the supply is the price-determining increment, Prof. Clark has made a ques- tionable application of his argument. He here confounds the last with the dearest increment as if they were quite equivalent expressions. In doing this he has committed precisely the same mistake that Marx made in following Ricardo and confounding the quantity with the cost of labor as the determining factor in value. When Ricardo said " the value of commodities is deter- mined by the quantity of labor devoted to their production," he really meant the cost of that labor. But he erroneously assumed that a given quantity of labor always represents the same cost 3 ; hence, the cost and quantity at any given time are equivalent expressions. Marx literally accepted Ricardo's expression, " the quantity of labor " without regard to its cost, the logical applica- tion of which led directly to the colossal error of declaring that profits are exploitation of labor, an error which the adoption of the other form of expression, " cost of labor," would have entirely obviated. 3 The position of Prof. Clark is another instance of the same kind. Ricardo's theory jof rent, which is the evident basis of his doctrine, affirms that the last increment of land brought into cul- tivation is always the no-rent and hence the price-determining portion. The idea he endeavors to apply to the whole sphere of 1 See Part III., chap. iv. 2 See " Political Economy and Taxation," ch. i., sec. ii. and iii. * See article on " Economic Basis of Socialism," Political Science Quarterly for December, 1889. THE LAST-INCREMENT FALLACY. 195 price phenomena. He assumes that the price of all productive instruments is determined by the no-rent increment, and that this is always the increment which is brought into use last. It is here that the element of error enters the doctrine and invalidates it as a scientific theory of prices, either of labor or of commodities. In making the last increment of land the rent-fixing increment, Ricardo confounded the last with the dearest increment, exactly as in the previous case he confounded the quantity with the cost of labor. The real reason Ricardo held that the rent of all land was fixed by the last increment brought under cultivation was, because he erroneously assumed that the last increment was always the poorest and therefore the dearest. Here as in the former case he assumed that the two were equivalent expressions but always spoke of the " last." Prof. Clark like Marx accepts the literal form rather than the interior meaning of Ricardo's expressions and with similarly fatal consequences. It can easily be shown that this " last-increment " theory is inconsistent with the facts, alike in regard to land, capital, and labor. It is well known that Ricardo's assumed order of cultiva- tion is entirely unhistoric. Instead of the best land always being used first and the poorest last, the reverse order more frequently occurs. For instance, when the land brought into cultivation last will yield more for the same investment than that already culti- vated, as is often the case, the price of the product will not fall to the cost of production on this last land, because in that case all the previously cultivated land would be thrown out of use by making the price so low as to render its cultivation impossible. If the product of all the land under cultivation is needed, the price must be high enough at least to enable the poorest portion to be cultivated without paying rent. Thus while the poorest portion will be the price-fixing and no-rent increment, it will not be the last, but the last increment, being the best or better than the poorest, will be a rent-paying and not the price-fixing increment. Having confused the last with the dearest increment, Prof. Clark's argument from this point on, like that of Marx, leads directly to error in proportion to the consistency with which it is pursued. He says " it is a familiar commercial principle that the last increment of the supply of any commodity fixes the general price 196 A NEW ELEMENT OF CONFUSION. of that article." Instead of that principle being familiar in commerce and manufacture, it is even less true there than in the case of land. There is no fact better established in the history of manufacture than that it is the oldest, poorest, and hence the dearest machinery and methods which yield no profits. It is the water-wheel factory, the small mules and slow looms that occupy the no-profit or minimum profit position. The new factories with the most modern improvements are those which yield the greatest profits, because they can sell at the same price while producing at a less cost than their price-fixing competitor. In manufacture and commerce, therefore, instead of being the \ last it is usually the first or oldest instruments 'in use which fix the price; but whether the oldest or newest, it is always the dearest. According to the last-increment theory, wages will always be determined by " the last laborers added to the social working force." ' If we observe the history of the mobility of the laborer whether it be from industry to industry, from locality to locality, or from nation to nation, we shall find, except in a few rare instances, that those who enter any given working field last are the most inexperienced, incompetent, and poor. It is the effort to improve their condition that induces people to change their country, locality, or occupation. That is why emigration is always from lower to higher wage-paying countries, why mechanics seldom become farmers, but agricultural laborers are constantly entering the factory and farmers' sons deserting the farms for the cities. The laborer who leaves his country or industry may be and probably often is one of the dearest of the class he leaves, but he is usually among the cheapest in the class he enters. If the poorest laborer fixed the wages when a new man entered any class, the wages of all in that class would fall to his level. The statement that the standard of wages is fixed by " the actual product created by ... the men who run no-rent machinery " introduces a new element of confusion. The men who run the no-rent machinery are not necessarily the last comers in that in- dustry. This is really confounding the price of the laborer with that of the product. Other things being the same, the use of the poorest instruments will determine the no-profit and price-fixing 1 " Possibility of a Scientific Law of Wages," p. 49. 2 Ibid., p. 49. CONFOUNDING WAGES WITH RENT. IQ7 point of commodities, because in that case the quality of the in- struments affects the cost of production. But this is not true of labor ; since the instruments are not used in producing labor- power, its cost, and hence its price, cannot be affected by their quality. As productive instruments are only used in creating commodities, it is the price of commodities alone that can be affected by the quality of such instruments. The price of the instruments may have been affected by that of the previous labor which was employed in their production, but when used as in- struments in production in conjunction with labor they are both simply items in the cost of producing a future product, whose price is fixed by 'them and not theirs by it. For the same reason that the price of raw material is not determined by the finished product into which it enters, but by the price of what enters into it, the price of labor power does not depend upon the price of what it produces, but upon the price of what it consumes i.e., the cost of its own production. Upon no other principle would the product made by the poorest tools be the dearest, and hence the no-profit portion. Therefore, instead of the price of labor being determined by the quality of the instrument it uses, it is the price of the result- ant product only that is so affected. The fact that the entrepre- neur who uses the poorest tools has to pay wages as high as those who use the best, prevents him from having any profit. As a matter of fact the laborer's wages do not grade up and down according to the superiority and inferiority of the instruments he uses. It is only profits which thus vary, and the reason they do so is because wages do not. Another source of confusion is the mistake of regarding wages as sustaining the same relation to labor that rent does to land and that profit does to capital. This it will be remembered was one of the chief errors in Dr. Wood's argument, and Prof. Clark seems not entirely to have escaped it. Although for a time he seems to treat wages as identical with prices, in his grand formula he treats wages as governed by the same law as profits and rent, 1 " The earnings of capital (profits and rent) are subject to identically the same law as those of labor ; they are fixed by the product of the last increment that is brought into the field." " Possibility of a Scientific Law of Wages," P- 53- 198 PRICE AND SURPLUSAGE. which is entirely erroneous. In the use of both capital and land, that which is necessary to replace the wear and tear is not profit or rent but necessary cost. It does not go to the owner of the land or capital, but is all consumed in maintaining its productive efficiency. Wherever land or capital is employed, and the prod- uct is only equal to this necessary cost, there will be no profits or rent. In the case of labor all this is different. All the laborer receives is wages, whether it is cost or surplus. Whether the laborer receives what will barely maintain his economic efficiency or a third more than that amount it is all wages because it is all in the price of his labor. In every class of labor under wage conditions there are some laborers who work at the bare cost point, and others who have a surplus. There is also land that is used at cost point and yields no rent or surplus, and land that yields a rent. 1 So too of capi- tal ; there is some that is used without profit and some that yields a profit. Now those laborers who have no surplus above their cost of living receive wages, and as high wages too as those of their class who have a surplus. But the owners of land and capital which only yields the cost of their use do not receive a surplus as rent or profit. To say profit and rent are governed by the same law as labor is to confound the law of prices with the law of surplus. Wages are the price of labor and are gov- erned by the same law as the price of land, gold, or shoes. Profit and rent, like the laborer's savings, are all surpluses and are governed by the law of surplus. The correct statement therefore is this : the surplus or savings from wages, rent of land, and profit of capital, are all governed by the same law the law of economic surplusage ; and the wages of labor, the price of land, and of commodities are governed by the same law, namely, the law of economic prices. 4. The fourth proposition is the natural outcome of the third. 1 In using the expression " no-rent," the existence of no-rent land and no- profit instruments, is assumed. If however a state of society should be reached where no-rent land does not exist, that would not in the least militate against the law. It would then be the minimum-rent land or tools that occupy the price-fixing position. Indeed the prefix " no " should always be taken to mean " minimum." Then where no-rent land or capital exists the statement is cor- rect, and where they do not exist it is the minimum-rent land or capital that is referred to. DEFECTS OF CLARK'S THEORY. 199 * The doctrine which makes the laborer's income depend upon the quality of his tools naturally leads to the conclusion that wages depend upon capital. Hence it is not surprising that Mr. Clark falls back into the fold of pure wage-fundism which makes the progress of the laborer subsequent to and dependent upon that of the capitalist. He says : " The sole hope of this multitude (the working class) lies in an advance of the margin of the field of capital, and in the retirement of the margin of the field of labor. By this twofold action only can wages rise with great rapidity, but the movement of its margins is possible only by means of a considerable excess of the supply of capital unbal- anced by labor." ' This contains the essence of about all the heresy of orthodox economics. It makes man depend upon wealth instead of making wealth depend upon man. Whatever the merits of this theory may be, it has three serious defects : (i) in assuming that prices are determined by the last instead of by the dearest increment of the supply ; (2) in treat- ing wages as a share of the division of the product instead of a necessary item in the cost of its production ; (3) in putting wages in the same economic category with rent and profit instead of in the category of prices. The natural result is to confound wages with profits, misplace the price-determining factor, and finally invert the economic relation of capital and labor. 1 " Possibility of a Scientific Law of Wages," p. 59. CHAPTER III. THE LAW OF WAGES. SECTION I. The Test of a Scientific Law of Wages. A SCIENTIFIC law of wages must afford a rational explanation of all normal wage phenomena. It must explain what wages are, why they are paid, and how their amount is determined. It must explain why the rate of wages varies in the same industries in different countries and localities, and why it differs in different industries in the same localities ; why the wages in agriculture are always lower than those of manufacturing industries in the same country ; why in the same industries and localities the wages of women are lower than those of men ; and why in all industries a portion of the laborers can save money while others of their class can scarcely make both ends meet. In proportion as any theory fails to account for these constantly recurring facts, it must be deemed insufficient to explain the economic law of wages. In considering the theories of others I have applied this test, and to the extent that they fail to fulfil its requirements, I have not hesitated to pronounce them incomplete or unsound. 1 All that I ask is that the theory presented in this chapter shall be judged by the same standard ; and if it fails to fulfil the require- ments exacted from others, it must share the same fate, and vice versa. In order to avoid confusion it is important at the outset that we definitely understand what the term wages is intended to mean. 1 The criticism of the wages-fund theory, Professor Walker's theory, and Henry George's theory will be found in " Wealth and Progress," Part II., chap. i. ; and that of Dr. Wood and Professor Clark in the preceding chapter. CHARACTER OF THE WAGES-SYSTEM. 2OI SECTION II. Definition of Wages. In the first place, the phrase wages has no economic meaning except under wage conditions ; that is to say, under conditions where the laborer's income consists of a specific amount paid by another for his service as such. Strictly speaking, wages are economically the price of labor. For instance, if a man works for himself, and either sells or consumes the product of his labor, what he receives will not be wages ; it will be the result of his labor, but that will consist of the product he created, whether little or much, good or bad, or indifferent, but it will not be the price of his labor. Nothing can properly be regarded as having a price which is not subject to the conditions of exchange i.e., is not bought and sold. When a man owns and sells the products of his labor, the product has a price but his labor has not, because as labor it has not entered the sphere of exchange, and hence is not subject to the law of prices. So too in slavery, where the laborer owns neither his labor nor his product. Here the product is bought and sold, and hence has a price, but the labor-power as such is not exchanged ; it is the laborer himself that is bought and sold. We do not buy the labor of the horse or the engine. It is true that the motive for buying the horse or engine is to obtain their productive power, but in order to obtain that power we have to buy that in which it is produced. Under slavery the laborer is economically iden- tical with the horse or the engine. It is he and not his labor- power that is bought and sold. The difference in the two systems, then, may be stated thus : under slavery the laborer is a commodity ; under the wages-system it is only his labor-power or service that is a commodity. With this change came a marked social distinction ; under wage conditions, the capitalist, instead of buying and selling laborers as under slavery, buys service and sells products, and the laborer sells service and buys products. Thus the laborer ceases to be a commodity and becomes a distinct social unit who buys and sells, and economic price is transferred from his personality to his labor-power. It is only under condi- tions where the laborer is personally, socially, and politically free and sells his service as such, that wages can properly be said to exist. The price at which service under such conditions is sold by the laborer is wages. 2O2 REAL AND NOMINAL WAGES. It is therefore not the amount received, but the way in which it is received that constitutes it wages. Whether the amount be a hundred dollars a year or a hundred dollars a week makes no economic difference. There is nothing in the nature of wages as such to prevent them from being increased to any amount. The essential characteristic of wages is that they constitute a definite as distinguished from a contingent income. It will be observed that this definition of wages includes the incomes of all, without regard to sex or social status, who sell their service for a stipu- lated amount. The term wages, then, as it will be used through- out this book, means neither more nor less than the price of 'labor '. In the text-books there is usually considerable discussion about nominal and real wages. This, however, need detain us but a moment. Nominal wages simply mean the price that is paid for a given amount of service expressed in the currency or money of the community. Real wages mean the actual amount of wealth or social well-being obtainable for a day's labor. Nominal wages are of no special account except as a mode of expressing real wages. 1 In considering the law of wages, therefore, the question is not how is the laborer's income determined when he works for himself, nor how it is determined when he is personally the property of another, but how his income is determined when he voluntarily sells his service as service. What the employer pays to the laborer is not in any sense a division of the product, but it is wholly an expenditure in purchasing the means of pro- duction. Thus labor (not the laborer) is in exactly the same economic category as raw material, machinery, or any other pro- ductive factor. For instance, when the manufacturer has pro- duced a thousand yards of cotton cloth he does not divide it with his laborers either practically or theoretically ; on the con- trary, all the wages for producing that cloth, including those involved in producing the raw material and machinery, have already been paid. They constitute a part of the cost, and hence the value of the cloth. Whether or not the manufacturer will gain or lose by the transaction is a subsequent matter, and entirely depends upon whether he can produce the cloth at as small a cost as his most incompetent competitor. The economic claim of the laborer therefore is to a definite price for his labor, and not to a proportional share of the prod- ' " Wealth and Progress," pp. 75, 76, 96, 97, 98. WAGES THE PRICE OF LABOR. 203 uct. This really constitutes the economic difference between wages and rent, interest and profit, and is the distinction already pointed out between price and surplus. If the laborer were a claimant to a given proportional share of the product, the size of his income would depend upon the quantity produced, and would thus become a contingent instead of a stipulated amount. In short he would be working in partnership and not working for wages. As before stated, the essential characteristic of the wages system is that the laborer is not a commercial partner ; he has no ownership in the finished product. His economic posi- tion is to sell labor and buy products, and that of the entrepreneur is to buy labor and sell products. Obviously then the laborer sells his productive power to the employer at a stipulated price ; he has no more claim to a proportional share of the product than have those who sell raw material or machinery. The law of wages, then, is the law of the economic price of labor. Therefore, in considering the law of wages the question is not what proportion of the product belongs to the laborer, but how the price of -his labor is economically determined. When we have discovered the law by which the price of labor is governed, we shall be in a position to consider how that price (wages) can be increased. SECTION III. The Law of Wages. One of the essential conditions of a scientific law of prices is that it must be applicable to all price phenomena. Wages being simply the price of labor, must be governed by the same law as the price of commodities. Consequently if the formula of the law of prices presented in a previous chapter ' is correct, we have only to apply that theory to labor in order to find the economic law of wages. If it does not explain the movement of wages as completely as it accounts for the price of commodities, we may safely conclude that it fails to fulfil the requirements of a scientific law. This law it will be remembered is : That economic prices con- stantly tend toward the cost of furnishing the most expensive portion of the necessary supply in any given market ; and that this tendency increases directly as the impediments to free economic movement are diminished. 1 Part II., chap. iv. 2O4 ECONOMIC LAW OF WAGES. 'Applied to labor then, this law is : That wages tend to move towards the cost of furnishing the most expensive portion of the neces- sary supply of labor-power in any given market ; and that this ten- dency increases directly as the individual freedom and mobility of the laborer advances. By the cost of a thing is meant not what it may have cost somebody else or would cost under any other conditions, but Avhat its owner actually gave for it or would have to pay to re- place it. The cost of labor-power then, is what it cost the laborer to furnish it. Obviously the cost of labor-power to the laborer is the cost of his maintenance or living. The cost of the laborer's living, however, is not limited to the simple maintenance of the individual laborer, but it includes all that enters into the neces- sary expenses of his social life. Since the maintenance of the family of the married man is as much a part of his necessary cost of living as his individual food and shelter, it is an indispensable item in the cost of supplying his labor power. Therefore the fam- ily and not the individual is the economic unit in the labor market. The law of wages then, may be more correctly stated thus : The rate of wages in any country, class, or industry constantly tends towards the cost of living of the most expensive families J who furnish a necessary part of the supply of labor in that country, class, or in- dustry, as shown in the following diagram : NO. I. C. 5 c. IO C. 15 c. 20 C. 25 c. $2 $2 $2 $2 $2 $2 Maximum cost $ A B C D E F. $1.95 90 Sour of vings. ce *T $1.85 80 . -. Sa $1 Minimum cost . $1.75 SAVINGS. WAGES. ACTUAL COST. COST REDUCED BY CHEAP LIVING. The reason wages in any class or industry are thus adjusted to the standard of living of the most expensive families is exactly the same as that which we saw caused the price of commodities 1 By the most expensive families is not meant the most expensive single family, but the most expensive ten or twenty per cent, of the class whose labor is required. COST OF LIVING THE BASIS OF WAGES. 2O$ to be adjusted to the cost of producing the most expensive por- tion of the supply. We saw that the price of commodities tends to a uniformity, because the lowest price at which one producer would sell was the highest at which the consumer would buy. This uniformity, through the pressure of the consumer to buy at the minimum, tends to be adjusted at the lowest point the pro- ducer can afford to sell, which is at cost. And since the price tends to uniformity at cost, wherever the cost varies, the uni- formity necessarily takes place at the cost of the dearest incre- ment. This is equally true of labor, and for precisely the same rea- son. Upon the same principle that the producer cannot or will not consent to continuously sell a commodity for less than it cost him to produce it, or than it will cost him to replace it, the laborer cannot or will not long consent to sell his service for less than it costs him (and his family) to live. He will, as ex- perience shows, often work for less than would supply him with exceptional comforts and luxuries, but he will not continuously work for less than will furnish him with those things which by constant repetition and the force of habit have become necessi- ties. Rather than forego these he will refuse to work, and will inaugurate strikes, riots, and other means of endangering the peace and prosperity of the community. If two dollars per day is the minimum amount upon which a cer- tain portion of a given class of laborers can or will consent peace- fully to live, then that amount must be paid them in order to ob- tain their labor. What the most expensive portion of a given class must receive, the others may and will receive. We know that the general rate of wages in the same .industry and locality is nearly uniform. We know, for instance that weavers, spinners, shoe- makers, carpenters, bricklayers, etc., working in the same shop or factory or on the same job, get the same rate of pay for work at their respective trades whether they are single or married, have large or small families, or live more or less expensively than their fellow-laborers. We also know, for reasons already given, that the most expensive among them must obtain for his service what will supply his family with what they regard as necessities. What will be sufficient to supply the urgent necessities of the most ex- pensive portion of any class of laborers, to induce them to con- tinue to work, will furnish all those whose cost of living is less, 2O6 RELATION OF CAPITAL AND LABOR. with a margin proportionate to the difference which may be saved or spent in what to them are luxuries. Thus through the law of price uniformity, by which the cost of producing the most expensive portion determines the general price of the commodity in that market, the minimum amount upon which the most expensive laborers in any class or industry will consent to live and continue at work, determines the rate of wages in that class. .There is one important distinction, however, between these two classes of price phenomena which should not be overlooked. Al- though all prices are governed by the same general law, the price of commodities and of labor move in opposite directions. While the dearest capitalist and the dearest laborer both fix the prices for their class, they occupy relatively opposite positions. The manufacturers who furnish the most expensive portion of the sup- ply of commodities are the poorest and lowest in their class, while the laborers who furnish the most expensive portion of labor- power are the best and highest in their class, as shown in the ac- companying diagram : NO. 2. PROFIT. PRICE. ACTUAL COST. COST SAVED BY CAPITAL. F E D C B A 1C. |c. fc. o c. 4c. 4 c. 46. 4c. 4c. 40. Minimum cost . . . 3c. . ^ Source -c. of 3fc. P . ^ic. rofits. fc.| ; . 4c. , 3- Maximum cost C. 5 c. IO C. 15 c. 20 C. 25 c. $2 $2 $2 $2 $2 $1 Maximum cost $2 A B C D E F . $1. 95 , . fti.oo T I -85 Source 80 ~ of Savings. $i Minimum cost . . $1.75 SAVINGS. WAGES. ACTUAL COST. COST REDUCED BY CHEAP LIVING. DEARER LABORERS HELP THE CHEAPER. 2O/ Here it will be observed the movements are all exactly the same as in the case of commodities (diagram No. i), but the relative positions of all are reversed. Laborer A, like capitalist A, is the dearest. His labor-power cost him $2 a day, and he sells it for $2 a day, and has no surplus ; but instead of being at the bottom of his class, he is at the top. The wages of laborer A, like the price of manufacturer A, are the same as, and fix, those of all the others. Just as the cost of living of the laborers A, B, C, D, E, and F recedes from the cost line of A on the right, does their net-surplus (or the possibility of it) increase in the savings column on the left. That is to say, in proportion as any of the other laborers live upon less than A they are enabled to sell their labor for more than it actually cost them. And the dif- ference, which in the case of the entrepreneur was profit, -consti- tutes a net-surplus for the laborer either to be saved, expended upon luxuries, or for any purpose whatsoever. Thus the lowest laborers are enabled to obtain wages higher than the cost of their own labor, because the dearest laborers are compelled to demand a higher price for their labor-power in order to obtain the equiva- lent of its cost. The relative positions of the laborer and capitalist being the inverse of each other, it will be seen that it is the most advanced laborer and the poorest capitalist who have no surplus. The rea- son for this is that in the progress of society the movement of the price of commodities is downwards, while that in the price of labor is upwards. That is to say, the dearest laborer occupies the top and progressive position, while the dearest capitalist occupies the bottom and receding position. The surplus of the less expensive laborers is the advantage they receive from the struggles of their most expensive brethren. We have thus a law of wages which is not limited to any special industry, country, or period, but whose application is as universal as the existence of wage conditions. 1 If wages are governed by the cost or standard of living, it will of course follow that wages will always be the highest where the socially established standard of living among the laborers is the most complex and expensive ; and, conversely, they will be the 1 See chapter on the Universality of the Law of Wages. " Wealth and Progress," p. 162. 208 WAGES IN DIFFERENT COUNTRIES. lowest where the standard of living is the most simple and in- expensive, and this is precisely what we find the world over. 1 We no sooner recognize this than the reason why the wages of the Asiatic are lower than those of the European becomes obvi- ous. The same difference, and for the same reason, exists between wages paid in similar industries in Continental countries and in England, and between those in England and America. The testimony of history is, that in all countries wages in the same industries have always been higher in large cities than in small ones, and so has the cost of living, which generally implies greater social advancement and general intelligence. This view is further emphasized by the fact that the industrial centres of the world have, from the dawn of human history, been the birthplaces of freedom and the nurseries of civilization. 2 Upon this principle we have no difficulty in understanding why the wages of agricultural laborers are always lower than those of mechanics, and why, as is universally the case, agricultural wages are higher in the vicinity of large cities and towns than in out- lying districts. 3 It is because the wants of the agricultural class are fewer, their social life simpler, and their standard of living lower. As a necessary part of this same fact, we find that agri- cultural laborers are always in the rear ranks of social advance- ment, and are the last to acquire industrial and political rights. The difference between the wages of women and those of men in the same industry is due to the same cause ; it is an entire mistake to assume, as some do, that the lower wages received by women are due to their inferior ability. If wages were determined by the skill and competency of the laborer, then the carpenter, mason, painter, or compositor in the country town with equal skill would get the same wages as those in the large cities. And laborers of equal skill in different industries in Pekin, Tokio, St. Petersburg, and Constantinople would obtain the same wages as those in New York City, whereas we know that the common laborer of New York obtains higher wages than the most skilled mechanics in most of the former places. Nor are the lower wages of women caused by difference in sex, 1 " Wealth and Progress," Part II., chapters iii. and vii. "Part I., chapter v. Also, "Wealth and Progress," pp. 116-119. s "Wealth and Progress," pp. 163-166. SA VINOS-BANK DEPOSITS. since in that case the wages of men everywhere would be higher than those of women anywhere, which is by no means the case. The wages of women in America are as high as those of men in the same industry in any other country, and, with the exception of England, and perhaps Paris, are actually higher. Obviously, then, the wages of women, like those of men, do not conform to the fact of personal skill nor to that of sex, but they do everywhere conform to cost of living. As elsewhere shown, 1 the average woman's cost of living is very much smaller than that of the average man, and her wages are correspondingly lower. The wages of women are lower than those of men for the same reason that the wages of agricultural laborers are lower than those of mechanics in the large cities, and wages for the same kinds of labor in Moscow or Constantinople are lower than in Paris, London, or New York. In short, the wages of women are gov- erned by the same law as those of men, namely, the cost of living, and the only reason the wages of women are lower than those of men is because women cost less. Another fact, of which no theory of wages hitherto presented affords any satisfactory explanation, is the savings-bank deposits of wage-earners. Since these deposits to the extent that they are saved from wages represent a net-surplus above the necessary cost of living, they are usually taken as conclusive evidence of high wages. They are frequently treated as a kind of wage thermometer, the rate of wages or social condition of the laborers being regarded high or low as savings-bank deposits are large or small. The correctness of this conclusion is commonly accepted as self-evident, and it is frequently cited as a conclusive proof of the wisdom of an existing or proposed industrial or political policy. The last presidential election in this country (1888) may be cited as an example of this. In order to show the striking contrast between the wages and social conditions of the laborers in this country and England, one of our most popular statesmen cited the fact that the savings-bank deposits in Massachusetts, with 2,000,000 population, are nearly two thirds as much as those of 1 For the further discussion of this point and the facts relating to the wages and the cost of living of women, the reader is referred to " Wealth and Prog- ress," pp. 172-178. 14 2IO SAVINGS NO CRITERION OF IV AGES. Great Britain with a population of 38,000,000, or over eleven times as much per capita of the population. This statement was accepted as showing the difference in the wages and material prosperity of the laborers in the two countries. A more mis- leading statement it would be difficult to imagine, as a little exam- ination of the subject will conclusively show. Although the economic and social conditions of the American laborer are decidedly superior to those of his English brother, this fact cannot be established by savings-bank statistics. Nor is the difference between the wages in the two countries any- where near so great as the difference in the amount of savings- bank deposits would indicate. If we compare the savings- bank deposits of the different States in this country the utter worthlessness of such data, for showing the difference in the rate of wages, will at once be apparent. According to the official savings-bank statistics in 1887, the deposits per capita of the population were : in Rhode Island, $169.41; in Massachusetts, $147.30 ; in Connecticut, $147.18; in New Hampshire, $125.52 ; in New York, $89.05 ; while in Pennsylvania they were only $10.81 per capita. In Ohio they were $4.32, in Minnesota $2.17, and in Wisconsin only .02 cents, and in a large number of the Western States there are no savings-banks at all. Now, if there is any virtue in savings- bank statistics as indicating the rate of wages and the industrial condition of the community, the laborers in New York State are only a little over half as well off as those in Rhode Island, and less than two thirds as well off as those in Massachusetts, Con- necticut, or New Hampshire, while in Pennsylvania the condition of the laborer would only be about one sixteenth as good as it is in Rhode Island. According to this notion the laborers of Italy are as well off as those in Pennsylvania, and vastly better than those of Ohio, Il- linois, Minnesota, Wisconsin, or any of the Middle and Western States, except California. A theory by which $4.32 per capita in Ohio, $2.17 in Minnesota, .02 cents in Wisconsin, and other Western States, as compared with $169.41 per capita in Rhode Island, are taken to represent the wages and social condition of the laboring classes in those States, bears upon its face the evi- dence of its own absurdity. Why the laborers of Rhode Island, THE SOURCE OF SAVINGS. 211 Massachusetts, Connecticut, and New Hampshire should be able to save a third more per capita than those in New York, 1 fourteen times as much as those of Pennsylvania, thirty-four times as much as those of Ohio, sixty-eight times as much as those in Minnesota, and several hundred times as much as those in Wisconsin and other States, is a complete enigma from the standpoint of any of the popular theories of wages, yet they are phenomena which a scientific law of wages is bound to explain. In the light of the theory here presented, however, these facts assume an entirely normal role and become perfectly explainable. In the first place, the laborers' savings-bank deposits, like the accumulations of any other class, are entirely of the nature of a surplus, 2 and therefore, like rents and profits, are governed by the law of surplusage. It will be observed that the surplus, which alone makes savings-bank deposits possible, is simply the differ- ence between the cost of living of the most expensive families of any given class or industry and those who, for whatever reason, live upon less. Thus wages may be very high, and still the pos- sible surplus be very small, and vice versa. For example, if wages in a given class or industry were $3.00 a day, and the established standard of living in that class was substantially uniform, the possibility of saving would be very slight, because the cost of living of each family would be practi- cally equal to, and hence consume, the entire wages. Under those conditions savings would be impossible, except to unmar- ried persons or those whose families were smaller than the largest, which at best would afford but a small amount of surplus for the class in general. Moreover, the possibility of savings from that cause would exist in any class, whatever the rate of wages. On the other hand, suppose that in a given industry the general rate of wages fixed by the dearest laborers is $1.50 a day, but instead of the standard of living being uniform throughout the class, it greatly varies through the difference in the social habits, as is actually the case in this country where American, English, Irish, French-Canadian, and Continental laborers are all employed in 1 Savings-bank deposits in Italy amount to $9.00 per capita of the popula- tion. Cf. Political Science Quarterly, vol. iv., pp. 483, 493. 8 See diagram No. 2., p. 206. 212 AGRICULTURE UNFAVORABLE TO SAVINGS. the same industry. Many of these foreign laborers, through their simpler habits of life, will be able to live on one half or two thirds as much as the American or English laborer, and hence will be able to save the difference. With this variation in the cost of living to different persons at the same rate of wages, a much larger proportion of savings per capita will be possible than in the former case, where wages were one hundred per cent, higher. That is precisely what exists in this country, and particularly in the New England States and manufacturing centres. From this point of view there is no difficulty in understanding why savings- bank deposits per capita are much smaller in the Western than in the Eastern States. In the Western States agriculture is the chief occupation. It is well known that agricultural life is more nearly uniform than that of any other occupation. Being iso- lating in its influence, it affords the minimum incentive for n.ew wants and a variety of social demands. Consequently, whatever rate of wages prevails, savings will necessarily be very slight in agricultural communities, while they might be relatively large in manufacturing centres, even with the same rate of wages. Indeed the savings-bank deposits in Italy are derived from wages much smaller than those in our Western States, where no savings-banks exist. The same is true of the different States in this country. Wis- consin, where the savings are but two cents per capita, is more exclusively agricultural than Minnesota, where they are $2 ; and Ohio is more agricultural than Pennsylvania, 1 and Pennsylvania than New York. In New England however the reverse is true. In Rhode Island, Massachusetts, and Connecticut there is the minimum amount of agriculture and the maximum amount of manufacture. Consequently they have a greater concentration of population and variety of social life among their wage classes. In addition to this, they have the greatest number of different nationalities engaged in the same occupation, thus greatly in- creasing the differences in the standard of living while the same wage level prevails. If we turn to England we find a very different state of affairs. 1 For social purposes, mining and raw-material-producing industries may be regarded as agriculture, because they are similarly isolating and non-socializing occupations. WHY FOREIGN LABORERS CAN SAVE. 21$ There the population is highly homogeneous ; hence, in each class there is a greater uniformity of social habits and cost of living, and therefore less surplus from the same aggregate income that is to say, there are none of those arbitrary differences in the style of living in the same class occasioned by an influx of for- eigners as in this country. The differences in the standard of living there, in the main, are only such as arise from the differ- ence in the size of families and the passing from one social grade to another. From the causes already explained, 1 whenever laborers migrate from one industry or social grade to another, while they frequently represent the top or most expensive portion of the class they leave, they usually represent the bottom, or least expensive, of that into which they enter. Just as fast as they are transferred from a position where they are the dearest to one where they are the cheapest, they are changed from a wage-fixing to a surplus-receiving position. The savings-bank deposits will naturally therefore, be much smaller per capita in a homogeneous country like England than in a heterogeneous country like Amer- ica, even though the wages were the same in both countries. Savings are not due to the amount of the wages, but to dif- ferences in the cost of living in the class where the same rate of wages prevails. This explains why such a large proportion of the laborers in this country who have bank accounts which is so commonly re- garded as conclusive evidence of superior character, are foreigners. If the possession of a bank account, or the ownership of what is so patronizingly styled " a little home " often a mere shanty, is evidence of superior character, why did they not have them in their own country, where that " superior character " was de- veloped ? It may be replied that it is because wages there were too low to leave a margin above what would give them a bare living. Precisely so ; but why was there no margin in their own country ? Why is there no margin for the best class of Chinamen in China, of Germans in Germany, Englishmen in England, and Americans in America, while there is a margin in almost any country in Continental Europe for the Asiatic, in England for the Continental laborer, and in the United States for the laborers of every other country in the world ? The answer is obvious. There 1 Section ii., preceding chapter. 214 WHY HIGHEST PAID LABORERS STRIKE. is no margin from which the best class of laborers can save in their own country, simply because there the general rate of wages is determined by their own standard of living. They can get wages which will leave them a margin over the cost of living, only by going where the price of labor is determined by a social char- acter and standard of living higher than their own, or, if in their own country, by adopting a standard of living lower than the highest of the class to which they socially belong. The fact that the lower thus always obtain the advantage acquired by the higher is the economic incentive for all indus- trial mobility. It is only because the laborer can obtain the higher wages previously established in the new country or indus- try, that he will ever undertake to face the disadvantages of emigrating to a foreign land or endure the inconvenience of entering into a new occupation. This law also explains why, throughout the history of industrial progress, the most intelligent and socially advanced laborers always constitute the discon- tented element in their class, and are usually the leaders in labor organizations, strikes, and other forms of industrial agitation. It is because being the most expensive of their class they have no margins and therefore experience the greatest pressure from the non-satisfaction of new wants and desires. The effect of the earnings of women and children upon the wages of men is another fact which the prevailing theories of wages have entirely failed to explain. Extensive investigations have shown that in those industries where women and children contribute to the families' maintenance, the wages of the men tend to fall directly as the amount contributed by the women and children increases. 1 If it is simply a question of supply and demand, as is generally assumed, the competition of women and children for employment would tend to reduce the wages of all laborers ; because as laborers increase in one industry they would migrate to others, and thus the effect would be the general reduc- tion of the rate of wages. Such, however, is not the case. The effect is mainly upon the wages of the man in the class where the women who work are a part of the same household. Thus we find that in the same social grade and locality, in the trades where the man supports the whole family, his wages are fully as 1 For the facts upon this point see " Wealth and Progress," pp. 167 and 172. FATHER'S WAGES AND FAMILY'S INCREASE. 21$ high as those of the whole family where the wife and one or two children contribute to the family's support. A table will elsewhere be found ' constructed from the indi- vidual statements of wages and cost of living of three hundred and ninety-seven families employed in ten different industries in Massachusetts. These facts show that the total yearly income of the family in the highest class was $821.40, and cost of living $772.21, and in the lowest the total income was $682.05 and cost of living was $650.81. In the highest class where the women and children who work were only as one fourth of one to a family, the wages of the man were $752.36. In the lowest class where the women and children who work were as one and one third to a family, the man's wages were only $424.12. In other words, in those industries where the women and children con- tribute only $69 a year, the wages of the man were only $19 less than the total cost of the family's living, whereas in the indus- tries where the earnings of the women and children were $257 a year, the wages of the man were $226 less than the total cost of the family's living. It will thus be seen that while the difference between the total income of the family in the highest and lowest class was almost exactly the same as that in the total cost of the family's living, the difference in the highest and lowest yearly wages of the man was greater than that in the cost of living by almost exactly the amount of the difference in the earnings of the women and children. That is to say, while the total income of the family varied with the total cost of the family's living, the ratio of the man's wages to the cost of the family's living dimin- ished directly as the total earnings of the women and children increased. 2 Thus whether the income of the family is all de- rived from one source or from several sources, its total amount tends to equal the total cost of the family's living. Therefore, from whatever standpoint we study the move- ment of wage phenomena, we find that the general rate of wages in any country, class or industry, constantly tends to equal the " Wealth and Progress," 171. " Thus, it is seen that in neither of the cases where the head of the family is assisted by his wife or children, does he earn as much as other laborers. Also, that in the case where he is assisted by both wife and children, he earns the least." Report of the Bureau of the Statistics of Labor, Massachusetts, 1876, p. 71. 2l6 COST OF LIVING HOW AFFECTED. cost of living of the most expensive families furnishing the necessary supply of labor. The cost of living may be affected in two ways, either by a change in the price of the commodities which the laborer con- sumes or by a change in the quantities of those commodities which enter into his habitual consumption. An increase in the price of commodities would be a rise in the money cost of living, but not a rise in the standard of living ; hence, while it would increase the money wages, it would not increase the amount of wealth the laborer receives for a day's labor. It would therefore be a rise in nominal wages, but not a rise of real wages. 1 An increase in the cost of living, arising from an increase in the commodities habitually consumed by the laborer, would constitute a rise in the standard of living. It would increase the actual amount of wealth daily received by the laborer, and hence would be a rise of real wages. Thus a rise in the cost of living and nominal wages is of no social advantage to the laborer except when accompanied by a rise in the standard of living and of real wages. 3 It is therefore a rise in the actual social standard and not in the nominal money cost of living, which is of importance in con- sidering the question of wages. Indeed it is in the minimizing of the money cost and the maximizing of the social standard of living that industrial and social progress really consists. In other words, the condition of the laborer improves only as the price of commodities falls and the price of labor rises. The standard of living in any class or country depends upon the social character of the people. Social character is chiefly deter- mined by the number and variety of established social wants, and the consequent simplicity or complexity of social relations. 3 It may therefore be said that wages finally depend upon the social character of the laboring classes, the restriction or devel- opment of which is mainly determined by the extent and perma- nence of their social opportunities. When we learn to regard 1 " Wealth and Progress," pp. 96-98. 'This law is just as true in "piece-work" as it is in "day-work." See chapter on " Piece- Work," " Wealth and Progress," p. 179. 8 For an extended discussion of the relation of social wants and character to the standard of living, see " Wealth and Progress," Part II., chap, ix., pp. 187-203. REMED Y FOR LOW WAGES. 2 1 J wages simply as the price of labor which is governed by the laborer's standard of living, we shall see that the laborer is not poor because the capitalist is rich, but that wages are low because the laborer is socially cheap. The true remedy for low wages : therefore is not to be sought in profit-sharing, nationalization of land and productive instruments, or in any other schemes for restricting the economic opportunities of the capitalist, but solely in conditions for extending the social opportunities of the laborer. CHAPTER IV. RENT, ITS LAW AND CAUSE. SECTION I. The Definition of Rent. THE definition of rent generally accepted by economists is that given by Ricardo, 1 namely, " that rent is that portion of the prod- uce, of the earth which is paid to the landlord for the use of the original and indestructible powers of the soil." 2 It is manifest that if rent is limited to what is paid for " the powers of the soil," or infertility of the land, then what is paid for land used for building, manufacturing, and commercial pur- poses is not rent at all, since the price paid for such land is entirely independent of the quality of its soil. Moreover, the rent paid for some of the most sterile land for building purposes is greater than that paid for the most fertile land in the world. A definition of rent that does not apply to land which pays the highest rent of all, and which is increasing as civilization advances, musi- surely be regarded as defective. Nor is this definition materially improved by Mr. Walker's qualification that the expression " original and indestructible powers of the soil " includes "not only arable land, but pasture and timber land, mineral deposits, water privileges, and building sites." 3 While in this case it includes all that is paid for the "original and indestructible powers " of any kind of land, it fails as a defini- tion of rent, because as we shall see rent is never paid for " the original and indestructible powers " of any land. It is true that some agricultural land has a high degree of original fertility, but there is no land whose fertility is inde- 1 " Political Economy and Taxation," pp. 34-36. "Walker's "Political Economy," p. 193. Also, McCulloch's "Political Economy," p. 142. * " Political Economy," p. 193. 3X8 RENT IS ECONOMIC SURPLUS. 2 19 structible. Every intelligent farmer knows that continuous cultivation without fertilization will impoverish or destroy the fertility of the most productive land ever known. The fertility of land is not only always destructible, as in the case of mines, but it is frequently not original ; indeed much of the most productive agricultural land in the world to-day owes its fertility not to its " original powers," but almost entirely to improvements created by the application of labor and capital. And the greater part of the land whose fertility is thus created commands a higher rent than much of that which possesses the greatest amount of " original fertility." ' In the case of land for building purposes alone, the so-called "powers of the soil," or qualities of the land for which rent is paid, are neither original nor indestructible. Indeed it does not depend upon any quality whatever peculiar to land. On the contrary, rent is entirely due to the presence of a highly civilized industrial community. If New York City were removed a hundred miles from Manhattan Island, the rent of the greater part of the land, some of which is the highest paid for any land in the world, would entirely disappear. Clearly therefore, if rent is limited to that " which is paid to the landlord for the use of the original and indestructible powers of the soil," almost none of the income from land is rent, since a very small portion of such income is paid for its " original " and none at all for its " indestructible powers." The chief difficulty with this definition is that it fails to dis- tinguish between price and surplus. Rent is not the price of land ; it is only the economic surplus arising from its use. In order to avoid confusion I define rent as the net surplus resulting from the productive use of land under all economic conditions for any purpose whatsoever. To explain how this surplus arises is to furnish the law of rent. SECTION II. The Law of Rent. Rent being an economic surplus, in seeking the law of rent we are simply seeking the law of surplus in relation to the produc- 1 Witness the high rents paid for the land used for market-gardening and the highly cultivated farms in such countries as Belgium and England, whose fer- tility is largely artificial, and the low rent paid for the most fertile land in our Western States, whose productiveness is largely original. 220 ECONOMIC PRODUCTION OF LAND. tive use of land. And as surplus is included in and 'received with the price, it being the difference between price and cost, it follows that the law of surplus is a necessary corollary of the law of price. In order, therefore, to ascertain the law of rent, we have only to apply to land the general law of prices presented in a previous chapter l namely, that in a given market prices tend towards uniformity on the basis of the cost of producing the most expensive portion. It is objected by some that since land is the " free bounty of nature " it can have no cost of production. This is a mistake. It should be remembered that economic pro- duction does not mean physical creation but only economic and social adaptation. This may involve a great deal of physical modification both in form and location, or it may involve little or none of either. The production of broadcloth or a gold watch involves a great deal of physical change in the wool and in the gold, steel, and other metals of which the cloth and watch are made, whereas the production of nuts and bananas involves very little. The more nearly complete is an object furnished by nature the less will be the cost involved .jn appropriating it to human uses, and vice versa. The cost of producing a power-loom includes all the expenditure necessary to complete it as an instrument for weav- ing. This of course does not mean the creation of the iron or wood of which the loom is made, but only their adaptation to productive purposes. It is in this sense that we speak of the cost of producing land, the term production having not a physical but only an economic signification. For economic purposes therefore, the cost of producing land, like that of any other productive instrument, includes all the expenditure neces- sary to utilize it as a means of production. The law of price in relation to land, therefore, may be stated thus : That under conditions of economic freedom, the price of land in any given community tends to equal the cost of its produc- tion i.e., the cost of actualizing its economic and social utility. Hence when the cost per unit of using all the land is the same, the price and the cost of production (economic use) will be identi- cal, and no surplus or rent will remain. And whenever the cost per unit of using different portions of land varies, the price per 1 Part II., chapter iii. THE LAW OF RENT. 221 unit will tend to a uniformity on the basis of the cost of actual- izing the utility of the most expensive portion of the land used for that purpose in that community. Thus while the price per unit of the whole land in that community tends to a uniformity, that of the portion whose utility costs the most to actualize it will consist entirely of cost, and that of the others will consist of cost and rent (surplus), the rent increasing as the cost of utiliza- tion diminishes below that of the most expensive portion used. Having found the law of prices in relation to land, we have as a necessary corollary the law of surplus i.e., the law of rent. It may be stated as follows : That under conditions of economic freedom, the rent of land used for any purpose tends to equal the difference between its productive utility and that of the poorest land used for the same purpose in that community, or which con- tributes to the necessary supply of the same market. It will be observed that the conclusion here reached is sub- stantially the same as that of Ricardo, stripped of many mislead- ing assumptions by which the Ricardian theory has ever been accompanied. In the first place, by treating rent as the net surplus resulting from the productive use of land, we entirely avoid the error in- volved in the Ricardian definition of rent as the price paid for " the original and indestructible powers of the soil." And by re- garding land simply as a productive instrument, thereby putting it in the same economic category with other forms of capital, we remove all grounds for the perplexing controversy as to whether the income from improvements in land is properly rent or profits. Since rent and profits are both economic surpluses, whether or not they are designated by the same term is a matter of entire indifference. We also avoid the confusing consequences of that erroneous assumption of Ricardo, that land is always utilized in the order of its fertility, the best being taken first and the poorest last, an assumption which Carey devoted tedious space to exposing, and which Walker and other Ricardians are still laboring to defend. From the point of view here presented, it is absolutely of no importance whether the land is cultivated in the order claimed by Ricardo or that claimed by Carey, the law will operate the same in either case. If the inferior land were used before the 222 RENT GOVERNED BY LAW OF SURPLUS. superior, as is frequently the case, the only difference would be this :. instead of the land employed last being used at cost, and that employed first yielding rent, as Ricardo assumed, the order would be reversed and the land employed first would be used at cost, and that employed last would yield a rent. Neither the amount of land used nor the amount of rent paid would be affected by that change. The difference in the productive utility of the land will be rent just the same, whether the inferior or su- perior is brought first into use. It is not the historical order of their use, but the difference in the degree of their productive utility, that determines the amount of the rent. The difference in the fertility of two pieces of land yielding twenty and twenty- five bushels of wheat respectively will obviously be just as great whichever is brought into use first. If the subject had been treated from the point of view here presented, these errors would have been avoided. It would then have been obvious that the order of use of superior and inferior land has no necessary relation whatever to the price-fixing or sur- plus-producing influence of either labor, land, or machinery. For in all cases and under all conditions where economic freedom prevails, the price is determined by the cost of using the least effective, and therefore the most expensive increment, and whether that be first or last makes absolutely no difference. By this treatment of the subject, we not only avoid the error and re- tain what is true in the popular theory, but we have a consistent classification of economic phenomena, by which the price of land commodities and labor is governed by the law of price, and on the other hand, the rent of land, the profit of capital, and the sav- ings of labor are governed by the law of surplus. SECTION. III. The Cause of Rent. No theory can be regarded as furnishing an adequate explana- tion of rent phenomena which does not explain the cause of rent. When we know how rent comes into existence, and by what social force it becomes economically possible, we shall be able to determine whether it arises from an economic necessity and is a social advantage, or whether it is due to economic despotism and is a social burden, as is commonly believed. Upon this point the popular doctrine is perhaps least of all satisfactory. Francis WALKER'S EXPLANATION OF RENT. 22$ Walker, who has probably taken more pains than any other writer to make good the deficiencies in the Ricardian theory of rent, endeavors to show that the difference in the productiveness of land is not only the measure and regulator of rent, but that it is also the cause or source of rent. He has endeavored to illus- trate exactly how, under the influence of self-interest, rent arises. 1 Like Ricardo, he begins by assuming the existence of a new country with four grades of land, which will yield, with the same expenditure of labor and capital, 24, 22, 20, and 18 bushels of wheat per acre respectively. He also, like Ricardo, assumes that the best land, or 24-bushel tract, will be cultivated first, and the others in the order of their fertility, and says : " Cultivation then descending to the 22-bushel tract, rent emerges. Under what im- pulse ? Why, by the simple operation of the principle of self- interest ; inasmuch as some of the would-be cultivators must go upon the 22-bushel tract, every person now in the occupation of a lot on the 24-bushel tract may just as well may he not ? pay something for the privilege of remaining where he is, as take up a lot of the new land for nothing ? If not, why not ? How much shall he pay ? Why, clearly, 2 bushels per acre, the difference between the yield of the two tracts under the same application of labor and capital." " This continues until the whole four tracts are brought under cultivation, rent rising 2 bushels per acre on each tract under cultivation, when the next is brought into use, and the rent on the different tracts is 2,' 4, and 6 bushels per acre respectively. Then further " to illustrate the operation of this cause " he assumes the existence of a distant tract of land that will yield with the same labor and capital 30 bushels per acre. But through its greater distance from the market 12 bushels are consumed in transportation, reducing the amount de- livered to the market to 18 bushels, or the same as the product of the poorest home tract. He then, by a series of improvements in the methods of transportation, reduces the cost of bringing the crop of the distant tract to market from 12 to 9 bushels per acre, and says : " The net produce of the distant tract (30 9) has now risen to 21 bushels. The 2o-bushel tract must be abandoned. . . . The highest grade of land now yields a rent of but 3 bushels an acre (24 21), the second of but i bushel. The aggre- 1 " Land and its Rent," pp. 10, 57. ' Ibid., p. 18. 224 FERTILITY NOT CAUSE OF RENT. gate amount received by the owners of land in rents sinks from 9 to 4." ' It will be observed that at the commencement of Mr. Walker's community we found the best land producing 24 bushels per acre and paying no rent ; then the same land, without any increase in its productiveness, pays a rent first of 2 bushels, then of 4 bushels, and finally of 6 bushels an acre. And then after the discovery of the 3o-bushel tract, without any diminution in its productiveness, the rent of the same tract falls from 6 to 3 bushels per acre. That of the 22-bushel tract falls to i bushel and that of the 2o-bushel tract disappears altogether. The question here is " under what impulse " does the rent of this land rise and fall without any change in its productiveness ? What new force came into operation to make the tract of land, which formerly could be had for nothing, yield a rent of 6 bushels and subsequently fall to 3 bushels per acre ? "Why," replies Mr. Walker, " by the simple operation of the principle of self-interest." By what course of reasoning can it be shown that the principle of self-interest in the land owner will always prevail against the self-interest of the tenant ? Again, if rent is caused by the fertility of the land or the self- interest of the land owner, or both, why did it not emerge when cultivation first began on the 24-bushel tract ? This was impos- sible, Mr. Walker would reply, because it was not until " cultiva- tion descended to the 22-bushel tract " that "rent emerges." If rent was impossible on the 24-bushel tract until the 22-bushel tract was cultivated, whatever power forced the 22-bushel tract into use, or made its cultivation possible, is manifestly the real cause of rent on the 24-bushel tract. This could not possibly be the fertility of the land or the principle of self-interest in the landowner, as these were just the same before as after rent was paid; Nor does Mr. Walker's distant-tract illustration throw any real light upon this question. It is true that rent on the home tracts falls when the distant tract is cultivated, but from what cause ? Mr. Walker replies, because " the net produce of the distant tract has now risen to 21 bushels." Nothing of the kind. So far as Mr. Walker, has shown, no change whatever has taken place in the 1 " Land and its Rent," p. 25. ORIGIN OF RENT SOCIAL. 22$ ! productiveness of the land. When we first saw the distant tract it produced 30 bushels per acre ; it does the same now. The only change that has occurred is a reduction of 3 bushels per acre in the cost of transporting the crop. Manifestly that is not due to any quality or condition of the land nor to the degree of self-interest in the landowner. These are entirely unchanged. It may with truth be said that cheapening transportation reduces the cost of producing the wheat, but it in no way changes the in- fluences of this land upon the cost of the wheat. The cost of the wheat has been reduced by the use of capital, but it is by a class of capital quite distinct from land. Mr. Walker has shown that rent began on the 24-bushel tract when " cultivation descended to the 22-bushel tract," and also that rent on all the home tracts fell when the cost of transporting the crop of the distant tract was reduced. But this does not explain the cause which brought all this about. To say that rent rises when inferior lands are cultivated and falls when transportation is cheapened, is only like saying the train moves when the engine starts. But what starts the engine remains to be ascertained before the cause of this movement is explained. In stopping at this point Mr. Walker repeats one of the chief mistakes of orthodox economists namely, the failure to connect economic phenomena with the social influences from which they arise. 1 What is the cause of rent is therefore still the question. Nor will the answer be very difficult to find if we pursue the inquiry along the lines already travelled and bear in mind the conclusions reached in the preceding section ; namely, that land like all other forms of capital is simply a productive instrument, and that rent is a net surplus resulting from its economic use. Since an economic surplus is the difference between the price of products and the cost of their production, rent can only be obtained from the price of the commodities in the production of which it is used as an instrument. Clearly therefore, it is to the influences which govern the price of the products that we must look for the cause of rent. Let us return to Mr. Walker's community and see if we can ascertain the cause that made the existence of rent possible, which he failed to explain. 1 This limitation in regard to the use of improved machinery has already been pointed out. See pp. 143-149. 15 226 RELATION BETWEEN PRICES AND RENT. In the first place why did not the 24-bushel tract pay a rent when first cultivated ? It was not because of its inferiority, since it was the best land in the community ; nor was it from any lack of self-interest in the landowner, for there never was a time when he would not exact rent if he could. The reason no rent could be obtained for it was that, there being only one grade of land in use, the cost of production, so far as it affected land, was uni- form. Hence according to the law of price already stated, the value of every part of the product was only equal to the cost of its production. Since the price of the wheat equalled the cost of production on the 24-bushel tract, in order to cultivate the 22- bushel tract without loss one of two things must necessarily occur either the price of the product must rise, or the cost of production must be reduced. We will consider first, how a rise in the price of the produce would affect the situation, since the expounders of the popular doctrine always assume that this takes place. It is insisted upon by these writers that rent does not increase the price of commod- ities to the consumer, because the rent is the effect of the price and not the price the effect of the rent. 1 But if it is true that rent can only be paid or, if already paid, can only be increased by a rise in the price of the produce, and that the rise in price is 1 " It is because its (the produce) price is high or low, a great deal more, or very little more, or no more than what is sufficient to pay these wages and profits, that it affords a high rent, a low rent, or no rent at all." Adam Smith, " Wealth of Nations," book i., chapter i., p. 115. " Corn is not high because a rent is paid, but a rent is paid because corn is high." Ricardo, "Political Economy and Taxation," p. 39. See also ibid., pp. 40, 61, 62. " The in- habitants must consent to pay such an additional price for raw produce as will enable the second quality of land to be cultivated. No advance short of this will procure them another bushel of corn. ... If they choose to pay a price sufficient to cover the expense of cultivating the land of the second quality they will obtain additional supplies, if they do not, they must want them." McCul- loch, "Principles Political Economy," p. 142. "Rent is the effect of high price. . . . It is not from the produce, but from the price at which the prod- uce is sold, that rent is derived." Buchannan, note, p. 40, Ricardo's works. " It is not the diversity of soils nor the law of diminishing returns, that causes rents, since these continue as before when rent ceases to be paid, but it is the price of produce under demand and supply that causes rent." Perry, " Political Economy," p. 292. " The rent of land is determined by the value of its prod- uce." Wade, " Political Economy," p. 101. ECONOMIC BASIS OF RENT. 22/ paid to the landowner in rent, it is little more than a quibble to say that the payment of rent does not increase the price of commodities. Whether rent is the cause or effect of rise in price, is of very little importance to the community if every rise in rent is accompanied by a rise in the price. If for example, it cost a dollar a bushel to raise wheat on the 24-bushel tract, it would, under the same conditions, cost a dollar and ten cents a bushel to produce it on the 22-bushel tract. If the wheat could all be sold at that price, it would of course yield a surplus of ten cents a bushel, or two bushels an acre on the 24 bushel tract. Were this the only effect it would be a simple matter, but there are other influences to be reckoned with. A rise in prices would be a practical fall in wages ; hence every extension of cultivation to poorer soils which increased the rent of the landowner would increase the poverty of the laborer. Were such the case, the con- dition of the masses would indeed be hopeless. Henry George's pessimistic declaration that " rent swallows up the whole gain and pauperism accompanies progress " would be literally true. Fortunately for civilization however, the testimony of history is all against such a notion. Rents have never increased so much as during the present century, and the general fall in prices was never so great as during the same period. Nor is it possible that it should be otherwise, except in a state of political despotism or industrial piracy. Under conditions of economic freedom, it is as impossible for rent to rise through increasing prices and reducing real wages, as it is for civilization to advance by increasing poverty. Economic law presents an ab- solute barrier to any such parasitic movement by which a surplus- rgceiving class can be permanently enriched by the impoverish- ment of the community. For the same reason that the landowner cannot obtain rent except when the land yields a margin above the cost of production, the cultivator cannot sell his produce at a price higher than the consumers can afford to pay. Clearly therefore, the product cannot be sold at a higher price unless the purchasing power of the masses is commensurately increased. A general increase of prices without a rise of wages would not only defeat itself by destroying the market for the products, but it would necessarily lower the standard of living and actually put back civilization. If a rise of prices is accompanied by a com- 228 EFFECT OF POPULATION ON PRICES. mensurate rise of wages, as it admittedly must be, 1 it would in- crease the cost of cultivating the land as much as it increased the price of the crop, making the cultivation of the 2 2 -bushel tract as impracticable as ever. Nor would a mere increase of population change the result. If population should increase and the consumption or effectual demand per capita of the community (real wages) remain sta- tionary, prices could not advance except with the same conse- quences as before. The mere fact presented by Mr. Walker, that the 24-bushel tract is " inadequate to the needs of subsistence," is not sufficient to insure the cultivation of the inferior tract. The community may lack subsistence, people may die of starva- tion, as they often have ; but nobody will cultivate the 2 2 -bushel tract unless its products can be sold at a price at least equal to the cost. It may be said that if the population increases, the aggregate income and purchasing power of the community would be in- creased, though wages were stationary. This is true, but since in that case the number among whom the purchasing power is divided would be increased in the same ratio, no one would be richer than before, and consequently, the purchasing power of the individual members of the community would not be increased. A mere increase of the population, other things remaining the same, would enable a larger amount to be consumed at the same price, but it would not increase the capacity of anybody to pay a higher price. If an article of food, clothing, or the like, cannot be produced for less than 25 cents, and at the prevailing rate of wages the laborer can only pay 20 cents, it is clearly out of his power 4o 1 " As the wages of labor are everywhere regulated partly by the demand for it, and partly by the average price of the necessary articles of subsistence, what- ever raises this average price must necessarily raise those wages." Adam Smith, "Wealth of Nations," book v., chapter ii., p. 691. Ibid., p. 693. " With a rise in the price of food and necessaries the natural price of labor will rise." Ricar- do, " Political Economy and Taxation," p. 50. " There can be no permanent fall of wages, but in consequence of a fall (in the price) of the necessaries on which wages are expended." Ibid., p. 75. " If they (the laborers) had to pay 8s. per quarter in addition for wheat . . . wages would inevitably and necessarily rise." Ibid., p. 93. Cf. Mill's " Political Economy," vol. ii., pp. 423, 424, 425. EFFECT OF IMPROVED METHODS. 229 consume it. Nor would any conceivable addition to the number of ao-cent purchasers add one whit to their capacity for pur- chasing 25-cent articles. The consumption and production of 25-cent articles can never be promoted by increasing the number of 2o-cent consumers. Nothing can make the produc- tion of 25-cent articles possible but the creation of 25-cent purchasers. Manifestly, therefore, other things remaining the same, it is impossible in any general sense to extend cultiva- tion to inferior land by merely increasing the price of com- modities. Since the use of the 22-bushel tract cannot be made feasible by advancing prices, the only means by which it can be made feasible is by reducing the cost of production. There are only two ways by which the cost of production can be lessened, either by a reduction of wages or the use of improved methods. 1 The former is impossible for the same reason that prices could not be advanced. The latter, therefore, is the only alternative consistent with a progressive state of society. What form im- proved methods will take depends upon the state of civilization. In a very early stage of society it might consist of substituting a spade for a crooked stick, or at a later period a plough for a spade, or mowing and threshing machines for the scythe and flail. At whatever period it occurs or whatever form it takes, since it cannot cheapen, it must save labor. This does not mean that it must merely discharge labor for, as already explained, labor is only economically saved when it is re-employed. Thus in the case of land, as in every other phase of economic move- ment, the successful use of improved methods of production must necessarily be accompanied by new employment-creating conditions. Nothing can create new employments except new demands, or an increase in the consumption of wealth per capita of the population, which of course means an increase in real wages. When by this means inferior land can be cultivated 1 Improved methods include every thing that makes the same land yield more or yield the same amount at a less cost. This may result from superior skill, better division of labor, more capital in the form of fertilization, better drainage, the substitution of animals for men, or steam for animals, improved implements for either, or any other labor-saving or cost-reducing appliances. 230 RENT FOLLOWS MOVEMENT OF WAGES. without loss, the superior land can be cultivated at a profit ; that is to say, when the price of 22 bushels of wheat will defray the cost of cultivating an acre of the 22-bushel tract, the 24-bushel tract will yield a surplus or rent equal to ten cents a bushel or two bushels per acre, without either increasing the price of the product or reducing wages. In the last analysis therefore, the' determining cause of the use of inferior land and the payment of rent on the superior land is the increased con- sumption of wealth by the masses. If we examine the cultivation of Mr. Walker's 3o-bushel tract we shall find that its use finally depends upon the same cause. He explains how what he calls its " net productiveness " rose from 1 8 to 22 bushels per acre, by improved methods of trans- portation. The moment we ask what made improved methods of transportation possible, the answer is simple and obvious. The railroads and steamships which enabled the lands of Dakota to contribute to the wheat supply of Liverpool and London were clearly due to the increased consumption of wealth per capita of the population, which made the construction and use of railroads economically feasible. Nor could this result from a mere in- creased consumption of wheat, but it required a vast increase in the demand for numerous manufactured articles whose produc- tion and consumption involved a large amount of travel and transportation. An increased demand for commodities and a higher social standard of living, which makes steamships and railroads possible, are simply the economic embodiments of higher wages. Thus whether land is cultivated in the order of the best first, and the poorest last, as represented by Mr. Walker's four tracts, or the reverse, as claimed by Carey, the result is the same, namely, that rent or a surplus from the use of land, like that of all other productive instruments, finally depends upon the increasing consumption of wealth per capita of the community. In other words, the cause from which economic rent arises is tilt- advancing standard of living and the rise of real wages among the masses. SECTION IV. Is Rent a Social Tax ? Were it not commonly believed that rent is an unjust burden upon the community, the abolition of which warrants the subver- TRUE NATURE OF RENT. 231 sion of existing institutions, the consideration of this question might properly seem superfluous. The claim that rent is a tax by which the land-owning class are enabled to live at the expense of the industrious community, legitimately arises from the Ricar- dian postulate that " rent is that portion of the produce of the earth which is paid to the landowner for the use of the original and indestructible powers of the soil." No more fallacious notion was ever taught than that rent, or any other economic surplus, is a price paid for the free contribution of nature. There is no economic law by which a charge can ever be exacted for the use of gratuitous natural forces. 1 This view is further supported by the no less popular doctrine that, in the economic order of dis- tribution, rent is paid before wages, and that consequently the laborer can only receive as his share of the product what is left after rent and profits are taken out. 2 The utter untenableness of both these positions having been already pointed out, the answer to the question " is rent a social tax ? " need not detain us long. Like all other forms of surplus, rent arises from the sure operation of the law of economic prices ; being simply the difference between the maximum and the minimum cost of pro- duction per unit of product. If this difference in the cost is due to the difference in the methods, such as a better division of labor, higher skill, more capital, better machinery, etc., the surplus created will go to the entrepreneur and in common phrase will be called profits. And if the difference in the cost of production is due to the different degrees of productive utility of the land, the surplus created will go to the landowner as rent. If the poorest instruments and the poorest lands are used together no surplus can arise for either the landowner or entrepreneur. But if superior instruments are used with inferior land, the entrepreneur may have a surplus without the landowner having rent, and conversely, if the superior land is operated with inferior instruments, the landowner may obtain a rent, while the entrepreneur can have no profit. Thus there can 1 Part II., chap, iv., pp. 21, 22. a Jevons' "Theory of Political Economy," p. 292. Walker's "Political Economy," pp. 248, 249. Sidgwick's "Principles of Political Economy," p. 322. Henry George's "Progress and Poverty," pp. 162, 163. 232 MACHINERY AND LAND. neither be rents nor profits unless the joint use of the land and implements produce at less than maximum cost, and the surplus if any, will be divided between the owners of these two classes of productive instruments or all accrue to either one, just in pro- portion as it is due to the superiority of the land or of the instruments. There is this difference, however, between land and other pro- ductive instruments : the different qualities of machinery always come into use in the order of the poorest first and the best last, whereas in the case of land, sometimes the best comes into use first. The reason for this is that, machinery being a human in- vention, each new device is the result of an effort to improve upon the last ; its superiority over existing methods being the only reason for using it, and the only motive for making it. On the other hand, land being a natural product whose quantity and locality are unchangeable, the use of the poorer or less productive land can only be made feasible by the employment of superior appliances. Thus, while it is always the best land and the best machinery which yields a surplus, in the case of land when the best is used first (as in the Ricardo-Walker assumption) it does not yield a surplus until the second grade comes into use, whereas in the case of machinery the surplus always commences on the best which is last when its own use becomes possible. But whether the use of land descends from the superior to the inferior through the use of capital in better drainage, improved tools, machinery, etc., or whether it ascends from the inferior to the superior through improved methods of transportation (as in the case of Walker's distant tract), makes no difference either in the amount of rent paid or the effect of rent upon wages and the welfare of the community. In whatever order improvements are applied to the use of land and a surplus is created, the rent will always depend upon the difference between the cost per unit of the product due to using the best land and that of using the poorest land employed for that purpose within the same competing group or community. Since rent can only be obtained from a surplus that remains after all costs of production are paid, and since wages are governed by social causes independent of the quality of land or machinery, and prices are determined by the cost of producing the most ex- RELATION OF RENT TO WAGES. 233 pensive portion of the supply which always includes wages, it follows that rent can only be obtained when a surplus remains after wages and prices have been determined. The economic re- lation of rent to wages and prices is illustrated in the following diagram, which represents Mr. Walker's four tracts producing 24, 22, 20, and 18 bushels per acre respectively, the assumption being that with wages at $1.50 per day the cost of production on the 18- bushel tract is a dollar a bushel. No. 3. RENT PER ACRE. SURPLUS PER BUSHEL. PRICE PER BUSHEL. WAGES PER DAY. COST PER BUSHEL. BUSHELS PER ACRE. $6.00 25 c. 18 c $1.00 Si oo $1.50 $T en Minimum cost, 75 c. 82 24 C. 22 $2 OO IO C $1 OO $1 50 . go c. 20 $O.OO OO C. $1.00 $I. 5 Maximum cost . *T~i-\/T r8 . JpI.OO 10 D From the above, four things will be seen : (i) That A, who uses the poorest land and pays no rent, sells at cost and has no surplus. (2) That, the price of wheat being the same with all, B, C, and D, whose land yields 2, 4, and 6 bushels per acre respec- tively more than that of A, have a surplus of $2, $4, and $6 per acre. (3) That the surplus in the rent column on the left only begins and increases as the cost line per bushel on the right re- cedes from (falls below) that of A. (4) That the increase of the amount in the rent column in no way affects the price or wages column ; D, whose rent is the highest, sells at the same price and pays the same wages * as A, who pays no rent at all." Since the consumer's price and the laborer's wages are both de- termined at the point where no rent is paid, it is manifest that 1 As a matter of fact the large concerns in both manufacture and farming represented by D, where the largest capital and best methods are used, are con- stantly tending to pay higher wages and sell at lower prices than small farmers or manufacturers represented by A. 2 If we assumed the four tracts of land to be of uniform quality and suppose the difference in the product to arise from superior skill, larger capital, better implements, etc., the result would be exactly the same, only the surplus column instead of representing rent would represent profits as shown in diagram No. i, p. 204. 234 HIGH WAGES CAUSE HIGH RENT. the surplus paid to the landlord is in no sense a burden upon either the consumer or the laborer ; that is to say, prices are not higher nor wages lower because rent is paid. Indeed, if rent were obtained at the expense of the consumer or the laborer, we should find that prices rise and wages fall as rents increase, whereas the reverse is universally true. The highest rents are paid in the most civilized countries, and in such countries rent is higher in the city than in the small town or rural district. And it is precisely in these countries and cities where rents are the largest, that wages are the highest, and gen- eral prices are the lowest. 1 Consequently we find the migratory movement of the laborers (which is always towards higher wages and better living) is constantly from low-rent countries to high- rent countries, from the rural districts where the rent is low to the cities where rent is high. This also explains why commodi- ties can often be obtained more cheaply in large cities than in small towns, as shown by the fact that thousands of people travel from fifty to a hundred miles to a city to make their purchases. This does not mean that things are cheaper or wages higher because a rent is paid, but that things are cheaper and rents are larger because wages are higher there than elsewhere. Nor is there any means, except charity or theft, by which the amount in the rent column can possibly be made to find its way to the laborer or consumer. The only economic way it can be given to the consumer is to compel B, C, and D to reduce the price of their product the full amount of their surplus 10, 18, and 25 cents per bushel respectively. Should D sell his wheat at 75 cents a bushel, nobody would continue to buy from C, B, and A, unless they sold theirs at the same price, which they could not do, since it cost them more than that amount. If the product of C is needed, 82 cents a bushel is the lowest price at which it can be supplied ; and if that of B is required, the price cannot fall below 90 cents a bushel ; land so long as that of A is needed, the price must be a dollar a bushel, because less than that will not repay the cost of producing it. No matter how the price is fixed or who fixes it, it cannot possibly be less than equal to the cost of producing the most expensive portion. 1 That is to say, the price of a day's labor will purchase the largest amount of wealth. EFFECT OF ABOLISHING RENT. 235 If the surplus is to be given to the laborer in any other way than by reducing the price, it must go in the form of in- creased wages. In order to do this wages must rise directly as the surplus increases. The same difficulty arises here as in the case of prices ; indeed, wages are simply the price of labor. If D pays higher wages, then the laborers of C, B, and A will refuse to work unless they can have the same. If A is compelled to raise wages equal to 25 cents a bushel, the cost and hence the minimum price of his product will necessarily rise to $1.25 a bushel, which will then be the price of the whole product. Thus, all that D, C, and B are by this means forced to give to the laborer in higher wages, A is forced to demand back again from the consumer in higher prices, and the difference or surplus will be exactly as before, the only change being that both wages and prices have risen 25 cents. In short, there are no economic means by which A can obtain an equivalent of the cost of his product which will not give B, C, and D a surplus ; and con- versely, there are no means by which D can sell at cost which will not bankrupt C, B, and A. There are two conditions which, under economic freedom, all competing producers must fulfil or leave the business : other things being the same, they must pay the same wages and sell their products at the same price as their competitors in the same market. For the same reason that D's price cannot be reduced without lowering that of C, B, and A, the wages paid by A cannot be reduced without lowering those paid by all the others, since whatever will enable A to either raise the price or reduce wages will enable B, C, and D to do the same. Manifestly therefore, if the landowner were prohibited from taking the surplus of B, C, and D in the form of rent, it would simply remain in the hands of the farmer or entrepreneur as profits. Since the surplus is not increased by virtue of its being divided between the landowner and entrepreneur, it could not be diminished by giving it all to either one of them. In other words, as the surplus arising from the difference in the cost of producing with the poorest and the best land would be the same whether rent is paid or not, the abolition of rent would simply be an increase of profits. Rent, in short, is entirely a question between the landowner and the entrepreneur and does not enter into the problem either of prices 236 RENT QUESTION SUMMARIZED, or of wages. It being impossible for the surplus of B, C, and D to go to the consumer either in higher wages or lower prices, whether it shall all remain in the hands of the entrepreneur or be shared between him and the landowner is of no economic or social importance to the laborer or to the community. The social welfare of the people can advance only as prices fall and wages rise, results which cannot be promoted by any manipulation of rent. It is by lessening the cost of production and not by appropriating the surplus that prices must be reduced. The cost of production can be lessened only by using improved methods. The successful use of improved methods depends upon increasing consumption and higher wages. Therefore the improvement of the social condition of the masses and the general advancement of society must be sought in the influences which promote the advance of real wages and not in any schemes for abolishing rents. The question of economic rent then, may be summarized thus : (i) That rent is a net surplus arising from the use of land as an economic instrument ; (2) That rent tends to equal the differ- ence in the productive utility of the different portions of land used for the same purpose in the same community or competing group ; (3) That the economic use of inferior land simulta- neously with superior, and hence the payment of rent, finally de- pends upon the employment of improved methods of production (use of capital) ; (4) That the successful use of improved meth- ods depends upon the increased consumption of wealth per capita of the community or a higher social standard of living among the masses and, that rent is not the cause of low wages, but the economic consequence of high wages ; (5) That since rent is an economic surplus the existence and increase of which depends upon the social progress and increasing wages of the laboring classes, it is in the broadest sense the interest of the landowning class to promote in every way possible the economic and social advancement of the laboring classes. CHAPTER V. THE LAW OF INTEREST. SECTION I. Popular Theories of Interest. INTEREST is economically analogous to rent ; it sustains pre- cisely the same relation to capital that rent does to land. In con- sidering the question of interest, therefore, we have to deal with essentially the same economic problem we considered in the last chapter. All the popular objections urged against the payment of rent as a burden to the community, an exaction from the laborer, etc., are presented with equal force against the payment of inter- est. And conversely, the same reasons that justify the payment of rent apply equally to that of interest. Scientifically therefore, all that is necessary in dealing with the question of interest is to apply to capital the law already stated in regard to land. Unfortunately however, in this instance, as in almost every other question in economics, a simple direct statement of the sub- ject is practically impossible without first clearing away some of the confusion in which it has been involved. The utter lack of logical consistency which characterizes the body of economic doctrines authoritatively taught is such that there is practically no mutual relation between the different departments of the sub- ject. There being no recognized common centre of movement, no order of relation and mutual dependence of phenomena, and hence no accepted general law which they shall obey, each phase of the subject is discussed for the most part as if it had no neces- sary relation to the whole but were governed by laws peculiar to itself. Thus we find Ricardo and other English economists teaching that profits are governed by a law entirely different from that which regulates rent. And now more than half a century later we have Mr. Walker declaring the same thing with regard to interest. 23? 238 WALKER'S VIEW OF INTEREST. This is the more astonishing in Mr. Walker's case, because he makes special claim to having presented a logical order of distri- bution. 1 When dealing with the question of rent, which he puts first, he never tires of proclaiming the doctrine that rent does not affect the price of the product, since that is determined by the use of no-rent land ; yet he fails to recognize this principle in the case of interest, and emphatically declares that " there is not any no-interest capital," and says : "We have seen that the whole theory of rent rests on the assumption that there is a body of no-rent lands. ... In the theory of capital there is nothing to correspond to this. The economist does not find any no-interest capital. In theory, all capital bears an interest, and all portions of capital bear equal interest. . . . But what has been stated shows how fundamentally the theory of interest differs from that of rent." 3 Why should we assume that " there is a body of no-rent lands " and that " there is not any no-rent capital " ? Upon what ground should we assume that " all portions of capital bear equal interest " ? Surely we have a right to demand some explanation, some pertinent facts in experience, or a well-established principle before we can be expected to accept such sweeping affirm- ations. If, as Mr. Walker says, " interest forms a part of the price of all products," 3 then all interest is a tax upon the consumer, and the wealth of the rich, so far as interest is con- cerned, is obtained at the expense of the poor. It will not be difficult to show that Mr. Walker's position on interest, which is essentially the same as that of Marx on profits, and George on rent, rests like theirs on pure assumption unsupported by estab- lished facts or verified principle. When discussing profits he in- sists that there is no-profit capital and says : " The employers of the lowest grade the no-profit employers, as we have called them must pay wages sufficient to hire labor- ers to work under their direction. These wages constitute an es- sential part of the cost to the employer of the production of the goods. The fact that these wages are so high is the reason why 1 " Political Economy," pp. 193, 248. * Ibid., pp. 222, 223. 3 Ibid., pp. 235, 236. SIMILARITY OF INTEREST AND PROFIT. 239 these employers are unable (their skill, etc. being the same) to realize any profit for themselves." ' If we ask Mr. Walker why there are " no-profit employers," which of course means no-profit capital, he will reply, as he has at length, that it is because, under free and active competition, prices tend to equal the cost of production under the greatest disadvantage. 2 If there is any economic power by which prices can be forced down to the no-profit point and to the no-rent point, why can they not, by the same power, be forced down to the no-interest point ? If the owner of the poorest tools in use is powerless to demand a price sufficiently high to yield a profit upon the capital invested in those tools, by what force in economics can he demand a price high enough to yield interest for that capital ? Obviously the same power that will enable him to insist upon the one will enable him to obtain the other. When considering the law of prices, 3 we saw that, at the price- determining point (producing at the greatest disadvantage), each factor in production obtained only the exact equivalent of the cost of its contribution to the product ; that is to say, that no factor in production can add more value to the product than it loses in the process. Consequently the price of the product cannot be greater than the equivalent of the aggregate cost of the factors jointly employed in its production. Clearly if there is any power by which more can be demanded from the product for capital than the equivalent of what it gives (the cost of maintain- ing its productive efficiency), the same power will enable the consumer and the laborer to do likewise. It is only upon the principle that capital employed under the greatest disadvantage will barely yield the cost of maintaining its productive efficiency, that no-rent land and no-profit employers are possible. It is solely because their product sells at cost that they occupy the datum-line or price-fixing position. Manifestly any social con- ditions or economic law which will make no-rent land and no- profit factories possible, will also make no-interest capital possible. 1 "Political Economy," pp. 240, 241. " Ibid., pp. 236-242. 3 Chapter iv., pp. 20-22. 240 NO-INTEREST CAPITAL. Moreover, facts everywhere sustain this theorem. There is probably no well-established industry, either in agriculture, man- ufacture, or commerce, in which there is not permanently a cer- tain amount of no-interest capital employed. There are hun- dreds and perhaps thousands of small farmers, merchants, and manufacturers in this and every other commercially advanced country, who remain in business for years and barely obtain a living and keep their capital intact. Nor do I refer to those re- sults of bad judgment and inexperience which Mr. Walker calls "accidents," 1 but only to capital which is so employed as the necessary result of economic law. Mr. Walker may reply that no one will accumulate wealth and invest it in production unless he can obtain a reward at least to the extent of interest. Even if this were literally correct and without an exception, it would not prevent the use of no-interest capital. Indeed if capital were never invested for less than the maximum profit the use of the no-interest capital would be not only possible but inevitable. Through the concentration of cap- ital and the use of improved methods, maximum-profit yielding capital is constantly being reduced to the no-interest point. Suppose for example, that in the manufacture of cotton cloth half a million dollars are invested in the plant which at the time is of the most modern type, and that the capital not only yields interest but a profit. In the course of a few years a great im- provement in machinery is discovered by the use of which the cost of cotton cloth is greatly reduced. Through the fall in price resulting from the use of this new machinery, the profits of those who still produce by the previous methods are entirely destroyed. The capital which at first yielded a high profit ceases to yield any thing above the bare cost of production wages, raw material, and actual wear and tear. Consequently, if this capital continues to be employed it must be used without profit or interest. Moreover, when through still further improvements the price falls too low for this now inferior machinery to be used without loss, the capital invested in the tools of the next grade above will fall to the no-interest point, and so on. Thus, while it may be true that no capital is originally invested without interest or even high 1 " Political Economy," p. 235. MOVEMENT OF CAPITAL. 24! profit, it constantly tends towards the no-interest point through the use of improved methods. This does not mean, however, that the same capital, or the capital of the same persons, continues to be employed at the no-interest point ; on the contrary, such capital is constantly struggling to move from no-interest to high- profit uses. This however, is often difficult to do without loss. If the capital is invested in machinery which is reduced to the no-interest point by the competition of larger concerns using su- perior methods, then it can only be transferred to high-profit uses by being invested in the superior methods and producing on a larger scale, and this usually involves a larger amount of capi- tal, the lack of which often makes such transfer impossible. Cap- ital is often thus retained in the same business for a considerable time after it ceases to yield interest, partly in the hope of doing better and partly from fear of a loss of the principal in any sud- den transfer to new fields. From these and many other causes which are constantly in operation, especially among small pro- ducers, capital is often continued in a business, not merely until it reaches the no-interest point, but in many cases until it is forced by competition to the losing point. Thus, while capital is constantly struggling to move from no-interest to high-profit uses, that portion of it which is used under the poorest conditions is always no-interest capital. If prices could never fall below the interest-paying point for the capital invested in the poorest tools, then the use of improved machinery would not cheapen commodities, but would simply increase profits. Nothing but working at a loss or the failure to obtain interest will enforce the disuse of the most inferior instru- ments, and permit prices to fall to the cost of producing with superior methods, and thus compel the advantages of improved machinery and concentrated capital to pass to the community in lower prices instead of remaining in the hands of capitalists as higher profits. This is what is constantly taking place in every progressive community. There is scarcely a machine-using industry in which capital has not been reduced from the high-profit to the no- interest point several times over during the present century. Take, for example, the cotton industry. In the first quarter of this century, capital invested in machinery that could produce 16 MOVEMENT OF INTEREST. calico at 30 cents a yard would yield a high profit. And before 1830 the capital invested in the same machinery could not yield interest, nor even be used without loss, the price of calico having fallen to 17 cents a yard. And the high-profit capital of 1830 reached the no-interest or losing point by 1843, when the price had fallen to 12 cents a yard. And the high-profit capital of 1843 again reached the no-interest point by 1850, when the price had fallen to 9 J cents a yard ; and so on, until to-day the capital can- not receive interest which is unable to produce the same com- modity at less than 5 cents a yard. Thus the whole circle from high-profit to no-interest has been traversed several times over during the present century. In fact, every dollar's worth of capital invested in the print-cloth business since the invention of the power-loom, that could not produce print-cloth at 4 cents a yard, has been reduced to the no-interest point. 1 Since Mr. Walker admits that this takes place in the sphere of both profits and rents, why he should fail to see that through the same law it must also take place in the sphere of interest, is not a little surprising. He appears to have fallen into the same error that the English economists committed in regard to rent and profits. They saw that rent is paid from a surplus above the cost, and hence is not an addition to the price of the product ; while they regard profits as the reward for the abstinence of the capitalist, and hence a necessary addition to the price.* Mr. Walker saw their error in not regarding profits as a surplus similar to rent, yet he has repeated the same oversight regarding interest. Indeed, he has taken their formula for profits and used it as a definition of interest, and says : " Capital, as we have seen, is the result of saving. Interest, then, is the reward for abstinence." * 1 ! the mm industries there are many large properties that are barely np to the level of no-interest mse without loss to-day which a few jean ago yielded high profits. The Jfcfrodarfina of tmmmful orrentiops has in any instances rcdaccd wnttttm* of dollars" worth of -i* ; T not merely to the no-interest foot, bat forced it oat of use altogether. * " Wealth of Nations," book L, chapter vi., p. y) chapter riL, p. 42 ; book T., eha^Cer n,~, p. 691. Rkardo's " Works," pp. 39, 68. McCnlloch's " Principles of Political Economy," p. 42. Mill's " Principles of Political Economy." *oL L, pp. 569-72. " Po6tal Economy," p. 224 ; also p. 66 ; ., the wages of every laborer must be equal to the cost of his own living. Now we know that in every industry the wages of the same class of laborers tend to a uniformity while the cost of living of the individual laborers varies greatly. For example, we know that in New York City painters, carpenters, bricklayers, cigarmakers, tailors, etc., who work on the same grade of work or in the same shop get the same wages, but individually the cost of their living varies in some cases several dollars a week. On the Marxian hypothesis, that the capitalist who sells his yarn for more than it costs him exploits some of the factors of production, the laborer who obtains more for his labor than it cost him must also have exploited some other factor. Marx would object to charging the laborer with robbery ; his purpose is to prove the other man the thief. Yet, if it is a law in economics that the possession of a surplus proves exploitation, then a surplus in the hands of the laborer who has sold his labor power for more than it cost him is as conclusive evidence of exploitation as is a sur- plus in the hands of the capitalist who has sold his commodity for more than it cost him. Scientific law does not discriminate 262 PRODUCT PROFIT AND WAGES. between individuals ; there is no operation of natural law under which the laborer is an honest man and the capitalist a thief, when both are doing the same thing. A theory which thus puts vice at a premium and virtue at a discount by showing that none but thieves succeed and that the only reward for honesty is failure and poverty, should only need stating to be rejected. SECTION V. The Ratio of Profit to Product and to Wages. One of the most prevalent assumptions regarding profit is, that it takes an inordinately large proportion of the product. The point upon which Marx lays exceptional stress is that profit prac- tically equals wages. Although few careful writers would now venture to contend that wages are actually diminishing, the idea of Rodbertus, that the laborer's share of the product diminishes as his productiveness increases, is very commonly accepted. How much of the product goes to profit and the ratio of profit to wages are mainly questions of fact ; it is therefore to facts that we must turn for any satisfactory explanation of the sub- ject. If the law of prices and wages presented in these pages is sound, and its corollary of the law of surplus (rent, interest, and profit) is correct, we may expect, under modern productive con- ditions, to find three important facts : (i) that real wages (wealth obtainable for a day's service] tend to increase both actually and rela- tively to the quantity of consumable wealth produced ; (2) that, while the surplus or profit increases in its actual amount, it diminishes relatively to the aggregate net product j that is to say, profit absorbs a diminishing proportion of the consumable wealth produced ; (3) that the ratio of wages to profits tends to increase, and that both the actual amount of consumable wealth and the relative proportion of the net product which goes to labor are greater than the amount which goes to capital, and that this tendency increases as the concentration of capital and the use of improved methods advance. \. Is the proposition that real wages tend to increase both actually and relatively to the quantity of consumable wealth pro- duced, sustained by the facts ? Fortunately, the industrial history of the present century affords ample data for a conclusive answer to this question. Let us take the cotton industry, which by this THE COTTON INDUSTRY. 263 time the reader has become quite familiar with. Moreover, this industry affords an excellent illustration of the principles under consideration, because it is a very extensive industry. It is also completely representative of the factory system, and as such has been in existence longer than almost any other industry. At the commencement of the present century the weaver could only buy ten yards of cloth with a week's wages. To-day (1890) he can obtain a hundred and fifty yards of his own product for a week's wages, while working about thirty hours less per week. That is to say, through a rise in his wages and a fall in the price of the product, he is able to obtain fifteen times as much of his own product for a day's work in 1890 as he could obtain in 1800. The factory period in this country really dates from about 1830. From that time to 1880 the investment of capital, the number of establishments, the amount and price of product, and the wages paid in that industry were as follows : 1830. 1880. Number of establishments 801 756 Aggregate capital invested $40,612,984 $208,280,346 Number of Ibs. cloth produced 59,514,926 607,264,241 persons employed 62,208 172,544 spindles " 1,246,703 10,653,435 Amount of capital to establish $50,702 $275,503 Ratio of Ibs. produced to capital 1.4 to $1.00 2.4 tofi.oo " capital to persons employed $652.85 to i $1,207.17 to I " spindles to persons " 22 to I 62 to I " capital to spindles " $32.58101 $19.55101 " Ibs. produced to persons employed 950.7 to i 3,519-5 to I " spindles 47.6 to 1 . 57.0 to i Annual consumption of Ibs. of cotton cloth per capita. . .5.90 13.81 Price of cotton cloth per yard 17 cents 7 cents Operative's wages per week $2.55 $5-4 It will be seen that in the 756 large establishments in 1880 in which the aggregate capital invested was five times as great as that in the 80 1 small establishments in 1830, the capital invested per spindl-e was one third less, the number of spindles operated by each laborer nearly three times as large, the product per spindle one fourth greater, the product per dollar invested twice as large, the price of the cotton cloth nearly sixty per cent, less, the consumption per capita of the population over one hundred per cent, greater, and wages more than double. 264 PURCHASING POWER OF WAGES. If we take the New England States, which comprise the leading cotton-manufacturing district in the country, and also that where the greatest concentration of capital and machinery in this industry has taken place, the results in this direction are still more striking. According to the statistics on wages and prices from 1752, gathered by the Massachusetts Labor Bureau, 1 in 1831 the ratio of spindles to operatives was 24 T f T to i. In 1880 they were 7iy{hy to i. And the ratio of pounds of product to operatives employed in 1831 was 1,484 to i, and in 1880 it was 3,633 to i. That is to say, during fifty years the ratio of spindles to operatives increased 184 per cent., and the ratio of product to operatives 145 per cent. During the same period the aggregate wages of men, women, and children rose 115 per cent., and the hours of labor were reduced 12 p'er cent., while the price of calico print fell from 17 to 7 2 cents a yard. Thus, while the wages in this industry rose 115 per cent., the purchasing power of those wages in the finished product increased 241 per cent. ; that is to say, through a rise of wages and fall in prices accompanying the concentration of capital and use of improved methods, the laborer was enabled to obtain over five times as much of his own product for a day's labor in 1880 as he did in 1830 the increase is still greater now (1890). If we consider the matter from the standpoint of value instead of quantity of product, a similar result is apparent. In 1850 the value of the product per operative in New Eng- land was $707 ; in 1880 it was $1,139 per operative, an increase of 61-^5*5- per cent. The wages in this industry for 1850 for New England are not obtainable, but if we assume that the proportion of the 1 15 per cent, increase from 1830 to 1880 was as great after as before 1850, a perfectly safe assumption, the rise in wages from 1850 to 1880 would be 69 per cent. Measured in money, therefore, the value of labor (wages) of cotton operatives rose 8 per cent, more than the value of their product. If we extend this generalization to the whole United States the result is very similar. The value of product per operative in the cotton industry in 1850 was $709, and in 1880 it was $1,112, being an 1 Report for 1885, pp. 185-189. 2 Ibid., p. 455- 1 1 have taken 1850 because the value for 1830 is not obtainable. MR. GIFFEN ON WAGES AND PRODUCT. 26$ increase of 56fa l P er cent., or 12 per cent, less than the rise of wages. Therefore, whether we view the question from the standpoint of quantity of wealth, purchasing power of wages, or the ratio of wages to product, it is equally clear that wages have increased both actually and relatively to the quantity of con- sumable wealth produced, as capital has been concentrated and as improved methods of production have been employed. Notwithstanding this rise of wages and fall of prices, it is insisted that the laborer is despoiled of a large part of the wealth he produces. As evidence of this we are pointed to the fact that in many industries the product per laborer has increased more than a thousand per cent, during the last fifty years, while their wages have not much more than doubled. This claim has been virtually conceded by Mr. Giffen, President of the British Statis- tical Society. He says : " On this head it may be admitted, to begin with, that there is apparent foundation for some of the complaints. Workmen in particular employments do not get a reward at all in proportion to the increase of production in those employments. The illustration of a cotton-mill is familiar. A single attendant on a number of machines will 'produce' as much in an hour as formerly in a year or two, but his wages are only double or perhaps not quite double what they were when the production was so much less. 2 . . . But the increased severity of toil, without proportionate remuneration, might be admitted in those special employments without altering the fact that remuneration has increased generally. What seems to have happened in these cases is that the development of society imposes a heavy burden on a special class." 3 While he tries to break the force of this complaint by showing that remuneration has increased generally, he practically admits the injustice, and treats it as an inherent element in the present industrial constitu- tion of society. This is all that socialistic reconstructionists claim ; it is because they believe that equity is impossible under the present industrial system that they demand its abolition. Nor can their claim be reasonably resisted unless these phe- nomena can be explained without assuming either that society 1 See U. S. Census (1880), volume on Manufactures, pp. 541-547. 2 " Gross and Net Gain of Rising Wages," Contemporary Review, December, 1889, p. 835. * Ibid., p. 838. 266 MR. GfFFEN'S ERROR. has developed in the wrong direction or that natural law is inherently unjust. Here is another instance of the error of treating wages as a share in the division of the product, instead of an item in the cost of production. If this view were correct, and wages in each industry should rise directly as the product per laborer increases, as Mr. Giffen's argument implies,, the result, instead of being more equitable, would be unjust to the laborers and more inimical to society. It would be unjust to the laborers because it would give all the increased product resulting from improved machinery to the particular laborers who happen to use the improved implements, thus depriving the laborers in non-machine-using industries of any advantage arising from superior methods of production. Upon what principle of equity should a weaver or shoemaker who happens, without any virtue on his part, to use improved instruments, receive fifty or a hundred times as much wages as the bricklayer, painter, compositor, and other hand- workers whose industries do not admit of the use of steam-driven machinery ? Manifestly any industrial system which would in- crease the wages of the factory-worker fifty or a hundred-fold, while it would only advance those of hand-workers ten or twenty per cent., simply because, in the nature of the occupations, the former could and the latter could not use labor-saving machinery, would be the very embodiment of injustice. It would be inimical to society, because it would make any general reduction in the price of commodities impossible, as the increased wealth would all go to the particular laborer who used improved machinery, thus depriving the community in general of any participation in the advantages of industrial development. It is hardly necessary to say that the use of steam-driven machinery is no more due to the particular operatives who use it than it is to the millions of compositors, bricklayers, farmers, and other laborers who do not use them. In the first place, it is the consumption not of the machine workers merely, but of the whole community that supplies the market which makes the use of the factory methods possible. And in the second place, it is the inventive genius developed by an advancing civilization, to- gether with the capital invested in the production of machinery to supply the need thus created, that furnishes the increased DISTRIBUTION OF BENEFITS. 267 product. Clearly therefore, if only the wages of those laborers were increased who used the improved instruments the market for the machine-made products would be too small to enable factory methods to be profitably employed. Thus a system which would give all the increased product resulting from improved instruments to the particular laborers who use those instruments would not only be highly unjust, but would defeat itself and arrest the industrial progress of society. If we examine the case of machine-using and non-machine using laborers in the light of the law of wages and prices heretofore presented, it will be apparent that the mere fact that the laborer produces more, has practically nothing to do with what he shall receive, because it has nothing to do with the cost of his living. The amount he produces by a day's work depends far more upon the kind of tools he uses than upon his personal quality. A twelve-year-old child in a New England factory can spin more yarn than a hundred of the most expert spinners that ever lived could produce with a spinning wheel. It is the price of the product, and not the price of the labor, that is determined by the quantity the laborer produces in a day. The cost of his living being the same if he produces twice as much, the cost of production and hence the price will be proportionately reduced. Thus any improvement of productive instruments which enables the laborer to produce more, his cost of living being the same, will show itself not in a rise of his wages, but in a fall of the price of the commodities he produces. On the other hand, the price of hand-made commodities rises in proportion as the laborers' wages increase. It thus appears that wages are determined by conditions which affect the charac- ter and cost of the laborer, and not by those which influence the quantity and cost of the product. When the standard and cost of living of the compositor, bricklayer, painter, etc., increase, the community has to pay more for the products of their labor, because there is not much improvement in the tools they use ; whereas the product of the factory worker is so much increased that, although his wages rise as much as those of other laborers, the cost of production is greatly diminished. That is why the price of all httfid-made products tends to rise while that of machine or factory-made products constantly tends to fall. It is 268 EQUITY OF ECONOMIC LA W. because the wages of the hand-workers have increased in a greater proportion than their product that those of machine workers have increased less proportionately to their product. By this means the disadvantage of inferior and the advantage of superior instruments is distributed uniformly to each person in the community to the extent that he is a. consumer. Thus the two prime movements of industrial progress, the rise of wages and the fall of prices, benefit laborers in all occupations and condi- tions directly as their wealth-consuming capacity increases and social character rises. It will be observed that, from this point of view, the case of the workman to whom Mr. Giffen referred as not getting " a reward at all in proportion to the increase of production," appears entirely different. What to him appeared to be a necessary in- justice is in reality the e'vidence of the supreme equity of economic law. The increased product being mainly due to the use of capital and improved tools, which has been made possible through the use of increased consumption and higher social life of the general community, it is to the community in general, and not to particular laborers who happen to use those tools, that the increased product in equity should go, and by economic law does go. The important fact that cannot be too much emphasized here is, that wages are paid for the economic cost, and hence for the social quality of the laborer. It is therefore what the laborer is rather than what he does that determines his wages, and this is true without regard to the nature of his occupation or the quality of his tools. 2. This brings us to the second proposition, that profits tend to absorb a diminishing proportion of the consumable wealth produced. In view of what has already been said, a discussion of this proposition might be properly deemed unnecessary. And were it not that one of our most trusted statistical authorities has apparently affirmed the opposite, I should so regard it. In the report of the Massachusetts Bureau of Statistics of Labor for 1885 the data for nine industries are given, which show that the percentage of the net product paid as wages fell from 59-^ per cent, in 1850 to 48-^ per cent, in 1880, and, after commenting upon the peculiarities of each industry, the repot** (p. 191) says : " An examination of these two tables would, we think, lead to RATIO OF PROFIT TO PRODUCT. 269 the conclusion that, although in every case money wages have considerably increased, yet in certain industries in which the principles of the factory system (i.e., the subdivision of labor, co- ordination of processes, and the application of a series of mutually dependent and practically automatic machines) have been most effective, such, for instance, as in the cotton and woollen indus- tries, the relative share of net product gained by the workmen tends to decrease. That is to say, in these industries perfection of machines and processes constantly tend to create a larger product with less capital, and the ratio of increase in productive capacity tends to outrun the ratio of increase in wages, so that of this larger product labor obtains a less relative share." They then take from the United States Census the same data for all industries in the country, and find that 5 1 per cent, of this net product was paid in wages in 1850 and only 48^^ per cent, in 1880, and say : " It appears that when the field is broadened so as to include the entire manufacturing industries of the country, labor's share of the net product has declined from 5 1 per cent, to 48^ per cent." In view of such emphatic statements apparently sustained by facts from such a reliable source, it can hardly be a matter of sur- prise that it is generally believed that wages obtain a constantly diminishing and profit gains an increasing proportion of the wealth produced. It is important, therefore, even at the risk of being a little tedious, to examine the process by which this con- clusion is reached. Nor will this be very difficult, since both the data and the method of treatment are amply stated. The method of procedure is to divide the product into gross and net value, the former being the value of the aggregate product, and the latter that of the product less the cost of the raw material. This is regarded as representing the net value created by the joint operation of the labor and capital employed in the enterprise. 1 If a diminishing proportion of this net product is paid as wages, it is concluded that an increasing proportion of it must go to 1 "Net product, or value of product remaining after deducting value of raw materials of manufacture, represents the direct result of the productive forces in the given industry ; or, in other words, it represents the value created over and above the value of raw materials by the effective operation of labor and capital united." Report of Bureau of Statistics of Labor, p. 190. 2/0 DEFECTIVE METHODS. profits. 1 This method of treating the subject is defective in two respects : (i) in regarding the ratio of the total wages to the net product (product less raw material) as indicating the economic condition of the laborer ; (2) in assuming that a diminution in the ratio of the total wages to this net product necessarily implies a proportional increase of profit. (i) That it is a mistake to treat the ratio of the aggregate wages to the value of product as indicating the economic condi- tion of the laborer, is shown by the fact that this ratio may increase and the laborer grow poorer, and it may diminish while the laborer's condition improves. Take, for example, the hand- loom weaver and the factory laborer. After deducting the raw material, nearly all the value of the product of the hand-loom weaver went to wages ; while, according to the bureau's figures, only about 48 per cent, of the product now goes to wages, yet no one would pretend that the hand-loom weavers were in a better economic condition than are the factory operatives to-day. Whether the amount paid for labor is one million or one thou- sand millions of dollars in no way affects the laborer's condition, except as it gives a larger amount to each laborer. The same is true of the proportion. Whether the 80 or 90 per cent, of the product received by the hand-weaver gave him more actually or relatively to the product than 50 per cent, will to-day, depends entirely upon whether it is paid to a relatively larger or smaller number of laborers. If the aggregate amount paid in wages relatively to the product were doubled, and either the number of laborers to whom it was paid or the time expended in producing it with the same laborers was more than doubled, instead of indi- cating an improvement in the laborer's condition, it would show a deterioration. Suppose for example, that under hand labor, 80 cents out of each dollar's worth of product go to labor, and are paid to 20 laborers, the ratio of wages per laborer to the value of the product will be as 4 cents to the dollar ; whereas, if, under the factory system, only 50 cents out of every dollar's worth of product goes to labor, if it is all paid to five laborers, the ratio of wages per laborer to the value of the product would be as 10 cents to the dollar. Thus every laborer would receive relatively 1 Ibid., p. go. MISLEADING DEDUCTIONS. 2? I to the product created two and a half times as much with the 50 per cent, under factory production as with the 80 per cent, under hand labor. Now this is precisely what has occurred in the development of factory methods of production. Clearly there- fore, it is not the proportion between the aggregate wages and the product, but the proportion between the amount paid to each laborer and the product that indicates his economic condition. In other words, it is the rate and not the aggregate amount of wages that is the true basis of comparison, because it is the rate of wages only that affects the laborer's economic status, either actually or relatively. (2) The assumption that a diminution in the ratio of aggre- gate wages to the so-called net product necessarily implies a pro- portional increase of profits is also a mistake. The fact that 51 per cent, of the net product was paid in wages in 1850 and only 487^ was so paid in 1880, does not prove that the percentage of the product going to profit has increased ; on the contrary, this might occur and profit be greatly reduced or annihilated alto- gether. All this fact reveals is that in 1880 the total amount paid in wages represented 2 T V per cent, less of the value of the product, after deducting value of raw material, than it did in 1850 ; but this does not show that more of the remaining 5iyV per cent, of the product went to profit. Until that remaining portion is accounted for, there can be no more warrant for saying that it went to profit than that it went to the moon. The only condition under which the amount of one item can be properly inferred from that of another is when the two represent the whole, or when the amount they do not represent is a known fixed quantity. Since all the product, less raw material, is not divided between wages and profit, the inference that the ratio of profit to net product increases because that of wages is diminished can only be valid when all the other items are definitely ascertained. That this has not been done in the present instance is shown by the following statement : " The value of net product forms, as we have said, a fund divisible into interest on capital, interest on loans, insurance, freights, rents, commissions, wages, and profits. Now if the relative share paid in labor in the form of wages is decreased, it is, of course, obvious that the share remaining for the other purposes mentioned is increased. If capital is also 2/2 OMITTED DATA. relatively decreased, then it is fair to suppose that the share chargeable to interest is also diminished. It is well known that the relative cost of freights and insurance has decreased." It will be observed that the above not only fails to definitely explain the relative amount of the other items in the cost of pro- duction and thereby obtain the proportion going to profit, but it omits some items altogether. In the first place, it only accounts for a portion of the amount which is paid for service, no account being taken of salaries of managers and other overseers, and agents, which are a part of the payment to labor, and are included in the cost of production as much as the day-wages of the laborers in the shop. In the next place it omits entirely the depreciation of capital, which is also a necessary item in the cost of produc- tion. The items thus unaccounted for necessarily go to swell the undivided surplus which is put down as profit. By this means it may be made to appear that a large profit exists, when in truth there has been a dead loss, and when a profit does actually exist this method of investigation will invariably make it appear very much larger, sometimes more than double what it really is." Both these items of cost affect the result in two ways. In the first place, other things being the same, they both reduce the undivided surplus going to profit to the full extent of their amount. In the next place, they both absorb an increasing proportion of the net product in proportion as factory methods of production are increased. It is impossible to state the exact proportion of the net product paid in salaries in the different periods, because that item has been entirely omitted by all industrial statistics until the Massa- chusetts Census for 1885. According to this report, the total amount paid in salaries in that State in 1885 was $10,846,367, which was equal to 3yV 3 " *' ^ ' giving a rate of surplus value of more than one hundred per cent. The laborer employs more than one half of his working day in producing the surplus value." Marx, "Capital, "p. 203. " Now, gentle- men, if you compare the working time you pay for, you will find that they are to one another, as half a day is to half a day j this gives a rate of one hundred per cent., and a very pretty percentage it is." Ibid., p. 211. " But the fact is and on that we lay stress that the workers receive only about half of what they produce. " Gronlund, '' Modern Socialism," p. 23. 8 These are exclusive of Boston. I have omitted Boston because for some unexplained reason the net product in Boston fell about 75 per cent. Such a change must be the result of some abnormal occurrence perhaps in a few indus- tries. Although it would greatly reduce the ratio of profits to wages in 1880, rather than use doubtful results. I prefer to exclude the whole of Boston data. a Exclusive of salaries. 278 RATIO OF PROFITS TO WAGES, representative concerns for a considerable number of years to- gether, than by a very much larger number of concerns for a sin- gle year. For instance, the complete facts for ten large corpora- tions for ten years together will much more accurately show the normal ratio of wages to profits in that industry than would the facts, equally complete, for all the concerns in the country for any given date. This investigation shows that the ratio of wages to profits in thirteen leading industries for a number of years to- gether, 1 to be as 4.20 to i. Taking the basis adopted by the Massachusetts Bureau for 1880, the relative movement of profit and wages from 1850 to 1885 has been as follows : ALL MANUFACTURING INDUSTRIES FOR THE UNITED STATES. Percent- age of raw material Percent- Percent- Value of aggregate product. and fixed costs in age of wages in age of profits in Average* yearly Ratio of wages to total total total wages. profits. product. product. product. 1850 $1,019,106,616 . . 67.61 23.23 9.16 $247-37 2. 53* to I 1860 1,885,861,676 . . 67.92 20.09 11.99 288.94 1.67 to I 1870 4,232,325,442 . . 71.79 18.34 9.87 376.59 1.85 to I 1880 5,369,579,191 . . 76.37 17.67 5.96 346.91 2.96 to I ALL MANUFACTURED INDUSTRIES FOR MASSACHUSETTS. 4 18751456,400,458 . . . 62.57 27.06 10.37 $445.00 2.6o 8 to I 1880 631,135,284. . . 72.79 21-75 5.46 364.00 3.98 to I 1885 674,634,269 . . . 70.88 23-45 5.67 388.62 4.13 to I 1888 402.45 THIRTEEN LEADING INDUSTRIES FOR 8 YEARS TOGETHER TO 1 889. 1889 $112,393,804.98 . 67.98 25.93 6.09 4.20 to I 1 Ten of these were for eight years in succession, two for ten years, and one only for four years. * It should be remembered that these figures do not represent the wages of men, but the average wages of men, women, and children all taken together. Since in manufacturing industries there is generally one worker besides the head of the family, and sometimes more, these wages only represent about half the in- come of the average family in these industries. s This column is exclusive of salaries. 4 Exclusive of Boston. I have omitted Boston because for some unexplained reason profits fell from an aggregate of $27,640,680 in 1875 to $7,162, 768 in 1880. Such a change must be the result of some abnormal occurrence perhaps in a few industries. Although it would greatly reduce the ratio of profits to wages in 1880, rather than risk doubtful results I prefer to exclude the whole of Boston data for 1885. * This includes salaries. ACTUAL RISE OF WAGES. 279 It will be seen from these facts, which represent the greatest body of statistical data ever collected upon the subject, 1 that the industrial tendency during the last thirty years has been steadily towards a greater concentration of capital and economy in pro- ductive power, resulting in an actual increase in wages both rela- tively to the product and per laborer employed, and also a relative proportional decrease of profit as compared with wages. 1 The figures for the United States are taken from the Census of 1880 and those for Massachusetts are taken from the industrial census of that State, rep- resenting for 1880 14,352 establishments in 80 industries with an aggregate capi- tal of $271,056,051 ; for 1885, 23,431 establishments in 83 industries, with an aggregate capital of $500,594,377. PART IV. THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL STATESMAN- SHIP; OR, APPLIED SOCIAL ECONOMICS. CHAPTER I. LAISSEZ FAIRE AS A GUIDING PRINCIPLE IN PUBLIC POLICY. SECTION I. A Protest Against Paternalism. ALTHOUGH laissez faire has never been the accepted rule of public policy in any country, the fact that for more than a century it has been taught by leading economists as the guiding principle of industrial statesmanship entitles it to prominent con- sideration. It should be remembered in the first place that the idea of laissez faire as applied to industrial statesmanship does not represent an inductively established principle in society ; that is to say, it is not a logical conclusion drawn from an ex- tensive study of industrial phenomena. On the contrary it came into existence as a watchword to express a protest against the high-handed paternalism of the feudal and mercantile systems ; and by the force of habitual repetition, sustained by a pardon- able bias against a land-owning class, it was subsequently elevated to the position of an economic principle. During the Middle Ages government was not only essentially paternal, but it was exclusively in the hands of the land-owning class. The interest class being chiefly local, industrial policy was naturally restrictive in character. Accordingly, in the earliest stages of manufacture and the growth of the free towns, industry was hemmed in by innumerable arbitrary regulations. Scarcely any occupation could be engaged in without paying tallage or tribute to the baron. And with the growth of the Free Cities and the decline of baronial power this privilege of exacting tribute for the right to engage in an industry was assumed by the guilds, and finally took the form of charters, by which the gov- 283 284 ORIGIN OF LAISSEZ FAIRE. ernment became the exactor of booty. In proportion as manu- facture and commerce increased, the evil effects of this policy became more and more inimical to public welfare, and made a new industrial policy necessary. Nor is it surprising that the new policy should be the very opposite of the old one. The remedy for the evil effects of too much government interference was naturally sought in a policy of no government interference. By the last half of the seventeenth century this anti-paternal feeling had become very strong, and was finally voiced by a prominent French merchant, who, when asked by Colbert, "What can we do to aid you?" promptly answered, " Laissez faire" Let us alone. This expression so completely represented the feelings of the mercantile class that it became the watchword for a new policy, and by the middle of the next century was made the basis of an economic theory by Quesnay and the Physiocrats, whose policy was concisely expressed as " Laissez faire et laissez passer " Let us alone and keep the ways free. In the last quarter of the eighteenth century this doctrine was revised and recast in England by Adam Smith. In many important respects the great Scotchman improved upon the doctrines of the French Physiocrats, especially in bringing out the economic importance of manufacture and commerce. But in view of the fact that the public policy of England was still largely determined by the landed aristocracy, who were traditionally hostile to the interests of the manufacturing and trading classes, Adam Smith naturally adhered to the doctrine of no government interference. Since his time the idea of laissez faire has beeh generally presented as representing a fundamental principle upon which the industrial policy of all nations should be based, any departure from this rule being justified only in special emergencies. In the next place it should be observed that the doctrine of laissez faire has not been verified by subsequent experience ; consequently, instead of being more implicitly accepted, its economic validity is denied just in proportion as the scientific treatment of the subject increases. As an axiom in public policy laissez faire is rejected by the inductive economists of the present generation with almost as much uniformity as it was accepted by the deductive economists of the previous half century. There- fore, the claim that the theory of laissez faire represents a CHARACTER OF LAISSEZ FAIRE. 285 universal principle in nature and society, and is entitled to the same unquestioning acceptance in economics that is accorded to the principle of gravitation in physics, is wholly unwarranted. SECTION II. Laissez Faire Essentially Unscientific. Considered as a fundamental principle in statesmanship, laissez faire is essentially unscientific. It is necessarily negative, while statesmanship is positive. All government, order, and progress imply affirmative action, and therefore are the op- posite of laissez faire. Science is essentially aggressive ; it implies the active policy of investigating, knowing, and control- ling things. Every improvement in the arts and sciences, every labor-saving appliance, is the result of man's interference with nature, of subjecting natural forces to human purposes. By studying the laws of chemistry, electricity, and mechanics, we know that under certain conditions heat, light, and force are developed. And instead of adopting the rule of laissez faire y and waiting till nature produces the desired result, we have learned to bring the particular forces together in just such relations as will produce that result much quicker. Consequently, we make steam produce our wealth, electricity do our errands, and natural forces serve us in every phase of life. The same is true in the animal and vegetable world. Our choicest flowers and vegetables are not the result of unaided natural selection, but of artificial cultivation ; that is to say, of the scientific application of the law of development. We have studied the conditions under which certain kinds of fruit, flowers, and vegetables develop their best specimens, and where nature fails to supply these conditions they are substituted by man. Our fast horses and finest breeds of cattle and sheep have all been produced in the same way. What is true in chemistry, mechanics, botany, and biology is equally true in sociology. Since affirmative statesmanship is necessary to government, and government is necessary to civilization, it is a contradiction in terms to speak of laissez faire as the basis of statesmanship. The science of government is not the knowledge of what not to do, but it is the knowledge of what to do and how and when to do it. To know what to do implies the knowledge of what not to do, but to know what not to do does not imply the knowledge of 286 ERRONEOUS POSTULATES. ^vhat to do. So long as government exists it must have a function a sphere of action. Scientific statesmanship implies a knowl- edge of the principle by which that action should be directed. Because the history of state interference with industry is the history of mistakes, it is commonly assumed that the only way to avoid mistakes of the past is to do nothing in the present It would be just as correct to say that because all mistakes are the result of affirmative action, inaction is the only means of avoiding error, the logic of which would involve the destruction of the human race. We cannot choose between doing and not doing, but only between doing wisely and unwisely. The doctrine of laissez faire, therefore, has no place in the science of statesman- ship or the art of government. This theory derives its chief plausibility from a seeming uni- versality in its postulates, which are : (i) That self-interest is a universal principle in human nature. (2) That each individual knows his own interest best, and in the absence of arbitrary re- strictions is sure to follow it. (3) That free competition always develops the highest possibilities by enabling each to do that for which he is best fitted, and thereby most surely advances the welfare of all. The proposition that self-interest is a universal principle in human nature is undoubtedly correct ; but there is nothing in experience or logic to warrant the assumption that the other two follow from it. That whatever is for the best interest of each promotes the welfare of all is indisputable, but that each individual always knows what is best for his own interest, and in the absence of arbitrary restrictions is sure to follow it, is by no means certain. Before each can know how to promote his own best interest he must know what his best interest is, which is precisely what the great bulk of the human race do not know. This knowledge can only be acquired by a more or less intelligent generalization from experience. Whatever tends to improve man's condition materially, socially, and morally, and increase the advantages of social life, promotes his best interests. To assume that every one knows what is best for himself is as unphilosophic as to assume that the child knows best what will promote its own welfare. Although many parents are ignorant, and often injure when they think to IGNORANCE OF SELF INTEREST. 287 help the child, the fact remains that the successful rearing of children chiefly depends upon the number of instances in which the wisdom of the parent, developed by experience, pre- vails over the ignorance of the child. Indeed the race would die out if the experience of parents werenot transformed into author- ity over the child. What is true of the child in this respect is still true to a very great extent, of a vast majority of the human race. Take for instance the people of Central Africa. The principle of self-in- terest is as universal there as in any part of the world. But no one would seriously claim that the average individual in that dark continent knows what is best for his own interest. On the con- trary, the most advanced scientists, philanthropists, philosophers, and statesmen agree that the best interests of the inhabitants of Africa can only be promoted by the interference of more ad- vanced and civilized nations. This same lack of knowledge of what is best for one's own interest, which is simply ignorance of the laws of social development, is still painfully apparent, not merely in every country, but, more or less in every class in the most ad- vanced countries. Those familiar with the laws of sanitation and hygiene know that cleanliness, fresh air, good drainage, and wholesome food are of vital importance to physical health, and therefore are of the highest interest to the laborer. But the ex- perience of health authorities shows that only with the utmost diffi- culty can the laboring classes, and particularly the poorer and more ignorant portion, be induced to pay any attention to these conditions. So too the employing classes, while more enlightened upon questions of science, literature, and art, exhibit scarcely less ignorance in regard to their economic interests. Take, for in- stance, their attitude towards the social condition of the laborer. They have assumed and have acted almost uniformly upon the assumption that high wages are inimical to their own interests, and consequently that to resist the rise of wages and social im- provement of the laboring classes is to promote their own pros- perity ; whereas, had they known their true economic relation to the laborer, they would have seen that every limitation of his social and material progress reacts injuriously upon the per- manence and extent of their own prosperity. The reason for 288 FALSE NOTIONS OF COMPETITION. their mistaken attitude is precisely the same as that which gov- erns the laborer when he endeavors to improve his condition by using dynamite, and when he resists the introduction of improved machinery, or evades the instructions of the Board of Health, namely, ignorance of what is for his own best interest. It is therefore fallacious to assume that every individual knows his own interest best, and in the absence of arbitrary restrictions is sure to follow it. The idea that free competition always develops the highest possibilities by enabling each to do that for which he is best fitted, is equally misleading. The popular idea of free compe- tition is that it means an unconditional struggle for existence among individual units, and that is the sense in which the term is usually employed by economists. This view is commonly re- garded as the application of the doctrine of natural selection to society ; and hence the policy of laissez fairs is claimed to be based upon the doctrine of evolution. This is a mistaken con- ception both of the doctrine of evolution and of the nature and function of competition, as will appear from the following con- siderations. The doctrine -of evolution is simply a theory of growth as distinguished from that of special providence. It teaches that whatever may have been the origin of things, progress towards higher forms of existence in all classes of phenomena takes place in accordance with a law of cause and effect, and that higher and more complex types of formation and the existence of new func- tions, appear only under conditions favorable to their develop- ment. In other words, opportunity for actualizing the potential qualities of higher types is indispensable to progress. There is nothing in this doctrine to warrant the assumption that such op- portunity can always, or even generally be best secured by the new type for itself, through a mere unrestrained struggle for ex- istence. On the contrary, the whole implication is that existing types must prepare the way and therefore create a favorable opportunity for the birth and growth of the higher type. Much of the error in this connection is due to a mistaken use of the phrases " nature " and " natural law." We commonly employ the term nature as if it represented only unconscious cosmic forces as distinguished from conscious human forces. And thus we USE OF THE TERM NATURAL LAW. 289 speak of the products of cosmic forces as natural and the prod- ucts of human device as artificial, just as if human arrangements were necessarily unnatural. The term " natural " applies no more to cosmic than to human forces. The consciousness and intelligence of man are as natural as the unconsciousness of gravitation or of inorganic substances. The term " natural " simply means that which is necessary to or inherent in the constitution of things. It is natural that man should have blood, nerves, and brain, because without these he would not be man, but it is equally natural that stones should not have them, because in that case they would not be stones. So with natural law ; a law is not natural or unnatural because it relates to conscious or unconscious objects, but solely because it relates to the nature and inherent constitution of things. It is just as much in accordance with natural law that under certain conditions electricity destroys our house, as it is that under other conditions it should light our streets. Natural law is simply the order in which phenomena necessarily occur under given conditions. Man cannot impose artificial laws ; he can only artificially change the relations of objects so that through the operation of cause and effect desired phenomena may occur sooner, more frequently and more continuously than they other- wise would. It is in this way, and in this way only, that man is ever able to aid progress. Therefore, in considering whether laissez faire or human inter- vention is to be preferred, the question is not whether one is more natural than the other, because in any case the result will be natural, but it is whether the desired end can be more surely obtained by intervention than by the unaided operation of unconscious forces. And this will depend entirely upon whether those who manipulate the conditions understand the laws of the phenomena with which they are endeavoring to deal, and there- fore can correctly predicate the result. Ignorant or unscientific interference may be worse than laissez faire. But this by no means implies that laissez faire is superior to scientific regulation. Another expression which is misleadingly employed is " natural selection." Here again the term natural is used as if all selection were unnatural that is not blind and unconscious. There are no natural and unnatural selections ; there are wise and unwise 19 2QO NATURAL AND HUMAN SELECTION. selections, and there are conscious and unconscious selections. It is as natural that ignorance will make poor selections as that intelligence will make good ones. Because progress in the physi- cal world has taken place mainly by unconscious selection, it is assumed that progress in society will necessarily be more rapid and continuous under a regime of laissez faire, If it were true that in physical phenomena an unconditioned struggle of units always produces the highest types and the greatest progress, it would not follow that the same should be true in society. But it is by no means clear that this is true even in the physical world. It is of course true that in the development of the earth and other physical formations where surviving forms were determined by the action and reaction of unconscious physical forces, those forms only were able to survive which could withstand the struggle. But it is scarcely less certain that many higher forms may have been destroyed during early stages of their development, which, had they been able to reach maturity, would have been better able to withstand opposing forces than those which did survive. It is highly probable that by this means millions of potentially higher forms were destroyed in their infancy by mature and lower types of formation. Thus under a regime of pure laissez faire the action and reaction of blind physical forces progress may have been greatly retarded, while inferior types for ages perpetu- ated their existence by preventing the development of superior types. Indeed, this is what we see taking place in every domain where laissez faire prevails, and development is left to an un- conditioned struggle for existence among individual units. In the sphere of vegetation for instance, it is now a matter of scientific knowledge that the choicest trees and most highly de- veloped plants of any species may be stunted and even destroyed by the presence of weeds and brush that had prior existence. This is a fact that every scientific farmer and horticulturist under- stands. As an illustration of the law of natural selection and the survival of the fittest, we are pointed to wild animals, say a drove of wild horses. It is assumed that those which survive are always best and that those which were killed off were inferior, from the mere fact that the former lived and the latter died. This conclusion, however, does not necessarily follow from these SURVIVAL OF THE UNFIT. 29! facts. Suppose, for example, a foal, which possessed all the pos- sibilities of being a faster or tougher horse than any in the herd, was kicked in the ribs by one of the inferior though mature horses and fatally injured. It is quite clear that in that case the inferior type would prevent the development of the superior. And this is what is constantly taking place wherever an unre- strained struggle for existence prevails, as all experienced horse- breeders know. By the study of appropriate mating and the protection of the superior young against the violence of the inferior old, speed, strength, and other desired qualities of the horse have been developed to a degree never before known. Thus under scientific selection, the higher possibilities of the horse have been developed incomparably faster than they ever were under natural selection. This is true in every sphere of phenomena to which human knowledge can be applied. In fact, progress everywhere increases directly, as scientific selection can supersede natural selection in proportion as knowledge of rela- tions can be substituted for blind experimentation. Were this otherwise, science and civilization would be no better than igno- rance and barbarism. Clearly therefore laissez faire is not the surest way to promote the survival -of the fittest even in the physical world. In society this is still more uniformly true by virtue of a differ- ent character in the phenomena. One of the most marked dis- tinctions between physical and social phenomena is the manner in which existing units influence the environment of future units. In the lower forms of life the opposition of the inferior mature to the superior immature (the established old to the unestablished new) is limited to a direct struggle between contending units. Consequently, the potentially superior has always a limited chance (say one in a million) of surviving, if only by evading the deadly opposition of an established type. In society this is different, and the chance of the new to escape the repressive power of the old is more difficult. Man, having acquired the power of consciously adapting means to an end, can not only resist the undeveloped new with the advantage of prior possession and mature develop- ment, but he also has the power of manipulating the environment of the subsequent generation so as to make the development of the superior impossible. GOVERNMENT INEVITABLE. One of the prime conditions of human society is consciously regulated order, and this implies government. Government neces- sarily dominates the social environment of the individual. Through social and political institutions, therefore, the opportu- nities for enabling the fittest to survive will necessarily be aided or repressed according to the notions entertained by those who determine the policy of government. By this means, through mere accident of priority, the inferior man can so regulate the conditions of existence for subsequent generations that the de- velopment of the potentially superior shall be impossible, and thus secure the survival of the unfittest instead of the fittest. The history of society is replete with evidences of this fact. Indeed every arrest of social progress is due to the fact that the inferior who obtained possession of authority have so dominated the environment as to cut off opportunity for the development of others, who with favorable opportunities would have been supe- rior to themselves. Under such conditions not only does the unfit survive, but its influence tends to perpetuate the reign of the less fit in two ways. i. By stifling the germs of superiority in humble classes, and thus cutting off the possibility of its develop- ment and actualization. 2: By stereotyping the character of the successful in giving it a monopoly of power and position. 'This is what took place in ancient Egypt, Greece, and Rome, and in mediaeval Europe, where both religious and civil authority was exercised to cut off all opportunity for the development of char- acter in those classes of the community not recognized as noble or royal. The masses, who have ever constituted the laboring classes, have been regarded as an inferior portion of society. Their social inferiority has not only been made a reason for their exclusion from social power and authority, but by destroy- ing the opportunity for actualizing their best possibilities it has been made the means of preventing their development and thus keeping them inferior. Laissez faire, therefore, is literally im- possible in society. There can be no choice between natural selection and human selection, but only a choice between scien- tific human selection and ignorant human selection ; not between government and no government, but only between wise or un- wise government interference. The chief fallacy underlying the doctrine of laissez faire is a ECONOMIC COMPETITION. 293 mistaken notion regarding the nature of competition. Because competition is rivalry between contending units it is assumed that all rivalry is competition, and hence that free competition is simply an unrestrained struggle for existence. As we have already seen, unrestrained struggle may and often does mean repression and despotism instead of development and freedom. It is entirely true that competition is indispensable to develop- ment, but in order to have competition that develops instead of a struggle that destroys, rivalry must take place under conditions which make the object sought reasonably possible to either con- testant. There can be no advantageous competition where the prize is impossible to one and certain to the other. Such an unequal struggle instead of developing the highest possibilities of both competitors, inspires neither contestant to do his best. To have effective competition the contest must be of such a character as to compel the winner and inspire the loser to the maximum degree of effort. This can only occur when the contest takes place between approximately equal competing units. Com- petition between unequals necessarily tends to crush rather than develop the weaker, although he possesses all the potential possi- bilities of superiority. Take, for instance the child of the poor laborer and that of the wealthy merchant. The former is sent to the factory or mine without any education or opportunity for social development ; it is reared in an atmosphere of ignorance, brutality and vice, while the latter receives all the education and incentives for culture that wealth and leisure can supply. When these two children grow up, can there be any inspiring competition between them as citizens for social position, public confidence, or even in the sphere of business, where education and mental training are necessary, indeed anywhere outside the sphere of manual labor ? The difference between them in this respect, which nothing but a difference in their opportunities creates, instead of inspiring both to do their best, will naturally create a feeling of shrinking inferiority in the one and an undue feeling of superiority in the other. These two opposite feelings necessarily tend to give the power of authority to the latter and the submissive position to the former. Clearly therefore instead of laissez faire necessarily securing 294 NECESSITY OF OPPORTUNITY. free competition and " the survival of the most fit," it is the policy which in society is most likely to prevent free competition and to promote the survival of the less fit. It is an indispensable condition to free competition and the maximum development of the competitors, that the contest should be between approxi- mately equal competing units. To secure approximate equality among competitors and hence the success of the superior, we must secure to each the opportunity for developing his best possibilities. In other words, to obtain the inspiring influence of free competition and to develop instead of crushing the potential capacity of the individual we must substitute scientific states- manship for ignorant authority. The question of statesmanship then is not whether or not the state shall interfere in the affairs of society, this it is sure to do so long as society exists, but upon what principle it shall act in order to promote maximum prosperity and freedom in the community. This involves a con- sideration of the economic and social functions of government, which will be the subject of the next chapter. CHAPTER II. THE STATE ; OR, THE NATURE AND FUNCTION OF GOVERNMENT. SECTION I. What is the State? IT is very common to use the term state as if it were synony- mous with society. That such a use of the term is too indefinite for scientific purposes becomes apparent the moment we attempt to consider the functions of the state. It is essential to the idea of society that there be more or less social intercourse- and inter- dependence among the individual units having some recognized common centre of interest and action. This is not true of all mankind. The human race is divided into groups or nations composed of individuals who have more or less social and indus- trial affinity. There is a great diversity of feeling, interest, and action within these groups, but each group has a common inter- est and will take common action as distinguished from any other group or nation. The maintenance of this common interest we call patriotism. Society therefore may be defined as an aggre- gate of individuals in any group, nation, or tribe. We cannot speak of the functions of this aggregate, because in its entirety society never acts. Even under pure communism, where the greatest uniformity of the units prevails, children, minors, and usually though not necessarily, women are excluded from active participation. Thus society as an aggregate never acts except through a more or less extended representation by which a portion acts for the whole. This representative portion, large or small, constitutes the state as distinguished from society ; it is the largest acting aggregate, and the individual is the smallest acting unit. 295 296 NO ABSOLUTE RIGHTS. The state then may be defined as the conscious authoritative expression of society. Since the aggregate is greater than, and includes the individual, the authority of the state necessarily in- cludes and is superior to that of the individual. The state then not only represents the authoritative action of the aggregate (society) as distinguished from that of the individual, but its authority is necessarily absolute over both the individual unit and social aggregate. We often hear such expressions as " absolute rights," " inalien- able rights," etc. Strictly speaking, there are no such rights in society ; not only the right to " liberty and the pursuit of happi- ness," but even the right to life in society is necessarily subject to the will of the aggregate, as authoritatively expressed in the state or government. This is indispensable to the existence of society. Society being an association of individuals whose im- mediate interests are not always identical and whose conceptions of the equity of their relations are frequently very different, the existence of a power superior to both, whose authority shall be absolute, is indispensable to social order. All rights of the indi- vidual in society therefore, must in the very nature of the case, be conditional. Absolute individual rights are a social impossi- bility. It is equally indispensable that these conditions should be de- termined and enforced by the collective authority, the state, since nothing short of that would command the confidence, sup- port, and obedience of the individual units. While the authority of the state is always absolute over both individual units and the social aggregate, it always represents a consensus of both. Although the state is always representative, it does not always represent in the same manner, nor derive its authority in the same way. In some stages of society collective authority is all invested in one person, as in the chief of primitive tribes, and forms an absolute despotism. This is sometimes due to superior physical force, and sometimes to a fiction of divine ap- pointment. In other stages of society authority is invested in a number of individuals by hereditary descent, forming an aris- tocracy or constitutional monarchy, and in others it is vested in a still larger number, chosen by popular vote, forming a democratic republic. But in every case the state represents the ALL GOVERNMENT REPRESENTATIVE. 297 authority of the aggregate. The Czar's proclamation is not the act of a mere individual, but the recognized authoritative expres- sion of Russia. The Pope's edict is not the voice of an individual Italian, but that of the Church. It may be said that one-man-power, as represented by a shah, a sultan, a czar, or a pope, is not representative but despotic. It is indeed despotic, but it is also representative. Representa- tion is to speak and act for others authoritatively. In this sense, despotism is no less representative than is democracy, but its au- thority to act for others is acquired in a different way. The essence of all collective or state authority is that the government derives its "powers from the consent of the governed." The ab- solute authority of the despots who rule Persia, Russia, and Turkey rests upon the consent of the governed as completely as does that of the President or Congress in democratic America. If the Czar of Russia had not the consent and confidence of the Russians, his proclamations would have no more authority in Russia than would those of any other individual. It is because they recognize his fitness to rule (to act for them) that they obey and support him. Their confidence may be misplaced, or may be due to a superstitious belief in his divine appointment as the head of the church and ruler of the nation ; but whatever the reasons, their confidence and consent are none the less complete, as is shown by the fact that they will not only work for him and worship him, but will by the millions fight and die for him. The only difference between despotic and democratic representation is that through poverty, ignorance, and superstition, the consent of the governed under despotism is given by silent acceptance of their rulers as inherently fitted and divinely appointed to govern, while under democracy this consent can only be obtained through the volitional action of the individuals. Thus the essential dis- tinction between despotism and democracy is not that the latter is more representative than the former, but that it is more elective. Poverty, ignorance, and superstition make political and social incapacity inevitable, which in turn make elective represen- tation impossible. Just in proportion as the individual units of a community be- come more intelligent and positive in character, does their con- sent to the authority of the state become less dependent upon 298 ELECTIVE REPRESENTATION. traditional usage and supernatural injunction, and more de- pendent upon individual judgment. Hence it changes from silent acquiescence to conscious choice, and then the repre- sentative function of the state becomes less hereditary and more elective in character. In such countries as Persia, Turkey, and Russia the consent of the governed to the authority of gov- ernment consists entirely in silent acquiescence, while in such countries as Austria, Italy, and Germany, where material condi- tions and the intelligence of the people are more advanced, there is a limited amount of elective representation. In England the elective principle is still more general, and in America it is most general of all, being directly or indirectly applied to every branch of government. But there is no country in which the repre- sentation is all elective. Even in democratic America women are still excluded from elective representation. The state, or col- lective governing authority, sustains exactly the same representa- tive relation to women in the United States as does that of the Czar of Russia or the Shah of Persia to the whole people of those countries. Hence the state, whether despotic or democratic, is always the authoritative expression of the aggregate. This is only another form of stating the principle so frequently emphasized in these pages namely, that all social institutions rest upon the habits and social character of the people. Society, therefore, differs from the individual, in that it represents a literal aggregate of which individuals are the units. The state differs from society and from the individual, in that it is the representative collective action of both, and its authority is absolute over both. In short, the state expresses authoritative social policy. SECTION II. The Relation of the State to the Individual in Progressive Society. In order to ascertain the true relation of the state to the indi- vidual, it is necessary, first of all, to examine the structural con- stitution of society. This brings us directly to the question, is society a higher organism, for whose preservation and develop- ment the individual units are the tributary means, or is it an asso- ciation created by and utilized for the preservation and develop- ment of the individual units composing it ? Upon the answer to GREEK IDEA OF SOCIETY. 299 this question depends the character of statesmanship and the governing principle by which public policy should be shaped and directed. If society is an organic entity, to whose development the individual is subordinate and simply tributary, then the true public policy would be to increase the functions of the state and limit the sphere of individual action and authority. And con- versely, if the development of the individual is the end to pro- mote which society is only a means, the true public policy would be to so mould and direct public institutions as to increase the functions, responsibility, and authoritative sphere of the indi- vidual, and to diminish those of the state. It will be observed that these two conceptions of the relation of the state to the indi- vidual logically lead to opposite theories of statesmanship, the one towards socialism and the other towards individualism. It is a peculiar feature of sociological literature that both socialist and individualist writers assume that society is an organic entity, and that it sustains the same relation to individuals that the individual organism does to the parts of which it is com- posed. This was the controlling idea of the Greeks and Romans, who regarded the state as every thing and the individual as noth- ing, except as he served the state. In his ideal republic, Plato makes the state stand for a great personality, in whom the differ- ent social classes are simply the functions. The ruling class, the military class, and the industrial class are presented as corre- sponding to the faculties of reason, will, and passion or force in the human organism. Upon this point at least, it may be truly said that all that has been written during the last two thousand years has been simply Platonizing. Hobbes endeavored to es- tablish literally by minute detail what Plato only introduced in general outline, by making society a colossal artificial man. He not only made certain classes of the community correspond to the reason, will, and passion of the human organism, but he went so far as to divide society into limbs, joints, nerves, memory, con- science, and even ascribed to it a soul. 1 This idea, with some qualifications eliminating the minutiae of detail introduced by Hobbes, is reaffirmed and extensively elabo- rated on the basis of modern science, by Herbert Spencer. 1 See preface to his " Leviathan ; or, The Matter, Form, and Power of a Com- monwealth, Ecclesiastical and Civil." 3OO SOCIAL ORGANISM THEORY. Therefore Rodbertus had the full warrant of the continuous teachings of philosophy from Plato to Spencer for his basic- socialistic postulate that " the community is the end in itself. In- dividuals are only the means for the promotion of social well- being ; they are in no sense ends in themselves." 1 From this point of view he logically held that public policy should constantly be directed towards putting the ownership of property, especially the means of production into the hands of government. This idea has been more thoroughly developed by Karl Marx, who endeavors to show that from the nature of economic phenomena the ownership of the means of production can only reside in the community, which theory is made the basis for public policy by all shades of socialists. That socialists should readily accept the traditional theory is not surprising, because it sustains their a priori assumption that the state should do every thing. But with Mr. Spencer the case is quite different, as he is the most extreme representative of the individualist school. He regards socialism as slavery, 2 and state ownership and con- trol of industrial enterprises as inimical to progress. Now the supremacy of industrial individualism is incompatible with the existence of a social organism. The question, however, is not whether Mr. Spencer's position on the organic structure of society is consistent with his theory of individualism, but whether it is scientifically and philosophically sound. This is the more im- portant, because Mr. Spencer stands pre-eminently for the scien- tific method of investigation. Indeed, his conclusions upon this point are regarded as the sociological embodiment of the doctrine of evolution, and may be taken as representing those of evolu- tionists generally upon this subject. The fact that Mr. Spencer occupies this leading position in the world of scientific sociology makes a careful consideration of his position on this subject of the utmost importance. In setting forth his reason for conclud- ing that society is an organism, he says : 11 So completely, however, is a society organized upon the same system as an individual being, that we may almost say there is something more than analogy between them. . '. . A still more remarkable fulfilment of this analogy is to be found in the fact, 1 Political Science Quarterly, September, 1889, p. 546. 2 " The Coming Slavery," Popular Science Mnnthly, April, 1884. SPENCER'S THEORY OF SOCIETY. 30! that the different kinds of organization which society takes on, in progressing from its lowest to its highest phase of development, are essentially similar to the different kinds of animal organi- zation." After a detailed illustration of the similarity between society and an individual organism, he says : " Thus do we find, not only that the analogy between a society and a living creature is borne out to a degree quite unsuspected by those who commonly draw it, but also that the same definition of life applies to both. Thus the union of many men into one com- munity ^this increasing mutual dependence of units which were originally independent this gradual segregation of citizens into separate bodies, with reciprocally subservient functions this for- mation of a whole consisting of numerous essential parts this growth of an organism, of which one portion cannot be injured without the rest feeling it may all be generalized under the law of individuation. The development of society, as well as the de- velopment of man, and the development of life generally, may be described as a tendency to individuate to become a thing. And rightly interpreted, the manifold forms of progress going on around us are uniformly significant of this tendency." l In a later work, 2 Mr. Spencer discusses the social organism at still greater length and defends his conception from the inconsis- tencies of the Greeks and also against those of Hobbes. After criticising these writers, he says : " Notwithstanding errors, however, these speculations have considerable significance. That such analogies, crudely as they are thought out, should have been alleged by Plato and Hobbes and many others, is a reason for suspecting that some analogy exists. The untenableness of the particular comparisons above instanced is no ground for denying an essential parallelism ; for early ideas are usually but vague adumbrations of the' truth. Lacking the great generalizations of biology, it was, as we have said, impossible to trace out the real relations of social organiza- tions to organizations of another order." He then discusses the points of general analogy between society and living organisms, which he sums up by saying : 1 " Social Statics," pp. 490, 493, 497. See also " First Principles," pp. 408, 413, 433-437- 2 "Illustrations of Universal Progress," chap. x. * Ibid., p. 391. 302 SOCIETY AND LIVING BODIES. " Thus we find but little to conflict with the all-important analogies. . . . The principles of organization are the same ; and the differences are simply differences of application. Here ending this general survey of the facts which justify the com- parison of a society to a living body ; let us look at them in detail." ' After devoting thirty pages to the discussion of details sustain- ing this analogy he concludes by saying : " Such, then, is a general outline of the evidence which justifies, in detail, the comparison of societies to living organisms. That they gradually increase in mass ; that they become little by little more complex ; that at the same time their parts grow more mutually dependent ; and that they continue to live and grow as wholes, while successive generations of their units appear ar>d disappear, are broad peculiarities which bodies politic display, in common with all living bodies, and in which they and living bodies differ from every thing else." * It will be seen from the foregoing that although Mr. Spencer objects to Hobbes' presentation of the analogy between the social and the human organization, he quite as emphatically holds to the conclusion that society is an organism, whose organic struc- ture is fundamentally the same as that of animal organisms. If this be correct, it of course follows that the relation of the units to the aggregate is the same and that the order of progress in society is the same as in the animal organism. In short, that a biological hypothesis adequately explains sociological phe- nomena. The fact that a theory correctly accounts for one class of phe- nomena does not warrant its application to another, unless it can be shown to adequately explain the new phenomena independently of its use in any other field of investigation. If we examine social phenomena independently of biological hypothesis, we shall find : (i) That although there is a general resemblance be- tween society and the animal organism, the difference between 1 " Illustrations of Universal Progress," pp. 397, 398. * Ibid., p. 428. That this represents Mr. Spencer's views upon the subject is shown by the fact that it is repeated in his latest utterances. See " Sociology." Also correspondence with Huxley in the Times, September, 1889, republished in the Popular Science Monthly, February, 1890. SPENCER'S POSTULATES. 303 them is sufficiently radical and fundamental to destroy the basis for the conclusion that society is an organism. (2) That such an assumption is not necessary in order to apply the theory of evo- lution to social phenomena. It is unquestionably true that there are many points of re- semblance between society and individual organisms, and so there are between individual organisms ajad inorganic bodies. The question, therefore, is not whether there are any points of agree- ment between society and an organism, but whether the points of agreement are sufficiently numerous and fundamental to make them constitutionally identical. Mr. Spencer presents four char- acteristics in which society resembles an individual, which he re- gards as sufficiently fundamental to warrant the classification of society as an organism ; they are : " i. That commencing as small aggregations, they insensibly augment in mass : some of them eventually reaching ten thousand times what they originally were. " 2. That while at first so simple in structure as to be con- sidered structureless, they assume, in the course of their growth, a continually-increasing complexity of structure. " 3. That though in their early, undeveloped states, there exists in them scarcely any mutual dependence of parts, their parts gradually acquire a mutual dependence, which becomes at last so great that the activity and life of each part is made possible only by the activity and life of the rest. " 4. That the life and development of a society is independent of, and far more prolonged than, the life and development of any of its component units, who are severally born, grow, work, re- produce, and die, while the body politic composed of them sur- vives generation after generation, increasing in mass, completeness of structure, and functional activity." ' There can be little doubt that in these four characteristics society resembles the animal organism ; nor can there be any doubt that the first two apply with equal force to inorganic de- velopment. These are as true of the development of inorganic substances as they are of the growth of plants, animals, or society. If, therefore, we are to assume that society is an organism because in these general and important respects it resembles an individual, then may we not say that vegetable and animal bodies are in- " Illustrations of Universal Progress," pp. 391, 392. 304 SPENCER'S ERROR. organic, because, in these fundamental characteristics they re- semble inorganic bodies ; and vice versa. If we should attempt to draw any such conclusion, Mr. Spencer would soon correct us by pointing out that the lower we go in the scale of development the greater is the simplicity and similarity of form. And thus, while in the first two characteristics animal organisms are similar to those of inorganic bodies, in the last two they greatly differ ; for, though mineral substances like organisms, increase in mass and complexity of structure, they do not develop the functional dependence of parts exhibited in the individual organism. 1 If the fact that the individual organism has functional activi- ties different from those of inorganic bodies, establishes the distinction between their classification as organic and inorganic, it follows that a similar difference between the constitution of society and that of an individual organism equally warrants a dis- tinction in their classification. If we examine the constitution of society and the individual organism, we find the following radical distinctions which are quite as great as those between organic and inorganic bodies as pointed out by Mr. Spencer. I. In an individual organism progress consists in the differ- entiation and specialization of functions in which the aggregate tends to gain a more complete control over the action of the parts, such as eyes, ears, teeth, tongues, feet, hands, etc., whereas in society progress consists in a differentiation of functions and definiteness of polity in which the parts constantly tend to acquire an increasing control over the action of the aggregate. II. In an individual organism the end of the parts is to serve and sustain the aggregate or organism, and when they fail to serve that end they become atrophied and disappear, whereas in society the end of the aggregate is to serve and sustain the individual units. III. In an organism, where consciousness and intelligence exist, they reside in the aggregate and never in the parts ; whereas in society consciousness and intelligence reside always in the parts and never in the aggregate. Indeed, the social aggregate has none of the attributes of a conscious entity. 1 ' ' Even such inorganic bodies as crystals, which arise by growth, show no such definite relation between growth and existence as organisms." " Illustrations of Universal Progress," p. 392. SOCIETY NOT AN ORGANISM. 305 IV. In an organism the existence of the parts is subsequent to, dependent upon, and developed through the unconscious action of the aggregate ; whereas in society the aggregate and its polity or representative action, is subsequent to, dependent upon, and de- veloped through the conscious action of the parts. V. In an organism the influences which promote differentiation of function must operate upon the aggregate or organism, and through it affect the parts ; whereas in society the influences which promote differentiation must operate upon the paits or in- dividual units, and through them affect the constitution of the aggregate anoVits active polity. VI. In society conscious wants, intelligence, and will, are the characteristic attributes of the units through which all the in- fluences affecting the differentiation of the social aggregate must finally act ; whereas in the individual organism the units have no such characteristics ; where these characteristics exist at all they are the attributes of the aggregate and not of the units, and in the lower forms of animal and all vegetable organisms they do not exist at all. It will thus be seen that, despite the general resemblance be- tween society and an individual organism, the difference in the functional relation of the parts to the aggregate, and the order of their development, is quite as marked and more fundamental than that between organic and inorganic bodies. The differ- ence between the organic and the inorganic consists mainly in the fact that the complexity of structure and interdependence of the parts are greater in the former than in the latter ; whereas the difference between society and an organism consists in the fact that the units sustain an opposite relation to the aggregate, and that progressive differentiation is in an opposite direction : in society the tendency being to increase the conscious control of the parts over the aggregate, and in an organism to increase that of the aggregate over the parts. So far from being an organic entity, society is only the systematized environment of associated individuals by whom and for whom it is created, and upon whose state of industrial, social, and intellectual develop- ment its existence, form, and character depend. Nor is this view inconsistent with the doctrine of evolution. This theory does not involve the assumption that society is an 306 SOCIAL PROGRESS UNLIKE PHYSICAL. organism. Evolution simply implies a progressive movement from a less to a more definite, coherent, orderly state of existence. But it does not follow that the more complex form must neces- sarily be organic ; since in that case inorganic development would not be evolution. Although evolution implies a greater definite- ness of functional relation, it does not necessarily mean the individualization of the aggregate. It is not strictly correct therefore, to say " the development of society as well as the de- velopment of men and the development of life generally may be described as a tendency to individuate to become a thing." So- ciety does not tend to become a thing, in the sensof an organic entity. Progress in society is not a tendency to individualize the social aggregate, but rather to de-individualize it, making its action more and more the consciously delegated expression of the individual. Indeed, the only individuality which social prog- ress develops is in the units ; institutions are specialized, but man only is individualized as an organic entity. If we regard society as an association of individuals for their common protec- tion and further development, the theory of evolution becomes rationally applicable to social as well as organic and inorganic phenomena. From this point of view the assumption that society is an organism is unnecessary, and the anomaly of creating a colossal social man with increasing despotic power over the individual disappears. Social progress then is seen to be an orderly movement towards greater individual perfection, and per- sonal freedom for man, which accords with universal history. So far as human knowledge goes, the highest individual or- ganism yet developed is man. In every stage of physical development, from the most incoherent homogeneous form known or inferred, the movement has been towards higher and more complex types of formation, each of which tended to make the existence of the next possible. And the crowning product of the whole series of inorganic and organic evolution is man. With the appearance of man began another phase of develop- ment which was neither inorganic nor organic, but SOCIAL. Progress in this sphere does not consist in the unconscious differentiation of an inorganic mass, nor in that of a living organism, but in a systematization of the environment and specialization of the efforts of individuals, which results in a SPENCER UNWITTINGLY SOCIALISTIC. 307 further development of the individuality of the units. It thus appears that man occupies the objective or crowning position in both physical and social evolution ; with this difference however : in the physical world he presents the highest type of an organic aggregate, and in society he occupies the position of a unit. Thus although evolution is fundamentally the same in society as in the physical world, in that it is a move- ment from the simple to the complex, the order of development is reversed ; in the physical world, it is a subordination of the parts to the perfection of the aggregate, and in society it is a subordination of the aggregate to the perfection of the units. In order therefore, to complete Mr. Spencer's statement, that " the development of society as well as the development of man and the development of life generally, may be described as a tendency to individuate to become a thing," we must add, that this individuating tendency ends in the greater individual- ization, not of society, but of man physically as an organism, and socially as a sovereign personality. It is evident, therefore, that the Greek and Roman conception that the state is every thing, the individual nothing ; and the socialistic position logically deduced therefrom, that " the com- munity is the end in itself, individuals being only the means for the promotion of social well-being, and in no sense ends in them- selves " ; and Mr. Spencer's assumption that " society is an organ- ism," are essentially erroneous. In this, as in all other cases of reasoning from mistaken hypotheses, the error only becomes important when the theory is made the basis of action. Like many of the immature postulates of the English economists, already referred to, Mr. Spencer's theory of a social organism unwittingly lays the logical basis for state socialism, a theory which he himself regards as the greatest of modern fallacies. The difference between Rodbertus and Mr. Spencer is precisely the same as the difference between Marx and Ricardo. 1 Marx arrived at the conclusion that profits are robbery by the logical application of the Ricardian postulate that the quantity instead of the cost of labor determines value. And Ricardo avoided the fallacy of Karl Marx only by failing to consistently apply his own postulate. So the theory of state socialism developed by 1 Part III., chap. vi. 308 PROFESSOR CLARK'S VIEW. Rodbertus is logically sustained by the Spencerian postulate that society is an organism, and Spencer avoids the fallacy of social- ism only by disregarding his own hypothesis. We are therefore warranted in concluding that society is not a colossal " artificial man," as affirmed by Hobbes, nor an " organ- ism " as affirmed by Spencer, nor an " end in itself," as affirmed by Rodbertus ; but on the contrary, that it is an association of indi- viduals as a means for the promotion of individual well-being. Indeed the history of government is the history of making and unmaking social institutions in order to render them more subservient to the needs of the social life of the individual. Nor is this view confined to Spencer and the socialists, but it is beginning to be accepted by liberal economists. Thus in his chapter on " The Basis of Economic Law " Professor Clark says : " The analogy between society and the human body was familiar to the ancients. It is a discovery of recent times that a society is not merely like an organism ; it is one in literal fact. . . . Political economy treats not merely of the wealth of individuals who sustain complicated relations with each other, but of the wealth of society as an organic unit." ' In a subsequent chapter (" Theory of Value ") he makes this social organism into an active contracting personality who buys every thing from the individual and sells every thing to him, and says : " Exchanges are always made between an individual and society as a whole. In every legitimate bargain the social organism is a party. Under a regime of free competition, whoever sells the thing he has produced, sells it to society. His sign advertises the world to come and buy, and it is the world not the chance customer that is the real purchaser. Yet it is equally true that whoever buys the thing he needs, buys it off society. ... In the process the social organism is true to its nature as a single being great and complex, indeed, but united and intelligent. It looks at an article as a man would do, and mentally measures the modification in its own condition which the acquisition of it would occasion, or which the loss of it wowld occasion, if once possessed." a It will thus be seen that according to Professor Clark society is not merely an organic entity, but it is a single intelligent be- 1 " Philosophy of Wealth," pp. 38, 39. 2 Ibid., pp. 85, 86. CONFOUNDING METAPHOR WITH FACT. 309 ing. If the analysis of the economic relation of individuals to society presented by Professor Clark is correct, then economic collectivism is scientifically sound and should be accepted as the basis of industrial statesmanship. But is the analysis correct ? Is it true that " exchanges are always made between individuals and society as a whole " ? Do such economic relations actually exist ? Where, how, and under what conditions does society "as a whole " buy wheat, potatoes, shoes, clothes, furniture, etc., from individuals ? When farmers and manufacturers take their products to the market they do not sell them to society, but to individuals, who invariably purchase them either for their own consumption or to resell them to other individuals. Nor does society, as an organism of which individuals " are but atoms," consume any of these products. They are consumed by indi- viduals, and by individuals only. Neither is the statement that " his sign advertises the world to come and buy, and it is the world and not the chance customer that is the real purchaser," any nearer correct, if the term world is used in any other sense than the individuals in the world. The social market simply expresses the aggregate consumption of individuals constituting any social group. Neither is there any truth, except as a metaphor, in the statement that " the social organism is true to its nature as a single being, great and complex, indeed, but united and intelligent. It looks at an article as a man would do, and mentally measures the modification in its own condition." Society, as an entity, does nothing of the kind. All the " mental measurement," all the " intelligence," all the con- scious action, is performed by individuals. A hundred indi- viduals equally intelligent do not constitute a single intelligence a hundred times as great as one. An intellectual giant cannot be made by simply adding mental Liliputians. Intelligence can only be increased by developing it in the individual organism. Notwithstanding the immense advantage of society over isola- tion and it constitutes all the difference between savagery and civilization, there are no facts to warrant the assumption that society is a new acting entity, much less an individual organ- ism. On the contrary, the advantage of society is entirely to individuals through their association with each other. In short, society is an association of individuals for the better promotion 3IO THE FUNCTION OF GOVERNMENT. of their own well-being, and therefore, in studying the law of economic movement we must have for our basis the individual ; in no other way can social progress be promoted. SECTION III. The Function of Government ; or, The Control- ling Principle in Statesmanship, Having seen what the state is and the relation it sustains to the individual, we are now in a position to consider its function as a factor in civilization. Nor will this be a difficult task, if we bear in mind the points already established, namely : that the state is but the representative expression of associated individuals, and that progress in society is a tendency towards the greater indi- vidualization of man, both a physical organism and as a sovereign social personality. As already pointed out, social progress has two fundamental characteristics ; one is economic, the other social. The former is a tendency towards more wealth for the individual ; the latter is towards more freedom for the individual. How to promote the increase of wealth and freedom for the individual therefore, is the problem of statesmanship and the end to which collective authority, or state action, should ever be directed. In considering this question it should be remembered that neither wealth nor freedom can be authoritatively given to the individual ; they must be taken by him. The only way in which the state can give wealth to the individual is by charity. Wealth so acquired, instead of promoting freedom, is one of the most powerful means of preventing it. Charity in any form tends to create obligation, stereotypes dependence, and thereby destroys individuality, and makes freedom impossible. The history of freedom is a history of the increase of the sovereignty of the individual over his own actions and the diminution of that of the state. It is sometimes said " that government is best which governs least." It would be more correct, however, to say that people is best governed which needs the least government. We should be careful, however, not to confound freedom with inde- pendence. The savage is independent of social restrictions, but he has very little freedom. He is in constant danger of his life from the defencelessness of his position. He has no friends because he befriends nobody ; he can obtain no assistance or protection because he assists and protects nobody. Indeed it is VIRTUE OF INTERDEPENDENCE. 31! because he is the least dependent upon his fellows that he is the most helpless and has the least freedom of any man in the world. Mutual dependence is the greatest promoter of freedom. When- ever the freedom of each depends upon the freedom of all, no one has any interest in preventing it, but every one has an interest in extending it. Mutual dependence cancels obligation and extends freedom, while dependence creates obligation and restricts freedom. It is only when everybody's safety depends upon pro- tecting the safety of his neighbor that freedom extends along the whole line of human relations. With the dependence upon authority the case is entirely different. There the obligation is all on one side. It is the relation of creditor and debtor, of the giver and receiver, of the master and ward, and not that of mutual helpers and the receivers of equivalents. Dependence upon authority is scarcely less inimical to freedom than non- dependence upon society. The one involves savagery and the other despotism. It is only the mutual assistance born of indi- vidual interdependence that can make the highest social life and the maximum individual freedom possible. In other words, the highest individualism promotes the most complete co-opera- tion of effort, unity of interest, equity of relations, freedom of action, and complexity of social life. Evidently then, it is the duty of the state to promote in every way possible the develop- ment of the individuality of its citizens, increase their mutual de- pendence upon each other and to decrease their dependence upon the government. Upon what lines should the public policy be directed to accomplish this result ? Paternalism fails to promote this end, because it tends to lessen instead of increase the activi- ties and responsibilities of the individual. Nothing develops power but activity, and nothing creates activity but the necessity for it. We never put forth effort to do for ourselves that which others will do for us. Since inaction is fatal to progress, the in- crease of paternalism is necessarily a great barrier to individual development. Nor is it less erroneous to assume that the sover- eignty of the individual can best be promoted by merely restrict- ing the sphere of governmental activities. It would be as correct to say that the withdrawal of parental care and education from children is the best means for developing the highest manhood. The way to increase the sovereignty of the individual is not to 312 BASIS OF PUBLIC POLICY. arbitrarily lessen the functions of the state, but to make its activities less necessary. The necessity of state action can be minimized only by maximizing the capacity of the individual. To break the egg from without is almost certain to injure if not kill the chick, but when it is broken from within by the increasing power of the chick itself, it only breaks when the chick is strong enough to do without it. So in society ; the authority of the state over the individual should not disappear by weakening the forces without, but by increasing those within him. In short, the indi- vidual is the initial point of social movement. The more intelligent and highly developed the character of the individual, the more capable he is of doing for himself and more reluctant to have others .do for him. Hence, throughout the his- tory of society we see that the greater the ignorance and poverty the more marked is the lack of individuality in the social units ; and the weaker the character of the individual, the more despotic is that of the government. A most significant fact in this move- ment is, that this transfer of authority from the state to the indi- vidual has always been exacted by the individual and reluctantly yielded by the stale. 1 Indeed it is a fundamental principle in both nature and society that man can only continuously have that which he can demand and maintain by force of character. Therefore the increase of wealth and the freedom of the indi- vidual must come through influences which tend to envelop his character, thereby making paternalism less necessary and des- potism less possible. It may therefore be laid down as a fundamental postulate in scientific statesmanship, that the controlling principle in public pol- icy should ever be to minimize the necessary sphere of governmental action and authority, and to maximize the possible sphere of individual action and responsibility. In other words, the function of govern- ment in all phases of industrial, social, and political life is to promote the development of the highest possibilities of the individual. 1 Witness the protracted agitation that is always necessary to extend the rights of the individual in any direction, the right of individual judgment in religion, the right to vote, the right for women to own property, the right to hold public office without regard to religious views, the right to democratic government, the right for women to vote, even in a Republic, etc., etc. DISADVANTAGE OF STATE ACTION. 313 In order to understand the lines of action which the application of this principle involves, it is necessary to consider : (i) Why, on general principle, individual effort and responsibility are pref- erable to state action and authority ; (2) What class of things can be administered better by the state than by the individual ; (3) What line of public policy should be pursued in order to maximize the sphere of individual action and responsibility and thereby minimize the necessity for governmental authority. i. On general principle, individual action and responsibility are preferable to state action or collective authority, because they possess the maximum possibility of directness, efficiency, econ- omy, and equity. State action, being representative whether elective or not, is necessarily indirect and arbitrary. Arbitrary action always involves the maximum amount of inequity and mistakes, because it is necessarily governed by stipulated rules, and therefore cannot be modified to suit the great variety of individual cases. The universal experience of mankind confirms the assumption that whenever individuals can settle their affairs between themselves, the adjustment is most likely to be equitable and mutually satisfactory, and hence the decision of a third party should always be a matter of last resort. This does not mean that all courts and other forms of governmen- tal action, or even war, are unmixed evils ; it only means that they are necessarily clumsy, because arbitrary means of accomplishing the desired end. Indispensable as war may have been, and im- portant as armies, navies, and policemen still are, it is universally admitted that the less the necessity for using them the better. It is because of the injustice which always accompanies battle-field decisions that war diminishes as individuality in the average citizen increases and civilization advances. The same arbitrary element runs through all collective action, though it is some- times indicated in less violent and repulsive forms. Take, for instance, taxation. How to equitably adjust taxation has been a perplexing problem since human society began. It is because taxes are levied by representative authority, according to some arbitrary rule which is utterly incapable of being adapted to a very great variety of conditions, that injustice is constantly being done to numerous individuals and frequently to whole classes. The same principle shows itself in our best courts THE DIVIDING LINE IMPORTANT. of justice, notwithstanding the jury system and the immense learning of advocates and judges. When a case is given to a jury the legal limits to their decision are fixed by the judge in his charge. They may think the defendant morally innocent or actually justified in his act, but by virtue of a legal technicality they are forced to vote him guilty and subject him to a punish- ment which both individually and collectively they would regard as unjust. And so on through the whole history of legal de- cisions. It is because of this preponderating probability of legal inequity that in civil cases wherever disputants can adjust the difference themselves they are generally encouraged to do so by the court. State action being necessarily arbitrary, and hence seldom capable of the highest efficiency, economy, and equity, it is important to consider what class of things, if any, can natu- rally be administered by the state better than by individuals, and vice versa. 2. Since association is better than isolation, and since govern- ment is necessary to society, it follows that while there are many things which the individual can do better than the state, there are some things which the state can do better than the indi- vidual. How shall we determine between the sphere of state and individual action ? If we take an extreme case from either class, there, is no difficulty in deciding to which sphere it naturally belongs. For instance, if it is a question of determining one's own religious opinions, we have now no difficulty in deciding that it belongs entirely to the individual. And on the other hand ? if it is a question of public defence, such as requires an army and navy, we have no difficulty in deciding it to be clearly one of the functions of the state. But when we come to the outer edges of these spheres of action where they merge together, the line of demarcation is not so easily observed. Here a new difficulty arises, because this is not only the point where a wise decision is most important, but also where the material for making a wise decision is most difficult to obtain. Although there is no differ- ence of opinion to-day as to whether or not the individual should choose his own religion or the government should control the army, there is an immense difference of opinion as to whether telegraphs, banks, mines, and railroads should be conducted by private enterprise or under state control. The difference be- SPHERE OF INDIVIDUAL ACTION. 315 tween the administration of the post-office and that of the tele- graph is so slight that public management of the former is made the basis for demanding state control of the latter. And if we have nothing upon which to base our decision but the facts in the two particular cases, it will be very difficult to decide. And if government control is extended to the telegraph, the question between that and the railroad becomes equally difficult to deter- mine. The steps from the railroad to the mine, from the mine to the farm, from the farm to the factory, are all equally short and, of themselves, difficult to determine. It is necessary there- fore, to have some broader generalization upon which to base our decision than the data which each individual case furnishes. This can only be found by viewing each individual case in the light of the general class to which it belongs. Since in the progress of society there is a constant tendency to transfer functions from one sphere to another, it is in the distinctive characteristics of these functions that we must seek the principle governing the line of demarcation between the proper sphere of state and indi- vidual authority, and thus be able to establish a scientific basis for determining whether or not in any given instance the sphere of state action should be extended or restricted. If we study the evolution of society from its homogeneous form, in which every thing was done by authority, to its present highly complex state, where most things are done by individual enterprise, we can readily see the leading characteristics of those functions which tend to pass from the state to the individual and those which tend to become recognized as distinctively the func- tion of government. Among the things which have indisputably passed to the sphere of individual authority are the right to per- sonal freedom, the selection of one's partner in life, and the charge of one's own children, the right of free speech, and of making industrial contracts. The reason why these are relegated to the individual is that in all such cases there are many subtleties in which the individual is more directly interested, and about which he is more com- petent to decide than any third party can possibly be ; and these subtleties increase with the advancing complexity of social rela- tions. Moreover in many of these intricate personal relations the decision must be made at once in order to be effective, 316 SPHERE OF STATE ACTION. and therefore can be made only by the individual himself. The arbitrary, red-tape character of government action neces- sarily precludes complete knowledge of detail and the prompt action necessary in such cases. Although no individual is yet perfect in this regard, he has infinitely greater possibilities of be- coming so than any form of representative authority can pos- sibly have. This is equally true of economic relations. In the early stages of society, when industry was very simple, being practically limited to agriculture, with crude hand-methods of production, it could be conducted by collective authority. But as wants were multiplied and occupations differentiated, economic relations grew more involved, and a more special knowledge became necessary, which made arbitrary administration very much less efficient. Consequently the ownership of property and the administration of productive enterprise gradually pass from public to private ownership and control, or from the sphere of state to that of individual authority, in proportion as the division of labor, the concentration of productive effort, and the social freedom of the individual increased. On the other hand, although governments have radically changed their character, certain functions have been relegated to them by common consent. Among these are protection against a common enemy, the maintenance of public order, the protection of individual rights, the enforcement of contracts, the administration of justice, the maintenance of public roads, canals, bridges, parks, museums, libraries and the enforcement of sanitary regulations. Nor is the reason for this difficult to understand. The administration of the army, navy, police, and the like, is pre- eminently the function of the state, because in such things effec- tiveness lies in the maximum aggregation of physical force, and this can be best obtained by all acting as one man under a single leader. Indeed the most perfect military force involves the maximum despotism and the minimum individuality, and hence can always be exercised most efficiently by arbitrary authority. The maintenance of public order, the enforcement of contracts, and the administration of law are also functions which can be best performed by the collectivity, for the reason that it acts uniformly for all, and its decisions are backed by the power of PUBLIC AND PRIVATE FUNCTIONS DEFINED. 317 all. Nor does the development of individual character tend to transfer the functions of the soldier, the policeman, the judge, and the jailor from the authority of the state to that of the individual. On the contrary, while it tends to make these functions unnecessary, so long as they are needed they can be better performed by the state than by the individual. The same is true of public highways, such as roads, canals, bridges, sanitary regulations, etc. They are common conven- iences which everybody needs, and their management is of the simplest character. To keep such public conveniences in repair calls for no special skill, and changes in method are so slow and infrequent that no inconvenience is experienced by having them under control of routine authority. Although unlike military and police functions, these do not diminish but steadily increase with the advance of civilization, there is no tendency to put them under individual control. The reason for this is that while these can be managed as well by the state as by the individual, the former has the additional advantage of giving greater freedom to travel by obviating the inconvenience of direct payment in the form of tolls, etc. And since these functions relate only to securing the maximum safety and convenience to individual enterprise and mobility, there is no incentive for individuals to undertake them because they have no interest in doing so. It may therefore be laid down as a general principle, that in proportion as social functions are complex, variable, and personal in their nature and interest, requiring instant decisions and expert skill, individual management is superior to state author- ity, and conversely, only in proportion as functions are simple, permanent, and arbitrary in their character, and impersonal in their nature and interest, can they be efficiently performed by the state. In other words, the functions of the state are essentially protective, judiciary, educational, and impersonal in their nature ; hence, all economic and social functions which are essentially personal, productive, commercial, or experimental in their nature properly belong to the sphere of individual action and responsibility. 3. This brings us to the consideration of the third proposition, namely, what line of public policy should be pursued in order to maximize the sphere of individual action and responsibility, and 318 PROTECTION AND PATERNALISM. thereby minimize the necessity for governmental authority. The doctrine that the state should do for the individual only such things as he cannot do as well for himself, of course implies that it should continue to do all those things which it can, under exist- ing conditions, do better than he. Hence, it does not follow that because the natural functions of the state are protective, judiciary, educational, and impersonal, that it should never perform any others. On the contrary, the state must continue to do whatever the individual is incapable of doing as well. The state should re- linquish no function until it can be performed as well or better by the individual ; otherwise many social duties would be abandoned alto- gether and progress greatly retarded. Paternalism in government is a necessary substitute for individual capacity, and consequently increases as we descend and diminishes as we ascend the scale of civiliza- Therefore, whenever it is necessary for the state to perform paternal functions doing for the individual, it should always be regarded as a temporary duty, to be transferred to the indi- vidual as rapidly as he acquires the capacity to perform it. In .the last analysis then, while it is the duty of the government to do those things for the individual which he cannot do as well for himself, the governing principle in public policy should ever be to protect and enlarge those OPPORTUNITIES, and to promote those influences which tend to develop the highest possibili- ties of the individual to do for himself. There is one other point worthy of note before passing to the application of this principle to the various phases of industrial and social life namely, the importance of distinguishing between paternal and protective functions. This distinction is indeed in- dispensable to scientific statesmanship. To confound the pater- nal with the protective principle in government is to destroy all philosophic basis for a public policy, yet this is commonly done by many of the ablest writers. For instance, such writers as Senior, Spencer, and the leading English economists oppose state regulation of the hours of labor, the sanitary conditions of workshops, employment of women and children in mines and factories, compulsory education of factory children, and free public schools, as being paternal legislation. They thus fail to recognize any difference between the policy of furnishing the DISREPUTE OF ENGLISH ECONOMICS. 319 child with wholesome sanitary surroundings and an education, and that of furnishing him with food, clothes, and shelter. 1 It is really this unphilosophic opposition to reform which has brought the doctrines of the English school into such disrepute among the more liberal and sympathetic portion of the commu- nity, and which in its reaction has given much plausibility to socialism. Indeed it has made individualism the synonym for anti-reform and its antithesis socialism the means of reform. Orthodox economists reason that because paternalism is in- jurious, protection should be abandoned; while, on the other hand, socialists conclude that because protection has been advanta- geous individualism should be abandoned and paternalism adopted. By overlooking the distinction -between protection and paternalism, we are logically driven to one of two unscien- tific theories of statesmanship laissez faire or socialism. The distinction between paternalism and protection is that a paternal policy implies doing the maximum for the individual, while a protective policy implies providing the individual with the maximum opportunity to do for himself. If this difference were clearly recognized the obvious error in the anti-reform atti- tude of let-aloneism and the stultifying influence of paternalism would be obviated. The duty of the state as essentially pro- tective and educational in the widest sense of the term would be easily understood. With this as the basis of public policy, the state can always be scientifically used as a means of promoting progress without hindering the growth of individual freedom. 1 This mistake is strikingly illustrated by Buckle in his able arraignment of what he calls the protective spirit in France as contrasted with the non-protective spirit in England. The truth is, however, that what Buckle was denouncing in France as protection, was paternalism. It was a reign of bureaucracy in which the state endeavored to do the maximum for the individual instead of enabling the individual to do the maximum for himself. The contrast was not between protection in France and laissez faire 'in England, but a contrast between pater- nalism in France and protection in England. See " History of Civilization," vol. i., chapters ix. and x. See also Spencer's "Coming Slavery," Popular Science Monthly, April, 1884. CHAPTER III. THE PRINCIPLE OF INTERNATIONAL TRADE. SECTION I. Increasing Social Opportunity Necessitates National Development. IN the preceding discussion four facts have been established : (i) That social progress is development of the character and sovereignty of the individual, to which end government is but a means. (2) That the let-alone doctrine is theoretically unscien- tific and practically impossible in society ; a negative government being a contradiction in terms. (3) That since paternalism limits the need of the individual to do for himself, it hinders rather than helps the development of individuality. (4) That freedom can only be increased by the growth of individual capacity, which in turn depends upon the opportunities for de- veloping individual character. In order to apply these principles to the various phases of social and industrial life it is necessary at the outset to under- stand what constitutes opportunity. In the first place it should be remembered that we are dealing with man as a social being ; hence it is only with the development of his character as a social individuality that we are concerned. Indeed this constitutes all the difference between savagery and civilization. Opportunity then, is necessarily social, and must be sought in man's social environment in his intercourse with his fellow-men. And since progress in society as elsewhere, is the movement from a rela- tively simple to a relatively complex state of existence, the social environment necessary to constitute opportunity must be con- stantly increasing in complexity. Social opportunity, therefore, 320 WHAT OPPORTUNITY IMPLIES. 321 may be stated as necessary contact with an increasing variety of social influences. 1 Society then, is a necessary prerequisite to individual advance- ment. Society does not mean merely an aggregation of human beings, but such an association of individuals as shall make fre- quent intercourse and mutual dependence between them certain. This implies the segregation of the human race into groups or nations in which the individuals have some industrial, social, and political affinity, without which the contact necessary to individual growth is impossible. Consequently the doctrine of increasing opportunity for individual development includes not only the re- lation of individuals to each other within a social group or nation, but also the development of the nation as a political entity. Although patriotism and the desire for national autonomy is a prominent feature in the statesmanship of every country, there is no recognized principle by which its policy should be governed. What relation the industrial development of the nation sustains to the civilization and freedom of the people ; why, and under what conditions national and industrial autonomy is necessary to industrial development, and what relation industrial and indi- vidual development sustain to each other, are questions to which neither economic nor political science has hitherto furnished any adequate answer. When we recognize the fact however, that a nation is but the social setting of the individual and that gov- ernment is but a means by which the resources of the nation are utilized for promoting the welfare of the individual, the im- portance of considering the development of the nation as a necessary means for promoting the progress of society at once becomes apparent. SECTION II. National Development Necessitates the Growth of Manufacturing Industries. In considering this question it is important at the outset clearly to understand what we mean by the expression, national develop- ment. It is commonly assumed that the development of the material resources of a country, as agriculture, mining, or manu- facture, is necessarily the development of the nation. This view confounds the physical qualities of soil and climate with the 1 "Wealth and Progress," pp. 231, 232. 21 322 THE NA TION IS SOCIAL. social qualities of the people which are essentially different. Such reasoning logically makes the industrial pursuits, and hence the social life, of the people depend upon the physical character- istics of the country. Thus instead of subordinating nature to man it subordinates man to nature, which is the reverse of all progressive tendencies in social evolution. When we separate physical from social phenomena and recognize the nation as the people this difficulty is obviated ; it then becomes evident that the social development of man is an end to which the physical development of nature is but the means. In considering the development of a nation therefore, the prime question is not development of the natural resources of the country, but development of the character of its people. The mere fact that the soil of a country is prolific is not a suffi- cient reason why all the people should become agriculturists. The cultivation of the soil or of any material resource of a country should be made subordinate to the cultivation of man. In other words, the development of a nation consists in the development of its civilizing and individualizing influences. To the extent that the people of a nation are isolated in their occu- pations and daily life, will their social progress be slow ; and the less frequent intercourse between individuals the less social- izing will its influences be. In order then, to increase the socializing influences of a nation, it is necessary first of all to promote the concentration of its population. Nor can this be accomplished by mere arbitrary authority. People will not con- centrate either in their social life or industrial pursuits merely because they are advised or ordered to do so. The concentration of population means greater complexity of social life, which is what man is apt to avoid except under the pressure of some desire or necessity. It is proverbial that the savage shrinks from the customs of civilization, and the rural peasant from contact with city life. Indeed, people whose social life is simple, always endeavor to avoid close intercourse with those in highly developed society, because it means new and at first, embarrassing experiences. Nothing will induce people to encounter the difficulties of a new environment but the strong desire for some object not otherwise obtainable. So long as people can gratify their desires without IMPORTANCE OF CITIES. 323 facing the difficulties of new and more complex social relations, they will continue to do so. Nothing will permanently centralize a people which does not make concentration indispensable to getting a living. Thus social concentration depends upon indus- trial concentration. The possibility of concentrating employ- ments depends upon the nature of the industry. Agricultural occupations cannot possibly be centralized ; they are isolating in their very nature, and hence are essentially non-socializing in their influence. The only industries which tend to centralize and socialize people are manufacturing. Social isolation is as impossible with manufacture as is social concentration with agriculture. The development of manufacturing industries then, is an indispensable condition to national development and social progress. The development of manufacturing industries is important in many respects. In the first place because it involves socializing occupations. Factory methods of production bring people into close social contact in the ordinary pursuits of industrial life. Whatever compels people to work together, makes their living in close proximity indispensable ; the modern city and all that it implies is chiefly the product of these two facts. From time immemorial the growth of manufacture and trade has been the means of developing towns and cities, 1 and these industrial centres have in turn ever been the nurseries of civilization. It is always in the cities that the most complex social environment arises, and it is always there that the greatest refinement and highest individuality exists, and hence it is there that the successful struggles for social, religious, and political freedom have always taken place. The difference therefore, between agricultural and manufac- turing employments is very marked. Agriculture is essentially isolating and non-socializing as an occupation, and its products relate almost exclusively to physical wants. Hence it does practically nothing either to create or supply the social wants and life of man. Manufacture, on the contrary, relates almost exclusively to the civilizing and refining side of man's character. The supply of clothing, furniture, the development of archi- tecture, music, literature, art, and every thing above the mere 1 \Vitness the free cities of the Middle Ages. 324 ECONOMIC OPPORTUNITY. physical needs of the savage, is directly or indirectly the result of manufacture and its socializing influence. These things are not only necessitated by man's higher social wants, but are largely consumed as the result of his social relations. Since manufacturing industries tend both to create a socializing en- vironment and to supply the social wants resulting therefrom, they are doubly indispensable to national development. SECTION III. Necessary Conditions to the Development of Manufacture. In discussing the economic and social wisdom of any public policy, the two important questions to consider are : (i) What is the end we desire to promote ? (2) What means will most surely promote that end ? 1. It may be safely assumed that the desired end, to the promo- tion of which statesmanship should be devoted and public policy directed, is the material and social progress of the people. We have already seen that this involves the development of the nation as a political entity, and also that national development necessi- tates social concentration and industrial diversification, which in turn depend upon the growth of manufacturing industries. The immediate question, therefore, for the practical statesman to consider is, what will best promote the development of manufac- turing industries. Whatever will promote this end will justify the means necessary to its adoption. The question to ask is not what will it cost ? but will it do it? 2. It is a universal law in nature arid society that growth depends upon opportunity. As already explained, opportunity is not to be interpreted as mere passive possibility, but as actual inducement. In nature opportunity for growth means the exist- ence of conditions and influences which make it easier to grow than not to grow. In society, it is contact with positive social influences which make refinement, knowledge, and general culture easier and more advantageous than ignorance and crudeness ; and in economics it is the existence of conditions which make it more profitable to do than not to do. Opportunity for the development of manufacturing industries therefore, means the existence of conditions which make manufacture not only physi- cally possible but economically profitable. NEED OF A HOME MARKET. 325 Obviously the first condition necessary to the growth of any industry is a market for its products. Now an economic market evidently cannot be made by mere fiat of government because it depends on the habits and social life of a people. But it can be preserved by protecting home industry in manufacturers to a cer- tain extent. How far? Why just so far as is necessary to prevent home products from being undersold by the products of lower paid laborers in other countries. This then is the sober rule and principle of protection as ministering to human welfare. The industries of a country should be protected to the full amount of the difference between the wage-level of that nation and the nations below it in average civilization using similar methods and no further, since thus the maintenance of its place in civilization is secured. A restric- tive policy can be justified only on the ground that it will promote greater social advancement than would otherwise occur. Nothing can justify the restriction of freedom except a demonstration that it will ultimately promote more freedom. Will the protection of the home market increase the opportunities for developing social- izing industries ? This is the immediate question to consider and it involves a number of most important questions, which will be taken up in their order as follows : (i) The economic and social superiority of the home market over the foreign ; (2) the economic basis of international competition ; (3) the relation of cost of production to international value ; (4) the effect of a tariff upon the price of home products ; (5) the relation of tariffs to wages in non-protected industries ; (6) the influence of pro- tection in the most advanced countries upon the progress of less civilized countries. SECTION IV. The Economic and Social Superiority of a Home Market over a Foreign. There are three important reasons why home markets are supe- rior to foreign markets, and why domestic trade and manufacture should always be encouraged in preference to foreign: (i) Because foreign trade is essentially wasteful ; (2) because foreign mar- kets tend to enable employers to permanently profit by low wages ; (3) because home markets most surely promote the diversification of industry and social progress. 326 FOREIGN TRADE WASTEFUL. i. Foreign trade is essentially wasteful because it necessarily tends to maximize instead of minimizing the distance between the raw material and the factory, and between the factory and the market. For instance, before the development of cotton manu- facture in this country, our cotton cloth was made in England. The raw cotton was produced in South Carolina, sent to England to be manufactured, then brought back to America. The con- sumer of cotton cloth in this country had to pay the cost of transporting it twice across the Atlantic, which was so much waste made necessary by uneconomic conditions. To carry a product six thousand miles in order to deliver it to consumers a hundred miles away is to perpetuate the most costly way of doing. Nothing can justify such waste except absolute inability to avoid it. The mere fact that England could, under existing con- ditions, do the manufacturing at so much less cost than we, as to be able to pay the transportation both ways, was no economic justification for our continuing to buy cotton cloth of her, instead of developing the methods for making it ourselves. Indeed such a policy would have been as obviously uneconomic as to have per- sisted in using the hand-loom and stage-coach in preference to the factory and railroad. The question in that case was not, can England, under existing conditions, supply our cotton cloth cheaper than we can make it ? but can we, by any change of conditions, develop the means of making it as cheaply for our- selves as she can make it for us, and thus eliminate for all time the unnecessary cost of double transportation ? This question was answered in the affirmative, and to-day cotton cloth can be made as cheaply here as in England, and more cheaply than in any other country, notwithstanding our wages are so much higher. Consequently that economic waste is saved not only to us, but to all future generations, to say nothing of the social advantage of developing the industry in our own country. It may be laid down as a fundamental principle in economic production that all commodities should be manufactured as near as possible to the raw material, or the market for finished products. If a nation possesses the raw material for a given article, it should always develop the facilities for manufacturing the finished product for its own consumption ; and any public policy which does not tend to promote this end is inimical to FOREIGN' MARKETS AND HOME WAGES. $2? national development. Therefore, instead of constantly en- couraging foreign trade, it should ever be a cardinal principle in statesmanship to develop domestic trade and home manufacture. 2. Another disadvantage of foreign as compared with home markets is, that they divorce the economic interest of the em- ployer and the employed. To the extent that the producers in any community rely upon a foreign market for their wares, the employers cease to have any economic interest in the welfare of their own laborers. Whenever the employer is independent of the laborers of his own country as consumers, he has an apparent interest in keeping down wages, because, under those circum- stances, every reduction of wages is an increase of profits. Sup- pose, for instance, an American shoe manufacturer sells all his product in Europe at a dollar a pair ; it is quite obvious that if he can obtain his labor at 10 per cent, less, it would be so much addition to his net profit, because the reduction of wages would in no way affect the consumption of his shoes, they being sold in another country where wages remain the same. Under a home-market regime the case is very different, be- cause in domestic trade there are no influences that militate against the material welfare of the laborers which do not react upon that of the employing class. The obvious reason for this is that no market for factory-made products can be permanently sustained without consumption by the laboring classes. Conse- quently when the employing class in any country have to rely on a home market for the sale of their products, their own prosperity depends directly upon the consuming capacity, and hence the wages, of the laboring classes in their own country. Under such conditions, whatever reduces wages and impairs the purchas- ing power of the laborer diminishes the market and undermines the prosperity of the employer. Thus, under a home-market regime, the employer's success is dependent upon and commen- surate with the prosperity of the laboring classes, because their consumption determines the market basis for his production. But the days of foreign markets, as the chief support of highly developed manufacturing industries in any country, are doomed. Frequency of travel and familiar intercourse between the most civilized nations tend to make exclusive knowledge of productive methods practically impossible. Hence, as fast as nations be- 328 A NATION IS RICH BY WHAT IT USES. come consumers of manufactured products, they begin to make them for themselves, and to use the improved methods developed by thfeir most advanced neighbors. Thus the tendency of civili- zation is to make the industries of all countries depend more and more upon home consumption. The economics of the future must be the economics of large production, home-market, and high wages, which are the only industrial conditions compatible with social freedom and political democracy. 3. The third and by no means the least important reason why home markets are preferable to foreign markets is, that they more surely promote the diversification of production and the sociali- zation of employments. One of the popular notions regarding foreign trade is that the prosperity of a nation is indicated by the amount of its exports, that it is rich by what it sells. This is a great mistake. Nothing indicates the prosperity and well-being of a people but what they consume. A nation may produce ex- tensively and export largely and the mass of its people remain very poor. To the extent that more manufactured products are exported from any country than imported to it, are its products not consumed by those who produce them. The prosperity of a nation therefore, cannot be measured by the wealth it exports to other countries, nor by the wealth it receives through the profits of foreign trade, but only by the wealth its own people consume, since that is all which really enters into their social life. Thus the extent of domestic consumption the home market is the real measure of the social status. Moreover, a home market supplies a double social current, whereas a foreign market for the same products only supplies a single current. In addition to the socializing effect of manufac- ture upon industry, the home use of manufactured articles tends to increase and diversify the market for such products by the social conditions necessarily connected with their consumption. For instance, the consumption of carpets, pictures, music, millinery, etc., imply more or less refined social relations, which stimulate not only the desire for more of the same kind of things, but also create tastes and desires for fresh varieties of products. Thus, while manufacturing industries always socialize, their so- cializing influence is necessarily the greatest where they produce for a home market. This must not be interpreted to mean that TEST OF ECONOMIC CHEAPNESS. 329 foreign markets are a disadvantage under all conditions, but only that wherever the development of a home market is possible it is always preferable to a foreign market. In other words, foreign trade is ultimately an economic disadvantage to a nation unless it can take place without substituting simpler for relatively com- plex industries or lowering wages, and should be encouraged under no other conditions. SECTION V. The Economic Basis of International Compe- tition. Competition is regarded as essential to industry, because it pro- motes economy in the production of wealth both by developing the highest capacity in the producers and by reducing prices, thus giving the community the advantage of the highest skill and the best productive methods. This unexceptionable proposition has the advantage of being one of the most uniformly accepted postulates in economic science. Here then we have a point of common agreement, namely, that no competition can promote industrial well-being which does not tend to make wealth cheap. (Neither a free trade nor a protective policy therefore can be economically justified, except as it squares with this proposi- tion.) In order to apply this test to public policy, however, it is necessary to understand clearly what constitutes cheap wealth, and how to determine accurately when commodities are cheap or dear. Commodities are said to be dearer as their value rises, and cheaper as their value falls ; but the terms dearer and cheaper have no meaning except as they indicate that the articles referred to have become more or less difficult for man to obtain. Wheat cannot be either cheap or dear to potatoes or gold, any- more than Easter bonnets can be cheap or dear to fishes. The value of wheat may be high or lo\v as compared with that of potatoes or gold, but value cannot be high or low to those articles ; it can be high or low only to man. Nor is the value of an article high or low to man because it will exchange for a larger or smaller quantity of gold or other commodities, but solely be- cause it will exchange for a larger or smaller quantity of his labor. In short, the terms value, price, exchange, dearness, and 33O CHINESE AND AMERICAN PRICES. cheapness have absolutely no meaning, and convey no idea except in relation to man. From this point of view the importance of economic movement does not turn upon the relation of one kind of wealth to another, but depends upon the relation of all kinds of wealth to man. Wealth is not necessarily cheap or dear according as it will ex- change for a large or small amount of gold, but only as it will exchange for a large or small amount of labor. That is to say, no matter what the ratio of exchange between different com- modities or between all commodities and gold may be, they are cheap or dear only in proportion as a large or small amount can be obtained for a day's service. It may be said that the ratio in which commodities exchange for gold always indicates the ratio in which they will exchange for labor ; that is to say, the gold-price always indicates the labor-price. This may be true to a limited extent within any given country, but it is almost never true as between different countries. Take, for example, this country and China ; suppose shoes of a given quality were two dollars a pair in this country and they were only fifty cents a pair in China, manifestly the amount of gold necessary to obtain a pair of shoes in America would purchase four pairs in China. Thus according to the gold standard of measurement shoes in America would be three hundred per cent, dearer than those in China, which is precisely what the current doctrine teaches us to believe. Consequently it is laid down as a self-evident proposition, that any discrimina- tion which would prevent the shoes of China from entering the market of America at less than two dollars a pair would make the shoes of the American consumer dearer by three hundred per cent.; therefore, the true economic policy is to have free trade between America and China, and thus enable the American citizen to have cheap shoes. If we examine such a transaction from the standpoint of man instead of gold, the utter fallacy of such a position will at once be apparent. To be sure the shoes in America cost two dollars a pair, but as the American mechanic receives two dollars a day he can obtain a pair of shoes for a day's labor, while in China, although the shoes cost but fifty cents a pair, the laborer receiv- ing less than ten cents a day must work fully five days to obtain CHEAP LABOR-PRICES ARE HIGH. 331 a pair of shoes. Thus while measured in gold, the shoes in America cost four times as much as those in China ; measured in labor, the Chinese shoes are four hundred per cent dearer than the American. Manifestly the two-dollar American shoes are cheaper for Americans than the fifty-cent Chinese shoes are for Chinamen. Professors Sumner and Perry would probably reply yes, but Chinese shoes would be cheaper for Americans than American shoes are, because we could get four pairs of Chinese shoes for the amount of service we now give for one pair. It is, they would add, just because the Chinese can make shoes for Americans cheaper than Americans can make them for them- selves, that we want free trade in order that we may obtain our shoes from those who can make them cheapest. Why should we give the shoemakers of Lynn or Marblehead two dollars for what we can buy from those of Pekin or Hong Kong for one dollar ? This argument has a very satisfactory seeming, but it has the disadvantage of failing to reckon with the facts. Like the Ricardian theory, that " profits can only rise as wages fall," it would be true provided the assumption upon which it is based were correct namely, that every thing else remains the same. Of course the American consumer would receive a net gain by purchasing his shoes from China at fifty cents a pair, instead of paying two dollars in America, if wages and other conditions remained the same, which would be an impossibility. It would be just as rational to say that ' other things remaining the same,' a brick will not sink to the bottom of a bucket of water. It is precisely because no two particles of the water remain the same that the brick sinks ; the disturbance caused by introducing the brick makes a readjustment of every drop of water necessary. The same is true in the case before us. The introduction of Chinese shoes into the American market would not merely give the two-dollar American laborer one dollar shoes, but to the extent that it operated, would make it a general industrial dis- turbance and therefore cause a readjustment of economic rela- tions. As already stated, whatever undersells succeeds, and whatever succeeds becomes permanent, and whatever becomes permanent establishes the methods by which its success is accomplished. Therefore if the shoemakers of China could undersell the shoemakers of America in the American market, 332 READJUSTMENT ON A LOWER PLANE. they would necessarily succeed in obtaining the custom of Amer- ican consumers. If this caused no other change than to reduce the price of shoes in this country, the case would be very simple, and the logic of the laissez-faire economist would be conclusive ; but this is not the case. On the contrary, it would make an entire rearrangement of industrial conditions necessary, at least so far as the 200,000 of American shoemakers are concerned. As soon as American consumers begin to buy shoes from China several forces will begin to operate, which will tend to revolutionize and ultimately readjust economic relations. The American manufacturer will endeavor to compete with the China- man in the American market, to do which he will be compelled to reduce the cost of producing shoes here at least to the level of the cost of production in China, together with the cost of trans- portation. This could only be accomplished in one of two ways, either by using superior labor-saving machinery or by reducing wages equal to the difference. The improved machinery could not be adopted for any such reason, because nothing has oc- curred to increase the market sufficiently to make its profitable employment possible. A slight increase in the consumption of shoes might result from lowering the price, but that would soon be more than offset by the reduced consumption among the discharged laborers. Hence it is manifest that such a change could do practically noth- ing to create the better machinery necessary to make a differ- ence in the cost of production. The only other alternative would be to reduce the wages of shoemakers here to substantially the same level as those in China. And this would not be limited to the men who simply manufacture the shoes, it must also apply to all those who produce the raw materials and tools used in making shoes. When this reduction occurs, all the cheapness of the imported shoes disappears, because the capacity of American la- borers to purchase shoes is reduced exactly as much as the price of the shoes has fallen. If wages are not reduced, then the China- man would produce the shoes and the American shoemaker would be forced into idleness, unless he emigrates to China, in which case he would have to work on the same terms as the Chinaman. Nor is there any warrant for assuming that the discharged laborer will find another occupation. Nothing will create em- LOW WAGES NEVER CHEAPEN WEALTH. 333 ployments except a market for products. Since nothing has occurred in this instance to create either a demand for new commodities or increase the consumption of existing ones, we have no more right to assume that the discharged laborers could find new occupations than we have to assume that they could live in luxury without employment. Thus in thelast analysis the shoes would either have to be made in China or in America by Chinese methods ; and in either case, American wages would be adjusted to Chinese prices. Consequently, instead of the low- priced products from China giving us cheap wealth in America, it would serve only to give us cheap labor and a lower civilization. It may be regarded as an economic axiom that nothing can perma- nently cheapen wealth which does not reduce the price of commodities relatively to wages, and this can never be accomplished by substituting cheaper for dearer labor, either at home or abroad. Nor is this all. Not only is it true that the low-priced shoes of China would not be permanently cheaper to anybody than the high-priced shoes of America, but to permit the products of the low-paid laborers of Asia to undersell those of the high-paid laborers of America, would be to prevent the growth of the only influences which can make wealth permanently cheaper in the future. Just in proportion as the high-paid labor of one country is superseded by the low-paid labor of another, is the simpler so- cial life and small consumption of the former substituted for the more complex social life and larger consumption of the latter. This check in the demand for an increasing variety of products necessarily prevents the diversification of industry and the de- velopment of manufacture, and consequently lessens the incentive for the concentration of capital, the use of steam-driven machinery, and all wealth-cheapening methods of production ; and thus not only fails to furnish cheap wealth for the present, but prevents the possibility of cheaper wealth in the future. It is manifest, therefore, that from a philosophic view of the case any public policy which aids or permits the products of the low-paid labor of one country to undersell the products of the high-paid labor of another, tends to arrest human progress by stereotyping lower civilization and preventing the growth of a higher. Whenever a struggle for industrial supremacy takes place between producers in countries of differing degrees of civiliza- 334 UNECONOMIC COMPETITION, tion, 1 one of two things must necessarily occur : either the higher must descend to the plane of the lower, or the lower must ascend to the plane of the higher. If the higher-paid producer descends to the plane of the lower, it will not be economic competition, because in that case the low-wage products will be sure to undersell the high-wage products, and thus enable the inferior to succeed against the superior. In such a struggle there is nothing to de- velop the best in the higher, but every thing to repress it. The cheap-labor competitor does not succeed through his economic superiority, but solely because of his social inferiority. Such a contest, therefore, is contrary to all conditions of economic com- petition. 2 Instead of being a contest between approximately equal competing units which tends to develop the best in both, it is an unequal struggle in which the inferior is sure to prevail against the superior. When competition takes place on the plane of the higher wage-level, the result is very different. In such a contest, who- ever succeeds is compelled to do so by employing superior ma- chinery, and that reduces the cost of wealth by saving instead of cheapening human labor. Every effort of the lower to succeed against the higher by such means necessarily tends to develop better methods of production, cheapen wealth and promote social progress in the less advanced country, even if it fails to undersell competitors in a foreign market. On the other hand, in every such struggle the high-wage producer is compelled to make efforts to still further develop the wealth-cheapening methods in the most advanced countries. Therefore the con- test on the higher plane is supremely economic, because it stimulates the best in both competitors, guarantees that only the superior shall succeed, and in so doing helps rather than injures the inferior. This is precisely what takes place in every other sphere of de- velopment. Evolution is a constant differentiation and higher integration with an ever increasing complexity of relations. So- cial progress constantly tends toward a greater variety of relations, 1 The most infallible test of a relatively high or low state of civilization in any country is the material or social conditions of the masses, which is always indi- cated by the rate of real wages. 2 See definition of economic competition, p. 293. BASIS OF ECONOMIC COMPETITION. 335 specialization of functions, and integration into larger but more diversified aggregates ; witness the tendency towards larger and larger cities and nations, through which greater freedom and more complex and socializing intercourse is steadily devel- oped. In all this progressive tendency each integration takes place by the lower rising to the plane of the higher, and never by the higher descending to that of the lower. And this progress can only take place by the lower becoming approximately equal to the higher. For instance, if one wants to move in a social class more cultured than the one to which he belongs, he can do so only by becoming more cultured himself. The more refined will neither take on coarser manners nor tolerate the n in another for the sake of his society. Indeed, were it otherwise, progress would be impossible ; because if the higher would descend to the lower, there would be no incentive for the lower to rise. Since nothing can cheapen wealth which does not reduce the cost of production without diminishing real wages, and since no industrial contest can be economically competitive which does not take place between approximately equal competing units, and since there can be no approximate economic equality between contestants except on the plane of the higher, it follows that the true economic basis for international competition is the wage-level of the dearer-labor country. In order therefore to apply the doc- trine of opportunity laid down in the previous chapter, and to establish international trade upon a strictly economic basis, it is necessary for the higher-wage country to discriminate against the products of the lower-wage producer to the full extent that the lower wages affect the cost of production, as this determines the competitive status of the commodity. Thus we have a truly economic basis for a tariff policy that shall be protective without being paternal. A tariff policy based upon this principle would protect the superior against injury from the inferior, without affording the slightest monopolistic impediment to economic rivalry. Instead of restricting wholesome competition, this would simply protect the competitive opportunity for the " fittest to survive," the test of fitness always being the ability to furnish low- priced wealth without employing low-priced labor. Under such conditions the products of foreign countries could never under- sell those of home industry, except when the lower price of the 336 SUPERFICIAL REASONING. foreign product is due to the use of superior la.boT-sam'n^a.nd not to labor-cheapening methods. Consequently whoever undersells confers a permanent advantage on the whole community. SECTION VI. Some Popular Fallacies Considered. It is a standing charge against the protective doctrine that it has no definable scientific basis, that it is grounded upon no general principle in nature, society, or economics. Nor is this charge wholly unwarranted when judged by the accepted reason- ing on the subject. It is a peculiar feature of the history of tariff legislation that it has been generally advocated for local or special reasons, and almost never based upon any economic principle susceptible of general application. In this country, where the protective idea has reached its highest development, the tariff advocate rests his claim almost entirely upon the fact that we have made marked industrial progress under a protective regime. He compares the wages and social condition of the laborers in high-tariff America with those of the laborers in free- trade England, and confidently exclaims : " Behold the superiority of a high-tariff policy ! " And, with equal assurance, he ascribes the poverty and social degradation of Ireland and India to the fact that British rule has prevented them from having a protective tariff. On the other hand, while the free-trader objects to this kind of reasoning by the protectionist as confounding coincidence with cause, he employs it with equal assurance in presenting his own case. Studiously confining his observation to European conditions, he compares the wages and social condition of labor- ers in England under free trade with those in continental countries under protection, but not with those in America, and triumphantly exclaims : " Behold the superiority of free trade !" By this mode of reasoning the English free-trader is as unable to explain why wages are higher in America under protection than in England under free trade, as is the American protectionist to explain why they are higher in England with free trade than in continental and Asiatic countries under protection. If the mere fact that prosperity accompanied free trade in England justifies the reasoning of the free-trader, then the fact that pros- perity accompanies a high tariff in America equally justifies the reasoning of the protectionist. And when the free-trader declares, LAW OF ECONOMIC PROTECTION. 337 as he does, that America is not prosperous by virtue of the tariff, but in spite of it, the protectionist can with equal force reply that England is not prosperous by virtue of her free trade, but in spite of it. This line of reasoning furnishes no scientific means of testing the merits of either doctrine ; it shows that progress is possible under both policies, but it affords no logical basis for the application of either. What these facts show is, that neither free trade in England nor protection in America prevented the growth of industrial prosperity in those countries, but they do nothing to prove that this progress was promoted by either policy. Free trade being simply the absence of protection, it follows that to discover the law of economic protection is to discover that of free-trade also, and since neither free trade nor protec- tion will produce the best economic effects under all conditions, it is only by the knowledge of such a law that any philosophic application of either policy is possible. If the conclusions reached in the preceding sections are correct, however, this law is already established, and we have a universal principle upon which a protective and consequently a free trade policy can be scientifically adopted. Briefly stated this law is : (i) that compe- tition can be economic only when it takes place between approximately equal competitors ; (2) that when there is any marked difference in the wage-level of the international competitors, such approximate competitive equality is possible only when the competition is based upon the higher wage-level of the higher ; (3) that no lowering of prices can cheapen wealth which does not result from diminishing the cost of production withotit lowering wages. Bearing these propositions in mind, we shall have no difficulty in seeing why a protective policy might promote industrial pros- perity and social progress in America, and have the reverse effect in Austria, India, and Ireland. . Nor will it be difficult to under- stand why America has more to fear from free trade with highly civilized England than with the less civilized nations of Asia and South America. And it will be equally clear why a tariff policy will not produce the same effect with a high-wage level in a small colony like Victoria with a million inhabitants, as in a large country like the United States, with sixty-five million of people. 1 1 See articles in The Nineteenth Century for September, 1888, and Quarterly Journal of Economics, October, 1888. 22 338 INFANT-INDUSTRY THEORY, One of the arguments much relied upon by protectionists is that known as the " infant-industry argument." The burden of this argument is that industries should be protected in their early stages to prevent them from being killed by competition before they are fully established, the implication being that when they become well established they will be able to hold their own against the world. For a time this idea was reluctantly accepted by anti-tariff people, but now that after having had protection for half a century and on the plea of " infant industries," a tariff is still demanded, the free-traders naturally ask " when do industries reach maturity ? " They regard such reasoning as far more in- fantile than the industry, and insist that if there is any virtue in the protective principle, it should be applied in behalf of the weak against the strong and not in behalf of the strong against the weak. Consequently, if protection can be justified at all, it is such countries as Russia, Turkey, Italy, Spain and the in- dustrially weak countries of South America that need protection against the United States, and not the United States against them. If the principle here laid down had been recognized, the obvious fallacy in both these positions would have been appa- rent ; and the talk about " infant industries " would never have been indulged in by the protectionist, and the free-trader's re- joinder about protecting the lower against the higher would have been too absurd for utterance. It would then have been seen that the products of America do not need protection against those of England because the industries are younger, but be- cause they are made under a higher civilization a civilization in which the human element in production is more expensive. Hence, to permit the products of America to be undersold by those of another country, the lower cost of which results entirely from the use of lower-paid labor, would neither give cheaper wealth nor better social conditions. It would also have been clear that this fact in no wise changes with age, unless either the wage-level of the lower-wage country rises, or the use of labor- saving appliances in the higher-wage country more than overcomes .the difference. Unless one of these things occurs protection will be as necessary at the end of a thousand years as it was the first six months, although both countries may have greatly advanced. THE HIGHER REQUIRES PROTECTION. 339 Indeed, the greater the advancement in both countries the greater will be the probability of their employing similar ma- chinery, thus making the necessity of protection depend entirely upon the difference in their respective wage-levels, as is the case with America and England to-day. Therefore, when the tariff advocate asks for protection simply because the industry is young, and the free-trader opposes it on the assumption that the producers in a superior civilization ought to be able to eco- nomically compete with those in an inferior civilization, they both mistake the true economic gist of the problem. Social superiority, instead of making protection unnecessary, is the very thing which makes it necessary, provided it is socially important to retain or further develop the industry. Nor is this peculiar to industry ; it is a general principle throughout society. In every phase of human relations, it is the higher that needs protection against the lower, and this because the latter will resort to methtfds of aggression and defence which the former cannot, for social or ethical reasons, afford to em- ploy. Take, for example, the criminal laws. They are enacted to restrain the morally lower from injuring the higher ; it is to prevent the dishonest from plundering the honest, the ma- licious from assaulting the well-intentioned, that police courts and jails are instituted and armies maintained. Indeed, there is not a restrictive institution maintained in society which was not called into existence to protect the higher from the injurious effects of the lower. It may be asked, if this theory is correct, why does not the American producer need a much higher tariff against the prod- ucts of China, Russia, or South America than he does against those of England, since her wage-level much more nearly ap- proximates to his own ? The reason for this is very simple. It is because the social chasm between America and those coun- tries is so great, that the use of labor-saving appliances here more than makes up for the difference in the cost of labor in the respective countries. In China, for instance, where almost every thing is made by hand labor, the product per capita is so small, compared with what can be turned off by steam-driven machin- ery here, that it costs more to produce an article there with labor at 6 cents a day than it does here with labor at two dollars a day. 340 INDIA, IRELAND, AND RUSSIA. But if the labor-saving machinery of America were introduced into China, and operated by their six-cent-a-day laborers, then an immensely high tariff would be necessary in order to protect the high wage-level of America, because, in that case, while all other items of cost would be the same, the human element in the pro- ductive process would be many hundred per cent, dearer here than there. This is why England is a more dangerous com- petitor to us than China. True, the wage-levels of America and England are more nearly alike than are those of America and China, but the machinery of America and England is still more so. Indeed, it is because the machinery used in America and England is practically the same, that all the difference in their respective wage-levels is directly expressed in the relative com- petitive power of the two countries. What is true of England is equally true of France, Germany, and every other country, to the extent that they use similar machinery but cheaper labor than we do ; yet they may have very much cheaper labor, and still be practically harmless as economic competitors, so long as they use poorer machinery or hand methods. Another error into which tariff advocates commonly fall, is in thinking that India, Ireland, or Russia would greatly improve their condition if they imposed a tariff against British products. Indeed, there are not a few Englishmen to-day who entertain a similar notion, and insist that England would be greatly benefited by adopting a tariff policy towards America. This is a mistake, for America's wage-level being higher than England's, we could not undersell her except by the use of superior methods, which either English producers would be forced to adopt or let Ameri- can producers do the work, and in either case English laborers would have a net gain. If the better methods were adopted in England, she would have cheaper products without lower wages, which would be equal to a rise of wages. If America made the products, the English laborer could emigrate to America and obtain American wages. The same is true with regard to England and continental countries. Competition between England and Russia would not injure Russia, because there are no economic methods employed in England which are not superior to those employed in Russia. Whenever Russia is undersold by England, her products will ENGLAND AND THE CONTINENT. 34! have to be made by English methods either in England or in Russia, and in either case the Russian people will be benefited. The only reason England is not injured to-day by competition with the countries in Continental Europe is precisely the same as that which prevents China from seriously injuring America, namely : that while her wage-level is higher, her machinery is so much superior to theirs, that it more than makes up the differ- ence in the cost of production. 1 England has less to fear, how- ever, from continental competition than we have, because their wage-level is nearer to hers than it is to ours, and to the extent that American and English machinery is adopted in continental countries faster than their wage-level approximates that of Eng- land, will their relative competitive power gain upon hers. In fact, unless the wage-level in continental countries rises very rapidly, it can only be a matter of time when they will occupy the same competitive position to England that she now sustains to America, in which case she will be compelled either to adopt a protective policy or surrender much of her manufacture to con- tinental producers. It will thus be seen that the seemingly inexplicable phenomena over which free-traders and protectionists have vainly contended, become perfectly explainable on the principle that international competition can only be beneficial when the competitors are ap- proximately equal upon the plane of the higher. Therefore a protective policy is beneficial to a nation, only as affecting its relations with less civilized countries. While America may need protection against the machine-made products of all other coun- tries, there is no country that can be permanently benefited by discriminating against the products of America. So too with England ; she may ultimately require a tariff against the machine- made products of all other countries but America, and so on. In a word, a tariff can only be of any permanent economic advan- 1 According to Mulhall, 80 % of the productive energy in Great Britain is fur- nished by steam, while in continental countries steam only represents an aver- age of 36 %. Consequently, the total cost of productive power per thousand foot-tons is 17 cents in Great Britain as compared with 27 cents on the con- tinent. " This advantage enables us (England) as far as labor is concerned to undersell continental countries by 12 #, although our workmen's wages are almost double." " History of Prices," pp. 54 and 57. 34 2 SUPERFICIAL OBJECTIONS. tage, to the extent that it protects the opportunity for industrial development afforded by a higher wage-level from the uneco- nomic influence of a lower wage-level and inferior civilization. SECTION VII. The Effect of a Tariff upon the Price of Home Products. There is no objection urged against a tariff policy so much emphasized and so frequently repeated as the charge that a tariff is necessarily a tax an oppressive burden upon the consumer. The free-trade advocates, especially in this country, deny that it is possible to improve the industrial condition of a community by any system of tariff legislation. They insist that at best it can only enable one class to gain at the expense of another. 1 Perry regards a protective tariff as an unmitigated curse, and says : " Political economy, denouncing it as the enemy of man- kind, hopes soon to throw upon its loathsome carcass the last shovelful of cleansing earth." 2 It will not, however, be difficult to show that despite the learn- ing and dogmatism on its side, this mode of treating the subject is exceedingly superficial. The assertion that a tariff is a tax bears the stamp of the declaimer rather than the economist ; while seeming to say much, it actually says nothing. A tax is simply a contribution to the public treasury, and is one of the innumerable expenditures that social life makes necessary. The payment of two dollars for a hat or a pair of shoes is just as much a burden upon the resources of the citizen as is a tax of two dollars for the government. Taxes, like all other kinds of expenditures, should be treated as an investment, the wisdom or unwisdom of which depends not upon its amount, but entirely upon whether it yields more in ultimate advantage than it costs in immediate disadvantage. This fact can be more easily determined in some cases than in 1 " We deny that they can gain any thing from us, on account of the law, but what we lose ; we deny that the total gains to one part of society by this process can ever exceed the total losses of another part i.e., that the process can increase the wealth of the community ; we deny, finally, that our share of these hypothetical gains can ever be redistributed to us so as to bring back our first loss." Sumner's " Protection in the United States," pp. n and 12. 2 " Political Economy," p. 477. TAXES ARE INVESTMENTS. 343 others. For example, when one buys a steak, by the next meal time he can determine whether or not he received an equivalent for what he gave ; whether the satisfaction was equal to the cost. If he purchases a suit of clothes, however, the result cannotPbe so quickly determined. It will take several months to ascertain whether or not an equivalent was given and received. And if he invests in a farm or a factory, a still longer time is required to decide the wisdom or unwisdom of the purchase. The indirect and impersonal nature of governmental expenditures makes a still longer time necessary to determine the exact results. In order to determine whether or not a tax is a good invest- ment, we have to deal with general tendencies or with ultimate rather than immediate effects. For instance, if the wisdom of the expenditure involved in maintaining an army, navy, police force, were determined by the immediate effects at any given time, it would be regarded as waste. Nevertheless the ex- penditure necessary to enforce law and order is regarded as a good investment even by free-traders. It procures as good economic results as the expenditure for food, clothes, or shelter, since it is essential to their enjoyment. The same is true of education, but the effects here are still further removed from direct observation, and consequently must be judged 6n a still broader general basis. There are in some countries, and indeed in some parts of this country, those who regard a tax for the public schools as an oppressive burden, an unjust exaction. But upon a broader view of the subject it appears that their general social safety, freedom, and well-being largely depend upon the intelligence of the great mass of the community in which they live, and this to a great extent depends upon opportunities for popular education. Experience has con- clusively shown expenditure in public schools to be a good invest- ment ; it comes back in better citizens and a higher civilization, which in turn supplies all the influences and conditions that make cheaper wealth and larger freedom possible. In the same way must we estimate the wisdom or unwisdom of a protective tariff. In considering the effect of a tariff policy upon the price of home products, we must not consider alone the direct and immediate effect upon prices, but also the indirect and ultimate effect. It has already been pointed out that the test of 344 TARIFFS AND PROFITS. cheapness is the ratio in which labor will exchange for wealth, things being cheap or dear according as a large or small quantity can be obtained for a day's labor. If home products can be undersold by foreign, solely because labor is cheaper abroad than here, the only result would be a readjustment of prices on the lower wage-level, with no advantage to anybody. Let us assume that a 20 per cent, tariff is necessary to prevent the home products from being thus undersold, that 20 per cent, would not in any sense be a tax upon the American consumer, because if that tariff were not applied, the wage-level would be commensurately low- ered and a day's labor would purchase no more wealth than before. To say that under such conditions the home producer is enabled to add as profit on his whole product an amount equal to the tariff upon the foreign product, is to exhibit a striking unacquaintance with economic phenomena. 1 All that a tariff can do in such instances is to prevent a readjustment of prices on a lower wage-level. Prices however, would be governed by cost of production, according to the law before stated, just as if there were no tariff. The competition between home producers, together with the effort of the consumers, to purchase at the minimum, will force prices down to the cost of producing the most expensive portion of the necessary supply. All who can produce at less than that, will obtain the difference as profit. Unless the cost of producing that dearest portion can be lessened by some other means than by lowering wages, it is utterly impos- sible to make any improvement by reducing price. This much however, only applies to the direct and immediate effect, and is usually the only aspect which the advocate of laissez faire stops to consider. The permanent economic influ- ence of a protective tariff upon the price of home products, however, is the indirect and ultimate effect rather than the im- mediate and direct. In preventing the products of dear labor from being undersold by those of cheap labor, the tariff protects the home market for the home producer. The economic effect of this, as already shown, is to promote the growth of manufac- turing industries, and to concentrate population, which in turn creates a social environment that develops new tastes and habits, and these elevate the standard of living among the masses, and 1 Cf. President Cleveland's message December 6, 1887. THE PRICE OF COTTON CLOTH. 345 consequently enlarge the demand for an increasing quantity and variety of products. The necessary tendency of this is to develop a higher grade of social character and general intelligence, more inventive genius and improved methods of production, by which the cost and therefore the price of commodities is ultimately lowered without reducing wages. From the foregoing it will be seen that a tariff or any thing else which prevents a readjustment of prices on a lower wage-level affords protection to the opportunity for devel- oping better productive possibilities through the use of labor- saving and wealth-cheapening methods. The effect of a tariff upon the price of home products, therefore, when applied accord- ing to the principles here laid down, is, first, to prevent a wasteful readjustment of economic relations on a lower wage-plane ; second, to protect opportunities for increasing productive pos- sibilities and thereby make a readjustment of economic relations on a higher wage-plane necessary. If space permitted it could easily be shown that, despite the frequent unseemly higgling and hauling to help local producers by absurd tariff schedules, this has been the general effect of the protective policy of this country. Take, for example, the cotton industry, to which reference has already been made. For reasons not necessary to explain here, the factory system had its rise in England, and by the close of the first quarter of the present cen- tury the use of steam-driven machinery, especially in the manu- facture of cotton cloth, had become well established. At that time the cotton industry in this country was in its infancy, being mostly carried on in small factories run by water-power. The difference in the development of this industry in the two countries is clearly shown by the number of factories, amount of capital, etc., which, in 1830, was as follows : England. America. Number of establishments . 1,151 801 Capital invested per establishment . Number of spindles per establishment Number of looms per establishment Number of operatives per establishment Weekly wages J Price per yard .... $147,680 $50,702 8,108 1,556 87 41 205 77 $2.51 $3.46 I5i 17 1 These figures represent for England (1833) the average weekly wages of 67,819 cotton operatives. And for America they represent the average wages of 31,471 cotton operatives in New England (1830). 346 PROTECTION GAVE OPPORTUNITY. It will be seen from the above that the English manufacturer had a double advantage over the American. In addition to having nearly half a century's start in the development of factory methods, by which he had acquired a much greater concentration of capital and more efficient use of machinery, he had an advan- tage of nearly 40 per cent, in the cost of his labor. No argument is necessary to show that under such conditions it was impossible to prevent our cotton cloth from being undersold by the English without reducing American wages fully one third. Nor would this reduction in wages have been limited to the factory opera- tives ; for even if the American manufacturer had imported English machinery free of duty, the higher wages of the brick- layers, masons, carpenters, painters, etc., would have made his building and general plant cost more than the English. It would have been necessary, therefore, to have reduced wages in all these industries to practically the same level as those in England, in order to be able to compete with the English manufacturer in our home market. To obviate this difficulty and make it possible for the American manufacturer to produce for the American market, a tariff was levied upon English cotton cloth. This, however, did not increase the price of the American product, as is commonly assumed, but it increased the price of the English product, there- by preventing the price of American cloth from falling to the English level, and making it unnecessary to reduce wages here in the cotton and several other industries. By thus putting the American producer on an approximate competitive equality with the English in the American market, an economic basis was furnished for the development of cotton manufacture in this country. Nor did this tariff create a monopoly, by which the price of cotton cloth could be abnormally increased and fabulous profits obtained by the American producer. On the contrary, it pre- vented the English producer from monopolizing the American market through the use of cheaper labor. So long as the English producer, by paying lower wages, could undersell the American, there was no inducement for the American to take the risk of investing capital in improved machinery. But when this uneco- nomic advantage was removed and the competitors in the Ameri- can market were put upon substantially the same wage-level, a IMPROVED METHODS.' 347 strong incentive for developing superior methods was created, since their use became the only means of success. With the rapid increase of population which our high wage-level stimulated the home market steadily increased, making a larger production necessary. This naturally led to a greater concentra- tion of capital, the use of larger factories and better machinery, and the result is that cotton cloth, which could not be produced for less than seventeen cents a yard in 1830, can now be furnished at a profit for five cents a yard, while the laborer receives double the wages he did then. 1 The development of wealth-cheapening methods in the cotton industry, which the protection of the home market has made possible, will be seen by the following facts for England and America in 1830 and 1880 : England. America. 1830. 1880. ^ 1830. 1880. Xo. of establishments . 1,151 2,671 801 726 Capital per estab. . . $147,680 $140,292 $50,702 $275,503 Spindles per estab. . . 8,108 14,798 1,556 14,089 Looms per estab. . . 87 192 41 298 Laborers per estab. . . 205 180 77 228 Wages $2.51 $4.66 $3.46 $6.45 9 Price of cloth per yard, 15^ 6f 17 .07 It will be observed from the above that in 1830 the concentra- tion of capital in the cotton industry was very much greater in England than in America, the ratio of capital to establishments being nearly three times as large, that of spindles more than five times, that of looms twice as great, and that of operatives nearly three times as great as in this country, while wages were 38 per cent, lower. But in 1880 their relative position is reversed. While in England the total, capital invested had a little more than doubled, in America it had increased more than 400 per cent. In England, with the increased capital, the number of establishments had been commensurately increased, while in America the number 1 See Part III., chap, iv., sec. v. s The wages in this table represent Massachusetts and England for 1883. The average weekly wages for the whole period from 1872 to 1883 inclusive, in the cotton industry, were : in England, $4.60 ; in Massachusetts, $7.68 being 66.96. percent, higher in Massachusetts than England. See "Massachusetts Labor Bureau Report for 1884," p. 419. 348 EFFECT UPON OTHER INDUSTRIES. of establishments was actually reduced. Hence, in 1880 the amount of capital per establishment in England was $7,000 less than in 1830, while in America it was five times as large. The ratio of spindles to establishments only increased in England about 82 per cent., while in America they increased 800 per cent. The number of looms per establishment in 1880 had a little more than doubled in England, while in America they increased six- fold. During this period the number of operatives per establish- ment in England diminished from 205 to 180, while in America they increased from 77 to 228 ; and while wages in England rose $2.15 a week, in America they rose $2.99 a week. All this clearly demonstrates that the concentration of capital and the use of labor-saving appliances in this industry made greater progress in America than in England after the home market regime was in- augurated. This is further shown by the fact that the price of the product has been reduced more here, even with a greater rise in the wages, than in England. Consequently, so far as the manufacturing process is concerned, cotton cloth can be made cheaper in America to-day than in England, notwithstanding that wages in the same industry are 38 per cent, higher here than there. Nor was the beneficial effect of protecting the home market in this instance limited to the cotton industry. The concentration of capital and development of large factories in the cotton industry naturally created a demand for machinery, which gave rise to various branches of home manufacture in the iron industry and the numerous industries involved in the building trades. With this growth of manufacture and diversification of employment, industrial centres became large cities, which furnished a steadily increasing market for the products of our food and raw material, producing population. This in turn necessitated railroads, which still further lessened the cost of production, diversified industry, cheapened travel, and thereby enabled the daily paper to penetrate the rural districts, and the country population to come into more frequent contact with city life ; and in other manifold ways de- veloped the socializing influences of the nation, thus reacting upon the social life, standard of living, and wages of the laboring class. Without attempting to follow the various phases of industrial development directly or indirectly resulting from the protection WAGES IN NON-PROTECTED INDUSTRIES. 349' of the home market, it is perfectly safe to say that, with the ad- vantage that England had in factory development, it would have been impossible to develop cotton and many other kindred manufacturing industries without the imposition of a tariff, or some other restrictive policy, unless we had lowered our wages to the English level. To have done that would have destroyed the incentive for emigration and thereby arrested the rapid in- crease of our population, which in turn would have commensu- rately checked the growth of our home markets, and thus necessarily have greatly hindered the development of many manufacturing industries. And if, without a tariff we had main- tained our higher wage-level, not only our cotton cloth, but nearly all our manufactured products, would have been made in England, and we should have remained practically an agricultural people, and hence, in all probability, would now be a third- or fourth-rate nation, with a scattered population of perhaps from twenty to thirty millions, having smaller wages, less general in- telligence, and therefore a lower civilization than England. SECTION VIII. The Relation of Protection to Wages in Non- Protected Industries. One of the most plausible objections urged against tariff legis- lation is that it affords no benefit to those engaged in non-pro- tected industries. It is insisted that in order to justify a tariff policy, its advocates are bound to show that it is as advantageous to those engaged in non-protected as in protected industries. Nor is this an unreasonable demand ; there can surely be no justification for any public policy which benefits one portion of the community only at the expense of another. That the theory of protection as hitherto presented has failed to fulfil this require- ment can hardly be questioned by its most enthusiastic disciples. The protectionists unquestionably believe that the whole com- munity is benefited by a tariff policy, but they have hitherto failed to explain how a tariff on the various articles of food, clothing, furniture, and the like, benefits the carpenter, painter, plumber, bricklayer, mason, engineer, compositor, and other domestic artisans. This is chiefly due to the fact that they have accepted the economic postulates of the laissez-faire economists, especially 350 GLADSTONE AND BLAINE. regarding wages, prices, and profits, thus rendering a philosophic conception of the protective principle logically impossible. We have a striking illustration of this in Mr. Elaine's argument upon that point in his recent controversy with Mr. Gladstone. He said : " He [Mr. Gladstone] sees that the laborers in what he calls the ' protected industries ' secure high pay, especially as com- pared with the European school of wages. He perhaps does not see that the effect is to raise the wages of all persons in the United States engaged in- what Mr. Gladstone calls the ' unprotected in- dustries.' Printers, bricklayers, carpenters, and all others of that class are paid as high wages as those of any other trade or call- ing, but if the wages of all those in the protected classes were suddenly struck down to the English standard, the others must follow. A million men cannot be kept at work for half the pay that another million men are receiving in the same country. Both classes must go up or must go down together." ' This statement, which represents the gist of the modern pro- tectionist position regarding the economic relation of protection to wages, implies two assumptions, neither of which is correct : (i) that wages are directly increased by the tariff in protected industries ; (2) that through competition the rise of wages in protected industries brings the wages in non-protected industries up to the same level. i. The idea that wages are high in protected industries be- cause the tariff enables the manufacturer to obtain large profits, and hence to pay higher wages, is one of the most popular falla- cies connected with the whole tariff discussion. Even if tariffs increased profits, that would not necessarily increase wages. Employers do not raise wages merely because profits are large. The increase of wages, except in rare cases, does not come through the generosity of the employer, but through the pressing demands of the laborer. Every laborer knows and every states- man ought to know that protected employers are as ready to reduce wages, as reluctant to increase them, and have as many strikes, as do unprotected employers. But the assumption that profits are larger in protected than in unprotected industries has no foundation in fact. Even if a tariff did at first produce this 1 North American Review, January, 1890, pp. 47, 48. BLAINE'S MISTAKE. 35 I effect, it would soon be destroyed by competition, as capital would leave unprotected to engage in protected industries, where larger profits would be obtained. Had the economic law of profits been understood, no such assumption would have been made. It would then have been seen that if there is any competition between producers in the same market, the price of the commodity would tend to equal the cost of producing the most expensive portion of the general supply. If the cost of producing the dearest portion is lessened by free trade, the price will fall ; if it is increased by protection, the price will rise. But this change will affect the consumer's price, not the employer's profit. The profit in either case will represent the difference in the cost of production, increasing as the cost diminishes below that of the dearest competitor, a difference which neither free trade nor protection can affect. 2. Mr. Elaine's statement, that " a million men cannot be kept at work for half the pay that another million men are receiving in the same country," is also very unfortunate, as that is just what is actually taking place all the time. Coal miners, agricultural laborers, and many others are working every day in this country, in many instances for less than half the pay that many classes of workmen in the cities are receiving. And what makes this posi- tion still more unfortunate is the fact that the printers, engineers, bricklayers, carpenters, and others, whose wages are the highest, are employed in non-protected industries ; hence this cannot be the result of competition with the lower wages in protected in- dustries. Neither is this difference in wages in the same country peculiar to nationality or to political institutions ; it is as great in America with protection and democracy as in England with free trade and monarchy, or as in Germany with protection and despotism. Instead of wages tending to uniformity in all indus- tries in the same country, they tend to a greater diversity as industrial differentiation advances. The only sense in which wages tend to uniformity is in the same industry contributing to the same market. 1 Nor is Mr. Elaine's statement, that " both classes must go up or must go down together," any nearer correct. Experience shows that they do not necessarily do any thing of the kind. For 1 See chapter on Wages. 352 CAUSE OF SLAINE'S ERROR. instance, in 1725 the wages of agricultural laborers in England were $s. ^d. ($1.28) per week ; those of carpenters, masons, brick- layers, and other domestic artificers were 6s. ($1.44) a week. In 1800 the wages of agricultural laborers were us. $d. ($2.74) ; those of domestic artificers iSs. ($4.38). In 1840 wages of agri- cultural laborers were us. ($2.64) ; of artificers 33^.' ($7.92). In 1877 wages in the London building trades were 4.2$. gd? ($10.26) a week, while in agriculture wages were about 13^. ($3.12) a week, being only 14.?. ($3.36) in'i884. 3 In a word, during the present century the wages of mechanics and artisans have increased more than twice as much as those of agricultural and other rural laborers. The truth is, a protective tariff does not affect wages in any such manner as indicated by Mr. Elaine. 4 The laborer knows from experience that an increase in the tariffs on the particular commodity he produces does not yield any commensurate increase in his wages. And to persist in telling him that it does, can only result in destroying his confidence in the economic advantage of a protective .policy. If working men are expected to take an intelligent interest in protection, a more rational explanation of its advantages must be presented. 1 Wade's " History of the Working Classes," p. 166. 2 Rogers' '' Six Centuries of Work and Wages," p. 539. 8 Mulhall's " History of Prices," p. 125. 4 This argument clearly shows that the American protectionist has not yet outgrown the English demand-and-supply (wage-fund) fallacy, which is further shown by the fact that Mr. Elaine actually ascribes the rise of wages in England to the increased demand for labor here. North American Review, January, 1890, p. 48. If this were true why did not wages rise still more in Ireland, Germany, Italy, Bohemia, etc., from which countries the emigration has been much greater than from England, and why have wages risen as much in France, with almost no emigration, as in continental countries, where emigration has been the greatest ? The truth is that voluntary emigration tends to check rather than promote the rise of wages, because it draws off the best laborers upon whom a rise in the wage-level depends. It is only when the lowest laborers are ex- ported that home wages are improved by the change. That is why the condition of the laborers in any country can best be improved at home. Hence the true economic policy is to develop the home market and diversify domestic industry instead of relying upon emigration as the means of relieving industrial distress. The true way to help the people of Russia, India, and China is to take our civilization to them and not to bring them to our civilization, and this can best be done by developing our own possibilities. See section ix., p. 98. HOW TARIFFS AFFECT WAGES. 353 Considered from the point of view here taken, however, these seemingly conflicting facts are easily explained. When we under- stand that the price of labor, like that of commodities, is governed by the cost of furnishing the dearest portion of the necessary supply, and that this cost is determined by the laborer's standard of living, which in turn depends upon his character and social environment, the whole subject assumes a new aspect. It then becomes apparent that no influences can permanently affect wages which do not operate upon the laborer's social life and standard of living. The only way a tariff can do that is by promoting the concentration and diversification of industry, thereby creating more complex social relations that, stimulate the growth of new desires and habits and a higher plane of living. Manifestly these influences operate just as much upon the laborers in non-protected as in protected industries. The non-protected printer, carpenter, and painter obtain just as much advantage from the social influences of a manufacturing city as do their protected neighbors, the hatter and cigar-maker. The wages of city mechanics are higher than those of rural laborers because their standard of living is higher, which is owing, to the more complex social conditions under which they live. It is only to the extent that a tariff promotes the development of these social conditions by protecting the home market that it in- fluences wages in any industry. Upon the principle therefore that protection is economically beneficial only as it tends to develop the socializing influences of the nation, it is clear that its effect upon wages is not limited to protected industries, but that it effects equally the wages of all laborers to the extent that it directly or indirectly affects their social environment. If it were true, as is usually assumed, that a tariff benefits the laborer through increasing the employer's profits and thus en- abling him to pay higher wages, it would be true as is often urged that the non-protected mechanic has no interest in a protective policy. And so long as that view is taught by leading protec- tionists, we may expect to see the intelligent laborers in domestic industries, especially in our large cities, become free-traders. But from the point of view here presented their interest in a protective policy is quite as great and often greater than that of those employed in the most highly protected industries. With- 23 354 SOCIAL FORCES OA'LY RAISE IV AGES. out the development of cities and manufacturing centres, as already shown, railroads, telegraphs and other industries, to say the least, would have been in a much less advanced state. 1 In which case the industrial and social environment of the great mass of mechanics would have been more homogeneous, hence a more simple social life and lower wages would have been inevitable, as is the case in small towns, rural districts, and non-manufacturing communities throughout the world. To the extent that a tariff policy has developed manufacture and the growth of cities, it has improved the. social life and wages of laborers in all industries in those industrial centres, protected and non-protected. And to the extent that it has developed railroads and telegraphs, it has shortened the distance between farm and factory, and thereby increased the opportunities that force rural laborers into more frequent contact with the social influences of city life, thus in its reflex action elevating the social life and wages of rural laborers. This explains why the wages even of agricultural and other laborers in isolating occupations are always higher in the immediate vicinity of cities and manufacturing towns. 2 This view of the subject also enables us to understand why a tariff will not produce the same effect in a small community like an Australian colony, that it will in a large country like the United States, even though the wage-level is as high there as it is here. It is because the population there is too small to furnish a sufficiently large market to sustain the use of the most highly de- veloped factory methods, without which the socializing environ- ment necessary to raise the standard of living and the rate of wages cannot be developed. There is one other fact that should be noticed before leaving this point. We are told that despite the improvements in ma- chinery and the general advancement, the condition of the factory 1 Witness India, Russia, and Turkey as compared with this country in these respects. There are six times as many miles of railroad in New York State as in all Turkey, and more miles of railroads in the United States than in all the rest of the world. * This fact has been universally observed though very little understood. See "Wealth and Progress," pp. 160-163 ; Rogers' "Six Centuries of Work and Wages," pp. 171, 172, 180, 327, 535, 536. Also " Wealth of Nations," Book I., ch. viii. For similar facts in India see Buchanan's "Journey through the Countries of Mysore, Canara, and Malabar," vol. i., pp. 124, 125. MINERS AND FACTORY OPERATIVES. 355 operatives of New England and the miners of Pennsylvania is no better, but in many cases is worse, than it was forty years ago, although the products of these industries are highly protected. There is some truth in this statement, and a great deal of error. In the first place, it is not correct in any general sense to say that the condition of the miners and factory operatives has not im- proved. It is true, however, that the condition of the laborers employed in those industries to-day, as compared with those of forty years ago, has not improved commensurately with the progress of the community. This fact is usually taken as con- clusive evidence that, through some unjust manipulation of in- dustrial forces, the laborers in these industries have been excluded from the beneficial effects of the increasing wealth and social advancement. A little closer examination of the facts, however, will show that this conclusion is erroneous. Suppose, for example, that in a given business the laborers were intelligent Americans in 1850, but for some reason they all left it and their places were filled by Italians or Chinamen, would it be any test of the industrial and social progress of the laborers in the community to compare the wages, character, and intelligence of these Chinamen and Italians in 1890 with those of the Americans who were employed in that industry in 1850 ? Such a comparison would be rejected by any fair-minded investigator as unworthy of a moment's consideration. He would very properly insist that, in order to ascertain the improvement in the laborer's condition from 1850 to 1880, we must compare the condition of the same laborers. The wages and social condition of the Chinamen and Italians might have improved a hundred per cent., and still be no better in 1890 than were those of the American laborers in 1850. The only way to ascertain whether or not, or to what extent, the laborer's con- dition has improved, is to compare the condition of the American laborers in 1890 with their condition in 1850, and also the con- dition of the Chinese and Italian laborers in 1890, not with that of the Americans, but with their own condition in 1850. Now this is precisely what has taken place in New England factory life. The operatives of forty years ago were mainly composed of native Americans, mostly children of the New England farmers. During this period the industrial history of 3 $6 EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRIES. America has been unlike that of any other country in the world. Owing to our higher wage-level and the protection of our home market, manufacture and a variety of occupations increased much faster than did our native population. The consequence was a continuous stream of emigration to this country. The introduc- tion of every new industry of a higher order naturally drew to it the more intelligent and characterful portion of the laborers from the grade below, their places being filled by the less competent. By this means there was an almost constant movement of laborers from the more simple to the more complex and artistic industries, and the less advanced laborers from other countries taking the simpler occupations. In the cotton industry, for example, as Americans moved up into the position of overseers, managers, or merchants, their places were taken first by English, next by Irish, and last by French Canadian operatives, so that to-day an Ameri- can is scarcely to be found in the cotton factories of New England, except in the superior positions, many of the various grades of overseers, machinists, etc., being English or English-Irish. Therefore, if we compare the wages and social conditions of the spinner and weaver in New England cotton factories to-day with those of 1840, we are not dealing with the same class of people at all, nor even with the effects of the same civilization. The French or Irish operative may not be very much better off to-day than was the American who occupied the same position forty years ago, and yet his condition may have been improved several hun- dred per cent. The same is true of the miners of Pennsylvania, who to-day are largely composed of the poorest laborers from Continental Europe. In order, therefore, to ascertain the progress that has taken place in the industrial and social condition of these classes of operatives, we must not compare their present condition with that of the American forty years ago, but with their own condition at that time. If we compare the condition of small merchants in New England to-day with that of factory operatives of 1850, or compare the condition of the English, Irish, and French Cana- dian operatives in New England and the miners of Pennsylvania to-day with what it was in England, Ireland, Canada, Scandi- navia, Bohemia, or Russia thirty or forty years ago, the improve- ment will appear as marked as in that of any other class in the EFFECT UPON OTHER COUNTRIES. 357 community. To overlook this is entirely to misapprehend the phenomena under consideration. These facts are not referred to here to give a rose-colored tint to the condition of these laborers ; on the contrary, I regard their condition, in many instances, as not only a disgrace but as a serious danger to our civilization. 1 They are referred to, only to emphasize the mistake of ignoring them in considering the effect of modern industrial influences upon the social condition of the laborers ; because it is only by recognizing all the facts in the case, that we can form any true estimate of the beneficial or other effects of any industrial policy. Hence it may properly be said that to the extent that protection has promoted the growth of manufacturing industries it has directly and indirectly improved the social condition and raised the wages of all classes of laborers in this country com- mensurately with the advance of the community. SECTION IX. The Influence of Protection in the Most Ad- vanced Countries upon the Progress of the Less Advanced. Perhaps the most specious argument employed in favor of a free-trade policy is that it is cosmopolitan in its character, that it rises above local, sectional, or even national considerations, treating all mankind as brethren, while protection is pre-emi- nently a local policy that endeavors to discriminate against the people of all other countries in favor of its own. It may be ad- mitted that any policy which promotes the welfare of one country at the expense of another is essentially unphilosophic, and that the best policy for any country is the one whose beneficial effects are most universal. The economic character of a public policy, however, should never be judged by its immediate or temporary effect, but always by its permanent and ultimate influences. Measured by this standard, it is not difficult to show that the protective principle as here laid down is pre-eminently cos- mopolitan in its character. It may be regarded as a self-evident proposition that he who would help others must first develop the best in himself, since not to develop his own capacities is to limit his usefulness. The most altruistic effects are usually produced by efforts to broaden and 1 See " Wealth and Progress," pp. 365-373. 358 SELF-IMPROVEMENT THE FIRST STEP. elevate our own social life, because every addition to our own life embraces more of the efforts, interests, and well-being of others. In proportion as the interests of others becomes iden- tified with our own, will our efforts be directed to promoting their welfare as much as our own. In other words, in proportion as we become socially interdependent do our efforts become altruistic and cosmopolitan. Indeed, it is only by increasing man's interdependence upon his fellow-man that the solidarity of the human race will ever be realized, and the altruism "which shall make every man's happiness include that of all mankind become an established fact. This is as true of nations as of individuals. The nation which would contribute most to the advancement of human progress must develop its own civilization. We might as well expect the weak to carry the strong, as barbarism to aid civilization. That nation which most completely develops its own industrial and social possibilities, creates the most improved methods of pro- duction. In this way it is not only able to obtain its own wealth cheap, but ultimately to produce many commodities at less cost than can be produced by the cheap labor of less civilized countries. Upon the principle that whatever undersells succeeds, the less civilized countries are compelled to adopt the superior methods. Thus the benefits of inventions which result from the development of a higher civilization are automatically transferred to the lower, and the socializing influences of improved methods of production become cosmopolitan. This is clearly demonstrated by the adoption of various kinds of American machinery abroad, without the use of which many European products would have been undersold by ours. Nor are the benefits which more highly civilized countries confer upon the lower, limited to what is forced upon them by competition in commodities which they both produce. A still greater benefit arises from the introduction of new commodities, which more diversified tastes and more complex social life of the more highly civilized country bring into existence. As a demand for new commodities increases, labor-saving appliances are invented to reduce the cost of their production, until they can be sold in foreign countries at merely a nominal price. In this case the products of a higher civilization are not competing with those ECONOMIC SELECTION' OF INDUSTRIES. 359 of a lower, but new products are being introduced into less civilized countries ; this stimulates a taste for articles they have not hitherto used, thereby introducing new elements into their social life. Just as fast as a demand for such new commodities is created, the social life is diversified, the standard of living is raised, wages are increased, and a market basis for new industries is established. This is what the diversified tastes and inventive genius of America have been doing in Europe and South America to an increasing extent during the last twenty years. Another advantage of a protective policy is that it tends to make the economic selection of industries possible, thereby promoting the only conditions upon which free trade between nations can ever take place without injury to the higher-wage country. The postulate, so frequently emphasized by the advocates of laissez faire, that nations, like individuals, should be enabled to adopt those industries for which they are best fitted, is unexcep- tionable. But in order to obtain this result, it is necessary to secure opportunities for developing the economic possibilities of the people. It should ever be remembered that the most effec- tive economic force in society is human invention and not natural resources, as is commonly assumed. For reasons already explained, labor-saving inventions can be developed only under the influence of socializing and diversified industries. These conditions, without which a truly economic selection of industries is impossible, are what protection furnishes. Although it may be possible for these conditions to exist with- out protection, history does not furnish an instance where such a thing has occurred. The way in which protection promotes this is easy to understand. In the first place, by raising the basis of international competition to the plane of the higher wage- level, it prevents the lower-paid labor of one country from being made the means of checking the growth of manufacturing in- dustries in another. This secures a home market for domestic products and furnishes an economic basis for a diversification of socializing industries in the higher wage-country. The greatest incentive is thus furnished for developing the most economic methods of production. With concentrated capital, the use of 360 PROTECTION PROMOTES FREE TRADE. highly perfected machinery, and the development of specialized industries, a truly economic selection of industries becomes pos- sible. The conditions will then exist for determining what things a nation can most economically produce, by reason of its pe- culiar character, natural resources, and civilization. When this point is reached, protection will be economically necessary only to the extent of preventing the substitution of simple for complex industries. It will then be to the advantage not only of that nation, but of the world, that it should devote its productive energies to those industries for which it has devel- oped the best capacity, and to relinquish all others to countries for which they are better adapted. Just in proportion as this takes place,, protection becomes unnecessary provided, however, that this change does not involve the substitution of simple for com- plex industries. For example, if America becomes highly profi- cient in the manufacture of jewelry and relatively deficient in the manufacture of silk, capital will naturally go to the former and away from the latter industry. Foreign silk might then be admitted free of duty without injury to the American laborer. It will thus be seen that protection (as here considered) not only prevents a less civilized country from checking the progress of a higher, but by promoting the substitution of economic for natural (blind) selection -of industries, it tends ultimately to make a mu- tually advantageous free trade possible. Thus a protective policy is not necessarily narrow and ex- clusive, but, when philosophically applied, is a most truly cosmopolitan doctrine of industrial relations, because it tends first, to develop home industry and civilization without injuring others, and second, to automatically extend these beneficial results to all mankind. Here, then, we have a truly philosophic and strictly economic basis for applying the protective principle both to foreign and domestic industrial relations. It consists in securing the present and promoting the future opportunities (incentive-creating con- ditions) for developing the highest industrial and social possibili- ties of a people, and may be briefly summarized thus : Foreign Applied to the industrial intercourse of nations, a true protective policy is to prevent the products of the more advanced countries from being undersold by the products PROTECTIVE PRINCIPLE APPLIED. 361 of less civilized countries, through the use of lower paid labor ; thereby securing opportunities for developing the best methods of production afforded by the larger consump- tion and higher social life of the more advanced country. Domestic Applied to the relations of individuals and classes within the nation, this policy is one to guarantee the safety of persons and property with the maximum amount of indi- vidual freedom, and to secure the education, leisure, and other like conditions, which tend to develop the best physical, intellectual, and moral qualities of the individual citizen. The scientific application of this principle to the various phases of industrial, social, and political life is the true function of statesmanship. CHAPTER IV. THE PRINCIPLES OF ECONOMIC TAXATION. SECTION I. The Economic Basis of Equitable Taxation. IN the preceding chapter, taxation was discussed solely as an instrument of industrial protection and national development. It is now proposed to consider taxation as a means of obtaining public revenue. In order to determine how to obtain the neces- sary revenue with the least expense and the greatest equity to all classes, it is necessary briefly to consider : (i) the principle which should determine the individual's contribution to the state ; (2) the source from which the contribution should be drawn. (i) The principle which should govern individual service to the state is a much debated one. It has been contended by some that a tax should be proportionate to the degree of pro- tection furnished by the state. According to this view, if one class of property is exposed to more danger than another, its owners should pay a proportionately higher tax. The objection to this is that it would place the greatest burden upon those least able to bear it. Assuming taxes to stay where they are put, under this system the owners of coal mines, stone quarries, and land would be almost exempt from taxation, -while those engaged in manufacture and commerce would have to pay very high taxes. Moreover, the very poor and helpless, who most frequently need the aid of the state in many forms and are least able to contribute, would be the most heavily taxed. Since the function of government is to protect and promote opportunities for increasing the well-being of the individual, the most equitable basis on which the individual can be called upon to serve the state, is evidently his ability to contribute without injury to him- 362 PROPERTY TAX. 363 self. This idea is more or less generally recognized, as is shown in the frequent demand to have a heavier tax imposed upon com- modities consumed by the rich than upon those consumed by the poor. And the frequent demand for taxing incomes above a certain amount, the exemption of wages and small homesteads, all of which are efforts to make the rich contribute more to the public revenue than the poor, upon the principle that they are more able to contribute. (2) From what source should this tribute to the state be drawn, or what is the best measure of an individual's capacity to pay without injury to his own well-being ? It is commonly assumed that the ability of a citizen to pay a tax is proportionate to the property he owns ; this, however, is far from being correct. For instance, one may legally own a large amount of property which is so highly mortgaged as to make his ownership merely nominal. To tax such a man in proportion to his property would impover- ish him, while the effect of a similar tax upon his neighbor whose property is free from mortgage would be relatively slight. One manufacturer with a large plant may, through a mere change of fashion or other social cause, be working at a loss, while another, with a similar plant, but who is unaffected by the fashion, may be making large profits. Clearly, to tax the property of these two at the same rate would be to deprive the former of his means of getting a living, while from the latter it would take but a fraction of his surplus, and hence would in no way impair his present industrial or social status. Manifestly then a uniform tax upon product or property would not fall with equal weight upon all. In other words, the owner- ship of property does not constitute a correct measure of the^in- dividual's ability to contribute to the public revenue. There is but one source from which wealth can be taken with the certainty that it will not inflict a burden, and that is, surplus income, which embraces all the forms of rent, interest, and profit. The reason this form of income can be taxed with the least burden to its owner is that it does not enter into the necessary cost of his living. The cost of the social well-being of all who participate in production being a part of the necessary cost of production is represented by wages and salaries, the surplus is what remains after these costs are defrayed. Consequently, ai- 364 MOBILITY OF TAXES. though to pay a tax from one's surplus is to lessen one's wealth, it does not intrench upon the normal means of social well-being, and therefore inflicts the minimum amount of economic and social inconvenience. Clearly then, the extent of the surplus in- come is the measure of an individual's ability to contribute to the public revenue without injury to his own well-being. How then can taxes be levied so as to be drawn from the economic surplus of the community without disturbing industrial relations ? This would be a very simple problem if the taxes would stay where they are put and were paid by those upon whom they are levied. But this is just what does not occur. In order therefore, to answer this question, it is necessary to consider the economic mobility of taxes. SECTION II. The Mobility of Taxes and their Relation to Wages. To ascertain how taxes travel from one to another class in the community, and to find by whom they are ultimately paid, we have only to follow a tax from where it is levied to the place where it cannot be further shifted. For illustration, let us sup- pose that a tax is laid upon land ; the land being the source of all raw material, such a tax would affect all commodities in the first stage of their production. Upon the principle that a commodity cannot be continuously furnished for less than it costs, the tax will be added to the price of the product in the same way as wages and other items, and must be paid by the purchaser. If the article is wheat, the tax is thus transferred from the far- mer to the miller. The tax being an inevitable item in the cost of the flour to the miller it is transferred by him to the wholesale merchant, and by him to the retail grocer, who in turn passes it on to the consumer. Manifestly unless the consumer can transfer the tax to some one else, he must pay it, because it is included in the price of his commodity in addition to all necessary costs. This brings us to the most critical point of the subject. All writers of any standing recognize the mobility of the tax from the raw material to the consumer of the finished product. But it is generally assumed that the tax cannot be made to travel any further than the commodity in whose cost it is an item, and con- sequently whoever consumes the article ultimately pays the tax. RELATION OF TAXES TO WAGES. 365 If we examine the matter more closely, however, we shall see that this conclusion is only partially correct. Whether or not those who consume the wheat pay the tax, will depend upon whether its consumption forms an item in any further series of production. Suppose, for instance, the wheat is consumed by horses that are employed in a brick-yard. The wheat in that case at once be- comes an item in the cost of using the horse, which in turn is an item in the cost of the brick. This point is very important here, because it has a direct bearing upon whether or not the laborer ultimately pays the tax included in the price of the com- modities he consumes. The laborer, it should be remembered, exercises two functions One is social, and the other economic. As a social factor he is a consumer, and constitutes an important item both in ^civilization and in the market. As an economic factor, however, he is simply a productive force. In this capacity he affects the price of the product in precisely the same way as does any other force so employed, whether it be through the instrumentality of ani- mals or machinery. Economically they all affect the cost and price of the product in the same way, namely, through the cost of procuring them. The cost of any productive instrument is what is consumed in maintaining its productive efficiency, and that cost must be replenished from the price of the product. Now, the cost of maintaining the productive efficiency of the laborer is his living. Whatever is necessary to that is a part of the price of his labor wages, and therefore becomes a neces- sary item in the cost of whatever he produces. Clearly, there- fore, the more his living costs, the more expensive will be his labor. If his cost of living could be reduced, either by inducing him to consume fewer commodities or by lessening the cost of those he does consume, his wages could easily be lowered. The price of labor in Asia and continental Europe is less than in America because labor there costs less. 1 For the same reason that the price of labor would fall if the cost of the laborer's living could be reduced, it must and will rise if the cost of that living is increased. Nor does it matter whether the increased cost is due to an increase in the amount of '"Wealth and Progress," Part II., chap, vii., sec. i., pp. 162-167; also Brassey's " Work and Wages," pp. 88, 89, 94-96. 366 THE LABORER SHIFTS THE TAX. wealth he consumes or to a rise in the price of that wealth. Thus, during the American war, when the price of commodities was greatly increased through the inflation of the currency, wages soon moved in the same direction and fell again when the prices were lowered as, indeed, they have throughout all history. 1 Clearly, therefore, if the price of a laborer's flour, sugar, coffee, clothing, and the like is increased by a tax, the result will be economically the same as if the higher price were due to the payment of higher wages to agricultural laborers, a rise in the rate of transportation, a failure of crops, or any other cause ; and if it becomes perma- nent it will result in his demanding and obtaining higher nominal wages. The laborer would not gain any thing in well-being by such a rise of wages, but it would be necessary in order to furnish him the amount of well-being to which he had become habitually accustomed, and without which he would refuse to work. In this way, therefore, the tax is transferred from the laborer to the em- ployer. 2 What is true of the laborer is equally true of all who receive stipulated incomes. To whom, then, it may be asked, does the employer transfei- the tax ? Here the answer is as before to whomsoever he can. And if he cannot transfer it to anybody, he must pay it himself. He will of course utilize all the economic forces at his command to pass the tax to somebody else. He may first try to make the 1 " Wealth and Progress," pp. 148-156; also McCulloch's "Principles of Political Economy," p. 181. 3 This fact was recognized by the early English writers, although, like many others of their best suggestions, it has been subsequently treated rather as an incidental than a primary fact. Adam Smith says : " Such a tax must there- fore occasion a rise in the wages of labor proportionable to this rise of price. It is thus that a tax upon the necessaries of life operates in exactly the same man- ner as a direct tax upon the wages of labor. The laborer, though he may pay it out of his hand, cannot, for any considerable time at least, be properly said to even advance it. It must always, in the long run, be advanced to him by his immediate employer in the advanced rate of wages." " Wealth of Nations," Book V., chap, ii., article iv., pp. 691 and 692 ; see also pp. 686, 693, 694, and 704. Ricardo says : " There can be no permanent fall of wages, but in con- sequence of a fall of the necessaries on which wages are expended." " Political Economy and Taxation," p. 75. "A tax, however, on raw produce and on the necessaries of the laborer, would have another effect it would raise wages." find., p. 93. " The effect of a tax on wages would be to raise wages by a sum at least equal to the tax, and would be finally, if not immediately, paid by the employer of labor." Ibid., p. 133 ; see also pp. 129, 136, and 141. TAXES DRAWN FROM THE SURPLUS. 367 laborer pay it by refusing to increase wages, but here he will be met by the laborer's refusal to work, and, should he try to put it on the consumer in higher prices, he will only be repeating the circle, because the increase in the price will act as before upon wages, and he will have to pay out to the laborer what he has thus exacted from the consumer. In the last analysis, therefore, the only source from which the employer can pay the tax is his surplus or profit. 1 That being, as we saw in the last section, the- true measure of the individual's ability to contribute to the public revenue without curtailing his own well-being, it is the most equitable basis of taxation. This brings us to the question how the employer replenishes his surplus from which taxes are finally drawn. SECTION III. The Ultimate Effect of Taxation upon Profits and the General Wealth of the Community. If the conclusion reached in the last section is correct, and taxes finally come out of the surplus product, then it follows that either profits diminish as taxes increase, or that the employer has some means of replenishing his surplus. We know from ex- perience that the aggregate amount of wealth taken in taxes tends to increase as society advances, and it is equally certain that the aggregate profits do not diminish. On the contrary, while there is a tendency to minimize the rate of profit per unit of product, the aggregate amount of surplus product in various forms un- questionably tends to increase. Clearly, then, there must be some means by which the employer can replenish his surplus when thus drained by taxation. How does he do it ? We have already seen that he cannot take it from the consumer 1 Accordingly, any extra pressure of taxation is always first felt by the business portion of the community in the diminution of profits. Hence we always find the commercial class the first to protest against excessive taxation. For this reason no representative government, and few despotic ones, could suddenly increase the taxation of the country by an amount equal to the aggregate profits of the community, because such an act would practically be a seizure of the total surplus revenue, which would, in all probability, cause a revolution that would destroy the government. That is why, whenever an exceptionally large amount is to be suddenly raised by taxes, it invariably takes the form of a loan for a long period, thus extending the ultimate payment of a portion of the tax to future generations. 368 HOW THE SURPLUS IS REPLENISHED. by raising prices, nor from the laborer by reducing wages. That he does not take it from either of these sources is further shown by the fact that contemporaneously with the increase of taxation, real wages have risen and the price of commodities has fallen. Manifestly then, the only way the producer's surplus can be replenished is by a new draft upon nature through increased production. Nor will it be difficult to see how this takes place, if we bear in mind the law of prices and surplus, previously presented. Under this law, whenever productive methods are employed by which nature yields a greater amount of wealth for the same effort, all other demands upon the product being fixed amounts, the whole gain naturally flows to the contingent surplus of those who use the new methods. Consequently, all increase in the wealth of any stipulated income class in the community, whether it be through lowering prices or increasing wages, must be drawn from the contingent surplus of the producers. For instance when, by the adoption of more productive instruments, the sur- plus of the most successful producers increases, there arises a greater inducement to invest more capital in the enterprise, and thus increase production. In order to insure the sale of this increased production, it is offered at a lower price. If this reduction be ten per cent., the uniform price of the total product in that market will fall ten per cent. Manifestly this fall comes directly out of the profits of the producers, and all who were previously making less than ten per cent, profit will now have to leave the business or adopt the methods by which the reduction was brought about. Thus the additional wealth resulting from the increased productive efficiency first flows to the economic surplus of those producing the improvement, and then by com- petition, is transferred from the producers' surplus to the com- munity in lower prices. An increase of wages takes place upon the same general principles, and with substantially the same result, but it comes in a somewhat different way. A reduction in prices is a distri- bution of the surplus through the aggressive action of employers. An increase of wages is a distribution of the surplus by the aggressive action of laborers. As already explained, the enforced transfer from profits to wages compels the producer either to TAXES INCREASE PRODUCTION. 369 work without profit, or perhaps at a loss, or to adopt some labor-saving means by which more can be produced at the same cost. Thus the laborer's encroachment upon the capitalist's surplus forces him, under penalty of poverty, to make nature yield more wealth for the same effort, thus replenishing what the laborer has taken from him, and making the community absolutely richer by the amount to which wages have been increased. 1 What is true of wages is true of any other form of increased consumption which adds to the cost of production. Taxation is precisely of this character. If 10 per cent, is added to the price of wheat or cotton by a tax, the mobility and ultimate economic effect upon profits and production will be identically the same as if 10 per cent, had been added to the cost by an increase of wages. The same economic power which would enable the farmer to add to the price of wheat an increase m the farm laborers' wages, and the miller, wholesale and retail merchant, each in turn to add it to the price of flour, and the mechanic, who consumes the flour, to add it to his wages, and thus ultimately take it from the employers' profits, will enable them to do pre- cisely the same by a tax which increases the cost of production in the same way, no matter at what stage of the process it is levied. Taxation, like wages, is simply a form of consumption, and hence exercises the same influence upon profits and the general wealth of the community as any other form of consump- tion namely, to increase the aggregate production, which added increment goes to replenish the source from which the tax was last taken the employer's profit. It will thus be seen that the entrepreneur does not pay the tax, in the sense of being permanently the poorer by it, any more than does the farmer, miller, merchant, or laborer. They each shift it on to the next purchaser of the product into whose cost it has entered. In the laborer's case, having become a part of the cost of his labor, it is charged to the employer in the same way. The employer, being unable to charge it upon any class of his fellow-men, is forced, by the impulse of self-interest, to exact it from nature, which he finally does in the form of a larger product. Therefore Professor Sumner's statement that " every 1 Part II., chap, v., sec. iii. Also " Wealth and Progress," pp. 31, 32. 24 37O IMPORTANCE OP TAXATION EXAGGERATED. tax is an evil " is essentially false. A tax is not necessarily an evil any more than wages or any other form of consumption. 1 It will thus be seen that taxation properly occupies no such important position in economics as is usually ascribed to it. If the total consumption upon which the $300,000,000 of taxes in this country is expended were abolished to-morrow, instead of adding to our wealth, it would create an industrial depression in this and probably in several other countries, until, by enforced idleness and bankruptcy, production could be readjusted on the narrower basis to conform to the diminished consumption or demand. Were this relation of consumption to production prop- erly understood, taxation would cease to be the hobgoblin of public affairs. The important question regarding taxation is not as to who shall pay the taxes, nor how much they shall be, but as to how they shall be expended. If a large amount of wealth is exacted from the community in taxes, and is squandered, then there would be no justification for a readjustment of economic relations which its production involves. If the tax revenue is used to repress any phase of social progress, as would be in maintaining a standing army, it is then a positive injury. Only when the wealth created by tax is used to further the social development of the people has it any economic or ethical justifi- cation. Upon what principle, then, should the public revenue be expended in order to justify its collection ? SECTION IV. The Legitimate Sphere of Public Expenditures. Since the public revenue is but the means by which government fulfils its functions, its expenditure is necessarily limited to the sphere of governmental action. We have already seen that the functions of government are essentially protective, judiciary, educa- tional, and impersonal in their character. Clearly therefore, the sphere of public expenditures is properly limited to the promotion of those objects which may be conveniently grouped into two classes as the Static and the Dynamic functions of government. 1 Whether or not a rise of wages or an increase of taxation will be beneficial will depend largely upon how it is expended, and this, in turn, will depend upon the influences by which it was brought about, but, in any event, it will cause an increase in production. TWO FUNCTIONS OF GOVERNMENT. 3/1 The static functions embrace all that is necessary to secure the community against a common enemy and to enforce the recog- nized system of social order as expressed in established institu- tions. This may require a large army, an extensive police force, and a numerous staff of judiciary and executive officers. The means necessary to sustain these instruments of public order should be supplied from the public revenue, for the obvious reason that it is the function above all others which can be best performed by the government, and without which it would be impossible for the individual to perform with safety and freedom any of the industrial and social duties of a civilized citizen. All expenditure for this purpose represents the price that civilization has to pay for guarding itself against the effects of barbarism, and should be reduced as rapidly as possible. To accomplish this reduction involves the exercise of the dynamic functions of government. These relate to increasing the opportunity for developing all phases of individual capacity and freedom. Opportunity, as the term is here employed, is distinctively educational in the broadest sense of the word. Every thing is educational that brings man into more frequent contact with an increasing variety of social influences which tend to stimu- late his wants and desires, sharpen his intelligence, and actualize the latent possibilities of his character. This embraces not only the elementary education furnished by the common school, which is of prime importance to citizenship, but it also includes the furnishing of clean, wholesome streets, good drainage, ventilation, and other sanitary requisites to wholesome domestic life, an abun- dance of public parks, gardens, museums, free lectures, reading- rooms, circulating libraries, and, above all, the leisure necessary to enable the masses to avail themselves of these and kindred educating and elevating influences. To the extent that these opportunities are increased will the intelligence and character of the citizen be elevated and the functions of the soldier, policeman, judge, and jailer become unnecessary. Consequently, to the extent that the public revenue is expended in performing the dynamic functions of the state will the amount required to perform the static functions diminish. This is the more import- ant because every dollar that is consumed by the government in exercising its static functions involves so much production 3/2 PUBLIC IMPROVEMENTS, without any real increase in well-being, it being all consumed in guarding what already exists. On the other hand, every dollar expended by the state in performing its dynamic functions involves an increase of production, all of which is a net gain in social well-being. Therefore, instead of treating all taxes as an evil to be dimin- ished, it is only the amount of the public revenue consumed by the government in performing its executive and police duties that can properly be so regarded. All that is consumed in extending the socializing opportunities of the people is a positive benefit and should be increased, especially as the increase of the latter is the surest way of diminishing the former. To oppose an increase of taxation for public improvements, in the name of economy, is a fallacy which cannot be too frequently exposed. It is just as important to have clean streets as to have clean houses, and the wealth consumed in the one contributes to civilization as much as that consumed in the other. The only question to be con- sidered regarding such expenditures, is whether or not they can be more efficiently conducted by the government than by private individuals. 1 But that the wealth so consumed should be increased is sustained by all the interests of civilization, and those who oppose it are unconsciously or otherwise obstructing the movement of social progress as surely as those who oppose popular education and favor long hours of labor and low wages. SECTION V. How can Taxes be Most Equitably Levied, Conveniently Paid, and Economically Collected? This proposition involves two questions : (i) How taxes should be levied. (2) What they should be levied upon. i. There are two general methods by which the public revenue can be obtained direct and indirect taxation. It is a peculiar feature in the history of taxation that those who are charged with the responsibility of raising the revenue and with the administra- tion of government, usually prefer to obtain the revenue through indirect taxation. On the other hand, revenue reformers and social reformers generally advocate direct taxation. Direct taxation is urged in preference to indirect, chiefly on the 1 See Part IV., chapter ii., section iii. DIRECT TAXATION. 373 ground that a tax is an evil which should always be minimized, and that if taxes were collected directly from the individual he would then realize how much he paid, and would therefore be more strenuous in his demands for a retrenchment of the public revenue. They insist that indirect taxation is simply a cunning device for making the citizen contribute to the public revenue under the guise of purchasing the necessaries of life, thus obtain- ing wealth from the individual which he would otherwise refuse to contribute. This position is based upon two assumptions : (i) that taxes are necessarily an evil to be minimized ; (2) that direct taxation affords each individual an opportunity of correctly estimating the amount he contributes to the public revenue. In the first place it is an entire mistake to regard taxes as neces- sarily an evil. We have already seen that they simply represent the consumption of wealth in a public form, and have the same economic effect upon production, industry, and commerce gener- ally, as does private consumption. And whether or not private or public consumption will be permanently beneficial to the com- munity depends upon how such consumption takes place. To the degree that wealth is consumed in extending public improvements and enlarging the social opportunities of the people, it is both economically and socially a positive advantage. The assumption therefore that taxes are at best a necessary evil is not only erroneous in fact, but it is extremely mischievous in its effect, as it inspires opposition to expenditures for public improve- ments. Nor is the idea that direct taxation enables each individual accurately to determine the amount he contributes to the public revenue any nearer correct. This is another of the numerous errors arising from a misconception of the law of wages. From what has already been said it will not be difficult to see that a direct tax upon the individual is just as mobile as an indirect tax levied upon the commodities he consumes. If a merchant can transfer a tax upon flour to the consumer, because it adds to its cost to him, he can also transfer to the consumer a tax upon his house or his horse for the same reason. The same is true of the laborer. A direct tax upon his house or his wages or any thing in his possession, is simply so much addition to the cost of his living, and can be transferred through 374 EVILS OF DIRECT TAXATION. higher wages to the employer in precisely the same way as is his house rent, and the cost of his food, clothes, and other necessaries of life. 1 In many parts of England the different classes of local expenditure such as the " poor's rate," the "cemetery rate," the " highway rate," the " water rate," the " local-board rate," etc., are collected directly from each householder by the tax-gatherer in separate items, and often by different persons. These rates however, enter into the cost of the laborer's living, and have to be covered by his wages just as much as the amount of his grocery bill or his house rent, and are everywhere so recognized. 8 Where the rates and rents are high, as in London and other large centres, the wages in all industries are correspondingly higher than in localities where these items are low, which is one of the reasons why wages are always higher in large cities than in small towns and rural districts. 3 The economic mobility of a tax is in no- wise affected by the fact that it is directly or indirectly collected. Whether the taxes are gathered directly from the laborer in a specific sum, or indirectly through the enhanced price of com- modities, makes no real difference. In either case it enters into the cost of his living and the price of his service, and hence is ultimately transferred to the employer. Instead, therefore, of direct taxation enabling the laborer accurately to determine the amount he pays to the government, it has the opposite effect, and he is deluded into the belief that he is heavily burdened by pub- lic expenditures, whereas he actually contributes nothing except temporarily during periods of readjustment. Moreover, the effect of direct taxation is pernicious in many ways. In the first place it creates a strong incentive for evading taxes, which is a standing inducement to dishonesty. So long as men believe that they are permanently impoverished by what they pay into the public treasury, they will endeavor to devise 1 " Wealth of Nations." 2 So manifest is this that where whole classes of laborers have to ride to and from their work, as in London and other large cities, the price of their fare is recognized as a proper cause for demanding higher wages, and in other districts where the employer furnishes the laborer's house rent-free, or the privilege of keeping a cow, etc., it is equally regarded as a legitimate reason for paying lower wages, and in such cases wages always are lower. 3 "Wealth and Progress," Part II., chap. vii. PROPERTY AND INCOME TAX. 375 means to elude the tax-gatherer ; the " tax-dodger " is a well- known character. 1 In the next place direct taxation creates a strong feeling of dissatisfaction among the different classes in the community as to the justice or injustice of taxing or not taxing different classes of property. Hence the interminable controversy as to whether or not workingmen's homes should be exempt from taxation. It is held to be unjust to tax the work- ingman's home because that would be putting the burden upon those who are least able to bear it. But if they are to be exempt, at what point should the exemption be fixed ? To exempt home- steads at a given valuation would tend to encourage the building of houses within that valuation limit ; and that would be a decided injury, because it would act as a check upon the building of superior houses, and hence tend to stereotype inferior domestic conditions. Again, whether or not all personal property should be taxed, and if not what kind should be exempt, is another point of con- tention. Some insist that productive property should not be taxed, because such taxation discourages industry, while others contend that to tax non-productive property is unjust, since it yields no income. And certain it is that every attempt to tax personal property encourages systematic misrepresentation and other fraudulent practices too numerous to recite. 2 The same is true of income tax. This tax is assessed on the assumption that it draws the revenue from surplus incomes which would otherwise escape taxation. But when it is understood that in the normal course of economic movement all taxes are finally drawn from the surplus product, the force of such reasoning entirely disappears. So far from direct taxation being the model method of raising public revenue, therefore, it is essentially un- economic and demoralizing. It involves the maximum incon- 1 In Boston for instance it has become an established practice among a large number of rich men to temporarily reside in Nahant, a small town a few miles from the city, where the local taxes are very light. By living there on the first of May, when assessments are made, they are taxed for Nahant instead of Boston. While they actually live in Boston, and obtain all the advantages of the large public expenditures there, they are only taxed according to the trifling expenditure in Nahant. * See Prof. E. R. A. Seligman on " The General Property Tax," Political Science Quarterly, March, 1890. 3/6 INDIRECT TAXATION. venience, puts a premium on dishonesty, and tends to make the average citizen a persistent enemy of public improvements, without affording any compensating advantages. In short, direct taxation is defensible only in cases of exceptional emergency such as wars, 1 and even then but for the briefest period pos- sible. Since the public revenue must be directly or indirectly col- lected, it follows that all the reasons for objecting to direct taxation obtain in favor of the indirect. While it is highly important that the individual should always be fully informed regarding real burdens, it is quite as important that he be not deluded into assuming imaginary ones. Since the public con- sumption represented by taxation is not a permanent burden upon any class in the community, the public welfare demands that taxes should be so levied as not to have that appearance. Consequently, instead of making taxes as direct as possible, thereby giving them the most burdensome seeming, they should be levied with the greatest indirectness, so as to be as impercepti- ble as possible. To the extent that the individual ceases to be conscious of his contribution, and its exact amount becomes difficult to determine, will the incentive for the various forms of dishonesty and corruption for evading taxation disappear. And when an important public improvement is proposed which in- volves a large expenditure, the decision of the average citizen regarding it will be less likely to be neutralized by the feelings of his own inability to contribute his share. By removing this con- scious personal element, the question of taxation will be considered solely with regard to its effects upon the community, thus removing one of the greatest obstacles to public improvements. With this view of taxation, all public expenditures of a protective, educa- tional, opportunity-creating character (judiciously applied) would be regarded as an actual addition to the wealth of the community, 1 The only reason for adopting direct taxation in case of war is that the surplus income is reached quicker by that means, but it is far more inconvenient and arbitrary ; and even in such cases it is more economic to borrow the necessary amount and let it be finally repaid out of the revenue indirectly collected. When it is thus furnished through the normal operation of economic law, it tends gradually to replenish the surplus from which it is drawn by increased production, and thus minimize, if not indeed obviate, the burden upon the com- munity. ADVANTAGES OF LAND TAX. 377 to be increased, instead of as at present being treated as a burden to be avoided at every turn. 2. Upon what class of property should taxes be levied is the question that remains to be considered. The important point to be considered in determining the class of property upon which taxes should be levied is how to obtain the greatest indirection of movement with the least cost of collection. Manifestly a tax will have the greatest indirection of movement, and hence be most completely subject to economic law which passes through the largest number of hands and enters into the greatest variety of productive processes. To give a tax the greatest indirection, therefore, it must be levied at the point farthest removed from those by whom it will be finally paid. Since all taxes are finally drawn from the surplus product, they would necessarily be most direct when levied upon profits or other surplus, and conversely most indirect when levied upon the source of raw material. Upon the same principle that a tax upon surplus incomes cannot be shifted to any other class in the community, because it does not enter into the cost of production, a tax on raw material can be shifted in a multitude of ways before reaching any class of consumers, because it all enters into the cost of production, and becomes an indistinguishable part of the price of commodities. Clearly then, the greatest indirection would be secured by imposing a tax on real estate, especially on land. A tax upon land would of course be an addition to the cost of producing every species of wealth in the community. It is equally clear that a tax upon real estate would be the most easy and inexpensive to collect. In the first place, it is the form of property that is most accessible, it cannot be con- cealed from the eye of the assessor ; hence it affords the least temptation 'for tax-dodging, or other dishonorable means of evasion. It is also the class of property whose value is most easily ascertained, because it is most frequently and permanently in the open market for sale or rent, either fact furnishing the basis for ascertaining its current value at any given time. This form of property has the further, advantage of being immovable. The owner may leave the city, State, or country, but the real estate remains as accessible as ever. Another advantage in this form of taxation is that it avoids all the objectionable inquisitorial 378 EQUITABLE NATURE OF LAND TAX. features involved in all direct, personal, and property taxes. There is no other form of property in society upon which taxes can be so easily and accurately assessed, so cheaply collected, and with as little intrusion upon the freedom of the citizen. Nor can there be any complaint that such a tax would press unduly upon the landowner, because, so far as the income from the land represents the cost of service rendered in using it for productive purposes, the tax will all come back in the price of the product ; and only that portion of the tax which falls upon the surplus as rent, interest, and profit will be untransfera- ble and finally paid by the landowner, the equity of which no one can question. Nor can any legitimate complaint be made by those who advance the tax at any of the subsequent stages. In every case, so far as it affects the cost of economic production either in the form of the cost of raw material, tools, labor, or any thing whatsoever, it can be added to the price. Neither could there properly be any complaint about the personal wealth of the rich escaping taxation, because the tax having been laid at the source of economic movement, its/#// amount is included in the price of every thing they buy. Hence their only means of suc- cessfully avoiding taxation would be to forego consumption, which is to relinquish wealth and civilization. If taxes were thus levied, the rich jewelry, wardrobes, furnishings, and equi- pages of the wealthy would all carry their quota of taxation, and so far as they represented the stock of the manufacturer or merchant, or were included in the necessary cost of living of any who render productive service, the tax included in their price would be transferable as in all other cases ; that portion of these forms of wealth only which was supplied from surplus income would have finally to bear the tax. There certainly could be no justice in making an article, which has already borne its full quota of taxation in its economic journey to the consumer, yield a fresh tax each year after it leaves the sphere of economic move- ment. Such a tax must necessarily act as a direct check upon all new forms of consumption, especially among the wage- and salary- receiving class, and thus be positively inimical to the development of a high standard of living and social progress. It will perhaps be objected that if taxes were all levied on real estate, and acted as an increase in the cost of raw material, the OBJECTIONS ANSWERED. 379 tax would fall the heaviest on those articles containing the largest amount of raw material. And since food and the coarser manu- factured products consumed by the masses contain a much larger proportion of raw material than the finer products of manufacture and art consumed by the wealthy, the tax would fall much more heavily upon the poor than upon the rich. This is an objection which can be easily answered, if we bear in mind the law govern- ing the mobility of taxes. It is true that in high-priced jewelry, pictures, books, and indeed the finer products of manufacture and art, the raw material forms the most insignificant portion of the cost. And if the tax represented in the price of such articles was limited to what is conveyed by the cost of raw material, it would indeed be very slight. The fact is, however, that the tax in such products enters mainly through the labor. Although the tax-bearing raw material in these products is very slight, that represented in the laborer's wages, which includes all that enters into his living, is very great, and as the high price of such prod- ucts is largely made up of the cost of labor, they bear the tax levied upon all the raw material consumed by the laborer. The tax, therefore, in the finer products of manufacture and art will not be proportionate to the raw material they actually contain, but to all the raw material that has been consumed by every thing used in producing them. In other words, their contribution to the public revenue will be proportionate to their value as finished products, and therefore they represent the greatest instead of the least tax-transmitting power. Another objection that will probably be urged against this position is, that a tax on raw material has the effect of adding to the price of the product not only the tax but also the profit upon the tax to those who advance it. This view has long been held by leading English economists. 1 According to this view, every time a tax is transferred it carries with it an added increment of 1 Adam Smith says : "A tax upon those articles necessarily raises their price somewhat higher than the amount of the tax, because the dealer who advances the tax must generally get it back with the profit. . . . His employer, if he is a manufacturer, will charge upon the price of his goods this rise of wages with a profit, so that the final payment of the tax, together with his overcharge, will fall upon the consumer." "Wealth of Nations," Book V., chap, ii., article iv., pp. 691, 692. 380 MILL'S ERROR. profit. Consequently, if it is transferred enough times, the amount of profit which is added to the consumer's price of the finished product by the tax will be greater than the tax itself. This doc- trine is a logical part of the orthodox theory of profits, according to which the normal profits of the capitalists form a necessary part of the cost of production, and hence of the price of commo- dities. In stating this theory, Mill says : " And profit, we have also seen, is not exclusively the surplus remaining to the capitalist after he has been compensated for his outlay, but forms, in most cases, no unimportant part of the outlay itself." And after enu- merating a long series of processes, in which the profits of each are compounded in the next, he adds : " All these advances form a part of the cost of production of linen. Profits, therefore, as well as wages, enter into the cost of production which deter- mines the value of the produce." ' Were this doctrine correct, it would certainly form an unanswerable objection to all indirect taxation, and indeed to indirect production also. Since every specialization and division of labor adds to the series of distinct profit-yielding processes, industrial improvements would serve to increase the power of the capitalist to add compound profit to the consumer's price of commodities. Fortunately for civilization, however, economic law permits no such compound profit-making process. We have already seen that the price of the product in a given market tends to a uniformity on the basis of the cost of furnishing tha dearest portion. 2 Consequently the profits of each producer can only be equal to the difference between his cost of production and that of those furnishing the dearest increment of the general supply, this increment being sold without profit. It is impossible there- fore in any market, or at any stage of the productive process, to add the producer's profit to the consumer's price, since competi- tion compels all who contribute to the same market to sell at the same price, which price is fixed by the cost of the no-profit produc- ers. Consequently, if there is any profit, it must be obtained from nature through greater economy in production. It will thus be seen that the claim that taxes upon land or raw material must be repaid with a profit to those who pay them, is a pure phantom 1 " Principles of Political Economy," vol. i., p. 568. 8 Part II., chap, iv., pp. 125-128. Cf, pp. 205, 206. POPULAR DELUSION. 381 which entirely vanishes in the light of the true law of economic prices, and with it disappear all the objections to indirect taxa- tion, based upon adding compound profit to consumers' prices. It will be seen that the question of taxation is much less funda- mental than it is usually made to appear. Like the question of money, it is frequently employed to influence public opinion on a multitude of questions on which it has practically no bearing. Taxation is simply the consumption of wealth in a public form, and has no more economic effect than the same amount of wealth privately consumed. The only interest therefore the community has in the question is that the taxes shall be economically col- lected and wisely expended. If this fact is once clearly under- stood, the misconceptions in which the subject has been involved will disappear. Then the popular delusion that all taxes are finally paid by the laborer would lose its political utility, and the equally erroneous notion of Henry George, that to levy all taxes "on land-values would abolish poverty and establish universal freedom, would at once be recognized as a mere social mirage. The only advantage in levying taxes upon land and real estate in preference to incomes and personal property is that the revenue can be collected from the former with greater ease, certainty, and convenience. CHAPTER V. BUSINESS DEPRESSIONS. SECTION I. Economic Characteristics of Business Depressions. THERE are few questions upon which a greater variety of opinion exists than business depressions. They are ascribed to a different cause in every country, and often to as many different causes in the same country as there are phases of social reform, political parties, sectional or industrial interests. 1 Before any intelligent understanding of the cause of these social calamities can be obtained, it will be necessary to consider their economic peculiarities, and the industrial or other conditions under which they occur. The first general characteristic of business depressions is that they are periods of exceptional industrial adversity. But there are two kinds of industrial adversity, whose characteristics and causes are widely different ; these are famines and business de- pressions. A famine is an actual scarcity of consumable wealth ; a business depression, on the contrary, is a relative plethora of consumable wealth. The first symptom of a famine is the failure to produce a sufficient amount of wealth to meet the existing de- 1 The business depressions of 1873-1878 were attributed to over two hundred different causes by the various economists, capitalists, philosophers, and re- formers, who testified before the Congressional Committee to investigate the subject. See reports of the Wright and Hewitt Congressional Committees on " Industrial Depressions," also the report of the United States Senate Com- mittee on " Education and Labor," 1885, and the report of the Commissioner of Labor on " Industrial Depressions," 1886. Also report of Royal Commis- sion (England, 1885) on the " Cause of Industrial Depressions." 382 DEPRESSIONS, FAMINES, AND PANICS. 383 mands of the community ; while the first indication of a business depression is the failure to find sufficient customers to carry off the existing supply of commodities. The economic distinction, therefore, between a famine and a business depression is that the former springs from a scarcity of commodities and the latter from a scarcity of consumers. , Nor do famines and business depressions both occur in the same countries. India, Egypt, and other less civilized countries, have frequently suffered severely from famine and consequent pes- tilence, as did also Europe during the Middle Ages, thousands, and sometimes millions, died of hunger and disease, 1 but they have no business depressions. America and the leading countries in Europe no longer have famines, but they have business depres- sions. Famines and business depressions are not only economi- cally distinct, and occur in different countries, but the very conditions which promote the one tend to prevent the other. The very specialization of industry and development of science that have steadily diminished the possibility of famines, have brought into existence involved commercial relations and the factory system which make business depressions possible. Nor must business depressions be confounded with financial panics ; these are disturbances of another kind. A money panic may arise in the midst of business prosperity as at present (1890). Although, like any other social disturbance, a financial panic has a harmful effect upon the industrial community, it being purely a fiscal disturbance the evil effect is largely restricted to the specu- lative class. A money panic may be the final straw which reveals a business depression, but if the consumption of commodities is practically equal to the production it cannot produce one. Busi- ness depressions, therefore, may be characterized as periods of industrial adversity peculiar to machine-using countries, and arise from a failure to sell and never from an inability to produce consumable wealth. Another characteristic of business depressions is that they are not local or even national in their movement, but that they occur with striking uniformity in all countries in which they occur at all. This will be seen by the following table, which shows the 1 Mr. Cornelius Walford, F.I. A., F.S.S., in a paper published in the Sta- tistical Journal, vol. xli., gives the history of 350 famines. 384 Hi 'STORY OF DEPRESSIONS, recurrence of business depressions in England, France, United States, Germany, and Belgium during this century. 1 England France. United States. Germany. Belgium. 1803 1804 1810 1810 1815 1813 1814 1818 1818 1818 .... 1826 1826 1826 1830 1830 ..... 1837 1837 1837 1837 , 1837 1847 1847 1847 1847 1848 1857 1856 1857 1855 1855 1866 1866 1867 1864 1873 1873 1873 1873 1873 1883 1882 1882 1882 1882 1885 1885 1885 1885 1885 By this table three facts are clearly indicated : (i) That busi- ness depressions are limited to machine-using countries beginning in England with the rise of the factory system. (2) That they have steadily extended to other countries as fast as factory methods of production have been adopted ; that is to say, as fast as they became manufacturing and commercial countries. (3) That business depressions have been practically uniform and international in their movement, and that all countries with- out regard to form of government, political institutions, physical or climatic peculiarities, when once afflicted are visited with every recurrence and almost simultaneously. With these facts before us regarding the nature and history of business depres- sions, we are in a position to intelligently consider the causes from which they arise. SECTION II. Cause of Business Depressions. In order to warrant the conclusion that any circumstance is the cause of succeeding phenomena, it is at least necessary: (i) that it should be adequate to produce the effect ; (2) that it sustain some necessary relation to it. In seeking the cause of business depressions therefore, we must first eliminate from the problem all influences which are clearly insufficient to produce them. Among the hundred or more specific causes assigned for 1 First Annual Report of U. S. Commissioner of Labor, p. 290. CAUSES ASSIGNED. 385 the business depression of 1873 in this country were excessive speculation in railroads and real estate, inflation of the currency, high protective tariff, and the unnatural stimulus given to industry by the war. 1 But when we observe that none of these things occurred in England, and that still the industrial depression was as severe there as here, it becomes clear that these causes were insufficient to explain the facts. So too in the case of France. The fact that at the close of the war in 1872 France was compelled to pay an indemnity to Germany of five millards of francs in gold, appears at first sight to furnish a sufficient reason why she should have experienced a state of severe business depression and poverty in 1873. But when we observe that the depression was just as severe and protracted in Germany, where this colossal indemnity was received, as in France, from whom it was exacted, the virtue of this explanation disappears. Its inadequacy be- comes still more apparent when we remember that although none of these circumstances existed in England, Belgium, and America, they all had business depressions equally severe and protracted. The same is true of causes assigned for the depressions of 1882 and 1885." Without entering further into details regarding this class of causes then, we are abundantly warranted in rejecting them as wholly inadequate to account for the phenomena. To what cause then can business depressions be attributed ? A business depression can never occur unless the equilibrium between consumption and production is disturbed in such a manner as to result in a diminution of consumption as compared with production. The first symptom of an approaching business depression is the inability of producers to find customers for their whole product at remunerative prices. Manufacturers will con- 1 " There had been a period of excessive speculation, especially in railroads and real estate, large failures following that of Jay Cooke, inflation of the cur- rency, high protective tariff, large immigration, and the unnatural stimulus given to industry by the war, brought the monetary affairs of the country to a crisis, resulting in general distrust, fall of prices, apprehension, and all the train of evils which follow such crises." " First Annual Report of the Commissioner of Labor," 1886, p. 60. 2 For the cause of the depression in 1882 see " First Annual Report of the Commissioner of Labor," p. 76, and for a summary of the causes and remedies recommended, see ibid., pp. 291-293. 25 386 THE REAL CAUSE. tinue to produce wealth and will prosper so long as they can find a remunerative market for their wares, even though wars rage or governments are overthrown. Production being but the economic response to consumption, it is to the influences which effect con- sumption that we must look both for the cause and cure of business depressions. Nor is this all. Since business depressions are peculiar to factory conditions, and the market for factory-made products depends chiefly upon the consumption of the laboring classes, it follows that it is the failure of the laborers' consump- tion to keep pace with the capitalists' production the failure of the home to grow as fast as the factory that really produces business depressions. Here then we have a cause that is both adequate to produce the effect and necessary to it. So long as the consumption of the masses i.e., the wage- and salary- receiving class increases commensurately with the productive capacity of the community, nothing can create a business depres- sion ; and whenever this does not occur nothing can prevent one. Why does the laborers' consumption periodically fall behind the capitalists' production ? Is it a necessary part of the present productive system, or is it merely incidental to it ? The essential features of capitalistic production are specialization of labor, concentration of capital, and the use of factory methods. As already pointed out, these are essentially socializing in their in- fluence ; hence, instead of being inimical to the growth of the laborers' consumption, they are characteristically favorable to it. This is also shown by the fact that all phases of social progress have advanced more in a single century under the factory or capitalistic regime than in any previous period of the world's history. And it may be added that this progress has been greatest in those countries where the factory system has most completely prevailed. Witness this country and England, as com- pared with the countries of Asia and Africa. There is another feature of this industrial regime, however, which should not be overlooked. In proportion as the factory system improves economically, it tends to make the laborer more and more a specialist of some particular part of the finished product. Thus, the manufacture of a shoe is now divided into nearly seventy specified occupations, and cotton manufacture into eighty-six. In proportion as the laborers' employment is thus PHASES OF FACTORY SYSTEM. 387 specified, the speed and quantity of machinery is increased, and the strain upon his physical and nervous energy intensified. With this concentrating and specializing tendency the piece- work system has been generally established, which places the laborers in severe competition with each other, and often results in overdoing. 1 Again, the use of improved machinery and the specialization of labor tend to diminish the necessity of a high degree of skill in the laborer. This leads to the employment of a large number of women and children in all branches of manu- facturing industries ; and, like the men, they too are forced to be automatic factors, their portion of the work being an indispensable part of the whole productive process. They have to labor the same number of hours, under the same constantly increasing strain and pressure, and under the same sanitary conditions as the men. The obvious effect of all this is to deaden the springs of ambition and check the growth of new desires and superior tastes and habits of life. The laborer whose energies are ex- hausted in the workshop is naturally impervious to more ele- vating and refining influences. His leisure moments find him physically tired, mentally dull, and hence morally and socially indifferent. The inevitable tendency of this is to cause him to gravitate towards the saloon rather than the reading-room, lecture-hall, or theatre for his instruction and entertainment. Persons who are subjected to such continued toil from child- hood up, in the foul air of mines and the s\ltering heat and stifling atmosphere of mills and factories, cannot be expected to develop the ambition and force of character necessary to inspire and elevate their domestic and social life. The effect of such conditions upon women and children is even more damaging than upon men. The employment of women, especially wives and mothers, in the factory tends to sap the very source whence the springs of social character arise. Just in proportion as woman is transferred from the home to the workshop is her in- 1 So general is this that in nearly all factory employments it is necessary to have a large number, often 5 or 10 per cent., of spare hands, or substitutes, who take the place of those who are compelled to be absent a day or two at a time through sickness, or for a rest to prevent sickness, etc. It is not an uncommon thing for this, in a large proportion of cases, to average as much as one day in a week. 388 ARREST OF CONSUMPTION. spiring, socializing, and humanizing influence in the domestic circle destroyed a condition that will inevitably result in stereo- typing the social life of the masses, and in checking the increase of their wealth-consuming capacity. This relative diminution of consumption soon begins to show itself in the accumulation of the merchants' stock, which reacts upon the manufacturer, first in diminished orders for his product, then in a severe competition among producers for the contracted market, in which th'e smaller concerns are compelled to close, finally creating among the laborers enforced idleness, the most powerful factor of all in promoting business depressions. When the laborer ceases to have employment he practically ceases to be a consumer ; for although in modern society he is not per- mitted to starve, he has necessarily to be supported by others, either in the form of indebtedness or charity. There is no one cause by which the aggregate consumption of the community is so rapidly diminished as by enforced idleness. Like a contagious disease, it rapidly increases its own power for evil. The actual restriction of the market resulting from enforced idleness still further limits the sale of commodities, rendering production un- profitable ; this again results in suspending production and in further discharges, inevitably culminating in a business depres- sion in which, through bankruptcy, the large capitalists absorb the smaller ones, and are thus -enabled to wait till the lagging consumption again overtakes production. Every such ruinous adjustment is a temporary arrest of progress, and the more fre- quently it occurs the more permanent becomes its evil influence upon society. Still another source of idleness is the use of improved ma- chinery. Indeed changes in machinery are only improvements in proportion as they are labor-saving i.e., labor-discharging. Hence machinery that will discharge the most laborers is always adopted. This takes place most frequently when trade is most prosperous, and in countries where machine-using methods are most general. Nor is it possible, or even desirable, that this should be otherwise, since it is only through the use of improved methods of production that the drudgery of human labor can, be reduced, the luxuries of life increased, and social well-being en- hanced. Manifestly unless new employments are created as fast MISTAKEN POLICY OF EMPLOYERS. 389 as laborers are discharged, enforced idleness and the recurrence of business depressions are inevitable. It thus appears that while the factory system necessarily creates socializing conditions, it has been accompanied by influences which tend greatly to neutralize their beneficial effect ; but it it is not difficult to see that these neutralizing influences are in no sense a necessary part of the industrial system. While the various forms of industrial specialization tend to increase the draft upon the laborers' energies, it is not at all necessary that this should be inimical to his social advancement. There is nothing in the nature of factory methods which makes it neces- sary that their use should be physically and socially deteriorating. Bad ventilation and other unsanitary conditions, dangerous machinery, overdriving, the employment of young children, and long hours of labor are not essential to the factory system, any more than slave labor and the cat-o'-nine tails were an essential part of cotton-growing. With increase of productive power and its accompanying pressure upon the laborers' resources should have come a com- mensurate increase in his leisure and opportunities for social improvement. The reason this has been neglected is entirely due to the mistaken social policy pursued by the employing class. For the same reason that the Southern slave-holder believed that slave labor was necessary to the cheap production of cotton and, consequently, to the prosperity of the planters, the modern employer has acted upon the erroneous assumption that cheap labor is necessary to his business prosperity. Accord- ingly he has resisted instead of promoting every effort to ameli- orate the condition of the laboring classes, from the same motive that the Southern planter opposed the abolition of slavery. All other efforts to increase the social opportunities of the laborer have been resisted by the employing class as mischievous agita- tions, until they were made imperative by statute law or social custom. Indeed their whole attitude toward the labor movement in general has been one of persistent hostility. The experience of the last fifty years, however, has shown that in almost every instance they were entirely mistaken. It is now admitted that free labor is more productive and economic than slave labor ever was. And instead of the prosperity of the manufacturing class 390 ECONOMISTS AT FAULT. having been lessened by the various restrictions imposed upon their inhumane and uneconomic policy, it has steadily increased. The employer of to-day, with wages twice as high, hours of labor one fourth less, and the sanitary and social conditions of the laborer a hundred per cent, better, is more prosperous than were his predecessors fifty years ago. Nor is this socially repressive policy due to any peculiar per- versity of the employing class. They are not less humane and philanthropic than any other portion of the community, as their liberal contributions to charitable, educational, and other public institutions conclusively show. Their antagonistic attitude arises from a misconception of their economic relation to the laboring class ; and for this, the economic teaching of the period is responsible. The failure of the economist to recognize the revo- lution in the economic relation of the laborer to the capitalist which took place with the inauguration of the factory system, naturally led to the mistake of ignoring the economic importance of the laborers' consumption as the market basis for factory-made products. With this ante-factory-period view of the laborers' economic position, it naturally appeared to the employer that the true economic policy was to obtain his labor as cheaply as possi- ble. Oblivious of the fact that the success of his factory as a mere money-making institution depends upon the character and wealth- consuming capacity of the masses, he has systematically regarded the laborers as merely so much productive force to be used to the limit of their endurance. Under the influence of such doctrines, it is not surprising that the employing class should use every effort, industrial and politi- cal, to resist all endeavors to increase the social opportunities or raise the wages of the laborer. 1 Thus, through'the influence of a mistaken industrial policy, the capitalist in the vain endeavor to increase his power to produce, by limiting the power of the laborer to consume, defeats the very object he most desires to accomplish, and instead of promoting his own permanent pros- perity, he is continually planting the seed of business depression, enforced idleness, and bankruptcy. Thus business depressions, instead of being a necessary part of the factory system, are really the penalty which the employing class and the community have 1 See "Wealth and Progress," Part III., chapters vi. and vii. FACTS TO BE RECOGNIZED. 39! to pay for ignoring the economic and social advancement of the laboring classes as the real basis of industrial prosperity. SECTION III. The Prevention of Business Depressions. It will be observed that business depressions are wholly a prob- lem of the market ; and also that the market, while furnishing the economic basis for production, is a social phenomenon, having its rise in the social life of the people. Whether scientific pro- duction shall continually cheapen wealth and increase social well-being, or whether it shall create enforced idleness and busi- ness depressions, depends upon whether new employments are created as fast as labor-saving appliances are adopted. Produc- tion being the response to consumption, new employments can be created only as fast as new demands for commodities arise among the masses. This involves an important change in the general point of view from which the economic position of the laborer is regarded. In the first place it must be distinctly recog- nized as an irrevocable historic fact, that with the inauguration of the factory system the economic relation of the laborer to the capital- ist was radically changed, and that under modern industrial conditions the market for the capitalists' production finally depends upon the extent of the laborers' consumption j hence business prosperity can be continuous only in proportion as real wages rise. And it must be no less distinctly recognized as a fundamental principle in eco- nomics that the cost of production is the controlling element in price movement, and consequently that the determining element in the price of labor (wages) is the cost of the laborers' living as determined by the standard of his social life, It should be' remembered, however, that capitalists are not philosophers, nor have we any right to expect them to be. They are captains of industry, and as such are too busy with the ad- ministration of affairs to solve economic problems. Their func- tion is to apply rather than to develop economic principles. The same is substantially true of the journalist. Although his posi- tion is that of an educator of public opinion, he is more like a manufacturer than a scientist. He is occupied rather with the popular presentation of accepted economic doctrines than with testing their validity. Like the capitalists, the ablest editors and 392 NATURAL REMEDY. essayists rely mainly upon economists for their economic princi- ples. It is to the economists, therefore, that we have a right to look for the recognition and active propagation of the economic truths underlying this important problem. When the foregoing propositions are emphatically taught in colleges and acted upon by capitalists, the first great step towards a solution, not only of industrial depressions but of the social problem will have been taken ; and the chief cause of an- tagonism between the laboring and the employing class will have been removed. So long as the laborer and capitalist believe their interests are economically antagonistic, unity of action to redress social evils is almost impossible. If, however, the employing class can be once made to realize (i) that there is no economic antag- onism between the laborers' interests and their own, and (2) that the initial point of industrial prosperity is not in production but in consumption not in the factory but in the home not in profits but in wages, there will for the first time be a common agreement as to the point towards which all efforts for industrial improve- ments must be directed, namely, the elevation of the laborer s stand- ard of. living. This fact established, the only question would be as to the best means of promoting that end, since whatever would do that would promote the welfare of the whole community. It is not to be inferred from the above that an increase in the laborers' consumption (real wages) is a simple matter that can be arbitrarily accomplished by an official proclamation or a legisla- tive enactment. On the contrary, the laborer's standard of liv- ing, being determined by his social habits, is a matter of relatively slow development. Although there is no immediate panacea for business depres- sions any more than for poverty, despotism, or other evils arising from the lack of social character among the masses, there are three ways in which their severity may be diminished and their ulti- mate elimination promoted : (i) negatively by lessening the ob- structions to the social progress of the masses ; (2) positively by constantly increasing the social opportunities of the masses ; (3) by establishing an international business barometer by which ap- proaching business depressions will be indicated sufficiently in advance to enable their severest phases to be avoided. i. The greatest obstruction to the social progress of the masses, 26 DUTY OF EMPLOYING CLASS. 393 as already pointed out, is the opposition of the employing class and their literary and legislative, allies. With the acceptance of the doctrine here indicated, there would naturally be a marked change in the attitude of the press and statesmen toward the social question, by which much of their opposition would be removed. In the first place, such men as Edward Atkinson, David A. Wells, and the leading commercial and political journals would no longer appear as the opponents of every proposition, legislative or other, for improving the laborers' social condition. Indeed much of their present attitude toward the social question would then be properly regarded as opposition to the public weal. The accept- ance of this view would also further the same end by preventing a vast amount of misdirected effort at social reform, the futility of which often serves to strengthen the hands of the opposition. If it were clearly understood that nothing can promote business prosperity which does not directly or indirectly tend to elevate the laborers' social life, and make a larger consumption of wealth necessary, then the various social chimeras such as land nation- alization, socialism, and the like would be discredited in advance as having no real bearing upon the question. 2. The disparity between the increase in the laborers' consump- tion as compared with that of the capitalists' production would be still more diminished, if the energy which has been constantly devoted to limiting the laborers' social opportunities were ap- plied to increasing them. Then every proposition for improving the condition of the masses would be approached with the desire of adopting whatever feasible element of good it contained, instead of a determination to magnify all its disadvantages for the purpose of defeating it. In order that the policy of increasing instead of restricting the laborers' consumption may be scientifically applied to the pre- vention of business depressions, it is necessary to have some means of knowing in advance the first indications of a business depression. It will be readily seen that if it could be correctly known that a movement towards business depression had set in, which if not arrested would inevitably bring a period of social disaster, all the wisdom of economists, statesmen, and capitalists would be applied to preventing its occurrence, and this could be done in two ways. 394 Aff INDUSTRIAL BAROMETER. In the first place, if correct economic doctrine prevailed, efforts would at once be redoubled in ajl manufacturing countries to use every known legislative, personal, social, and industrial means of augmenting consumption among the masses. This would involve efforts to raise the laborer's standard of living, which of course means an improvement in his social condition. If such efforts were made in all machine-using countries as soon as the symp- toms of an approaching depression appeared, it could always be weakened and in many cases obviated. In the second place, if the consumption of the masses in the various countries could not be increased sufficiently to offset a threatened diminution in the market, the depression could be largely mitigated by a movement of capital. As soon as it was definitely known that the relative diminution of the market had set in, while established industries could not, without injury, cur- tail their production, the investment of new capital could and would be curtailed. By curtailing investments sufficiently in advance much new capital would be saved, and the shock to established industries would be greatly reduced. Moreover, as business depressions generally arise from a dis- parity between consumption and production in certain lines of commodities, a proper knowledge of business phenomena would indicate in precisely what line of industry the disturbance existed, and thus enable a more economic direction to be given to new investments. By this means much of the capital that in such periods is wasted in America, England, France, and Germany might, and often would, be made to render a service to civiliza- tion by developing the social resources of South America, India, China, and other non-manufacturing countries. Is it possible then to establish such an industrial barometer ; is there any means by which the early symptoms of a business depression can be surely indicated ? I think there is. Although the first symptom of a business depression is the failure of the producer to find a profitable market for his whole product, this may occur from causes which do not necessarily indicate a depression in business. A change of fashion for example, or the substitution of a superior for an inferior product . through the use of better methods, may produce that effect in a specific industry. In that case however, the dulness in the old STATISTICS OF IDLENESS. 395 industry would be practically offset by the briskness in the new. Such a disturbance therefore will only be a temporary perturba- tion incident to the movement of capital and labor from one industry to another, and might indeed be a sign of business pros- perity rather than adversity. But there is one fact in the indus- trial world which infallibly indicates an approaching business depression, namely, enforced idleness. There are many ways in which enforced idleness may be produced in machine-using countries, e.g., by the immigration of laborers from non-machine- using countries, by discharges through the use of labor-saving machinery, or by the suspension of industry consequent upon a declining market. But from whatever cause or number of causes enforced idleness arises, unless it is arrested, an industrial depression is inevitable. It is equally certain that nothing can produce a business de- pression of serious proportions which does not create enforced idleness ; indeed, so long as the laborers are all employed a busi- ness depression is practically impossible. Therefore, while enforced idleness may not be the initial cause of business depressions, it is one of the earliest and most infallible indica- tions of it. Since a knowledge of the phenomena is a necessary prerequisite to scientific action, the first practical step toward prevention of business depressions, is the collection of statistics of enforced idleness. Nor would this be a difficult task, since the machinery for collecting industrial data is now fairly well established in most civilized countries. Statistics of enforced idleness not being of an inquisitorial nature, there could be no valid objection to their collection, especially as no class in the community would have any motive for withholding the information. In order that these statistics may have the utmost utility, the investigation should be authoritative, universal, and frequent. To make the investigation authoritative, it should be under- taken by the state. Moreover, it is a work which peculiarly be- longs to the government, because it is of universal importance, and can be performed more extensively, efficiently, and eco- nomically by the state than by the individual, especially in the less civilized countries. To give reliability to the data, the in- vestigation should be as extensive as the factory system, includ- 396 NECESSITY OF FREQUENT DATA. ing at least America, England, France, Germany, Belgium, Switzerland, Austria, Italy, and Spain. These statistics should also be collected as frequently as pos- sible, not less than once a year, and half-yearly or quarterly would be even better. Frequency of collection is one of the most essential requisites of idleness statistics, because it is only by a frequent collection of facts that the symptoms of an on-coming industrial depression can be observed in its early stages and hence the most efficient means of prevention adopted. Such a body of data would furnish an inductive basis for the scientific application of economic principles to market phe- nomena, besides being invaluable in the treatment of all other phases of the social question. While it is not pretended that business depressions can be summarily abolished, it is indisputable that with full, frequent, and reliable statistics of enforced idleness in all machine-using countries, together with sound views regard- ing the economic relation of the laborers' consumption to the market, a great step would be taken towards their diminution and ultimate elimination. CHAPTER VI. COMBINATION OF CAPITAL. IT is a peculiar feature of the industrial history of society that every movement towards concentration or more complex associa- tion of industrial forces has always been viewed with alarm, and has had to encounter serious opposition from the community. The landed aristocracy saw with dismay the rise and growth of the mercantile class from the fifteenth to the eighteenth century, and accordingly used all their social and political power to harass and hinder the development of what to them contained naught but evil for society. With the introduction of the spinning-jenny in the eighteenth century, this social alarm was taken up by the hand spinners. Their horror and indignation at the idea of a machine spinning eight threads where they could only spin one were such that they ransacked the home of Hargreaves, broke his machines, and drove him from his native county for inventing it. A similar alarm was raised in the first quarter of the present century by the hand- loom weavers against the introduction of the power-loom, and they went from town to town destroying the steam-driven ma- chines. The small factory owners, who had encountered the violence of the hand laborers, subsequently raised a similar alarm against the corporation, and now small corporations, individual factory-owners, laborers, and non-commercial classes all join in raising a similar alarm-cry against trusts, syndicates, and other corporate combinations. Perhaps the most remarkable feature in the attitude of the public towards industrial combination is their disregard for the lessons of history. The fact that in almost every instance the opposition to new forms of industrial organization has been a 397 398 IMPORTANCE OF CORRECT VIEWS. mistaken resistance to what finally proved to be a permanent benefit, seems to have almost no modifying influence upon their belligerent attitude. The opposition to trusts to-day is scarcely less intense than was that against the machines of Hargreaves and Arkwright a century ago. 1 A very little reflection will show that -this opposition to capi- talistic concentration is as uneconomic and impolitic as is the crusade of capitalists against the combination of labor, and for substantially the same reason. The fallacy underlying both these positions is the assumption that an improvement in the con- dition of either is obtained at the expense of the other. The capitalist is opposed to labor-unions because he believes that a rise of wages involves a fall of profits ; and the public oppose the combination of capital because they believe that the large profits of a successful corporation are necessarily obtained at the expense of the laborer and the consumer. In the light of the economic law of prices, surplus, and wages, -as heretofore presented, the fallacy of such an attitude becomes apparent. When we once realize that profit is not added to the consumers' price, but that it represents a surplus produced by the use of superior instruments and natural forces, it is clear that the wealth of the capitalist is not drawn from the incomes of the other classes in the community, but from nature. 2 And so with the capitalist ; when he understands that a rise in wages is not a permanent tax upon him, but is ultimately replenished through an increased product hence, like his own profit, is not drawn from his fellow-man, but from nature, the ground of his opposition to labor combinations will disappear. Since neither the employ- ing nor laboring class can permanently improve its condition by impairing that of the other, but only by increasing the product of nature, it will be obvious that neither one has any thing to gain by suppressing the combination of the other ; but, on the con- trary, if combination will increase their economic power, every- body has an interest in extending and strengthening such combination. 1 In 1888 a bill was introduced into Congress proposing to levy a tax of 40 per cent, on the products of trusts. In 1889 two other bills were introduced into the United States Senate, practically making trusts criminal conspiracies. s Chapter on " Prices." TWO KINDS OF WEALTH. 399 Without stopping to consider whether or not the trust form of combination is superior to any other, it may be laid down as a fundamental principle demonstrated by the history of industrial evolution, that the combination of capital is indispensable to economic progress. This consists in cheapening wealth as com- pared with labor. Capital and labor being the only two factors which enter into the cost of production, it follows that wealth can be cheapened only by increasing the productive capacity of capital. It is a fact too obvious and universal to need discussing, that an increase in the productive efficiency of capital is obtained by means of greater specialization and concentration, which in- creases as civilization advances. Of this, every successful factory, railroad, and steamship enterprise is a demonstration. This much will be conceded by the most ill-informed anti- combinationist. But the objection commonly urged is that the gain resulting from this economy in production mainly accrues to a small class. It is insisted that this tends to create a double evil, by at once promoting industrial monopoly and political des- potism. They assure us that wherever wealth is accumulated in the hands of a few, the poverty of the people, political corruption, and private immorality increase, and that intellectual, political, and national decay inevitably set in. 1 Although few arguments have more effect upon the public mind than this, there are none that reveal a greater lack of economic insight. It proceeds upon the assumption (i) that all accumulation of wealth in the hands of a limited class is injurious to the welfare of the community, and (2) that the concentration of capital necessarily destroys competition. i. If we bear in mind the economic distinction between con- sumable and productive wealth or capital already referred to, we shall have little difficulty in seeing the error of this proposition. Whether or not the accumulation of wealth in a few hands will be beneficial or injurious to society, will entirely depend upon whether it is consumable wealth or capital that is accumulated. No one acquainted with the subject will for a moment contend that concentration of consumable wealth in the hands of a small class is advantageous to the community. Since this class of 'See author's article on "Trusts," Political Science Quarterly, vol. iii., pp. 403-406. 4OO CAPITAL ONLY IS ACCUMULATED, wealth only ministers to human welfare when in the possession of the consumer, it follows that it can only yield the largest benefit to the community when it is most extensively distributed among the people. With productive wealth or capital, however, the case is exactly the reverse ; its functions being solely that of a productive instrument, it can minister to human welfare only by producing consumable wealth. Clearly therefore, whether or not capital is any advantage to its owner or to the public, depends entirely upon whether it is advantageously used in creating en- joyable commodities. Since capital will only furnish consumable wealth to its owner in proportion as he can sell his products, its possession can only be advantageous to the capitalist when the consumable wealth it produces is generally and liberally consumed by the community. It may be observed in passing that there is no tendency in modern society to accumulate consumable wealth. On the con- trary, the very prosperity of the community depends upon the constantly increasing consumption of consumable wealth. When we speak of the accumulation of millions in the hands of a single individual or family to-day, it should be remembered that cap- ital and not consumable wealth is referred to. With the excep- tion of a small amount personally consumed and dispersed in charities, the large fortunes of the Vanderbilts, Goulds, Astors, Rothschilds, and other millionaires are productively employed. Indeed, it would be regarded as the insanity of financiering to accumulate consumable wealth, because the only result of such accumulation would be deterioration and loss. As shown in the preceding chapter, any tendency to prevent consumption from keeping pace with production, which is simply accumulating con- sumable wealth, surely leads to business depressions, and entails inevitably bankruptcy, and often ruin upon the owners of capital. Since capital can be of no advantage to its owner except when it is profitably employed in producing consumable wealth, and since it can be so profitably employed when its product is consumed substantially as fast as it is produced, it follows, as an economic necessity, that consumable wealth is most widely distributed where productive wealth or capital is most concentrated. Thus we again arrive at the oft-repeated proposition that the prosperity of the capitalist finally depends upon the consumption of wealth by the masses. CONCENTRATION AND COMPETITION. 40! 2. The second objection is that combination of capital tends to destroy competition. If this assumption be correct, the power of competition will necessarily diminish as the combination of capital increases. Whether or not this has taken place can be determined only by the facts. In order to determine whether or not effective competition increases or diminishes with combina- tion of capital, we have only to ascertain whether or not prices tend to press closer to the line of the cost of producing the most expensive portion of the general supply. Tried by this test, the assertion that the combination of capital necessarily tends to destroy competition will be found to be entirely erroneous. There never was a time when economic combination was so great as it is to day, nor was there ever a time when competition was so fierce and unsparing that is to say, when the margin between the cost of producing the dearest portion and the selling price was so small in such a large proportion of industries. In- deed, it is one of the chief indictments against the capitalistic system of production that it is a "competitive system." If we follow the combination of capital from the hand-loom weaver and the spinner of a single thread to the trust and syndicate, we shall find that the margin of profit per unit of product has steadily diminished a fact which every business man knows. The reason for this is obvious. For instance, when the hand-loom weaver could only turn off forty yards of cotton cloth a week, a margin of a cent a yard would yield but an insignificant amount of profit. The profit on the product of fifty weavers would only be $25 a week, whereas the same margin on the product of fifty weavers to-day would yield a profit of $1,080 a week. Much of the error in this connection is due to judging compe- tition from the standpoint of the deposed or receding competitor. Thus, when the products of a small factory undersold those of a hand-loom, judged from the standpoint of the hand-loom weaver, competition was destroyed and monopoly established. Such however was not the case, as everybody now knows. What really took place was a readjustment of economic factors, made necessary by the introduction of superior methods, which resulted in transferring competition to a new plane, where its effectiveness was greatly increased. The same was true when the small factory was superseded by the corporation, and is true now when the corporation is superseded by the trust and syndicate. 4O2 THE CRITERION OF COMPETITION. It should be remembered that the influence of competition does not depend so much upon the number of competitors as upon the effectiveness of competition. Competitors may be very numerous and still competition be ineffective, as in the case of the hand-loom weavers. And conversely, competitors may be few in number and still be very effective, as is the case of large concerns to-day. One Macy furnishes more effective competi- tion than a hundred small merchants with a few hundred dollars capital each. This does not mean that reducing the number of competitors will necessarily increase effective competition, but it demonstrates the fact that high competition is possible with a small number of competitors. Indeed, it is the severity of com- petition thus developed that has brought the trust and other forms of industrial confederation into existence. That effective competition has thus increased with the increas- ing combination of capital, no one acquainted with the subject will dispute, but the alarm raised is ostensibly for the future. It is upon what trusts may do, and not upon what they have done, that the present opposition is based. It is said that the object of the trust is to monopolize the market. Even so ; there is nothing new in that. That has been one of the objects of every other in- dustrial improvement. What motive could there be for intro- ducing better methods and investing large capital, unless it would give the owner more advantage over existing competitors. To condemn an industrial institution because the object of its pro- moters is to undersell and supersede traditional producers and methods is economic insanity. It is not the motive of the capi- talist but the economic effect of his action that must be deter- mined in judging the social utility of industrial methods and institutions. Whether the capitalist acts as an individual pro- ducer, small factory owner, corporation, or trust ; whether he produces cotton cloth, shoes, or petroleum, conducts a railroad or publishes a newspaper, his motive is substantially the same ; namely, to obtain more wealth " to make money." Will it pay? is the question upon which the doing or not doing in every sphere of industrial activity is determined. The tone and politics of the newspapers are determined by that fact about as completely as is the form and quality of hats and shoes. Newspaper corporations have not invested hundreds ECONOMIC INCENTIVE. 403 of thousands and even millions of dollars in buildings, large and fast presses, automatic folders, foreign correspondence, special telegrams, high salaried editors and reporters, special trains for deliveries, etc., merely for the sake of furnishing the public with ample, early, and reliable news. This has all been developed by the effort of each to outdo his neighbor in the contest for obtain- ing public patronage the market. It was only because this could not be done without furnishing a larger or a better paper at the same price which nothing but a greater combination of capital and superior methods made possible that the immense improvements in the daily paper have been produced. The same motive which has induced newspaper corporations to furnish a daily history of the human race for two cents, has given us our railroads, telegraphs, steamships, and other time-and-space- reducing and wealth-cheapening institutions, of which trusts are the most recent form. And the reasons for suppressing one will apply with equal force to suppressing the others. The opposition to the larger combinations of to-day will be found to have its root in the error which has characterized all previous opposition to productive integrations. The averagely intelligent antagonist to trusts will readily admit that all the evil predictions regarding the earlier stages of capitalistic combina- tion were mistaken. He will also admit that the mistake consisted in the failure to recognize the increasing competitive power which the larger factory and corporation possessed, especially when accompanied by the daily press, the telegraph, and the rail- roads. The more intelligent now see that a multiplicity of com- petitors is not necessary to effective competition, having learned by experience that this may result in a great waste of economic power instead of a cheapening of commodities, and that compe- tition is quite as effective, and far more economic, with a limited number of competitors. While they recognize the folly of assuming that any diminution in the number of competitors must weaken competition, they tenaciously insist that to permit the com- bination of capital to increase until the actual competitors are re- duced to zero, must destroy competition. In other words, they insist that competition is impossible unless the competitors are actually present in the market. The error in this view arises from overlooking the influence of 404 POTENTIAL COMPETITION. potential competition. If we examine the subject from the standpoint of modern phenomena, we shall find that there is potential competition as well as actual, and that the economic effect of potential competition increases as its phenomena grow in complexity. The competitive power of capital will be found to ultimately depend not merely upon its actual presence, but upon its known availability at any given time and place. Consequently, the more intelligent and economically powerful competitors are, the more effectual will be their potential or possible competition, and vice versa. For example in the ante-factory period, with neither railroads nor telegraphs, the only capital known to be available was that visibly present ; hence, none other exercised any competitive influence in the market. With the development of modern industry all this has changed. Electricity and steam have so diminished time and space, and concentration of capital has so increased the economic power of the producer, that now both capital and products thousands of miles away are economically available, and therefore exercise a positive competitive influence upon the market. Accordingly the wheat in India, Russia and Dakota, now exercises practically the same competitive influence in Liverpool as does that which is stored there, and solely because it is known to be actually avail- able for the Liverpool market if the price rises high enough to warrant its movement thither. Thus through improved means of communication and transportation, products in the most remote parts of the earth exercise a competitive influence upon a market they may never actually enter, simply because it is known that they can be there if needed. What is true of commodities is even more true of fixed capital, and as will readily be seen, potential competition or the power of the possible competitor increases as the combination of capital enlarges. Capital is proverbially one of the most sensitive things in the world. Although it will take great risks for large profits it will timidly recede at the sight of loss. There are many reasons why large combinations are more amenable to the influence of potential competition than small ones. Although more powerful, they yet have more at stake. The very fact that capital is cow- ardly makes it careful, and, since fear of loss next to hope of gain is the most powerful motive which governs its movement, the first INABILITY OF LARGE CAPITAL. 40$ condition to be secured is safety against loss. The greater the concentration of capital, the more serious and difficult this be- comes. It is a principle in economic progress that as the mobility of consumable wealth increases that of productive wealth diminishes, because the very means which promote the easy transfer of prod- ucts involve a greater fixity of capital. In proportion as capi- tal loses its mobility, the necessity of maximizing its economic utility in its existing form increases ; and when the concentration is very great, that becomes the only means of preserving it from deterioration. Take, for example, the Vanderbilt railroad system with its investment of $170,000,000 and 60,000 employe's; this is excellent property so long as it can be economically employed for its present purpose. If, however, it should be superseded by a superior system of transportation, the greater part of that prop- erty would be worthless, the capital invested being absolutely non-transferable. Such parts of the equipment as the rails, road- bed, engines, cars, and stations (rep resenting nearly $150,000,000) which now have a full value as finished products, would in that case practically be reduced to the value of old iron. Three fourths of their value would vanish as completely as if the prop- erty were reduced to ashes. If we bear in mind the fact that capital is simply an economic instrument whose decay can only be prevented by maintaining its productive utility, it will be manifest that in proportion as its con- centration increases, the very life of capital depends more and more upon its wealth-cheapening efficiency. It will probably be replied that this may all be true so long as any actual competi- tors remain, but when the combination of capital has reached a point where the production of a given commodity is practically in the hands of a single concern this restraint will disappear, and prices can be indefinitely increased to suit a monopoly. Here is where the error of ignoring the influence of potential competition again shows itself. The very fact that capital cannot take wings and fly away, but is compelled to work where it is or perish, gives potential competition its greatest influence ; that is to say, gives the non-employed or less remuneratively employed capital its maximum price-reducing influence It should never be forgot- ten that in a progressive society, where alone the greatest combi- 406 EFFECT OF NO-PROFIT CAPITAL. nation of capital is possible, two things are more or less con- stantly occurring : (i) the accumulation of wealth available for productive purposes, which increases as the margin of profit rises ; (2) the reduction of capital to no-profit uses, which in- creases as superior productive methods and management are adopted. From these two causes, which are as universal and constant as social progress, capital seeking remunerative employ- ment is constantly increasing. Hence this idle or unremunerative capital has the same eco- nomic effect upon productive capital that the wheat in India or Russia has upon that in Liverpool ; it is waiting for an opportu- nity. In the absence of legal restrictions, nothing will prevent this anxiously waiting capital from actually entering the field except keeping the margin of profit too small to warrant the risk. This of course involves the lowering of prices commensurately with the diminished cost of production, which is all the fiercest actual competition can do. It may be said that if new capital enters the field a monopoly will buy it up. But that takes more capital ; a million dollars invested in buying up a competitor is so much added to the cost of production, and directly dimin- ishes profit. Clearly the million thus invested might just as well be surrendered to the community in lower prices. That this would be a safer and more economic method is manifest : (i) because lowering the price tends to increase the consumption of the commodity, extend the market, and make a still smaller margin of profit yield a greater aggregate return ; (2) because a new competitor is an unknown quantity, and may prove too strong to be bought up, in which case existing producers may be driven from the field, or have their profits reduced to zero. Since the least danger to existing corporations lies in keeping out rather than buying out new competitors, and since reducing prices alone can do this, it follows that the larger a corporation the greater is its interest in keeping prices low enough not to induce the organiza- tion of counter-enterprises to jeopardize its existence. It is thus evident that with economic freedom, the potential competition of available capital is essentially the same as if a new competitor were actually on hand. The fact that he may come any day has practically the same competitive influence as if he had come, because to keep him out requires the same kind of price-reducing LIMIT OF CONCENTRATION. 407 effort that would be necessary to drive him out. Since the former always involves less risk and generally less cost than the latter, it is most likely to be adopted, in proportion as an intelligent under- standing of economic movement prevails. It is a great mistake to suppose that the investment of large capitals is specially desirable to the capitalist. On the contrary he avoids this as much as possible, always preferring to get along with the minimum rather than to use the maximum capital to accomplish any given result. Indeed to accomplish the greatest result with the least investment is the very art of economic pro- duction. Moreover, with every increase in the size of invest- ments capital becomes more fixed, involved, and unwieldy, redu- cing margins and making it possible for great losses to result from very slight mistakes ; consequently greater expertness of management becomes necessary in every department of a colos- sal enterprise. Larger investments increase the risk of the capi- talist and further outlay will be adopted only under the spur of some economic inducement such as avoiding a loss, replenish- ing a diminished profit, or perhaps obtaining a still larger profit. The economic movement of capital being governed by the law of increasing returns, it follows that capital will not (except by mistake) go into new industries, unless it can obtain a greater return per unit than it is already receiving. So, too, of concen- tration or combination ; capital will continue to concentrate only so long as it can obtain an increasing return per unit by so doing. When that ceases to be possible the motive for combination dis- appears ; and when the point of diminishing returns is reached self-interest is positively against further combination. That there is a point in any given state of society at which further concentra- tion of capital will fail to yield increasing returns, and at which diminishing returns set in, cannot be doubted. Whether or not this point will be reached before the actual competing producers in the same market disappear cannot now be determined. Nor is this of any real importance since concentration will continue only so long as it will give increasing returns to the capitalist and cheaper products to the consumer. There is therefore no eco- nomic reason why the state should do any thing to limit the con- centration of capital, since that will be arrested by the capitalist when it ceases to economize production and cheapen the wealth 408 EFFECT OF CONCENTRATED CAPITAL. of the community. In other words, in the absence of legal re- strictions economic law is more effectual in determining the equi- table movement of capital than statute law can possibly be. That this has been the general effect of the concentration of capital during the present century is abundantly proven by the fall of prices and rise of wages as shown by the increased pur- chasing power of a day's labor during that period. The follow- ing table shows the average weekly wages and their relative purchasing power in 200 staple articles for 1860 and 1885 : ' i8( )O. i8i *5. INDUSTRIES. Number of branches. Weekly wages. Purchasing power. Weekly wages. Purchasing power. Percentage of increase. Arms and ammunition 12 &I4. IS IOO iiiil'} IS IIQ IQ Artisans' tools IO 8 4S IOO II ZlS 74 Boots and shoes 17 II 4.2 IOO 10 63 1 2O 2O Carriages and wagons 7 IO 47 IOO 12 8O IC7 1:7 Clothinf II 8 26 IOO 8 19 127 27 Cotton goods 86 6 50 IOO 6 4S 128 28 Flax, hemp, and jute ie 4. OT IOO 6 46 1 80 80 Leather 8 IO OI IOO II. OI 141 41 Liquors 8 IO ~T\ IOO 11.7-2 141 41 Machinery IQ 7 OO IOO II 7S IQ2 02 Metallic goods IO Q O7 IOO II. 2S 161 6l Musical instruments 8 IO.Q4 IOO 12. Q4 152 52 Paper goods 18 8 63 IOO 7 6l 114 14 Print and dye-goods 26 Q QO IOO 7.67 IOO Silk and silk goods Q R.QI IOO 6.QI 167 67 7 8 OI IOO 12 OI IQI Q7 58 e.*8 IOO 7.QO 180 8q Worsted goods 22 6.12 IOO 6.12 I2Q 29 Carpetings 25 6.62 IOO 6.62 129 29 Building trades IO 0.87 IOO 14. QQ 196 96 Average (Total 386) 8.64 IOO 9.88 150 5 This tendency is still more conclusively shown by the fact that the fall in prices has been greatest in those commodities in whose production there has been the greatest concentration of 1 The \vages in the above table represent 386 occupations in Massachusetts ; the data for iS6o will be found in the Report of the Labor Bureau for 1884, and those for 1885 in the Census Report for 1885 (volume on Manufactures). EFFECT OF TRUSTS ON PKICES. 409 capital, as will be seen by the accompanying table, which shows the purchasing power of weekly wages in commodities furnished by trusts and other colossal combinations for 1860 and 1890 : Purchasing power of weekly wages. 1860. 1890. Percentage of increase. Cotton-seed oil, number of gals. . . Sugar refined, number of Ibs iSyV QOTAA 2Q T 9 A ie.2 66 67 Freight New York to Chicago. First class 530 Ibs 1317 Ibs 148 Second class O^d 1520 ' T12 Third class 822 1076 f 176 Fourth class I3OQ 2822 ' lie Telegraph messages, number of. . Pretroleum refined, number of gals. 8AV I07A 9 TT 3iT 6 Tnr ' io86flfr ' 283 907 It will be seen from the above tables that, although the general purchasing power of wages has greatly increased since 1860, the increase has been very much greater in those industries where the greatest concentration of capital has taken place. Taking 200 staple articles together, the increase is 53^0 P er cent., whereas, in cotton-seed oil, it is 66 per cent. ; in sugar, 67 per cent. ; in transportation (all classes) together, it is 142 per cent. ; in telegraphy, 283 per cent. ; and in petroleum, 907 per cent. It should be observed in this connection that the figures for cotton- seed oil only extended to 1878, and that more than \^ of the entire fall in the price has taken place since the trust was formed in 1884 3 ; and also that the fall in the price of sugar during the last thirty years has all taken place since January, 1882.' It may be said that the point has not yet been reached where actual competitors are reduced to none, and therefore the cor- rectness of the theory here presented cannot be inductively verified. It is true that there are very few industries in which the actual competitors are not still relatively numerous. Nor is there any sufficient ground for concluding that the time will ever come 1 The figures in this table are for 1878. These figures are for 1866. 3 In 1878 the price of standard summer oil was 47^0*5 cents a gallon ; in 1883 it was 47y rise of, in i4th century, 110-130 ; arrested in isth century, 132-144; move- ment of, from 1 5th to igth century, 145-160 ; universality of law of, 162-178 ; under piece-work, 179- 186 ; ultimate analysis of law of, 187-203. (See also Index to " Prin- ciples of Social Economics.") Wages-fund, its statement, fallacy, and inadequacy, 35-52 Walker, Francis A., 53-59, 62 Wants, how effected by social con- dition, 120 ; they determine the standard of living, 187 ; their rela- tion to wages, 176, 177 ; how cre- ated, 201 ; their basis, 202 Wealth, prevalent notions about, i ; condition of man before the accumu- lation of wealth began, 2 Women, wages of, 168, 172-174; their economic condition, 207 WEALTH AND PROGRESS. A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE LABOR PROBLEM. BY GEORGE GUNTON. 12JVO, 400 PAGES. PAPER, 50 CENTS; CLOTH, $1.00. OPINIONS OF THE PRESS. " Mr. Gunton has written one of the ablest works on a question of vast interest which has issued from the press in many years." Chicago Times. "It is a plain, practical, common-sense view by a sensible American, where every point is argued and a plain reason given for its adoption." Chicago Inter-Ocean. " The book is one of infinite suggestion and also of practical value." Boston Traveller. " No one can rise from the reading of ' Wealth and Progress' without the profound conviction that it contains the first attempt ever made to put the claim for an eight-hour system on a truly economic and scientific basis." New York Star. " Mr. Gunton's work may be declared without hesitation to be the most notable contribution to the science since Walker's ' Wages Question.'" Po- litical Science Quarterly. " The book contains a great deal of good sense, especially in its criticism of the one-sided views of the standard economical teachers. " New York Sun. " The book contains an immense amount of exact information regarding all branches of the subject, and will be valuable as a book of reference to all students of the economical question." New York World. " Mr. Gunton has performed his task in a brilliant and masterly manner, and with a logical clearness and accuracy in argument that leaves scarcely a question of the truth and soundness of the position he has taken. The book is in many respects the most important, most thorough, and most satisfying that has been added to the literature of the subject." Boston Evening Gazette. " The author is very thorough, and contributes much valuable thought to the subject." Brooklyn Eagle. "The author presents a picture of the 'social crisis,' and develops his theory by historical illustration and demonstration. His presentation is fas- cinating and skilful." Boston Journal. "It is at once philosophic and eminently practical. It announces the natural laws which lie at the basis of the labor problem, elucidates them by historical data, and enforces their soundness with a logical cogency that carries conviction." Eastern Argus (Portland, Me.). " Mr. Gunton is the latest comer in the field, and he performs the job that he undertakes. We have never seen a neater piece of refutation than that to be found between pages sixty and seventy, wherein the George theory is particularly analyzed." Journal of Commerce (New York). "The practical experience of Mr. Gunton gives particular interest and value to his book, which in manner and matter would do honor to the most practised writer." Commercial Advertiser (New York). " It is the most thorough and comprehensive treatment of the labor ques- tion ever presented." Pater son Labor Standard. " The book is conspicuous for its close backing of all theory by practical demonstration." North American Review. " His book is the work of a sincere man and careful thinker, and deserves wide reading." Boston Post. " If any one cares to know what makes for human 'progress in the field of economics, here is the book of all books which America has ever produced." The Public (Abington, Mass.). "We commend Mr. Gunton's book as a calm and instructive argument, which is entitled to serious consideration, and he deserves the thanks of all sound economists." The American (Philadelphia). " Mr. George Gunton has done a real service in publishing his ' Wealth and Progress.' It is refreshing to read the utterances of a man whose tal- ents and studies have fitted him for the work he has undertaken." Boston Advertiser. " If the arguments in this book could be taught in every high-school and college in the land, we might hope for a speedy settlement of the trouble- some and knotty problems of the day." Public Opinion (Washington, D. C.). " It is the most noteworthy of recent American contributions to the eco- nomics of the labor problem. It will at once give its author an assured standing as a political economist." Chicago Dial. " It contains much originality of thought, boldly asserted and consistently maintained, and is presented in such pleasant and attractive form that much of it possesses the interest of a novel." Fall River News (Mass.). "We are impressed with the thoroughness of the author's investigation and the strength of his argument, no less than by the clearness and vigor of his style." Christian Advocate. ' ' The argument of Mr. Gunton is supported by many facts well calculated to prove his theory." Chicago Herald. "It is a very remarkable book, and at the outset it will be very highly appreciated by those best versed in economic science." Sunday Tribune (Minn.). " ' Wealth and Progess ' is a handsome contribution to the science of eco- nomics which is sure to command attention." New Orleans States. " It is a contribution to economical literature of marked value." Scien- tific Arena. " Mr. Gunton has brought to his task a large practical experience with industrial affairs, extended observation both in Europe and America, and clese study of economic questions." San Francisco Bulletin. " The book is well written, and, while wholly opposed to socialism or the vagaries of Henry George's school, is yet strongly in the interest of the laboring clashes." San Francisco Call. " It is one of the most comprehensive discussions of the labor question of the day." Buffalo Advertiser. " The subject is treated in a masterly manner, and will not fail to instruct and profit those who are interested in that all important theme. New Bed- ford Standard (Mass.). "We have in this volume the last contribution of science to the science of political economy, and, as it seems to us, the most valuable." Daily Herald (Omaha). " The present volume is clearly written, and is, to our mind, one of the ablest contributions which has of late been made upon the vexed subject." Buffalo Times. ' ' Wealth and Progress ' is a book designed to mark a new era in the history of political economy." Commonwealth (Boston, Mass.). " The author makes an exhaustive and able presentation of the subject, and his work is entitled to serious consideration." Syracuse "Journal. " The book contains a large mass of valuable statistical information, and should be in the library of every student of the social problem." Labor Leader (Boston). " The author has produced a decidedly readable and suggestive work, giving good proof that political economy has become a study of prominent interest. He is no visionary socialist, but builds his propositions on facts and sound common-sense." The Moravian. " It will be readily admitted that he has in this volume made a valuable contribution to the discussion of one of the burning questions of the day." Washington Post. " We may fully commend it as presenting many aspects of the great ques- tion with remarkable force." Hartford Courant. " By none could such a work have been written but by a master of eco- nomic science, a thorough reader of statistics, a lucid and comprehensive thinker." Catholic Quarterly Re^tieu<. ' ' Wealth and Progress ' will in time effect a revolution in what is known as political economy." Record and Guide (New York). 4 ENGLISH NOTICES. " Mr. Gunton is known in the United States as a hard student of eco- nomic questions, and as a writer of high ability. That character is fully borne up by his volume ' Wealth and Progress.' " The Scotsman. " Mr. Gunton throws fresh light on a much-discussed subject, and we cor- dially recommend his book to our readers." Belfast Northern Whig. " The work contains immense and laborious research, and is entitled to a thoughtful perusal and unqualified respect." Liverpool Post. " Mr. Gunton's book is a very important contribution to economic science, and deserves the most earnest consideration from all classes in the commu- nity." Literary World (London). " ' Wealth and Progress' is certainly a work of great suggestiveness and usefulness. The practical value of its conclusion is undeniable. Its theory goes beyond explanation, and guides action giving, indeed, a new scien- tific sanction to schemes of social amelioration hitherto taken in a spirit of vague philanthropy. He has gone far to achieve what economists and so- cialists alike have failed to do. He has developed a theory of wages in harmony with the social instincts and tendencies of to-day." Scottish Leader. " The performance leaves little to be desired for clearness of statement or for aptness of illustration." St. James's Gazette (London). " The idea is presented with clearness, and the arguments in its favor, as well as some of the objections to its practical workings, are ably stated." Morning Post (London). "The importance of the question, the ability, earnestness, and experi- ence of industrial affairs which Mr. Gunton brings to the study of a difficult problem, entitle his work to respectful consideration. Mr. Gunton's book is very welcome, as it enforces from an economical point of view the great importance which must be attached to character." Charity Organization Review (London). " Mr. Gunton's book is written with great clearness and force of style and thought, and attacks two of the most long-standing doctrines in Political Economy the doctrine of the wages-fund, and the determination of wages by supply and demand." The Spectator (London). For sale by booksellers ; or will be sent by mail, postage-paid, on receipt of the price, one dollar. D. APPLETON & Co. MACMILLAN & Co. i, 3 & 5 BOND ST., NEW YORK LONDON, ENG. UCSB LIBRARY ' ."gSOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY