THE "CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION" A Realistic Psychology BY ROBERT CHENAULT GIVLER, Ph. D. Instructor in Psychology in the University of Washington PSTCH COPYRIGHT APPLIED FOR DEDICATED TO ALL THOSE NOT YET BEDEVILED BY THE DOCTRINE OF HARD ATOMS AND SOFT SOULS, BUT WRITTEN FOR THE OTHERS 332654 INTRODUCTION Memories of Aristotle, together with the latest popular information about the nerves, make up the bulk of the usual text-books in psychology. Faculty psychology is still with us, however much we may have renounced it in our sane and critical moments; our lan- guage flows on by momentum as it did of yore, and the old nouns still call seductively. For in the midst of our revolt against substantialism, we know not yet how to speak in a constructive manner. I am convinced that no pussy-foot departures from this type of psychology will render adequate service to the matter involved, and I mean, furthermore, that these pages shall bear witness of that conviction. Even in some of the better universities of this country there is a great discrepancy between the psychology verbally taught in the lectures, and that which the student reads in the assigned references. Even the usual book on the subject is a popular phrasing of the enjoyable lecture material of the author's previous years, and not that psy- chology which represents the best of his pres- ent estimate of the subject. The ways of men INTRODUCTION seem to be so incurably pragmatic, that it is dan- gerous to publish the untried. I offer this outline of a realistic program for psychology as something but partly tried. By realistic I mean that mind is treated as some- thing observable, something mentionable in all of its phases, as well as in its last analysis. There will not be urged any non possiunus intel- legere at the close of the book, however many special matters must be left untouched for lack of space. The claim here made is that mind, soul, thought, consciousness, and all other terms referring to personality, are in no need of being interpreted by way of Paddock, but rather that they mean things which can be discussed and understood by any one so disposed. Psychol- ogy is a natural science, — that is, it requires no concept of trans-empirical things to deal with it exhaustively. This will heartily displease a host of readers, and those who "imagine there must be the indefinite something in the mys- sterious all this" will not be enthusiastic about the ideas hereinafter to be presented. There are two ever-recurring items in this book to which signal attention may be called. The one is the special form of analysis used, and the other is the continual reference to deep- seated errors in popular psychology. For both INTRODUCTION of these characteristic attitudes I am glad to acknowledge my indehtedness to Professor Ed- win B. Holt, of Harvard University. His "Con- cept of Consciousness," from which I have un- sparingly quoted in these pages, may be said to have furnished the foundation upon which this whole structure has been laid. The title of this book itself is one of his keenest phrases. I am not sure that he will acknowledge the whole pro- gram employed herein as deducible from real- istic premises, but I feel sure that many com- mon parts exist between his exposition of real- ism and mine. Either logic or flapdoodle. This is the thesis defended in this book with regard to the anal- ysis of mind. If one is to speak at all about any matter, let him first of all be clear and de- finitive. Fusion and synthesis come fast enough to undo the work of separating things into their elements for the sake of a clear comprehension of them. For the business of speaking in gen- eral about matters that are particular is not only avoiding the issue, but it is even a tacit attempt to traduce the factual status of the terms involved. In following this scheme, the student will find a bit of ditficult reading here and there. Nevertheless, the ultimate grounds of logic are not only what every vigorous stu- iii INTRODUCTION dent deserves to know, but that which he straightway asks to have exhibited to him as well. This method may be altogether too am- bitious, but if logical treatment cannot be em- ployed in psychology, we had better not talk of a science of human consciousness. For the general polemical tone of this book no apology would be sincere. Students come into psychology with all sorts of quaint notions about themselves, which only a wholesale, im- mediate house-cleaning will suffice to eliminate. Nothing is of so much benefit to a man as to realize once in a while that he has been going by momentum rather than by initiative, and a course in psychology is scarcely beneficial if it does not pluck one clean from his worst ruts. In fact, the writing of this book is designed to stimulate to that end rather than to perpetuate drowsiness. The reader is hereby assured that all of the notions combated in these pages are combated in a manner specifically meant. As is well known, realists do not usually have the reputation of apologizing for their directness, and if they are wrong, no one need hesitatingly whisper back the verdict of error. As a last special item to be mentioned, this book is not a behavioristic psychology, however much the words "organism" and "function" may INTRODUCTION appear in it. As I understand it, behaviorism is a theory of the criteria of mind, and not a system that can be substituted for psychology. It is rather a thesis defending the notion of continuity in the animal kingdom, — something, to be sure, no realist would sanely controvert, — and upon inspection, its chief motive turns out to be an animism with the "anima" left out. It is not an exhaustive study of even the behaviors of the organisms whose tropisms it records. This book is a realistic program for psychology and thereby holds that the environment is al- ways to be kept in view along with whatever the organism may be internally or externally accomplishing upon it. Not all has been accomplished, however, that was in the original plan. As a text-book it is full of gaps. But, inasmuch as it was writ- ten solely for use in my own classes, and is to be supplemented by lectures to fill in these gaps, only the general plan is offered for crit- icism to the general reader. Few signally acute experiments have been cited, and those are rep- resentative rather than exhaustive reckonings with the data involved. The empirical status of mind is the central item of this book, as well as the continual warnings against mysticism INTRODUCTION and sentimentality in regard to the science of psychology. The bibliography included in this book has JDeen devised for elementary students who do not readily read French or German. It contains but few references, and these few are selected with a view to supporting rather than inhibiting the theses contained in the text. In the preparation of this book for the press I have been assisted in various ways by those to whom this public thanks is due. To my col- league, Dr. E. R. Guthrie, 1 am indebted for very helpful hints as to some of the logical matters involved in the first two chapters; to Margaret Givler, for a thorough inspection and criticism of the text in point of diction and rhetoric; and to Mr. William R. Wilson, of the University of Washington, for assistance in proof-reading as well as for suggestions as to clarity of expres- sion from the student's standpoint. Seattle, Aug. 1, 1915. VI Terniinolog CONTENTS Chapter I. Page 1 Chapter II. Psychological Analysis 39 Chapter III. The Sensitive and Perceptive Organs 71 Chapter IV. The Emotional Complex 302 Chapter V. Matters and Minds 374 THE "CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION" CHAPTER I. TERMINOLOGY 1. There are two fallacies, either of which usually bothers the tyro in psychology: the first is, that since everybody has a mind, each one on that account knows more than any one else can know about his own mind; and the other is, that mind, being that unique and most intricate thing in the whole universe, contains something so elusive and mysterious that it can never be fully known. 2. The first thing to do is to surmount both of these statements so that they will not plague us any longer. They are both samples of reasoning by analogy, rather than reasoning from principles concerning which there is no room for quibbling. If a thing can be dis- proven by the same sort of reasoning by which it was proven, it cannot be sound. We shall, then, first disprove them by analogical reason- ing, and later on, by another and better kind, so that they will be permanently surmounted. Now, everybody not only has a mind, but a deceased ancestor, a mesentery, and at an early 1 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION age, a future. But who would claim to know his own deceased ancestor as well as some one else might have known him, or that the healthy or diseased state of his own mesentery were as plainly before him as the news of to- day's paper? Nor, again, can it be maintained that one necessarily knows his own future or what its development will be as well as those who, having followed his family history, might safely predict after watching his habit forma- tions ripen into maturity beyond voluntary re- call. This shows sufficiently the purely verbal character of the first fallacy in the preceding paragraph. 3. For the second one, a similar treatment will suffice. The mysterious element in mind is said to stand in the way of a scientific psychol- ogy, inasmuch as mystery is a word usually employed to indicate an inherent property of things not yet known. But, besides this, there is no reason why one should reserve his mys- teries until the last chapter of psychology, rather than plant them squarely at the begin- ning, or why that part of psychology which is open to investigation must therefore be pes- tered by some beetling mystery which comes ominously near and provokingly soon. To carry this fallacious argument to its limits, one 2 TERMINOLOGY would be permitted, in solving a mathematical problem, to excuse his errors in calculation on the ground that numbers were pure figments of the imagination anyway, and that his imagina- tion was at least as good as that of the early Egyptians. 4. This is, however, only meeting poor arguments with equally poor ones. A fallacy is not merely something that can be laughed off, but in these cases it is something which needs to be surmounted by an appeal to exact principles rather than to the playfulness of words. As soon as one begins an argument, he lays himself open to the perils of argument; it will also be public information whether what goes for proof can withstand all inquiry that is brought to bear upon the statements uttered and defended. The difficulty with these two fallacies is that they contain words which can- not be pressed for their meaning within the total context in which they are embedded; lack- ing the form of clear-cut statements, they can- not be pressed for conclusions. Chaff put into a hopper will not grind into wheat in any mill except the one owned by Grimm and Grimm. Let us carefully show how this is. 5. Every science is a collection of observed facts gathered together under the guidance of 3 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION a permanent interest, plus as many conjectures as to the relationships of these facts to one an- other as are required to arrange them in a sys- tem or to apply them to things of the street. A system is an arrangement of things from sim- ple to complex, fundamental to variable; a pile of rubbish is not a system, while the plans for building a pyramid are. The facts of a science must first be supplied with names, and the sig- nificance of the names lies in what the things named will do to one another under certatin fixed conditions. So that which was first named by means of a noun, implying substance and fixity, often later on comes to mean what we express by verbs, — valences, chronic in- stabilities, readiness to affect or be affected by other things. Over the terminology, however, usually not much difficulty seriously arises; our language is not so petrified as to forbid a change of meaning without a change of form. But it is not such a simple matter when one comes to the conjectural part of a science. To formulate the laws of the way things behave, to be sure that one's sampling of behaviors is broad and salient, and to arrange the laws in a logical system, — here in the case of every science there is much difficulty, more disagree- ment and a maximum of doubt as to what can 4 TERMINOLOGY actually be deduced from a system so formed, no matter what the science may be, — Geometry or Ethics. 6. Every science, therefore, might be said to have two sides, — one of observation and the other of logic. We perceive well enough, per- haps, what is before us, but we cannot speak well enough to cover the facts or to convince the audience. To offset this as much as pos- sible, every science reducible to exact termin- ology and quantification is phrased in symbols peculiarly specific and univocal in character. Words of many meanings will not do. It thus uses expressions which are defined, or limited in scope which cover precisely the data in- volved and have the same, rather than a differ- ent meaning to every one more or less con- cerned. One beginning the study of such a science often is disappointed at finding himself in the dark in regard to the thing to be studied, — he had thought that it was to have much more connection with his daily, pressing needs. The reason for this is that those who have devel- oped the science had first themselves to unlearn the current, metaphorical, inexact speech in order to make any headway in it. To com- mand nature, they found they had first to obey THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION it, and so the lesser good had been butchered without a public ceremony of apolog>\ 7. Thus every science aims to be symbolical and univocal in its terminology. However, in psychology, one can hardly ever be said to be clear of that realm of discourse where the pri- vate interpretation of a word may not interrupt all attempts at deductive formulation. Almost every statement can be challenged, almost ev- ery fact be named in several fairly satisfactory ways. But this by no means relegates it to the realm of clannish prejudice. For when a fact has the possibility of being named in many ways, it means only one thing, — that it is no simple, single fact that is before one. One must then look to his terminology to see how much and in what essentials his names for facts have differences irreconcilable with straightforward deductive formulation. Everything is equally a matter of fact, and no datum has any special privileges. If one's logic cannot take care of this or that sufficient statement, it is time for logic to be amended to fit a world whose scien- tific battles it fights. 8. One thing more : no facts have the plas- tic character which language has. One goes to the facts, observes them, analyses and orders them; reconsiders, re-observes and carefully 6 TERMINOLOGY names them over again, — if his need for nam- ing comes out of a dominant motive in his en- deavors,— and no amount of juggling with the words apart from the facts can alter their status in the universe whose laws they exhibit. Hasty conclusions, private uses, idealistic or theological motives may seem to have the power of twisting out of their orders in the world the brute items of empirical nature, but a little watchfulness will serve to undermine such traducing of things empirical and render again to the Caesar of organized facts the things that are none but his. Even the private realm of one's own thoughts has of late years been ob- liged to yield to exact statement. Where, too, formal logic was insufficient to show the bear- ings of private thoughts upon behavior, an in- formal logic has been used to suit each indi- vidual case, thus meeting the unique and "mysterious" upon its own grounds. The growth of abnormal psychology has done much to tear away the mask from the so-called "inner self" and render its crab-like movements pain- fully visible to any curious passerby. 9. But to the theme. The first two state- ments of this chapter were called fallacies not only because of their being controvertible by a mere twist of words, but rather because they 7 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION used concepts in a way totally inadequate to their logical significance in psychology. One argues only by means of logic. There are no "psychological" or "moral" or "economic" rea- sons, — not to say, of course, that psychologists or moralists or economists do not argue. Noth- ing powerful or superior, however, lies in any special kind of reasoning. All reasons are couched in "the rules of the game of talk," as my colleague. Dr. Ducasse, would say, and have validity only in so far as they conform to that pattern of expression. Other things may pro- voke belief, or persuade the lazy not to stew any longer in their own juice, but reasoning is like a game of chess, — it has inviolable rules. It has more, since every science is a case of ap- plied logic. The data of science are not in- vented, but discovered, and certain few things can be done with them and certain others can- not. Only when "dass Lied ist auss," does there come a hankering after any "special" type of reasoning. 10. "Because I have a mind, therefore I should know more about it than any one else," — were this merely a verbal fallacy, one could easily laugh it down; but it contains a more serious fallacy than that. The expression, "I have a mind," harmless enough in itself, is a 8 TERMINOLOGY statement from which nothing can be argued, IF THAT STATEMENT IS THE STARTING POINT. The speaker of it considers himself a psychologist and intends that it shall be valid for psychology. What else could it purport to be? But as formulated, it is an inexact ob- servation, a bit of random thinking that needs to be drawn and quartered rather than em- ployed determinately. It is really a coales- cence of two statements, and belongs to the in- trospective psychology of selfhood rather than to the outspoken formulations of mental life. As a random thought, it exhibits the informal logic of random thinking; but statements meant for the public ear must be couched in the rules of the game of talk. It is not a premiss from which, by itself, anything whatever can be con- cluded. "Having," in fact, is a derivative of other things, — familiarity, acquisition, constant dealings with, something spoken or spoken of, and the like, and not an orginal, first-hand mat- ter at all. The other statement,— the one in- volving the Mystery and tacitly invoking her at the same time, — exhibits several fallacies, which are: (1) that a mystery would not re- main a mystery if it were knowable, and (2) that the part depends upon the whole for its existence and significance. It will be seen 9 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION later on in the chapter on psychological anal- ysis that, even if the naming of all the parts of a whole does not appear to exhaust or explain the properties of that whole, it is not due to thinking, but to the organization of the parts by an extra-mental set of functions, which ac- counts for the "mysterious" element to a large degree. The first of these statements under dis- cussion is a fallacy, therefore, because it is an inexact formulation. The second, likewise, be- cause it violates a law of the logic of organiza- tion. 11. It will be advantageous, then, for the student to approach psychology without any presuppositions. Other assumptions than the aforementioned fallacies may arise in the read- er's mind; some of these coming from trivial, others from earnest desires in regard to ones- self. Yet hasty formulations are always un- wise, and usually, wrong. Psychology is a $tudy of facts, facts not altered by thinking, and only the inability to back off" from them as readily as from the facts of the physical sciences is responsible for the popular view of it as be- ing a study of the way one "feels" about things. Only because psychological things make up to so large an extent the tissue of human afi'airs is one led to infer that the naive expressions of 10 TERMINOLOGY popular speech can become the terminology of the science of psychology without alteration in meaning. "Mind," "consciousness," "thought," "emotion" and the like are all terms as familiar to the psychologist as to the man on the street, but the two cannot converse scientifically on the slender basis of this familiarity. Both care- ful examination and redefinition are essential if understanding is to accompany the use of such words. The need for such careful exam- ination is nowhere so revealed as in cases of naive prediction and reasoning about things mental. In the writings of certain mental heal- ers of today, for example, alliteration is the highest "logical" category; "experience proves" is a shibboleth from another quarter, from per- sons blissfully ignorant of the fact that experi- ence is both a noun and a verb, usually em- ployed in an equivocal sense. "It is unthink- able" asserts a third party, and then he goes on to state just how carefully the "unthinkable" has been thought out. From such pitfalls of ex- pression one needs to be emphatically warned in psycholog\\ 12. Add to that this: there is as yet no com- plete, univocal terminology in psychology. Modern Logic has evolved a set of symbols which avoid careless interpretation of the pro- 11 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION cesses in that science. The physical sciences, and, to a large extent the biological, also, need not always name their facts by such terms as can be quibbled over by those not initiated. Psychology, however, lying on the topmost froth of things, has never been and can never be, wholly free from the errors of verbalism. If it had radically fashioned its own set terms, and used heiroglyphic symbols to express them, this very fact might be a sign of its incapability to serve that human interest out of which it sprang and whose evolution it seeks to register daily. For while every deductive science is a case of applied logic, and while logic and mathematics are basically one, the universe of science rests not altogether solidly, but rather totters on the mathematical foundations to which we ulti- mately appeal for proof. 13. For, if one goes to the facts of a science to find out what shall be said about them, and finds there a number of curiously enigmatical things, yes, even "mysterious" things, as one sometimes does, it would be lazy-mindedness and vanity alone which would lead him to call by simple names things which were exceed- ingly complex. Psychology is full of just such complexities. For example, one starts to in- vestigate a certain phenomenon, say memory; he 12 TERMINOLOGY names it by its accustomed name and sets an experiment which has all possible control over the conditions involved. But frequently the simple, first name given to it begins to prove inadequate; it is not simple, and the single noun, such as memory, adaptation and so on, will no longer do at all. Together with this, frequently conclusions will be drawn from the fact that simple words seemed to fit together to make conclusions sought for as words usually do, whereas the facts referred to by such words had need of being reinterpreted for use in any other context than the small one determined by the rigid conditions of a single experiment. The interests of science were thus curtailed. Clean experimentation, however, cannot be sat- isfied with such methods. If the simple name first given to the phenomenon is inadequate, or if the control of the conditions of experiment interferes with the free operation of the func- tions to be investigated, the work is dropped, the experiment reset, and the old categories are dis- carded. In psychology, as the signal example of a science whose reagents in the laboratory are human beings, one must be prepared for any emergency of this kind. Only a few hu- man beings make good subjects in psychology, and even those must go through a serious and 13 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION long training in accepting the instructions given and keeping even-minded in order to be valu- able for the work under investigation. Psych- ology, as a record from which general state- ments can be made, is thus a study of the re- actions of selected human beings; its data are gathered from persons found fit to accept the conditions of experimentation, and not others. Figuratively, it is an assay of the highest grades of ore. Life is too short to evolve a deductive science of individual meteors. Not to say, how- ever, that with brows uplifted and eyes aloft, psychology neglects those unregenerates who fail to come up to strict laboratory require- ments; for this would be both pharisaism in science as well as unfairness to my fellow psychologists. Only this is meant, that to re- port specifically upon a matter requiring selec- tive attention, selective attenders of such a stripe are the only possible grist. When the erratic are in the majority, we are only experi- menting upon erratics and not upon the in- tended datum set forth. 14. Coupled with the above warnings in the approach to psychology, a little need as well be said about the use of proof and deduction after the data of the science have been correct- ly named, the experiments cleanly performed, 14 TERMINOLOGY and the chief and subsidiary facts arranged in proper order. "This fact proves," it is some- times said, and about such statements the clans of science divide and dispute. There are cases, of course, where this is true, but one needs to be wary. All the sciences are of two kinds on this score, — those which are altogether deduc- tive and those which are slightly deductive and mostly empirical. Pure mathematics is the only strictly deductive science; all the others are of the latter class. 15. Let us elucidate this difference. Deduc- tion starts with principles, which when in- volved, produce results and conclusions which are new in the sense of not being apparent from the original principles, but are "gener- ated" by the interaction of statements. This does not mean that some stater behind the statements does the generating, but that the empirical properties of a logical statement alone furnish the parts out of which the new formula- tion is made. For the stater behind the state- ments is but a mass of unformulated material, which must come out and "lie flat on the brush" before it can be claimed to have the persistent being of generating things. An empirical science, such as geology, on the other hand, first gets principles from observation, and in 15 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION seeking to deduce other principles from them, MUST ALWAYS FIND FACTS OR TERMS which will satisfy the conclusions arrived at. All else is talking in the air. The chemist or the physicist can see how the conclusions of his statements ought to reach this or that end, but only the residues in the retort or the pattern of crystallization on the stone shows him what the upshot of his statements should have been. To a larger extent than the physicist or chem- ist will admit, also, most deduction in his science is just plain memory, — "it will happen again because it has happened before," sums up much of the claims for deduction in most of the natural sciences. Their power lies in the control of conditions, rather than in the ability of their conclusions to produce the facts in a presto manner. 16. From all this it can be seen that the words "logical" and "factual" are not synon- ymous. Arguments about any matter may en- tirely jump the track and evaporate in non- sense. They may, again, run parallel, and, in that amount of a science which survives time, they do. But one needs always to be alert for the fact that will exactly fit his statements as well as for the statement that will exactly fit his facts, facts being rather hard data and not 16 TERMINOLOGY to be treated with impugnity. For while any statement derived from logic has a certain validity, and may be satisfied with terms from some sort of trans-experiential realm, unless the terms can be plainly exhibited to all comers, they should form no part of the body of the science. 17. The use of the proper language and the understanding of just how much of the lan- guage one uses is pertinent to the matter in liand is so important for psychology, that I shall give on the next few pages samples of speech containing psychological as well as non- psychological material, some of which will be analysed for the student, the remainder being left for him to analyse for himself. At first, of course, he will not be able to see the full drift of it, but with further study, new insight will come. To many this will seem a curious and backhanded way of beginning the study of mind, for most text-books start in with an eluci- dation of neural processes and the gospel of dendrites, — things which only the post-mortem anatomist experiences first hand. These anal- yses we shall undertake are of things far more of the now and always, and the claim is here made that it is with this sort of thing that psychology is after all mostly concerned. Let 17 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION US analyse the following statements in common use: 1. The action of the heart is purely me- chanical. Psychological interest is here focussed on the word "purely." First compare the above statement with what is left with this word omitted. The action of the heart is mechanical. The action of the heart is purely mechanical. Logically it is the same, unless "purely" means "nothing but" or some such equivalence, gratia verborum, but psychologically this word adds one of several items to the situation, (a) It delays the utterance of the adjectival predi- cate "mechanical," and in so doing intensifies the effect of that predicate, and by the delay it causes also allows the first five words better to be assimilated and perceived as a unit. Or, (b) the word "purely" insinuates, by the tone of voice used in uttering it, something not alto- gether complimentary to the heart action and we are immediately affected by this bias in it. 2. Where did you go yesterday? The answering of this question implies a memory. The full psychological putting of the matter would be something like this. The sen- sations of what objects and movements are 18 TERMINOLOGY restored to you upon the mention of a time twenty-four hours previous to this? Of course as a statement in psycholog>% it is very con- densed, and does not ask by what means the memory is preserved, whether by vision, au- dition, movement, or speech; nor whether there is clarity or obscurity in the content of con- sciousness provoked by the question. 3. I have never heard of it. We are concerned here wdth three things: (a) the past tense of the verb "hear," (b) the meaning of "never," and (c) the use of the prep- osition "of." As for the first of these, it refers again to memory; the second differs from the word "not" by temporal extent, drawn-outness, — "not" meaning a single point of time, while "never" means many "nots" in a continuous stream. The word "of," harmless as it sounds, is indicative of a very complex relationship. Whatever "it" means, whether an engagement between two lovers or a "cat's-paw" in calm weather, is surely a datum mentionable, hap- pening somewhere, and more or less related to other things. But we do not say "I hear of a noise," as the Greek language says it; we say hear a noise, see a light, smell a rose; and only a few verbs in English are followed by the prep- osition in comparison with many other lan- 19 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION guages dead or living. What, then, do we mean by "hear of it," in referring to a thing past? Why, this, that the observer himself told it, and we heard him tell it, and thus we use the word "of" for things that come to us in relays rather than directly and immediately. But this does not mean that the expression "think of it" is ex- plained in the same way. "Think" is not al- ways followed by a preposition, nor are the words which follow the prepositions necessarily things relayed to the thinker. We shall take up this matter vigorously when we come to the old bugaboo, "consciousness OF." 4. I like this ever so much more than that one. Liking is something peculiarly psychological, and is the starting point for choice. It cannot be referred to logic, for people "like" that which all arguments show is false, dangerous, and sure to produce an aftermath of ill. "Ever so much more" is an attempt to make a scale of values, and is an example of the only "mental" arithmetic there is. "Ever so much more," also differs from plain "more" by the greater num- ber of syllables intervening between "this one" and "that," allowing the voice to add emotion to the comparison. 20 TERMINOLOGY 5. "Sicklied o'er with a pale cast of thought." This line from Hamlet is an hyperhole in rhetoric, while it is a case of empathy in psychologj^ Empathy differs from personifi- cation in that it neither capitalizes the import- ant word, nor does it imply as much animation as the latter. Thus, empathically, a mountain bears up the sky above it, while in personifica- tion the mountain is a man whose shoulders are overburdened with the weight of sky they support. Two of the words in this expression are strictly poetical, — "sicklied" and "o'er." "O'er" is used for smoothness and fine sound, while "sicklied" is a "new" word, psychological- ly. It arose from the mood background which dominated the author. The word "cast" is used to express inertness, referring at the same time to the fixity and whiteness of plaster; the sound of the w^ord also helps to convey one of these meanings. The above expression, taken as a whole and apart from the context in which it was uttered, need not have any clear, whole- some meaning at all, for it was not uttered as any thing to be formally defined or analysed. Certain sayings are indexes of moods, and moods are not always possible or profitable to press for their signification. 21 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION 18. The student will analyse for himself as well as he can the following expressions: 1. Fatima cigarettes are "Distinctively Indi- vidual." 2. The price of this waist is $2.98. 3. He completely forgot himself. 4. Friends, Romans, countrymen, lend me your ears. 5. By merit raised to that bad eminence. 6. I have a good mind to do it. 7. The spirit is willing, but the flesh is weak. 8. Why, then the devil give him good of it. 9. He thanked his stars. 10. I only hope it is not so. 19. Out of the preceding examples much more could be derived than has been indicated, but the analysis of a thing as it stands is quite different from an historical account of its de- velopment. This item has particular point in psychology, for here one has to explain how things started as well as why they continued and what they are now. This, of course, brings one face to face with what are called causes, and every science is supposed to have ready- made answers to every question beginning with "why" that can be formulated. And while this is a logical matter entirely, this much needs to 22 TERMINOLOGY be said about it at this point. Some questions beginning with "why" are answerable, and some others are not. If the reader will look into a text-book of Logic for the "fallacy of many questions" and study the examples there given, he will understand that every question begin- ning with "why" is answerable only when it contains one question and only one. Moreover, only such things have a cause as can be ana- lysed where at least one of the elements de- pends upon a temporal sequence for its specific effect in the whole to which it contributes. Furthermore, there are in every science what are called "elements," "primary facts," "irre- ducible first principles," and to ask the reasons for them in that science is to ask a question to which there is only an "old wives' fable" for an answer. 20. This can be directly shown by the fol- lowing: As the writer understands it, the dif- ference between mathematics and the other sciences is Time. There is, indeed, no mention of time in either Geometry or Algebra. Their principles, it is true, were found out by cul- tured gentlemen in this or that decade or cen- tury, but there is no t or t- in mathematics as there is, for example, in physics. Time being the one fundamental, independent variable of 23 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION science, the sciences are logically arranged in point of the amount of dependence they show upon this temporal factor. In such an arrange- ment the sciences based on psychology are at the extreme end of the list, farthest from mathe- matics, — that is, from the mathematics which deals with general data and does not need to discount its answers upon meeting with the empirical situation. Less and less intric- ately involved in the temporal dilemma than is psychology are first the biological sciences, next the chemical, and next the physical. In the mathematical sciences, which come next, time is replaced by the sort of activity which generates the number system. As the time element increases in complexity in the scale of sciences, also, less and less do they become reducible to a mathematical or equa- tional form. Now the questions propounded to the physicist which ask "why" are explained either by reference to mathematics, or by the elements of his own science; those put to the chemist are referred either to his own data, to those of physics, or those of mathematics; and so on throughout the list. But not every "why" in any one science is necessarily referred be- yond that science. Some things are chemical, and that ends it. Thus, also, some things are 24 TERMINOLOGY psychological and nothing else, and the answer is vanity that attempts to find a first cause for them in the realm of things remote. The above- mentioned order, also, of the sciences is not reversible. One does not go to psychology, for instance, to find out the fundamental facts of geology, nor to the realm of esthetics for the fact that there are but three laws in Newton's formulation of the activity of moving bodies. 21. Many writers call these "elements" or "primary facts" assumptions, and mean by that word something not altogether complimentary to the science. It is not here to be argued why these should not be accepted as assumptions, with all the unlovely flavor that has accrued to the word; but, on the other hand, it must be re- membered that no one starts a science, and that an assumption is not the first thing sought for by scientists. All science is chasing flying game, and no fair-minded scientist "assumes" except for the purpose of tentatively arranging facts in a probable order. 22. The principal thing, also, in answering the question "why," (which is far less important than the questions "what" or "how"), is not to explain things away by reference to something remote or forgotten, but to point out the func- tional dependence of various things on each 25 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION other. Cause is no longer a live word in science. Only naive minds seek for a cause. Just as the words "must" and "ought" have finally lost their zest, even in Ethics, so the word "cause" is nothing to conjure with today. Cause always had the ultimate meaning of "who made it?" and "making" is nothing with which science has to do. That vis viva or Anstoss which for- merly was said to make a stone in the air fall to the ground, or make a man follow theft with theft, is not any longer harbored in scientific thinking. Functional dependence has replaced it entirely, and by functional dependence the following things are meant: (1) that all nat- ural laws are laws of description and not of necessity, and (2) that those laws are exhibited only when terms are free to be involved in the relations they entail. If a room is full of il- luminating gas, only when there are persons in it will there be any deaths from asphyxiation; similarly, a nation will be successful in war only when patriotism is backed by a purse. "Only when," "when this, then that," "the con- ditions being fulfilled,"— these are the salient words in science today. Cause is nothing to be wept or argued over; the question "why" is sheer myth and biography. 23. It is by means of this principle of func- 26 TERMINOLOGY tional dependence that the empirical sciences, incUiding psychology, become deductive as well. We shall see later on why, (apply the func- tional meaning from now on to this word), psychology is not a science of the "shreds and clippings of other things," nor a study of illu- sions or of brain perspirations, but a study of the functional dependence of mind upon the objects within reach of the sensitive and per- ceptive organs on the one hand, and of the ac- tion of auto-catalysed nerve colonies within the body on the other. A detailed explanation of the meaning of these expressions will be given in succeeding pages. Suffice it to say here, that the term "functional dependence" does not mean any chain-system of fore-ordained hap- penings, but rather the readiness of storehouses of energy to discharge upon the presentation of an excitant sufTicient to arouse such dis- charge. The old idea of a cause (usually cap- ital "C") too often meant a subtle, monistic push, which in the same way and to the same end brought about every change or effect. The idea of functional dependence, on the contrary, assumes no such gratuities; things which stand in a functionally dependent relationship need have nothing in common, — no subtle, interpene- trating power which on the one hand allows, 27 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION and on the other hand brings to bear, the act- ing force. Every change, to be brief, comes about by virtue of an unstable equilibrium; but there are equilibria of continuity as well as of position. This is the same as saying that ev- erything in the cosmos, unless it is manifest- ing this or that property exhaustively, is not fixed in that way of acting indefinitely, but is subject to any other combination of things strong enough to "capture" it. To use a crass figure, — if it does not do well in one occupation, it is free to enter another. 24. What bearing this has upon psychology will at once be seen, if we consider that all such discussions as the "dualism of mind and body," "the eff"ect one mind has upon another," or "the way mind controls the body," have absolutely no meaning under the concept of functional de- pendence of mind both upon its objects and upon the neural processes which grow toward certain independent tendencies within the body. In this book no word will be said either for or against the dualism of mind and matter, for or against the way minds control bodies, and the like outworn doctrines. Mind shall be re- garded as a cluster of objects and a colony of functions, and not as some hidden, uncanny ghost that roosts on a certain gland in the cere- 28 TERMINOLOGY brum, dabbling her feet in a puddle of lymph. The reader may be disappointed at not being able to while away a few more hours of his life with these old, old questions of such great moment. But a science does not begin with that sort of dawdling, nor is it furthered by per- sisting in it. We shall treat of mind empirical- ly, as something that is just as patent as bricks and barley, and for such a treatment the reader is invited to be fully prepared. 25. It is now time to define the subject of this book — consciousness. Consciousness is the objects within responsive range of the nervous system, and the manner in which they are re- sponded to by the nervous system. It is thus a content, or various kinds of things more or less organized together, as well as degrees of closely knit or looser organization. The most accurate as well as the most brilliant putting of this idea is to be found in Edwin Holt's "The Concept of Consciousness," Chapter IX, from which 1 shall quote at some length, (p. 168) "Let us suppose that a plane mathematically true but one milli- metre thick passes perpendicularly through the roots, trunk and branches of a tree; and let us suppose all the molecules of chemical sub- stances belonging to the tree and included with- in the section, to be simply enumerated. It is 29 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION clear that this collection is an actual part of the tree, and yet one that in itself would con- tribute very little to the life and development of the tree Yet this would not be a random collection, for it would include none but vegetable molecules included within the intersecting millimetre plane. The plane, with what it includes, is exactly defined in terms of the entire tree and the position of the plane. Merely from the point of view of the vital or- ganization of the tree would this collection be a random one. The law that defines the lie of the plane is not among the laws that define the anatomy and vegetable economy of the tree. Such a collection may be called a 'cross-section.' Similarly the prime numbers are a 'cross-sec- tion.' "Again, if the plane is a geometrical one of no thickness and passing horizontally through the trunk, it defines by its intersection a col- lection of contours that is a true portion of the tree, but one that is even less significant for the total economy of the tree than the collec- tion previously defined. A complete knowledge of it would be next to no knowledge of the tree as a whole. It would be, roughly speaking, merely a circular contour containing an infinity of minor contours." 30 TERMINOLOGY "Now the cross-sections so far adduced are not merely insignificant for the whole of which they are a part, but they are also rather insig- nificant for any system, howsoever inclusive. There are other cross-sections, however, which do have a prime significance in and for some manifold more complex and inclusive than the manifold through which the cross-section is initially made. Thus the sum total of all whales living in certain given waters is a cross- section of the sea that is significant for the whalers who are trying to locate and gather them in. The various shafts and levels of a mine are a cross-section of the mountain, and of import to the shareholders; it is the business of the engineer so to direct the workings that this cross-section shall coincide with that other cross-section that is made by the vein of ore. "Once again, a navigator exploring his course at night with the help of a searchlight, illuminates a considerable expanse of wave and cloud, occasionally the bow and forward mast of his ship, and the hither side of other ships and of buoys, lighthouses, and other objects that lie above the horizon. Now the sum total of all surfaces thus illuminated in the course, say, of an entire night, is a cross-section of the region in question that has rather interesting 31 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION characteristics. It is defined, of course, by the contours and surface composition of the re- gion, including such changes as take place in these (specially on the surface of the waves), and by the searchlight and its movements, and by the progress of the ship. The manifold, so defined, however, is neither ship nor search- light, nor any part of them, but is a portion (oddly selected) of the region through which the ship is passing. This cross-section, as a manifold, is clearly extended in space, and ex- tended in time as well, since it extends through some watches of the night. This cross-section, furthermore, is in no sense inside the search- light, nor are the objects that make up the cross-section in any wise dependent on the searchlight for their substance or their being. "Now cross-sections that in many respects resemble the one just described are found in any manifold in which there is organic life." "It is to certain features, and not to others, of its environment that the living organism re- sponds, and the group of things to which it thus reacts constitutes a cross-section manifold that is of prime importance to one who is study- ing the organism and one that is of the most vital importance, of course, to the organism itself." 32 TERMINOLOGY (p. 173) "We have always known, of course, that plants 'respond' in a general way to sun- light, air and water. More recently we have become acquainted with processes that are more appropriately named responses. Roots do not grow downward by chance nor by any pre-established harmony, nor yet by instinct, but they respond mechanically to the attraction of gravitation, nor is this merely due to the general weight of the root, since by a compar- able mechanism the stems grow contrarily to gravitation. The roots are positively geotactic or barotropic, while the stems are negatively, and many kinds of branches transversely baro- tropic. Similarly, and by virtue of a distinct mechanism, the various parts of a plant respond variously to light of different colors and in- tensities, growing toward or away from such light: they are variously heliotropic. There are similar responses in vegetable organisms to thermal, chemical and even electrical stimuli, and we are gradually coming to know that these involve a well-differentiated and oftentimes a highly elaborate mechanism of response. Now clearly in the case of a given plant these baro-, helio-, thermo-, chemo-, and galvano-tropisms, these several mechanisms of response, define a certain cross-section of the plant's environment 33 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION that is comparable with the cross-section de- fined by the searchlight. , . . And these forces, be it noted, to which the plant responds are distinct from the mechanism by which the response is effected; they are a portion of the environment." (p. 178) "In the case of vegetable organisms we found that the sum total of entities in the surrounding physical system t ) which a plant responds, forms an intricate and in some re- spects an interesting cross-section of such physical system. And from the point of view of the plant, clearly, this effective environment is all the environment that it has; and this en- vironment is distinct from its own organic structure. We saw, furthermore, even in our earliest cross-sections, in inorganic manifolds, that the cross-section often so cut the manifold as to reveal the conceptual or neutral nature of physical objects; the velocities of all flying projectiles, and the section of a tree cut by a mathematical plane, were such cross-sections. They are true parts of the projectiles and the tree, respectively, yet they are not ponderable physical bodies: they are certain neutral com- ponents of these bodies. The same is a fortiori true of the cross-sections defined by plant re- sponses. The leaflet bends toward a ray of 34 TERMINOLOGY light (a physical energy, if you will), but it re- sponds more rapidly to a more intense ray, and to a very weak ray it will not respond at all. It therefore responds not merely to light, but also to intensity. In responding differently to different grades of intensity, it defines grades of intensity as well as light energy, as components of its effective enviromental cross-section. Now whatever light may be, grades of intensity are not physical objects And these grades of intensity are not in the plant, certainly no farther in than the surface of the leaves. In a similar way plants respond in all their tropisms very specifically to direction 'as such'; and di- rection is a neutral entity. It too is not in the plant. And if we were thus to study plant re- sponse in detail, we should find that very few indeed of the factors to which the plant re- sponds are such entities as would ordinarly be said to have 'physical' existence; although both the plant and its environment are plain, phys- ical objects." (p. 182) "We have seen that the phenomenon of response defines a cross-section of the en- vironment without, which is a neutral mani- fold. Now this neutral cross-section outside of the nervous system, and composed of the neu- tral elements of physical and non-physical ob- 35 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION jects to which the nervous system is respond- ing by some specific response,— tliis neutral cross-section, I submit, coincides exactly with the list of objects of which we say we are con- scious. This neutral cross-section as defined by the specific reaction of reflex arcs is the psychic realm : — it is the manifold of our sensations, per- ceptions, and ideas: — it is consciousness." In this conscious cross-section, furthermore, let it be understood once and for all, that everything ever called mental, psychical or any other term referring to knowledge, awareness, feeling or judgment is unequivocally and thoroughly con- tained. If there be mystery, also, it is right there; as well as dreams, hallucinations, and the other twilight phenomena of psychology. Those "having minds, and therefore claiming an a priori peek into their nature," are none the less referable to this concept of consciousness for an explanation of their sayings and think- ings. For while we select for our laboratories only those having gumption and grandfathers, a complete psychology accounts satisfactorily for the whole gamut of human interests, affec- tions and disaffections. Furthermore, we shall not say anything about the 'purely' mechanical or the 'purely' mental; things will be just plain mechanical and phiin mental, instead. Hard 36 TERMINOLOGY atoms and soft souls may suit the tempera- mentally minded, but whatever vanities science may exhibit, temperament is not one of them. However, psychology being the realm in which temperaments operate, no grudge need accom- pany the task of explaining them. 26. We are then not going to study capital M mind, nor are we to treat of consciousness as an inner imp. We shall treat of it as a vary- ing content, as a shifting process, and as a man- ifold with a highly unstable center of refer- ence, — the pronoun I. The language by which we express our thoughts has been shown to be now too abbreviated, now too redundant and oftener than either, too erratic to be depended upon for scientific purposes without pruning and redirection. Our naive view of mind, also, must for a time be passed through the fine sieve of analysis in order that confusion of words be avoided. This is not a materialistic psychology, but a realistic one which is here presented. In the next chapter it will be shown why materialism is too theological for scientific purposes. A scientific psychology has neither intention nor power to deny the existence of anything which humanity has found meaning- ful, but there is no law in the universe which guarantees that accuracy shall be evolved from 37 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION chronogenetic thinking, nor that what we are wont to say about ourselves need have any truth in it at all. Bibliography. Holt, E. B., "The Concept of Consciousness," especially chapters VI, VII, VIII and IX. James, W., "Essays in Radical Empiricism," especially Chap. I, "Does 'Consciousness' Ex- ist?" and Chap. Ill, "The Thing and its Rela- tions." Mach, E., "Contributions to the Analysis of the Sensations," especially the "Introductory Remarks. Antimetaphysical." 38 CHAPTER U. PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS 1. Whether one asks "what" the mind is, "how" it acts, or "why" it does thus or so, the answer is to be sought for only in analysis. For all such questions insinuate either a content or a process not yet discerned in its parts or rela- tions, and only an answer that is explicative will suffice to enlarge our knowledge of the subject. The test of analysis also rests upon its giving such answers as will clarify rather than be- cloud the matter under investigation, but it scarcely needs to be said that the goal arrived at does not gain its validity from squaring with naive expectation. 2. Psychological analysis concerns only the data of psychology. We do not analyse glaciers by it, nor do we seek to discover by its use the laws of thermo-dynamics. But the col- ors of glaciers may be analysed by psychological means without any reference to the speed of those masses of moving ice which are colorful as well as cold. In the same way, the manner in which the laws of thermo-dynamics were found are material for psycholog>', since the human beings who struggled to know them rea- 39 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION soned from the data as minds are always wont to reason. Notice these cases of such analysis. (a) Orange is a mixture of red and yellow, while violet is a mixture of red and blue. The position of these colors in the spectrum tells nothing about their properties when abstracted from such a series, Imt by means of the eye alone we detect something both reddish and yellowish about orange, and something both reddish and bluish about violet. On the con- trary, we cannot analyse either green, yellow, blue or red into anything else, and so for phy- chology these are ultimate hues. (b) One closes his eyes, and tells as well as he can the direction from which a sound is coming. By turning his head this way and ttihat, by pausing and carefully listening, he Anally decides upon the general direction by means of his ears and movements alone. Then, under the same conditions, two sounds are employed which he is to distinguish as being equally or unequally far away, symmetrically or unsymmetrically placed with reference to the head, and so on. Each time he attends, es- timates and judges by the same means and thus is said to analyse the situation psychologically. (c) While we are sitting in a hotel lobby, a scuffle occurs on the street outside and some 40 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS one is badly hurt. The matter becomes of legal proportions and our testimony is required to determine the exact status of the offense. We saw something, heard something, and were somewhat disturbed over it, but just what oc- curred that we can swear to is not quite clear and plain. Court-room testimony follows, and, by reason of agreement among veracious wit- nesses, there is a verdict. The process of re- calling what happened, how it developed, and why the case ended as it did is entirely a psychological matter, and the results are vainly appealed to other than psychological beings, — justice or injustice being the residue of seeing, hearing, remembering, feeling, intending, and so on, with which no physicist, chemist, astron- omer or other scientist is able to deal with first hand at all. Psychology exhausts it utterly. (d) An old and wealthy uncle does not shake off the mortal coils soon enough to suit his prospective legatees. They each know what his will provides for them, but, fearing that he may change his mind any moment, try to get him committed to some asylum in order to gain their present ends. But the uncle is individual- istic, and far from allowing himself to be beck- oned unresistingly away, fights the attempt by legal means. Alienists are called in and his 41 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION mind is thoroughly tested by analysis to prove or disprove the charge made against him by his relatives. Whom else should they call in except psychological analysers? Psychological data are the ultimate things in the case, — the uncle's habits, temper, typical manifestations of all kinds, — and when these are sifted over and over again to a conclusion, there is no ap- peal beyond it. The uncle is what he does, says, feels, and the like, and the result is total- ly in and of psychology. These will suffice as a preliminary to other analyses which must be delayed until later topics in the book introduce them. 2. Just what analysis properly is may be shown by the following quotation from E. G. Spauding's "A Defense of Analysis," from the "New Realism" (p. 161) : " Given a whole which, for one rea- son or another, is known to be analysable, then analysis reveals parts, but it also reveals the re- lations which relate and so organize these parts into some kind of a whole. Consider also those properties which, in some cases, the whole, as a whole, may have different from those of the parts. Of course, analysis reveals these also. The analysis may be incomplete in the sense that there may be further parts, that is, parts of 42 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS parts, which are not yet revealed; but, if ana- lysis is incomplete only in this sense, that is, if there have been revealed parts, their organizing relations, and, in some cases, the possibly specific properties of the whole, then the ana- lysis may be said to be adequate. It exhausts the whole up to the point that it reaches, in that, while the specification of all that the analysis reveals does not specify the whole, the whole, nevertheless, is the parts and their prop- erties and the relations relating the parts and the possibly specific properties of the whole. There may be further parts of parts, more prop- erties, more relations to be revealed, but this of itself does not invalidate the position that the properties of the parts and the generating re- lations which are revealed are quite as real as is the whole which is analysed, are not con- tradictory of the whole, and exist, or subsist, in- dependently of the discovery and of the speci- fication." To apply this to a case in point in psychology, the analysis of a so-called "mental" situation into object and response, or into con- tent and process, does not make it "physical" or "neurological" to the exclusion of its being "psychological"; no more than does the analysis of the pictorial representation of a triangle into three straight or three curved lines make absurd 43 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION or impossible the mention of triangularity along with the mention of the lines. This also is a vital point: that the psychological simplicity of things is too often mistaken for logical simplic- ity; for it shall happen that ever so much more than we suspect is blended into a single sensa- tion, emotion, or perception, which only ana- lysis can reveal. But we shall find that there is nothing "mental" behind the psychological wholes we analyse into parts, or those psy- chological things we split into their attributes. The "mental" is an organizing relation, separ- able from the organized elements, and in no sense bewitching them when out of such rela- tion. 3. There is today in some quarters much opposition to the analytic method in psychol- ogy. It is said to invent rather than discover the parts and relations it finds. This hails from that era of lazymindedness when a "mental" substance and a "physical" substance were said to irrevocably dichotomize the universe; from which substances bodies and souls, matter and mind were held to emanate. Two great un- knowns were hypothecated, — unknowns, mind you, and yet mentioned with all the toplofty grandiloquence of philosophy's worst. Objects and thoughts were then simply the scruff of 44 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS these mentioned unmentionables in which rea- son, value and stability were forever snugly sequestered. To be sure, death has been kind enough to remove some of the upholders of this doctrine from our sight, while the advance of general intelligence has revealed the unpleas- ant, ulterior motives lying behind it. 4. Even today a timidity characterizes some of those who defend analysis. One defender to whom I could specifically refer asks why he shouldn't use it, since even its defamers employ it in their attacks. Another avers that for "scientific" purposes one must assume the analysability of all subject matter, — for since minds are free, they are therefore even at lib- erty to consider themselves purely or grossly mechanical, just as they choose. Both of these defenses are all too timid, and the flank attacks they allow and invite would be in both cases deadly, if undertaken. Let us surmount these arguments as we have done former ones. As far as the first is concerned, it is a lame excuse to claim the victory on a draw. If defamers of analysis use it, of course they involve themselves in a net, but that is hardly the point. The point is whether they have used it expressly to get in- volved in the net, for if this can be shown, we 45 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION need only account it another defeat for verbal- ism. And verbalism is just what it always turns out to be. This is, indeed, being almost too generous; for having to extricate from their own "mire of logic" those who wilfully fall therein, would not be half so pathetic if it might only show in this case that analysis had been a word misunderstood, — a name much taken in vain. To show where analysis is ef- fective, one has only to point to those cases where it neither controverts itself nor fails to reveal the parts or relations it chases hot-foot after. 5. As for the second of the above state- ments, it misses the whole point in the matter under discussion. Analysis defines neither freedom nor continuity. It arises merely from the wholesome suspicion that the safest and wisest thing to do is to continually regard as ultimately compilex that which appears psy- chologically simple. It grants, for instance, that looking at a color and saying nothing about it may be a single, illy defined state of mind. But that is not the only sort of color experienc- ing we find in the cosmos. Artists and physi- cists mention their colors and thereby get in- volved in the game of talk; and, curses or no on the man who discovered logic, the mention- 46 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS ing of colors even throws light upon the ex- periencing of colors without mentioning them at the time! Besides, according to this wisp of a sentence about "mental freedom," almost any sort of declaration one felt eager to make might have a place in the sun. 1 vaguely recall read- ing somewhere that the word "Adam" (the gar- den variety) means "a dam" or "obstruction," whence is proven that "mortal mind" is very, very impervious to spiritual influences. There was a day, I am told, when word-juggling such as this passed for logical astuteness, 6. My own defense of analysis is as follows. Even if there should be in everything one at- tempts to analyse two series, — one, an indefinite continuity, the other a discrete discontinuity; the first giving it thinghood out of ineff"able substance, the second giving it thinghood out of elements in relation, — only the latter being reduced to parts by analysis, — then it is high time to enquire w^hat is the difference between them in the aggregate which they form. If, for example, there are two coats in the coat I wear, — the one made up of the pieces of cloth sewed together, and the other a something which as a concept or idea is not destroyed though the coat be cut up into patches, — then of course what I analyse in this and in other 47 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION situations is made of parts, and not that coat "which was from the beginning and is now." But even if a concept, or idea, say that of a coat, can be shown to differ from another con- cept, say that of a card-case within the coat pocket; and if their differences can be made specific, then what is different must differ in nameable ways. And if the difference between concepts is such a one as this, and it is, then all concepts are as analysable as are "things," for one concept will differ from another in the same way as one "thing" from another. Thus the "mental" and the "physical" are both equal- ly mentionable and analysable. We shall see presently of what their parts are made. And if any one says that the science of psychologj^ does not come within three miles of explaining his mind, I shall only remand him either to poetry for solace, or to these words of William James for reproof: "Things of an unexperi- enceable nature may exist ad libitum, but they form no part of the material for philosophic debate." Again, if it is said that one loses most of the specific properties of the whole in the midst of analysis, and has but "shreds and clippings" for his pains, one then but sees what a powerful logical weapon it is, for by means of it he can find out, as his analysis proceeds, 48 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS just where this or that property of an organ- ized whole vanishes from the complex. So that along with the "immoral value" of destruction comes the cognitive value of locating and trouncing the "mysterious." 7. Rebounding flabbily from these argu- ments, the adversary once more challenges: "What you should do is to 'synthesize' rather than analyse; build up rather than destroy in your scientific endeavor." We reply with a double answer. Things are first found synthe- sized, but the fusion and confusion thereby en- tailed is quite opposed in many cases to the purposes of science. You cannot make a Bot- any out of the chronogenetic order of trees and flowers; indeed, you can just passably make a garden. And this: the synthetic, temporal or- der of nature is not the only synthetic order possible; nor is it the order, whether or no, which makes any science deductive. So that, far from avoiding the issue, the scientific analyst accepts the task of two lifetimes, — both that of following the chronogenetic syntheses of na- ture and that of planning the way for that synthesis which shall best suit the practical concerns of subduing nature for his own spir- itual ends. 8. Psychology, as the science of the con- 49 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION scious cross-section, is stated in the same way as any other science, namely, by the use of terms in relation. For example, Boyle's Law states that, "For the same temperature the density of a gas is directly proportional to the pressure acting upon it." Now as it stands, the chief relational aspect is contained in the words "directly proportional." Also as it stands, the terms are these three: (1) For the same temperature, (2) the density of a gas, and (3) the pressure acting upon it. But (2) and (3) are alone immediately related to the ex- pression, "directly proportional"; for when the temperature varies, another relation replaces it. But in psychology, one frequently finds that the expression "other things being equal" (such as equal temperatures in physics) does not often suffer itself to be used in a formula. That is to say, that one difference between physics, as a fairly deductive science throughout, and psy- chology as a science deductive only in point of large masses of terms in relation being con- strued as units of functionation, is that we can- not confine the "proportionality" of terms to that immediate relationship in which we seek to embed them. For instance, one can predict the actions of a crowd better than those of a single individual, on account of the motives 50 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS there operative having a maximum of impera- tive urgency. The problem of three celestial bodies perplexes the astronomer, while three "busy bodies" gives the psychologist no concern. It is the business of psychological analysis to find the extent to which deduction of one kind or another pertains to the whole diameter of the conscious cross-section. 9. The use of relations demands that they be distinguished from one another. We saw in the first chapter what one meaning of the "of" relation resolved itself into. "Having" is also a complex set of relations and functions all telescoped together in language. One differ- ence between legal and logical form may be here inserted for the benefit of the light it throws upon psychology, — and that is that the law repeats the psychology entailed in a situa- tion by the use of synonyms, rather than it de- fines unequivocally any term or relation em- ployed. To insure the "having" relation, one legally gives, bequeaths, bestows, etc., rather than signifies what all this business specifically means. The number of relations is well-nigh legion, and for many of them our names are inadequate. "Before" has no linguistic differ- entiation when used as a temporal expression from what it has when used as indicating log- 51 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ical priority. Likewise, "next" is used for a spacial as well as a temporal, or other relation without any change in spelling. Such examples could be multiplied ad libitum, but suffice it to say that this condition of inexact definition in language is what makes oratory possible. There are spacial relations, temporal relations, logical relations, and still other relations, not a few of which are psychological; for which, following the example of symbolic logic, fit expressions will be eventually found. But before this is done, we can still point out a few character- istics of relations in general which must be kept in mind in order to understand the logic of any science. As follows: — (1) Transitivity. If "R" between x and y indicates that they are in relation, then the re- lation is a transitive one if .tRi/ and yRz togeth- er imply xRz. Otherwise it is intransitive. For example, in learning some complicated opera- tion, such as piano playing, every distinct move- ment or set of movements is serially focal in consciousness. Whereas later on, upon the mere mention of this or that piece of music, consciousness is solely involved in the motor aspect of a tidy performance, the stages of learning having been looped into the co- or sub- 52 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS conscious, never to reappear unless aroused through interruption. (2) Symmetry. If xRy implies i/Rr, the re- lation is said to be symmetrical. This will have bearing for us in the phenomenon of sim- ultaneous as opposed to successive presenta- tions of a stimulus. Indeed, "before" or "after" in psychology always involves something more complex than at first sight seems. The touch of velvet after the touch of emery paper may arouse one kind of feeling-consciousness, while the result of reversing the process may produce another or even the same kind. Temporal suc- cessions in psychology are very delicate and intricate things to handle. But the very same phenomena are found in other sciences. Even the business of making microscopic slides in- volves an asymmetrical temporal series of in- filtrations. The chef also uses this principle in making butter sauces. (3) Correlation. This is of two kinds, or- dinal and mixed. For instance, if there are two series of measurements, 5 and s, the terms of which are A, B, C, D, E, F N and a, b, c, d, e, f....n respectively, and if Aa, Bb, Cc, Dd, etc., are specifically coupled together in this as well as in the reverse order, we have a case of ordinal correlation. In some cases of paired 53 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION comparisons with steady and constant subjects, such a correlation has been approached for psy- chology in a limited series. Oftener, indeed, the mixed correlation is derived, which consists in the coupling of any term of one series with any term of the other in any order. In all cases of relations, the domain of the relation has to be considered. Consciousness of we shall see has but a limited use. Likewise only a few series will be transitive, symmetrical or ordinally correlated. What series they are as well as the precise meaning of these rela- tions in psychology should be at all times clear- ly kept in view. 10. Before sorting the conscious cross-sec- tion into its different compartments, I shall quote from an article by R. B. Perry entitled "A Realistic Theory of Independence," found in "The New Realism," to lay the ghost of some common notions in regard to the nature of com- plexes. This will be the last mention of sub- stances in this book. The quotation starts on page 107 of the above mentioned book with an analysis of certain further relations common to the material of psychology. "Whole-part. — A whole is said to be de- pendent on its parts, — on what it contains, and can be divided into. It is worth while to in- 54 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS troduce at this point a distinction between 'ma- terial' and 'formal' instances of the whole-part dependence. The first is exhibited in the re- lation between the present city of London and Trafalgar Square. . . . The second is ex- hibited between a city and its streets. . . . In other words, a material relation is a relation between particular values of variables, while a formal relation subsists between the variables themselves. The dependence of whole on part may be of either type. "Part-whole. — Parts are said to be depend- ent on the whole to which they belong when these wholes are 'organic' Thus the hypoth- enuse of a right-angle triangle is . . . de- pendent on the definition of the right-angle tri- angle." ". . . its magnitude is determined by its interrelation with other parts, such as the opposite angle and its adjacent sides." "Similarly, an organ or member in the biolog- ical sense is said to be dependent ... on the integrity of the organism to which it be- longs. "But such dependence would appear to be reducible to dependence of other types" . . . "we are virtually naming a part for its partici- pation in a whole." "Or it may be construed as meaning that a part cannot be a part, that is, 55 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION belonging to a whole, without the whole. But this is equivalent to saying that the complex relationship of part and whole depends on the whole as one of its terms. And this is a case of dependence of whole on part, and not of part on whole." "The dependence of members of a living organism may be disposed of in the same man- ner. The respiratory system cannot be a vital function without the whole organism. But this is merely to say that it cannot belong to an organism without an organism to belong to. To make the dependence of the part evident one must describe the part as part-of-whole. But the dependence of member-of-organism on organism is not a dependence of part on whole, but rather a dependence of whole on part. It asserts the dependence of a complex relation- ship on one of its terms. "Thing-attribute.— [This] relation presents no novelties in connection with the matter of dependence." "... where a thing is re- garded as dependent on its attributes, it is either 'made up' of them, or defined 'in terms' of them. . . . Both would be instances of the whole-part type of dependence as described above." (This has an insistent bearing upon 56 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS the analysis of sensations which we shall take up in the next chapter.) ""Attribute-thing. — The question of the de- pendence of attributes on the thing to which they belong, resembles the question of the de- pendence of part on whole. Red cannot be attribute of the rose without the rose; nor would it bear the peculiar relation that it does to odor, form, and growth of the rose, were it not for the nature of the rose as a whole. But this will, I think, turn out to mean either that a rose is a rose (redundancy) ; or that the red- rose relationship depends on 'rose' as one of its terms (whole-part) ; or that the redness of the rose is determined by its age, chemical structure, nutrition, etc. (causation). We may therefore dispense with the attribute-thing re- lation as a primary type of dependence. ''Causation. — " . . . Causality is a ma- terial relation between two complexes, derived from a primary formal relation between their constituent variables." (N. B. This is what I meant in the first chapter by saying that ev- ery science was a case of applied logic.) "Thus if v=gt, for all values of these variables, then any given velocity (f), is dependent on the con- stant of gravity {g), and some magnitude of time (0- The formal relation among the vari- 57 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ables is called the 'law,' and the material deter- mination of the values of the variables, as pre- scribed by the law, is causation. ". . . it is customary to limit the adjec- tive 'causal' to laws which contain time as a variable; and to treat time in the positive or forward direction as the independent variable." "It is to be remarked that causation is con- ditioned by the law. In other words, it takes place only within the system which the law de- scribes; [N. B. the use of "only when" in the first chapter] and can be attributed to a com- plex only when the complex is identified as 'a case of the system. . . Causes and effects are thus interdependent within the given sys- tem, or under the law. These determine their behavior under certain conditions, but do not prove that the conditions themselves are nec- essary. For it is possible that a given complex should be accounted for in terms of one system, and yet conform to the requirements of another system as well." Or not conform, equally well either. It does not need to be an illusion, or a thing to be apologized for that some things are psychological and nothing else. My uncle's house can well be mortgaged and part of my summer night's dream world at the same time. "Reciprocity. — It is customary to use the 58 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS term 'reciprocity' to express a relation of the same type as causation, but without the same emphasis on temporal antecedence and conse- quence. It is evident that the relation among the various values of the variables of a law is mutual. It is possible not only to predict the future, but also in like manner to infer the past. Similarly, it is possible to infer simul- taneities, as e. g., in the case of the configura- tion of the planetary system, or the co-presence of extension and color in the visual field. It is not even necessary that time should enter into such calculations at all; as is illustrated by the interdependence of spacial magnitudes as for- mulated by geometry. 'Reciprocity,' then, may be taken to mean the mutual determination of values of variables under the law, where the factor of time-direction is not essential." 11. Now the very reason substances have had their little day and cease to be in enlight- ened science is just because the pursuit of re- lations to their lair has shown not only that they are neither mental nor physical, but also that they are the very tissue of the organiza- tion of the cosmos. It is these which cement the elements of things together, and are not substantial in any sense in which that old pair of disreputable cronies. Matter and Mind, were 59 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION latterly regarded. The significant differences in the universe are relational, not substantial, and not "mental," either, in the sense of being generated, altered and dominated by thinking. Relations are indeed the hardest data of the cosmos, and inasmuch as they are the core of every fact, must be treated with something else than other-worldly-mindedness if one is to treat with them at all fairly. I promised in the last chapter to show why materialism is too theological a doctrine for scientific purposes. This is the pat place for doing so. The "logic of relations," into which we have entered here at some length, would serve in physics to show that there are some things which are not phys- ical or material even in that science, and that those things (relations) are quite more import- ant to the universe than the miscroscopic and Oh so hard! brick-bats which the old-line ma- terialists claim to be the ultimate stuffing of the cosmos. Every substance-theory of the uni- verse is theological. The absolute idealist and the absolute materialist differ only in the amount of personality they ascribe to the prime substance behind everything. Ego, egg, atom, ether-squirt, ether-vortex, hole-in-the-ether, — whichever of these one chooses, it is only a different name for something hidden and mys- 60 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS terious,— something supposed to add profundity to the faith by virtue of its remoteness and awe- inspiring character. As we approach nearer to the data of psychology, also, it will be seen that all of these notions must be discarded. "Spirit- stuff" is as relational as "matter," and when one analyses even "souls," one finds no hidden, mysterious thing there at all. At this the stu- dent may well throw up his hands, wondering what there is, if matter and mind are equally to be pushed aside. 12. It is now time to sort the data of the conscious cross-section. By consciousness we shall mean every object within range of the nervous system, — whether it be our neighbor planet, a finger nail, a mathematical problem, or a call from starving India; as well as every neural process going on entirely within the epi- dermis, — such as the gastric and other splanch- nic functions, spinal perceptions, or cerebral functlonations; in addition to which are the re- sponses from body to object, no matter how far distant or how abstract it is. But among this host of objects and responses only a few are within instant report, — only a few items of the possible content are taken up and dealt with furtheringly or effectively. Now, bare notice, without naming or further handling, as well 61 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION as such items barely noticed, we shall call awareness or sub-focal consciousness. Those we fix upon and deal with furtheringly, we shall call focal or attentive consciousness, as well as so denominate the processes involved. Those contents and processes which are the next less clear than awareness or sub-focal consciousness, we shall call the co-conscious; while those proc- esses only (not contents, for the contents cease with co-consciousness), which serve especially to others than ourselves to elucidate the status of these first three elements, we shall call the sub-conscious; meaning also by the term that they are evermore present as physiological processes defying any kind of elevation to fo- cality. While the term un-conscious shall be used to indicate those physiological processes which have less and less specific and directly traceable influences upon the more focal di- visions of consciousness. Language normally functions for but the first three divisions enum- erated above. Abnormally, however, it func- tions for the fourth, but never for the fifth. This, I take it, is the logical division of the conscious cross-section into its grand divisions; and it must be noted that it makes no more provision for genetic psychology than a gen- eral treatise owes to such a subject. 62 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS 13. The above analysis may be briefly termed focal distribution. What become focal are, in the main, three items, — sensation, per- ception and emotional complexes. Now sensa- tions illustrate the attribute-thing relationship, perceptions illustrate the part-whole type of organization, while the emotional complexes il- lustrate a special type of attribute-thing-func- tion. Furthermore, sensation is found in the sub-focal, focal and co-conscious divisions, per- ception is found in these also with the sub-con- scious added, while the emotional complexes are chiefly concerned with the sub-, co-, and focal consciousnesses. The causal sequence of these will be shown in the special chapters treating of them, as well as the succession of the various focalities of consciousness owing to qualitative and quantitative elements in the sensations, perceptions and emotional com- plexes to be presented. 14. From this it can well be seen that one starts with nothing "simple" in psychology. In the next chapter sensations will be analysed into more than a dozen elements. Perceptions will turn out to be sensations organized into structures which have meaning when there is motor readiness to act somehow in regard to them. Again, in the emotional complex it will 63 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION always be a situation to which we shall refer, and not to a conscious atom to explain the "mental" aspect of the items discussed. Every bit of our living and moving is immensely com- plicated. But this does not make it impossible for psychological "simples" to be found. They will not, however, be stated by the use of nouns, but of verbs, adjectives and adverbs. It is the manner of the response to the environment which defines psychology, — not the things re- sponded to. Also remember this: that the en- vironment referred to in various situations means neither "that mysterious 'external' world beyond the limits of our skin," nor does it mean the same in each mentioned case. Often the environment is within the body. When we say we have a toothache, it certainly means that the vocal organs are functioning the response of the general somatic condition to a special environment centered in the tooth. Individual environments also frequently occur. From a large group of things we select only specially interesting features as material for speech and memory. For example, the brute mass of a football field and the players is first grossly cross-cut by the two sympathetic teams of "rooters" opposed to each other in the grand- stand; and again curiously cross-cut by any in- 64 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS dividual witness whose special interests center in one or more of the padded giants in the turf. An account of the football game, if complete, would then be the sum-total of all spoken or unspoken judgments, emotional or otherwise, that those preparing for it, witnessing it, and remembering it would make. However com- plex the physical situation there might be, the psychological aspect would outdo it ten to one. To ask which of the football games as reported is the real one, has no meaning for psychology. It is the task of our analysis to determine the order in which things get known, as well as the succession of impulses which determine the selection for speech and recall of several items out of a possible multitude. 15. It is clear that in the realm of psychol- ogy more newness continually develops than in any other field. As we develop from childhood to age we get a personality, a bias, a way of em- ploying the material of the cosmos in such a manner that there arise from our own nervous organization certain dependent sets of functions which point our doings in ways that are "new" with regard to the material they respond to. Within our own bodies, also, there are colonies of nerve fibres which act upon and are reacted to by other colonies, in such a way that rcfer- 65 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ence cannot be made solely to the common, un- critical names for one's environment to explain why our actions are thus and so. This also must be kept clear: that if the responses to their objects by one nerve colony is of one kind, and the responses by another nerve colony is of another, that the responses of the first colony, say, — to its objects, — may be so modified by the intercolonial responses that the result will be "new" and unpredictable from the mere knowledge of the way in which either colony alone would have reacted to the situation. It is the task of analysis, again, to label correctly all the "new" responses, — those primes in the series of psychological events. 16. Much perplexity often arises over the question of the position of things in mind. "Where is a tooth ache, especially its disagree- ability?" "Where is the pleasure of a good meal?" are typical of the questions sometimes asked. This question ultimately concerns the nature of series, and I submit this as an answer. Some series are in time and space, while some otiiers are not. Those in time have position in time and those in space have position in space, while those in both have two positions. But when one asks where the discomfort of a toothache is located, or where hope, fear and 66 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS joy may be found during their office hours, the answer is that there is at least one more order than the temporal or spacial order in psychol- ogy, and that is the order of knowledge. ("For space and time are continuous, while knowledge is not") Only this order is not independent, as are the orders of time and space, but dependent partly on them and partly also upon the logical, deductive orders of things, which are neither temporal nor spacial. For example, the vir- tuous kings of England, if named in the order of their virtue, would not perhaps come in the same succession as they did chronologically to the seat of the Confessor. The order of their virtue could not be deduced from this other order any more than the order of their sen- iority upon ascending the throne. The orders, or cross-sections, of these British monarchs would show no ordinal correlation. And when any other order than the spacial or temporal order is involved, "position" cannot mean something geographical, any more than the phrase "in my mind" needs to refer to the head or the bone-bound mass of wrinkled gray mat- ter within it. Now, the toothache is not in the front sidewalk, to be sure, nor is the pleasure of gourmandizing in the handle of the knife that carves the truffied grouse. In both of these 67 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION cases we have series to consider, and if the toothache or the dinner-delight is anywhere, it is in that manifold which is defined either by the terms of tooth, nerves and rest of body; or grouse, unobtrusive waiter and the other fine business of eating. Its position in these com- plexes somewhat compares to the meaning of "never" in contrast to "now." 17. There is but one more thing to which I wish to call attention before we pass on to the next chapter. It is the use and meaning of "and" in psychology. We shall find that a sen- sation as well as a perception, a sentiment, a will-act, a soul, is a complex, — a number of things more or less organized together. They bear to one another in psychology among oth- er things, the "and" relation. Now this "and" is one of the psychological simples mentioned before, — one of the things which is psycholog- ical and nothing else. It is the first one men- tioned, and it is to be expressly noted and filed away for reference that it is not a "noun," but a "conjunction." We shall get the verbs and adverbs by and by. Here we may see one of the points at which logic, psychology and gram- mar coincide, — namely the letters making the word "and." But spelling here serves a func- tion that analysis must undo. The grammat- 68 PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS ical "and" is of course a special form of the logico-psychological "and," being exclusively neither nor all of both; it is something ele- mentally linguistic." The grammatical "and" is sometimes expressed by a comma. This again means a pause in the voice, or, logically, an enumeration without inference. Grammar- ians call this repetition, — as for example, "Hun- dreds and thousands of dead and wounded." Variation or dijRference with insinuations is an- other meaning; as "there are lawyers and law- yers." Or, the attributive relation may be poetically expressed, "thy fair and outward character," i. e., outwardly fair character." Se- quence is inferred, or causation, — "I say 'go,' and he goeth." It sometimes means "or," as in the expression, "taxable for state and county purposes." In the expression, "I shall try and learn," it means "in order to." In symbolic logic the same sign is used for both "or" and "and"; the interpretation and reading of the sign being dependent upon its place in the sub- ject or predicate. Now the use of "and" in psychology may, possibly, be any one of the above uses at times, but the peculiarly original psychological use of the conjunction "and" is as follows: Consciousness is both a content and a process, and the contents, which are all THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION analysable into non-mental material as well as are the processes, exist together and arouse im- pulses in a way that is not found elsewhere. The combination, the organization of these con- tents and processes we shall call, for brevity, an exhibition of the "with-for" relation. And let us add that it is not mysterious. If a realis- tic psychology needs any justification, it will be found in the development of this principle throughout this book. Bibliography. Perry, R. B., "A Realistic Theory of Inde- pendence," in "The New Realism," by E. B. Holt and others. Spaulding, E. G., "A Defense of Analysis," in "The New Realism." Holt, E. B., "The Concept of Consciousness," especially Chapter X, "The Empirical Proper- ties of Consciousness." 70 CHAPTER III. THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS 1. ". . . there are not sensations and perceptions and their objects. There are ob- jects, and when these are included in the mani- fold called consciousness they are called sen- sations and perceptions." . . . "In sensation the neutral qualities, the so-called 'secondary qualities,' come and go as more or less unre- lated elements: while in perception they enter and depart in groups — smaller or larger. Doubt- less few, if any, qualities (sensations) enter consciousness absolutely single: they too seem to come and go in larger or smaller masses. But . . . the term sensation is usually ap- plied to them so long as the mass of qualities that enter together has within itself little or no logical structure or unity, no internal relation- ship : while in perception the groups have some logical coherence." This again from Holt with many thanks. 2. Why do we habitually say, "I have a sen- sation OF color"? Or why, again, do we as- sert our recollections OF people, our feelings OF sadness, our consciousness OF this or that? Is it because we feel a gulf deeply fixed be- 71 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tween ourselves and this world of ours which so constantly stays with us? Or is it a defect of language, and has a little wall-eyed preposi- tion the power of dropping a veil over our eyes, thus making us like unto the Turkish ladies who are calamitously and at all times cut off from the bright realities? 3. Two possible explanations are open and we shall consider them both, (a) The Lin- guistic approach. Usually such expressions can be avoided by the use of other words. "I have a sensation of blue," means something diif erent, does it or not, from the expression, "I sense the blue object"? "I recall him," means what dif- ferent from, "I have a recollection of him"? "1 feel sad," is or is not the same as to say, "I have a feeling of sadness"? Or when the psy- chologist says, "It is in my consciousness," does he not mean that he is conscious of it? These all seem to be the same thing in a different form, allopathic or homeopathic, just as you wish. But if language can be twisted in such a manner, then not in language itself can be found the solution. The OF-ness has as much right to be primary as does the more direct ex- pression. The problem is still unsolved, — it remains a dilemma. Let us see whether this antique dilemma hath not a third, rudimentary 72 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS horn, the grasping of which will lead us per- manently out of the pinch. 4. (b) That the thing may be a relayed form of consciousness does not solve the dif- ficulty. All consciousness might turn out to be rp-presentative, rather than immediate, the re- layings differing only in complexity. We shall then appeal to logic as our old standby. The names of things are not the things, which every one will gladly admit, for the traveler lost in the desert cannot slake his thirst by the repeti- tion of the word "water." If it had been so, the problem of the relief of the poor could never have been a university subject for which the student gets full credit. But to use the word "water" is not necessarily indicative that it is in the mouth of the user at the time. "Water" is the conventional English symbol for a liquid which, in some countries, is used to slake the thirst, — a word to which sensorial wetness per- taineth not. And the "meaning" of the word "water" is dependent in such a case upon what others will do when it is uttered. "Meaning," in psychology, at least, lies in what will be done in a situation involving the name of the thing meant. Meaning is therefore motor; it refers to functional sequences, and is an example of the "with-for" relation. Now, if words are re- 73 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION lational, just as consciousness is relational, in that it is generated out of responses to an en- vironment by a nervous system, then the old bugaboo of re-presentation need no longer be of any trouble to us. Every idea consists of positionless parts or properties of a thing. The use of the preposition in such expressions as "feeling o/," "consciousness of," etc., simply in- dicates, — barring the linguistic fallacy, — that the thing so mentioned is one of the elements making up the conscious manifold, and nothing else. Otherwise, the expressions "unclear," "a minor element," or "sub-focal" provide for all cases in which it is ever properly used. The logic of relations thus accounts for certain ele- ments in genetic psychology, — only the psy- chological aspect in language frequently swal- lows up the logical one. For when the logical orders get distorted by the introspective con- sciousness, and are reinterpreted by way of it, they suffer the lapse of their scientific validity. The introspective order is not the logical one, and the introspective consciousness is not in any sense the primary, immediate fact of conscious- ness. It is belated consciousness, and when too often referred to is indicative of an incipient division in personality. 5. The reason, then, for attaching validity 74 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS to the expression, "consciousness o/," is one of "informal" logic. But this does not apply to those relational states in which, as Professor Perry says, we "surround and surmount our past, incomplete experience." To say "I judge that I was wrong," is certainly a case of "con- sciousness of"; but the point to be made is that the "o/"-ness" in such an expression ipso facto defines its own non-immediacy or non-focality in consciousness. Furthermore, the point is to be made that one cannot have this o/"-relation occurring twice in succession. There is no "of- consciousness-o/"" anything, if by the expression we mean to link co-ordinate states of conscious- ness together. / may recall "that" my uncle mortgaged his house "when" 7 was a mere child, but the Vs and the my are very different things each time, bearing in psychology a subordinate relation to each other, and a non-reciprocal re- lation as well. Bluntly spoken, naively taken, these expressions have nothing dangerous in them, but the naive is not the systematic except by a coup de Dieu. The logic of introspection is informal logic: as Matthew Arnold would say, it "is eloquent, is well, — but is not true!" 6. We have been using the term conscious- ness as something already built up and guar- anteed by responses, but not as something not 75 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION yet functioned for or organized out of nature. Introspection is not the primary, immediate fact of consciousness because it is found only in a consciousness set a-brewing, and in this brew we find ourselves long before we first make wise inquiry after the nature of our being. For the "introspectional feltness" of a thing is no more sufficient to explain the origin or per- sistence of a thing, than the condition of being a debtor, will ipso facto satisfy one's creditors. Now, having cleared the logical grounds of all expected difficulties, we are ready to begin a systematic analysis of consciousness. We shall first treat of sensations and perceptions, and then of responses and meanings, including speech. Next we shall see what emotions and feelings are, following this with an explanation of interest, purpose and the creative faculties. Finally, there will be a brief but wide study of the ramifications of psychology throughout our practical, daily life. For psychological things are what we have to live with, if we live at all; indeed, other than by a perspicuous use of psy- chology, there is no escape from certain an- noyances but by death, and this latter business is often a great inconvenience to our relatives. For them psychology remains the proh'em, sur- viving even if we do not. 76 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS 7. This is the program: First to analyse objects from the standpoint of their being sensed, and then to analyse the physiological sensing process. By this means we shall answer all three of the questions regarding conscious- ness, — what, how, and why. From the first standpoint it will be seen that there are two kinds of properties or attributes which give the sensation its thinghood: essential and inessen- tial. These will be dealt with in the above order. Every one of the essential properties at least will be furthermore seen to be a series, and the sensation to be a cross-section of those terms of each such series which, while the sensing process is going on, are contingent in time and space. But corresponding terms in each series need not be present at the same time. For ex- ample, shapes, colors and distances are all series, but the moon which is at a certain point on the linear space series distant from the ob- server may be at no comparable point in the shape or color series, nor yet in the bigness series. Even some of these series are prime to each other. Furthermore, while the terms of these series making the sensation are contin- gent, they need have none but the loosest func- tional interdependence, not yet having the structure requisite for the formation of per- 77 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ceptions. It is thence that some of the in- formal logic of certain kinds of consciousness is derived. It is not here, however, that one finds any original "consciousness stuff"; for these various series are not generated by the consciousness relation, even if one should bol- ster up his argument by saying that continued fixation of a color appears to reduce its bright- ness. 8. Thus sensations have no substance, — they are not the ultimate brickbats of existence. But, added to this, two warnings. This does not mean that we, as human beings, are possessed of a special stability or specific gravity which, by comparison, makes the rest of the world in- constant, filmy and tottering; nor that when I rap on the table before me and say: "This is one of my realities," that I deny that the table is hard. Absolutely the contrary, beyond cavil and argument ! A series can well be a series of hardnesses as well as one of preferences or di- vorces, and with this statement the philos- ophical program of this book must close. 9. Consciousness was defined for us as both a content and a process; some of its elements are likewise of this twofold character, and sen- sations are such elements. For instance, if someone holds up a patch of red in front of me 78 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS and I see it, the red color is my content of con- sciousness, while the action of the retinal nerves guarantees the continuance of the sensing proc- ess. The retinal nerves do not become red, nor is it a reddish neural process w^hich is going on, — it is a red-sensing process. However ,on the content side, we have a red sensation, for while there is a functional relation between the neural action and the patch of color, there is an iden- tical one between the object and the content of consciousness. In our discussion of visual sen- sations further on, it will be seen why, in the case of the color-blind person, the content is always, regardless of optical defects, to be as- serted of the object. For psychology, an object is something that can stimulate, just as a rubber ball is something that will bounce, but the com- mon name of the object is by no means a suf- ficient catalogue of its functional possibilities. If one were to enumerate all the things a certain object would do, he would then, but not before then, have a respectable estimate of what a sensation is. To completely exhaust it would require that it be, first exhibited; second, enumerated as to its properties; and lastly, de- fined as to its reaction possibilities in all situa- tions where its effects made a difference to the outcome. 79 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION 10. But no dismay need accompany the reading of this last statement. The cases where it does make a difference are limited and known; at least if not fully known, known as to inveterate trend. The series has been plotted to its bounds, and whatever we lack is a term or two within the known range, if, indeed, we lack anything. Eighteen such terms, or attrib- utes of sensation exist; seven of these are es- sential, while the remaining eleven are inessen- tial. The whole eighteen never exist at the same time, it being a temporal impossibility, but whatever of them do exist at any instant or pulse of time, define the sensation for us, and at the same time exhaust it. Some of them are temporal, others spacial attributes; some are neither spacial nor temporal, but quantita- tive or qualitative instead: while all of them refer either to the content or the functional side of consciousness. Membership in one of these classes does not exclude the possibility of mem- bership in another, but no single attribute is found in all six classes. 11. The Essential Attributes of Sensation. (1) Modality. This is a functional attribute, referring to the sense field operating. There are no nameless sensations; every object is functioned for by some specialized group of 80 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS cells, — the organ and the intra-neural connec- tions; sight is one modality, sound is another, pain is another, and so on. There is, further- more, no transition possible from one sense field to another; a prime relation exists between them. And while modality is functional, it is not quantitative, but qualitative. Ether waves, which produce lights, may be just another kind or degree of vibrations from those producing sounds, but they are even thus multifarious enough in their quantitative or formal relations to be called qualitatively different. Modality is not spacial or temporal either, — it is qualita- tively functional, and that alone. (2) Quality. This attribute refers to such things as colors, tastes, smells, tones, and the like, for every sensation is not only taken up by some sense organ, but within each modal range are various qualities; in some cases, such as tastes, very few, while in the case of colors, exceedingly many. Qualities are intra-modal, and as such, exhibit transition in some cases, but not in others. Thus a saline solution may, if the quantity of the solvent be increased, be- come a burning sensation, but never sugary or sour. Likewise, with the decrease in the pro- portion of the solvent, no other taste will be induced when the salty one ceases to be ef- 81 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION fectual. Nevertheless, pure distilled water tastes slightly sweet. Quality is of course a non-spacial and non-temporal affair; it is a physical and meta-physical question as to whether it is ultimately quantitative. Ulti- mately for psychology, however, it is not. (3) Intensity. This word refers both to content and function in sensation. Every sen- sation has its own specific intensity, — it is some- where in the qualitatively intensive series. This series is non-temporal and non-spacial. Inten- sities cannot be added together arithmetically to produce a sum, just as no number of undersea- soned dishes at a dinner will give the requisite flavor to it, no more than will the addition of pinks give a crimson. Intensity is always unique. We may not be able to tell how bright a color is, nor how intense the toothache, but the naive speech reaction is pragmatic and not specific, nor are all conscious contents open to steady inspection. As a functional affair, the intensity of sensation refers to the vigor of the transmission of the nervous impulse, — we are stunned by the detonation of the ordnance, or shocked by the electric current. Or, again, at the rose-carnival our own entries were not so red as those of another, though we once thought them superlatively so. Here, intensity is quan- 82 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS titative; in many cases measurable by galvano- metric methods. But it is not spacial, and not in point of rise and fall, temporal. (4) Latent-period. This term is functional, and means the time elapsing between the ap- plication of the stimulus and the reaction upon it by the sensing organism. It is, therefore, solely a temporal phenomenon. There are also two kinds of latency, — focally conscious and sub-conscious, as follows: Rain falling on a sleeping soldier's upturned face on the battle- field might cause him to cover it without awak- ening, — without his being brought to the notic- ing or naming consciousness. This would be, of course, reflex action occurring after a sub-con- scious latent period. If the soldier awoke, knowing and naming the rain, to defend him- self from the elements, he would be said to be focally conscious of the affair after a latency ending in focal consciousness of the situation. In both of these cases, the latency would be de- fined in temporal terms, — i. e., as a time be- tween the mechanical or chemical onset, and the movements of defense or speech, or both. Latency has much to do with intensity of the functional kind: it is, caeteris paribus, in de- fined situations, inversely proportional to it. 83 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION But the intensities must be incremental to sliow this. (5) Another derivative of intensity is the Threshold. Threshold is the functional ter- minus ad quern of the latent period. If, in the above case, the sleeper had moved to cover his face from the rain, some threshold of arousal would have been reached, the stimulation would have proved effective, and the with-for relation become operative. While being at the end of a temporal series, it is not itself a temporal mat- ter, but rather a prime in that series. Thres- holds are, indeed, measurable, but not usually by means of definite terms in the number series. Sometimes they are defined, as by Titchener, as those points on the intensive scale (mechanical measurements) where the sensation is aroused (noticeably, self-consciously) 50% of the time. This, however, is the better way to define them, — as having membership in a class of positions in the intensive series between those points where the sensation is noticeably aroused and those where it is not noticeably aroused; a de- cent illustration of which would be the area between two intersecting parabolas in the same plane. It is not a point, but an area, not such a quantity as 8, but rather 8 as any place be- tween 7 and 9: the threshold is thus shown to 84 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS be a quantitative tendency. Of thresholds there are two kinds, the upper and the lower. They are at opposite ends of the intensive series, and usually exist for both focal- and sub-conscious- ness in every modality. But the operation of the with-for relation certainly largely depends upon the focally-conscious aspect of the thres- hold, or limen, as it is often called. (6) Duration is the chief temporal attrib- ute of sensation. It can be applied to the period of time between the onset of the stim- ulus and its withdrawal, to the temporal extent of sub-consciousness, or to the focal-conscious- ness of the sensation. It is also functionally important for the intensity, considered as a functional attribute. We likewise speak cor- rectly of the duration of the latent period. Peculiarly psychological is the report of the duration of a state of consciousness, in contrast, but not contradiction, to the amount of time in- volved in the physical presence of the excitant. (7) The chief spacial attribute is Extensity. As an elemental attribute of sensation this cor- responds very much to qualitative intensity. A pin prick is "smaller" in extensity than is the touch of a blunt pencil point; a toothache is also usually "smaller" than a sensation of nau- sea. It is not alone the functioning organ 85 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION which makes this difference, — not alone the knowledge of the size of stimulus or organ, but an original and irreducible attribute of the sen- sation itself. Now, the extensive magnitudes are not absolute, but relative; they are a series, a scale, and we always make the estimation by employing terms of comparison. We can- not tell how big a sensation is, nor how much bigger it is than another one, but the psychol- ogical number system is of this kind, and one must be forewarned of it. It may well be, also, that the space of psychology is not Euclidian space, but a space very like that of a fourth or even an nth dimension. That it exists cozily along with Euclidian space, however, is scarce- ly to be denied. 12. To resume and further elaborate these seven essential attributes of sensation. One of them is spacial, extensity; two, temporal, — latency and duration; the rest are neither spa- cial nor temporal,— modality, quality, intensity, and threshold. As regards content, we have quality, intensity and extensity; as regards function, we have modality, intensity, latency, threshold, and duration. Intensity was also shown to be related to both content and func- tion, while the functional character of other things, such as duration and latent-period, may 86 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS frequently tend to induce qualitative diii'erences in the content. As attributes of sensation, these seven terms illustrate the attribute-thing rela- tion, mentioned and discussed in the preceding chapter. Duration, linked with intensity, func- tionally construed, as well as latency, refers to the causal relation, including as both do the temporal aspect. Now, while objects are ma- terial, none of these attributes are material, and yet an object sensed is often a material object. But just as physical and chemical analysis finds no brickbat-matter in the universe, neither does psychology: which, however, does not preclude that matter may not be the coagulation of non- material things. I fling the material stone at the material cat, but on the levels of physical and psychological analysis, qualities only tend to displace each other in the above act. The practical cat dies, let us admit; but the cat of analysis is merely redistributed : the stone is his passport to non-Euclidian space. 13. We now pass to a consideration of the inessential attributes of sensation. The rubric, inessential, does not mean that when they are present, they do not contribute emphatically to the then status of the sensation. They do, and as attributes they are constitutive in no small degree of the with-for relationship of the item 87 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION of consciousness called sensation. A harmless analogy is the following: A household may consist of from two to n members, only two of which are essential; but the children, relatives, visitors and spungers all contribute to it, even if by hunger and fracas alone. In the follow- ing sections we shall take up the nature of these attributes from the standpoint of content, func- tion, temporal and spacial significance, as well as relate them to the essential attributes just considered. (1) Summation is the term used to indi- cate a number of applications of a stimulus be- fore an arousal occurs. It is a temporal ele- ment, and functional. The heartless fly bites the sleeper's nose a dozen times before he awakens. Each stimulus, as a mechanical or chemical unit, is in itself insufficient to provoke the arousal, but as the result of repetitions near enough together so that the organ does not re- cover between times, summation is produced, the threshold is passed and the with-for rela- tion firmly established in the defense. Bare intensity refers to one application of the stim- ulus; summation, on the other hand, means many (usually identical) applications. Sum- mation plays a large part in quotidian affairs; "till seven times" is an expression based 88 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS upon it, as well as the fact that a basehall team loses heart after the fifth or sixth scccessive de- feat of the season, though their playing all along may have been equally poor. The sleep- meter that jangles us back into life in the morn- ing, the final yielding of the maiden sister to the fatality of spinsterhood, — ^these are both summation. To some persons there seems to be a qualitative aspect to summation differing from that of an equable, supra-liminal sensa- tion. It is more extensive, they say, and of a texture more subtle and more elusive; if so, it would be another case of psychological new- ness. As such, this "element" is adjectival. (2) The after-image is that part of the object which survives the temporal extent of its application to the sense organ. The phy- sicist witnesses summation in the number of shots a piece of ordnance will stand; he would likewise find positive after-images in echoes, at least in so far as acoustical effects are con- cerned. The "kick" of a gun might also be a sort of negative after-effect. Both of these are illustrated in psychological material, for there are two kinds of sensorial after-images, positive and negative. If we look fixedly at the yellow sun, upon turning away, greenish-blue blobs pepper the landscape. But if we gaze less long 89 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION at an illumination of a milder intensity, the original colors are usually more faithfully pre- served in the neural momentum. The after- image is qualitative and quantitative, depend- ing upon many things, namely: intensity, qual- ity, duration, extensity of the stimulus, and in pathological cases upon emotionality, intricacy of the situation, and even upon habitual lying or truth-telling. The after-image is not an il- lusion, but consists, in vision, at least, of but the shape and color of the object sensed, which, by the way, have no position, and may be any- where. (3) No sense organ functions without chemical changes within it, and when they be- come such as to impede the transmission of the impulses throughout the system. Exhaustion takes place. This is not the same as fatigue, which will be discussed under emotion. Ex- haustion is a function of intensity, duration, extensity and certain plain qualities, specially smells. Curiously enough, also, the sense-or- gans are attuned to the reception of just so much stimulation, teleologically or not, just as either disputant avers. Leaving before the sym- phony is finished, drowsing through the mis- sionary sermon, sleep, death, quitting college before the degree is conferred, — such cases 90 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS usually exist by virtue of a complex in which it is more or less nuclear. We shall discuss its physiological side in a few moments. (4) Adaptation appears to be a kind of partial exhaustion, and as such is a derivative of intensity; it is temporal, and in its different aspects, qualitative. In exhaustion the fuse is burned out; in adaptation there is a shunting of the current to a transmission circuit of exceed- ingly low potential. I call adaptation those cases of partial exhaustion where the sensation can be restored through attending to it or ex- pecting it; exhaustion exhibits no such resurg- ences. The wearing of clothes, glasses, and the like, marriage, accepting life or death in the trenches, failing to notice how bad mannered we are, are cases of adaptation. Perhaps the "ship that found herself" illustrates it, as well as the fact that machinery runs better after a few hundred pulses than it did at first. But here the analogies run rather to seed and so we shall migrate to the next topic. (5) Inhibition is a case where, for example, but one of two or more possible objects of a group gets functioned. It may follow exhaus- tion or adaptation, and appears to be a deriva- tive of intensity. While intent upon our tele- phone conversation we do not notice that the 91 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION fire-engine has clanged noisily down the street, though the sound it makes is physically in- tenser than the voice over the wire. Again, dis- agreeable table companions keep us from en- joying an otherwise satisfactory meal; or the fear of an impending final examination abol- ishes the memory of things we were positive we had at instant recall. Inhibition is a temporal and quantitative affair, and in psychology plays a considerable role. Indeed, one author, Muensterberg, regards it as the central fact of psychology. (6) When two or more sensations blend so that each to a certain extent loses its independ- ent character, the resultant is called a Fusion. This is a case of both psychological and logical newness. Fusion is both a process and a con- tent. On the side of extensity it is sometimes easily comparable and again curiously incom- parable to the elements from which it was de- rived. The discussion of the various sense fields will illustrate this. Fusion is partial, mu- tual inhibition; wherever it occurs, it is very likely to become adapted, and often seems to be a sop thrown to exhaustion. It will be seen later on to be one of the integral parts of per- ception. Language itself is a case of fusion. We do not think of the separate letters of words, 92 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS but of the words as a whole; again, orange is obtainable by mixing red and yellow pigments, but it goes by a simple name and usually passes by unanalysed; the doctrine of the trinity was a theological fusion. Fusion and confusion are interesting to compare, — they seem to have many common parts. The latter term, how- ever, refers to the meaning-side of the situa- tion, — the degree of confusion implying the amount of labor it would take to make order grow where chaos did before. (7) When, again, sensations appear to- gether and neither inhibit each other nor fuse, we have a case of Contrast. This is a qualita- tive and sometimes a spacial attribute; it is like- wise often a derivative of intensity. The chef applies chemical fusion to the making of the salad, while the hors d'oeuvre which preceded was concocted for the sake of contrast to it. The uses to which contrast effects are put are apparently unlimited, and yet quite closely re- lated to certain definite principles of order. It would be more "stunning" to wear two gloves each of a different color, but we prefer in such a case bilateral chromatic symmetry; in fash- ions again, suits all of a piece are not disdained in favor of polychromatic clothing whether or no. Besides this, we may be passionately fond of 93 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION change in many directions, and yet always eat the same breakfast, or walk to business down the same street. But where contrast effects are produced, each of the components more or less emphasizes the elfect of the other. It is thus a case of the opposite of fusion in its two prin- cipal aspects. It is curious to note in what special ways it differs from inhibition. (8) Clearness is predicated of the content side of a sensation when, in the midst of other sensations, it defines them in terms of itself. Thus it takes a relational aspect to provide the existence of this attribute. As we never get but one sensation in consciousness, there is al- ways more or less clearness in the cross-section. Clearness and inhibition are closely related in this way, — the inhibiting sensation may be clear, the clear sensation always inhibits. To accomplish this, the clearness takes on the tem- poral aspect of duration, and through duration the inhibition gets functioned. In point of de- fining the context in terms of itself, this at- tribute has important bearings on perception. If it leads to inhibition, it relates itself to in- tensity; while, as it frequently appears to come from emotional backgrounds, it often loses its purely original qualitative and content aspect on this account. 94 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS (9) Vividness is a compound of clearness and inhibition simultaneously occurring. Clear- ness defines the background in terms of itself, — in vividness we have a lost background, and an increase of intensity due not to the inhibit- ory crowding-out of the other contents, but of the sudden wilting of the conflicting functions. Crudely, it could be compared with a land- slide to a certain political candidate by virtue (or vice?) of the withdrawal of his opponents, rather than to his own efforts in spite of them. This latter would rather be a case of inhibi- tion. Physicists are acquainted with a half- brother to this attribute in some of the phenom- ena of refraction. In psychology, I am con- vinced, the index of refraction in the case of vividness is frequently emotional. (10) The attributes of sensation may have no position alone, but the cross-section of their series takes position with reference to the ob- ject and the sensing organ: we call this the Local-sign (or Local-signature). I am touched with a pencil point upon variously functioning organs, and the name of the sense field comes with the touch (or other) sensations. We al- ways report things as being somewhere, — not only in the case of sensations which arouse a unique quality upon various skin areas, — but so 95 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION inveterately do we apply perspective to the contents of consciousness, that all things seem to have a place. And, in one sense, they do; dreams are in dreamland just as fairies are in fairyland. But, on the other hand, just as the non-spatial attributes of sensation are position- less, so are many of their combinations into things or wholes; especially is this true of the part-whole masses, of which dreams and fairies as well as logarithmic functions are examples. (11) Some sensations are pleasant or un- pleasant, and these terms signify Feeling-tone. This is an originally qualitative aspect, and nothing more ; but there are grades of it, loosely called, for want of a better name, intensities. The nature of feeling is not as obscure as the dissertations upon it, — it is a function of cer- tain equilibria, — neural, muscular, sensorial, and the like, — several variables, whose ex- pected quotient is found to shrink in a sur- prising manner. For without the proper regard for the psychological plus, only nonsense arises from the addition of certain elements in the conscious cross-section. Psychology furnishes the basis for the empirical status of the irra- tional numbers in the above case, just as in fusions we find that to add is to subtract. In these, as in other cases to be met with, nascitiir 96 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ridiciiliis mus is the authorized shipman's card. We are sometimes found furthering or hinder- ing those sensation masses including pleasant or unpleasant feeling-tones respectively, but not always, for usually displeasure is more heavily socially subsidized than is pleasure, as is the case with error and untruth. These two feeling-tones are not incompatible psychological opposites, and when found together, they need neither fuse with nor inhibit each other, which is a curiosity. We have discussed the "posi- tion" of pleasure in a previous paragraph, and those authors who interpret feeling as indicative of the fact that the sensation to which it per- tains is referred to the body rather than to the "external" world, are in error. What a dis- mal time others than ourselves must be hav- ing, according to this bit of wisdom ! 14. The table on the following page will illustrate the relations of both the essential and inessential attributes to one another. 97 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION Is 1 CQ 1 o 1 1 c • .2 I 2 ' 3 : Q ■ S < 1 1 & Intensity Latent-Period Threshold Duration Extensity > ■-13 .-^ Modality Quality Intensity 1 o C 3 Modality Intensity Latent-period Threshold Duration § > 3 o > C CO >* lO «; ! a :| : bn -P .|i • 3 OS M ; i i- . >-< ■-£ . M 3 cS . ;«f- 3 • <; feO h:i . ^ rt 3 o o ■3 o)-^-^ ^ w u 3 ? M 3^ H-< i^-a 0-2 g ^ W< W &H 1 H 0) 3 o 0) ••43 3 4^ ^ S.l^ M W ^ a-2s bo :1s 3 -P usion ontras learne ividne ocal-S eeling 3**- 1— 1 -^ oQhJfe i_^ 1 o cS s CS P,^ s 3 -3 cS-3 M 3 • ^^^.^ : , 1 3Sg?J^ : 1 usio ontr lean ividi ocal «H <: &hOO>J . 1 - (M az Tjt 10 ?o t- 06 Oi c ;:j| 98 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS 15. These eighteen attributes are the stuff of which sensation is made. They are attrib- utes, rather than parts, and illustrate the attrib- ute-thing relationship mentioned and defined in the previous chapter. As such, they make up sensation, for sensation, apart from their con- stituting, contributing relationship, does not oc- cur. Thus it is incorrect to say that "a sensa- tion varies," for these attributes are all series, and as such alter in their changing the nature of the sensation they constitute instead of being altered by it. Sensational consciousness varies with its object, but, by virtue of our function- ing a larger environment than that of the bare object of sense, reports upon its variation are obtained. From this it is likewise perceived that what the physicist means by "object" and what the psychologist means by it are apparently dif- ferent things. In psychology, however, we use the word stimulus to indicate the physicist's "object." Sensation is more than stimulus. Sensation is the object, and what it will do; or, in other words, the psychologist's "object" is the content and functions of a consciousness when within receptive range of the physicist's "object" or stimulus. For neither can all of these attributes occur at the same instant of time, nor does the identity of the sensation with 99 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the object exhaust it. Surely the stimulus, as a physical datum, will affect other physical data in a way that differs from its directly af- fecting a nervous system; or it may have chem- ical properties, or a geological system to sup- port. But in either case, the sensation is iden- tical with whatever of the object is material for psychology. Series and properties only delimit the fields of the various sciences. Questions on the foregoing: 1. Enumerate three common cases of adaptation and three of exhaustion not men- tioned in the text. To what sort of stimuli are they referred? Tell in each case why you think the one attribute appears instead of the other. 2. "Quality" is under the heading "qualita- tive" in the above table. Can you suggest a better term than the latter in order that the same word need not be used in two senses? 16. I propose now to indicate what the nervous system has to do with sensation. Let me first lay down the principle that neural ac- tion is concerned more with the functions of consciousness than with its content. To be sure, we should never see yellow without a physiolog- ical eye, nor taste lemon without a tongue, but physiological psychology is the science of the functional maintenance of the content of 100 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS consciousness rather than something concerned with the question of why we see yellow instead of red or taste lemon rather than lemonade. For the qualities of the content are implicit in any neural action at all, while the functional and quantitative series do not follow such an un- eventful history. This may sound far from obvious, to say the least of it, and yet the whole history of psychology is befuddled with bulle- tins from Paddock, aggravating in their gloomy references to that moist bundle of strands with- in our bodies known as the nervous system, in which sensation, perception, emotion and rea- son were said to keep a heirarchy of thrones whose exact location was a perpetual discom- fiture to the invading investigator. To be spe- cific, there are, for example, but four simple taste qualities, while there are nine functional attributes of each of them. Now responses to the chemical stimuli known as tastes are re- stricted to these four qualities, but not in any way so attached to the functionally quantitative series of sensational attributes. Response, be- ing a process, is therefore superlatively con- cerned with functional attributes: and to this we shall direct our attention. 17. A schematic representation of the nerv- ous system would incline toward the shape of a 101 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION funnel, the large end of which is located in the skull. Thence, thinning down, to the base of the spine, it ends as a notable, separate struc- ture. It is, therefore, almost entirely posterior to the countenance. Just as visually we walk about headless, so we are never aware of the nerves as such. But from this central, funnel- like nervous system, there are prolonged in- numerable and immensely complicated bundles of fibres, ramifying to all parts of the body, and varying from a fraction of an inch to five or six feet in length. Functionally, the mass of the nervous system does not assist us in un- derstanding it. It is best regarded as a sys- tematic set of strands, called cells. Let us be emphatic here, however, and take notice that the word "cell" does not mean a little, roundish affair. The cells of the nervous system are long, tiny strands, contrasting in shape with bone and other cells in the same way that a tall flag-pole contrasts with a chopping block. The functional construction goes farther. The physiological unit of response is not a single cell, but a set of at least three such long fibres, articulating in such a way that a stimulation, say, from the surface of the body will be car- ried as an impulse along all three of them in linear succession, and arouse at the end the 102 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS release of energy required to make the stimulus effective. Such a linear series of nerve cells or fibres is called a reflex arc, and consists of three parts (the three cells) as follows: recept- or, conductor and effector. The receptor starts with or in the sense organ, and extends to some part of the central nervous system, — brain or spinal cord, — where it ends as a fibre. But functionally it continues in the conductor, which interlaces it with the effector, whose further end is attached to a muscle by means of a little pad or end-plate. The action of this response mechanism is usually more useful to study than are pictorial representations of it, since they are all idealized. The best way to understand the scheme is to procure some nice animal, kill it, and trace out some special set of nerve fibres; for by this means alone the curious, angular character of the nerve-path can be appreci- ated. 18. The cell is primarily a white fibre. Somewhere along the fibre will be found a cell- body, colored gray; the term "gray matter" in- dicates that the cell-bodies are on the surface of the brains while below the surface in the spinal cord. There are about eleven thousand million of these nerve cells in the human body, each of which derives its nourishment from its 103 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION own gray cell-body. They thus communicate impulses, but not food. The nerve strand has two sheaths, an inner or myelin sheath, and an outer, called the neurilemma. The function of these concern electro-physiology, however, rather than our own science. Special psycho- logical interest attaches to the appearance and function of the physical termination of the nerve strands, one of which is the end-brush, the other, the dendrites. It will be noticed that the names are similes, and as such explain nothing functional. The end-brush of one fibre meets the dendrites of another, or aborizes with it; and right at this juncture psychology finds its chief interest in the nervous system. This is not to say that latency, for example, is uncon- nected with the rate of the nervous impulse, which makes it impossible for the "speed of thought" to be more than one or two hundred metres per second. Nor is it unimportant that the nervous action is chemical rather than elec- trical, even though the action of the cell is ac- companied by electrical phenomena detectable by a galvanometer, and that there is chemical substance freed by the nervous action of re- sponse. Important as these are, they concern not intimately the conscious cross-section. But the fact that the change of the direction of the 104 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS current through this neural arc is irreversible, and that it proceeds from sense organ down the receptor fibre, through the dendrites of that fibre across to the end-brush of the conducting fibre, and so on to the end-plate of a muscle ready to be aroused into changes of form, elas- ticity and the like, — this point is so important for psychology that we shall take it up in con- siderable detail. It is, indeed, the backbone of our knowing and doing. 19. Reflex action is the occupation of the reflex arcs. "When one touches oft" a charged Leyden jar, incalculably more energy is dis- charged from the jar than was contained in the mechanical connecting of the two poles by the discharging wire. The release of energy in ex- ploding dynamite far overtops the mechanical blow from the percussion cap. These are help- ful analogies in considering reflexes. Reflex action means that more energy is discharged from the arc than was imparted to the organ- ism by the stimulus. It also means that the "end effect is mediated by a conductor, itself in- capable of mediating that particular end effect." Furthermore, in all animals having a compli- cated nervous system, we find the reflexes de- fining the environment in point of being specifi- cally and selectively excitable. Some respond 105 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION but to grades of temperature, others to lights, still others to sounds, or to mechanical, chem- ical, electrical and other eiffects; and thus by their cross-sectioning the environment, unite in forming that which we call consciousness. There are, of course, other responses, such as, for example, those which calls from starving In- dia would provoke, but these are not simple reflexes. According to recent investigators, the difference between the higher and the lower animals, insofar as neural action is concerned, lies in the fact that the unicellular organisms take but two chapters in physiology to exhaust them, — one on surface, and the other on internal phenomena, — while multicellular organisms supply a third chapter on intercellular physiol- ogy by virtue of intercellular deposits. Now when these deposits are solid (e. g., bone) we have mechanical or lever operations to con- sider; when they are liquid, we have chemical; and when, lastly, the intercellular connections are by virtue of real, living protoplasmic masses, whose business it is to connect, intercommunica- tion becomes possible by reflex action. Now we can see why the foregiven analogies of the Leyden jar and the dynamite are going to prove psychologically inadequate. And yet mechan- 106 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ics has a finger in reflex action as will forth- with appear. 20. In the succeeding paragraphs, until we come to the detailed relating of the attributes of sensation to the action of the nervous sys- tem, I shall draw largely upon the work of C. S. Sherrington and others, as given in his "In- tegrative Action of the Nervous System," in which, by the way, is recorded the most signif- icant information upon physiological psychol- ogy that has appeared for many centuries. The student will profit largely by studying some parts of this book in detail in connection with this present chapter. "A sense organ is a recep- tive surface." From whatever parts of the body a reflex can be elicited, nerve fibres run to the conductor involved in the response, and those parts are the sense organ for that reflex. "The eye is a glorified heat spot, the ear a glorified touch spot." The long and eventful history of evolution traces the contraction of those sense fields receptive to ether and air vibrations to certain restricted areas, furthermore formed into organs which lie half embedded under apertures in the skin, neither strictly within nor on the surface of the body. Of stimuli that will excite the reflex chain implicit with the presence of a sensory surface there are four 107 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION kinds. The first and largest class are the ef- fective stimuli, by which is meant all means, mechanical, thermal, chemical, etc., that will start neural action along the arc. Of these ef- fective stimuli, however, some are adequate, or those to which the organ is normally attuned, such as sight to the eye, sound to the ear, and so on; while others are inadequate (let us say for true perceptions) such as a blow on the eye, or a foreign substance in the ear. All other stimuli are ineffective, that is, cause no arousal whatever, such as a beam of moonlight stream- ing into the ear. Considered from the stand- point of modality, the sensory reflexes define a modality of adequate stimuli only, the blow on the eye being a mechanical jar, transmitted to the optic nerve not by the retina but by a se- quence of concussions through the coats and liquids of the eye-ball. The sensory surfaces are thus selective. Sherrington reports that the plantar reflex of the brainless dog and the pinna reflex in the cat can be elicited by only mechan- ical stimuli. Electrical are wholly ineffective. As a last general word on the receptive sur- faces, it is found that if we consider such field as that whole collection of points on the skin from which an identical reflex may be elicited, that a weak stimulus in the center of the field 108 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS has about as much of an effect as a strong one on the periphery, A schematic representation of a reflex field would have to include the item of varying penetrability. 21. Some reflex fields overlap. Especially is this true of the so-called proprio-ceptive and the extero-ceptive reflex fields, the former be- ing the sub-cutaneous receptors for organic stimulation, while the latter are on the skin surface, or superficial. The dermal senses ex- hibit this overlapping all the while, and in ex- perimenting on touch, one finds that most in- vestigation is meaningless without taking ac- count of this fact. Thus for the modalities known as touch, warmth, cold, and pain, there is a rather illy defined set of dependable re- flexes for functioning them. Sometimes, also, there is interaction between overlapping sense fields, setting up a new condition in their re- lation, known as the "reinforcing of reflexes by each other," This has bearings upon intensity, both qualitative and quantitative. Sometimes reflexes widely apart (dermographically) com- bine and interact, as in synaesthesia, by which is meant the co-presence of the qualities of one object (the stimulus) with the presence of those of another object of a normally unrelated mo- dality. This is especially instanced by the 109 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION musician who has his "white" and "blue" minor tonalities. 22. Reflexes also are set off in certain se- quences. The sight of a fly causes a hungry frog (doubtless visually more alert through hunger) to dart out its tongue, the movement of the tongue arousing salivation, which again leads to the business of swallowing. The stim- uli to such reflexes usually overlap each other in time, and the threshold of excitability of each succeeding one is lowered by the excita- tion just in advance of its own. It is almost needless to say that most of our learned habits are of such a sequential reflex character, called con-sequential when the with-for relation is present. As a rule, furthermore, the series is intransitive, which is exactly what irreversibil- ity of the transmission of impulses along the neural arc must be understood to mean. 23. Curious among the reflexes are those whose response functions pain. The pain sense organs are "anelective," that is, their modality includes exceedingly heterogeneous objects. Very many kinds of stimuli are painful. And if the stimuli are normally inadequate, when danger to the whole organism is threatened, they become adequate, — that is, the threshold is then very low. Especially js an exposed 110 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS nerve susceptible to low intensities of noxious stimuli, and as such represents the imperative- ly protective character of the pain reflex. The pain reflex exhibits another curiosity in point of being aroused, for example, by a harmful touch on a certain spot of the skin, where a harmless touch would be insufficient. The re- sulting actions, likewise, from these two char- acters of stimulus are diametrically unlike. 24. Our fund of health is guaranteed by an immense number of tonic and other reflexes. The vegetative functions, cardiac, respiratory and other valiant reactions against an environ- ment we propitiate by metabolism, guarantee a certain vital momentum, — on the basis of which we are free to function extero-ceptively, — and depend for their integrity upon retaining their receptive surfaces, modalities and thresholds intact. In a way, we might be said to thrive principally upon the funded increment of the unconscious, for only by means of the warn- ings of pathological symptoms do we recognize the stabilizing character of these background reflexes of our organism. 25. All the reflexes may be said to be pur- posive. That is to say, they maintain the ani- mal against some, maybe not the choicest, por- tion of his environment. For those parts which, 111 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION in a case of danger, cannot withdraw, evoke by mediation of pain reflexes those which can ef- fect a withdrawal. Sherrington also points out that the scratching by a dog of his own bitten skin grooms the skin so as to protect the sen- sory surface against becoming of too high a threshold value for the inevitable noxious stimulus. 26. After this brief account of reflexes in general, we turn to the specific relation of the reflex arc to sensation and its constitutive at- tributes. It will be remembered that the three strands in the nerve path were the receptor, the conductor and the effector, each of which has a different function. As may be already in mind, the function of the receptor is implicit in an adequate description of a receptive sur- face. But to go farther, the function of the receptor (fibre and sense organ together) is "to lower the threshold of excitability of an arc for one kind of stimulus, and to heighten it for all the others." In our own terms, — to specify more and more the limits of the modality. For example, there are no electrical receptors: na- ture excludjgs volts and amperes from the list of adequate stimuli, — from modalities. But the selective excitability of the receptor not only limits the number of stimuli within the mo- 112 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS dality, but provides increasing responsiveness to them, and heightens it superlatively for a special few. As far as the efllector is concerned, it is connected with the muscle on its end-plate, and the end-plate is indefatigable. No amount of stimulation exhausts it, — it has no threshold. 27. But when one asks what happens in the conductor, the array of facts and functions is not so abbreviated as in the above cases. Now if, instead of stimulating the sensory sur- face of a reflex, we dissect in under the skin to the nerve trunk, and, leaving the receiving organ out of the experiment, stimulate a con- duction path, the results will differ from those derived from intact reflex arc conduction in the following ways : "Conduction in reflex arc exhibits, (1) slow- er speed as measured by the latent period be- tween application of stimulus and appearance of end-eff"ect, this diff'erence being greater for weak stimuli than for strong; (2) Less close correspondence between the moment of cessation of stimulus and the mo- ment of cessation of end-eff'ect, z. e., there is a marked "after-discharge" ; (3) Less close correspondence between the rhythm of stimulus and rhythm of end-eff'ect; (4) Less close correspondence between the 113 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION grading of intensity of the stimulus and the grading of intensity of the end-effect; (5) Considerable resistance to passage of a single nerve impulse, but a resistance easily forced by a succession of impulses (temporal summation) ; (6) Irreversibility of direction, instead of comparative unfatigability of nerve trunks; (7) Fatigability in contrast with the com- parative unfatigability of nerve trunks; (8) Much greater variability of the thres- hold value of stimulus than in nerve trunks; (9) Refractory period, inhibition, and shock, in degrees unknown for nerve trunks; (10) Much greater dependence on blood circulation, oxygen; and (11) Much greater susceptibility to various drugs — anaesthetics." I have italicised several words in this quo- tation for the purpose of showing the trend of my interpretation of the nervous system; and it will be noticed also that these eleven points of difference sum for us into a general concept of something like a blockade. And the place where these blockades occur has been quite clearly indicated to be not in the nerve cell bodies, nor the sustaining tissue between nerve fibres, but in the surfaces of separation be- 114 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS tween the end-brush and the dendrites, called the synapse. Now a surface of separation is physically a membrane, — the nerves do not con- join any more than the fleshy surfaces of the hands touch when one clasps his gloved hands. Correlated with the irreciprocal permeability of the synaptic membrane is the irreversibility of the nervous current, — a phenomenon well known as a phase of osmosis. Now the nervous conduction is not preeminently chemical, as is witnessed by the facts of its speed, freedom from the effects of temperature changes, and its facile excitation by mechanical means. Right here, then, is where mechanics and physics come in for their own in psychology. In order that a transverse membrane become a conductor, it must be modified by doing the conducting, and such we find to be the case with reflex conduction as differing from nerve trunk con- duction. This feature defines many of the phenomena of physiological psychology as types of auto-catalysed neural activity, and has no end of bearings on personality. 28. We are now ready to indicate the re- lation between the attributes of sensation and neural activity. Of the first two essential at- tributes, modality and quality, we have suf- ficiently spoken. The next in order is inten- 115 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION sity. The first point to make is that the in- tensity of effect is less well graded with the mechanically measurable stimulus in the case of the intact reflex arc than in the nerve trunks. In the latter it is almost a one-to-one correla- tion, while in the former it looks like all or nothing. So that internal neurological condi- tions play a greater role than do external ones in reflex conductions as compared with those in nerve trunk conductions. Especially is this to be noted, in the different grading of effects in various reiiexes. The series are not ordinally correlated either. And yet intensities in these cases are connected with the number of ele- ments coexcited, acting by irradiation. How- ever this may be, the reaction, as it irradiates, treats the motor element, the effector and its connections, as a unit. For the whole motor center functionally belongs to each and all of the groups of receptors proper to the reflex. Much light is thrown by this knowledge of the working of reflexes upon both the qualitative and quantitative aspects of intensity. Unless we are merely sparring for time, the unique- ness of qualitative intensity means in connec- tion with reflexes, that the "all or nothing" principle implies too sudden an inlet and out- go of energy' for any intercolonial responses to 116 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS furnish an equilibrating neural background at the time of the release of reflex energy; while the quantitative and functional aspect of in- tensity lies unconcealed in the two principles of irradiation and difterences of grading in the various reflexes. This grading is found to be a constant function, but its mathematical ex- pression is far from being reducible to a sim- ple linear equation: its formulation includes at least two dimensions. 29. In connection with the next attributes of sensation to be disposed of, it is requisite that we consider briefly certain characteristics of the release of neural energy in the effector nerves. Sensory surfaces, as we have just seen, may be very large or very small, but in either case the sensory (receptor) fibres leading from them pass toward some part of the central nervous system, there to be gathered together in a bundle to guarantee that the response me- chanism shall not be at all hit or miss, but rather specifically differentiated from that mechanism fed by the sensory fibres from an- other sense field. Now, however, several sense fields frequently are connected by receptor fibres to the same effector mechanism, so that the stimulation that gets there first will close the "valve" against the later arrival and crowd 117 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION it out of action. The simultaneous or even successive debouching of nervous energies upon the same undischarged effector does not behave always in the above manner, but whenever any effector amenable to neural discharge from sev- eral sense fields functions in this way it is called a "final common path." Before the final common path is reached, however, at least one synapse has to be passed, and the condition of passage at this surface of separation is of such a character that sensory selectivity is very sim- ple and easy to comprehend in contrast to the eccentric character of the release readiness at the entrance to this final common path. The motor cells do not conjoin. Only a functional union knits them together, and here in connec- tion with this neuronic threshold of release we may freely mention all but a few of the re- maining attributes of sensation, — not only men- tion them, in fact, but at the end propound a very searching and insistent question. 30. Intensity has been shown to concern the release of energy all along the neural arc. "The entrant path tends to run in certain di- rections or not at all," for other paths may lead to the same conductor and the two sets of forces may conflict. Then, either irradiation or sum- mation of stimuli must overcome the neuronic 118 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS threshold, "and irradiation extends per saltum rather than ad gradatim." The strongest stim- ulated afferent arc is the most likely to capture the final common path, — strong and weak re- ferring not only to mechanical or other stimuli as such, but also to the relation they bear to the focus and fringe of the receptive field. Typ- ical of the sort of data the psychologist must not haggle over, is the fact that the threshold of excitability in the reflex mechanism is more variable than in the nerve trunks. Stimulation in the undissected animal is, pro tanto, destined to be more eventful than that in the mutilated specimen. There is in James' "Psychology, Briefer Course," (pp. 92-101), an account of the behavior both of a mutilated frog and of a pigeon, in which the diff'erences between them and their whole fellow creatures is taken up in considerable detail, just in point of what the neural connections contribute to conscious- ness, as we are doing here, with a conclusion that I am certain is in serious error. I shall quote just enough of this chapter both to be fair to its author and to make my point: ". . . the main difference between the hem- isphereless animal and the whole one may be concisely expressed by saying that the one obeys absent, the other only present, objects." Again, 119 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION "Within the psychic life due to the cerebrum itself the same general distinction obtains, be- tween considerations of the more immediate and considerations of the more remote. In all ages the man whose determinations are swayed by reference to the most distant ends has been held to possess the highest intelligence." I cite this nmch quoted expression right here, even at the risk of losing my reader's memory of the issue I have started to make pertinent for him, for the exact purpose of showing just what inadequacy has characterized many a psy- chologist's treatment of neural connections. For not only are there innumerable present objects and immediate considerations which even the whole, undissected animal cannot obey or re- spond to, — on account of the selective excitabil- ity of the neural arc and the neuronic thres- hold, — but there are also recent investigations upon dogs, by Goltz, Pavlow and Rothmann, showing that new tricks, habits and memories may become the possession of animals with spines transected and brains dissected out. Let any one make out of this whatever he pleases, remembering also the nudge we gave in a pre- vious paragraph regarding the heirarchy of dark thrones in the wilderness of the central nervous system, 120 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS 31. Due to the energy required to overpass the neuronic threshold, not immediately upon the application of the stimulus does the release occur. But the latent period (refractory phase) in the nerve trunks is only about one sigma (one- thousandth of a second), while in the case of the reflex arc the pause is considerably longer and more variable. Besides, in the latter case it often "misses a stitch," — the eft'ect of the stim- uli thereafter being poorly graded with the amount of mechanical or electrical stimulation. Something is happening, nevertheless, in the refractory phase, which is only "that state dur- ing which, apart from fatigue, the mechanism shows less than its full efl'ect of excitability." The summation of stimuli also "produce a con- dition at the synapse similar to that normally present in the nerve trunk.' Lhis phenomenon is not due to the muscle, but is wholly a reflex arc affair. Very feeble electric shocks will summate, and one weak stimulus followed by another one as far apart as 1400 sigma (1.4 sec.) may summate with it. This phenomenon lurther means that "the nearer together two points are in the receptive field which get stim- ulated, the greater coalition there is between the reflexes elicited." For "where conduction lines run together, there is a reduction in re- 121 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION sistance," and this is primarily what summation means. At this point we may also speak of vividness and clearness. When an "initial re- flex is followed by an incremental one, the lat- ency of the latter is shorter than that of the former." The synapse was "set," and the qual- itatively different, but modally-prepared-for stimulus got functioned on the background of this neural readiness. 32. The final common path being captured, adaptation may set in; in which case less en- ergy from the stimulus will be then needed to produce a release equal to the original reaction. The bridge is built, and merchandize may be shipped across it ad libitum. "The length of latency being inversely proportional to the re- flex intensity," before the synapse is "set," there follows in cases of adaptation the maintenance of a transmission circuit at the expense of very little energy from the stimulus. In conduct we call this feature "poise." The final common path is a common conductor for many impulses, arising from many sources of reception. When impulses producing allied rather than opposed effects play upon it, we have a case of fusion, which is summation minus the time element, considered from the standpoint of reflex readi- ness, though the qualitative character of the 122 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS fused elements is apparently a derivative of time itself. 33. Linked with the amount of receptive surface stimulated is the attribute of extensity. It appears now why this and other attributes are referred to content rather than to function. For if fusion exhibits the fact that in psychol- ogy to add is to subtract, extensity of receptive field or surface needs not go hand in hand with summation of releases or end-effects. This very item indicates the different dimensionality of quantities and qualities. Yellow, for exam- ple, is not just a certain number of vibrations. It is also yellow, — ^the physics of color defines not that other dimension into which the concept of color is embedded. So with extensity: we might even add contrast to the list, for the items of sensation in regard to which we have to be exceedingly perspicuous and rigidly empirical began as far back as the paragraph on the neuronic threshold. Contrast is represented, or better shared in neural-arc releases by an en- largement of the concept of the neurology of fusion: I mean the simultaneous and balanced use of final common paths for allied effects even within different modalities. 34. The receptive surface of a reflex has bounds, and functionally thins off in a manner 123 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION specified before. The local-sign of an object stimulating it will then more accurately cor- respond to its position in space, the more ortho- gonally it impinges upon that field, functionally considered. For an erroneous judgment in terms of local sign means only a certain obliq- uity of stimulus in relation to the field as a re- ceiving apparatus. This concept will be elab- orated in the paragraphs on illusions. 35. The attributes of duration and after- image are best treated of together in connection with neural action. We saw that the latent period included the element of time. These do also, but in the following special manner: Sen- sations, qualitatively construed, may endure as long as, not as long as, or longer than the ap- plication of the stimulus. Indeed, the latent- period implies that the effector fibre shall re- lease its energy later than the receptor; after- images merely require the concept of more slug- gish time without necessary diminution of ef- fect to explain them. For, as formerly asserted, time in psychology is not solar time, and for the differences no one on an empirical mission needs to make any apology. We find that the after-discharge of reflexes may be very incal- culable. It may be, for example, the same fot nine stimulations as it is for three stimula- 124 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS tions, each of which is mechanically thrice the quantity of the one used nine times. Or, again, after a number of subliminal stimuli there may be a pause without discharge, but during which the stimuli are summing, followed by a vigor- ous discharge, then another pause, then an after-discharge, — a thing not so different after all from one's experience with induction coils and Leyden jars. 36. Exhaustion is a function of time and intensity. As a reflex tires from excessive stim- ulation, it not only declines in the amount of release of motor energy, but becomes also more and more markedly tremulous. Opposed to this effect is that of an adapted reflex, as noted above. Exhaustion is also a function of po- sition or direction. Some reflexes which tire when aroused from one spot in the sensory surface, can be aroused again to full activity by stimulating another spot some little distance away. With judicious use, the reflexes are rel- atively indefatigable; for by the shifting of briefly lasting stimuli from point to point in the field, one can produce a longer lasting re- action than when the same stimuli come at equal intervals at the same point. Now in spite of the fact that reference to the sensory sur- face is a great factor in exhaustion, the phe- 125 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION nomenon is not sensory, but directly referable to the conduction fibres within the central nerv- ous system. But here we have to include the fact that "only when" the sensory surface is treated thus and so does the internal conduc- tivity become involved in the manner so far shown. 37. Inhibition is manifested in the reflex arc action in many ways, some of which are quite curious. We have spoken of the incre- mental reflex, — ^where the second, say, of two stimulations being suddenly intensified, arouses sudden intensification of the motor result. In such a case, whenever there is a latent period other than one might expect for such a change in intensity, it means the checking, or inhibi- tion of spreads of discharge to other centres than the one concerned with the discharge into the final common path then in operation. Again, the after-discharge may be prevented by stimulating another reflex which uses the same final common path for an eff"ect contrary to the first one. What else, also, is the latent time itself than a period of inhibition? But we usually speak of this phenomenon as occurring after the inception of some other fully opened discharge mechanism. Now come the curios- ities. Reflexes of a simultaneous double sign 126 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS (that is, where the motor nerve of the extensor muscle of a limb and that of the flexor muscle have opposed end effects) are neither exclusive- ly excitatory nor exclusively inhibitory. Be- sides, certain other reflexes are purely inhibi- tory, (that is, they are nihilistic in character, — dogs in a manger). They check all end eff"ects possible, producing none but those of their own release. Inhibitions usually also leave the nervous tissue better fitted for more extensive functioning after their occurrence, though some are neutral, leaving the tissue neither exhausted nor surcharged as to energy. 38. There is but one more attribute of sen- sation to be considered in this wise. This is feeling-tone. It was suggested previously that not quite all the data of sensation could be harnessed to neural action, and this intricate and mooted point of the neural nature of feel- ing now confronts us. These other seventeen attributes are all accounted for by intra-neural categories; feeling-tone must be accounted for by means of inter-neural relationships. But the problem is not acute: in case of the readi- ness of an arc to respond, or in case of the readi- ness of transfer of energy from one arc to an- other, or in case of a readiness to inhibit, — such items as these sum up most of the neurol- 127 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ogy of feeling-tones. Whatever other empirical conditions may be found to be the bases of feel- ing will, of course, but plot other points in the same series. We like not only to be doing, but also at times to keep ourselves and others from doing, as well as we like changes and novelties. That these are implicit in the general neurology of sensation is evident from a careful perusal of the above explanatory and analytic para- graphs. 39. But now there comes an insistent ques- tion with regard to all the foregoing. Is what the nerves are doing, sensation? And are the attributes of sensation which are carefully and completely welded to neural releases to be taken to imply that the sensation is in the nerv- ous system? Is the fluent speaker after all only emptying his spine and cranium upon his hearers? For it is exactly at this point in most treatises upon things mental, where psy- chology meets its unpremeditated Golgotha. And here a large two-horned dilemma pokes its nose over the horizon, for there seem to be but two alternatives from which to choose in this and every other similar case. One of which dilemmas I have elsewhere in this book called the gospel of dendrites; and the other of which I shall have no trouble in allying to the theory 128 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS of soft souls. The gospel of dendrites asserts that sensations are in and of the nervous sys- tem exclusively. My preceding paragraphs, with the exception of a few phrases about series, (odious and sour to the hide-bound physiologist), are welcomed no doubt by the upholders of this doctrine, and they point with triumph to the harnessing of every last attrib- ute of sensation to the internal workings of the body. '''There the sensation is," they say, "it is just what the nerves are doing." The other party, breezing forth the doctrine of a soft soul, retaliates vigorously upon the preceding by as- serting that the neural action heretofore de- scribed has nothing to do with sensation as ex- perienced. "It doesn't feel that way to look at yellow, nor to taste lemonade, nor yet to be pricked with a pin. The experiencing of things is unique, and all your nervous action and conceptual series are preposterous and ar- tificial." 40. But both of these objections come about through a clear case of total misapprehension. It was not a dilemma that appeared above the horizon, but merely a unicorn, which only to the strabismic showed a bifurcated frontal excres- cence. And I shall treat of these two doctrines in exactly the inverse proportion to their pop- 129 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ularity. In the first place, the gospel of den- drites gives no sufficient account of the object stimulating the arcs. In the second place, the theory of the soft and elusive soul spurns all identity between that which sensations can be analysed into (attributes) and the character- istics of neural action as shown by investigators who, by the way, do not thus cavil at what they find to be the case. For to speak intro- spectively about sensations in any manner ex- cept simply to blurt their names and their im- mediate effects, is to use memory and judgment, which are not sensations. But then, the hope- lessness of persuading the soft-soul theorist against his assumptions is worth nothing in comparison to keeping others from becoming so unregenerate as he. Of course the object is not the neural action. When we ask, as Holt asks in regard to reflex activities, ''What is this organism doing" in the presence of the fateful stimulus? the answer, if complete, can neither be in terms of the neural release alone as tested on laboratory specimens, nor yet in terms of the object we care to assert is the only possible potent object within range of the nervous sys- tem; but our answer must rather be, that "the organism proceeds to do something, of which the strict scientific description can only be that 130 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS it is a constant function of some feature of the environment; and this latter [the environment] is by no means necessarily the stimulus itself." ("Response and Cognition," by E. B. Holt, Jour. Phil., Psych, and Sci. Methods. July 8, 1915.) 41. The physiologist cannot, with a mere wave of the hand, banish all other objects than the one he is especially interested in testing upon the organism. Neither is the soft-soul theorist putting away nonsensical things in as- serting that the object sensed is not the object as described; for when he says "sensation," he means "object in an environment colored by the environment." Of course he cannot under- stand why you are talking about one thing when he is thinking about fifty. So that it is neither neural action that is the sensation, nor yet the "experience" which no one can mention, but the sensation is the object and what it will do in that environment to accomplish the release of energy in the nervous system. And these two things, what it is and what it does, while un- separated in that which the soft-soul theorist calls his "experience," have just been separated in this treatment of sensation. This point ex- hibits an explicit case of the with-for relation; things and doings are blended in unanalysed consciousness, — blended to make consciousness, 131 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION — and it is upon the basis and according to the character of these blends that we ever thought of using the pronoun I. 42. But lest 1 be misunderstood at this junc- ture, let me say that, insofar as the neural ac- tion is concerned with the sensation, it is iden- tical with whatever of the sensation can be de- fined by reference to the attributes constitut- ing it. Some of these attributes are also identi- cal with the object, the stimulus. In adaptation the nerves are becoming adapted to the con- tinued release of their energy; in summation, they sum their efiects, and so on throughout the list. Sensation, however, is made by an object within an environment upon nervous arcs with- in the eleven thousand million cells of the sys- tem. The object is not cleft from its environ- ment nor are the specialized arcs separated from their gray and white bedding. For the at- tributes that refer to content are of the object as well as exhibited in the response, and partial naming of them with reference exclusively to one or the other is fallacious. Mind and body are the same thing, and of the attribute-thing character; only the possible attributes are not ever all together in time or space, since the orders to which they belong forbid such a con- dition. 132 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS THE SPECIAL SENSES /. Internal 43. Typical of the internal sensations and doubtless of prime importance to the reader is the sensation of hunger. This sensation is to be cleft from appetite, for the desserts we eat are not taken to satisfy hunger, but merely to please us. Furthermore, hunger often forces people to take food when it is both distasteful and nauseating. It is specifically characterized by "a dull ache or gnawing localized at the low- er mid-chest region and the epigastrium, be- coming more local the intenser it becomes." This dull ache is also accompanied by lassitude, drowsiness, faintness, headache, irritability and restlessness at times, these being the inessential concomitants of the sensation. It is not a gen- eral somatic condition, nor is it due to nerve cells "suffering from a shortage of provisions," for after the first few days of a fast, hunger wholly disappears. The absence of hunger in fever, that there is no evidence for the sudden changes in the blood corresponding to the sud- den and intermittent onsets of the pangs, and the fact that hunger is gone too soon after eat- ing for the replenishments it provides to become effective, together with the illustration that to eat moss and clay, indigestibles that they are, 133 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION allays the pangs, — these point to a special loca- tion for the stimulus. Neither is it due to emptiness of the stomach alone, nor to the tur- gescence of the gastric glands, for after one swallows indigestibles, causing no secretions of gastric juice whatever, hunger is assuaged. 44. Hunger is rather the "result of contrac- tions of the muscle fibres of a wholly empty stomach" (in health), and "such contractions may be even stronger than during digestion." This has been shown by means of detecting manometric contractions caused by rubber baloons connected with tubing temporarily swallowed and allowed to be inflated so as to receive the impacts of the stomach wall. The fact that hunger is often felt higher up than at the stomach is accounted for by the similar finding of synchronous contractions in the low- er oesophagus. The cause for these contrac- tions is not known, but writers incline to the view that habit rather than specific bodily need causes them. The expression "too tired to eat" means that fatigue poisons in the blood relay their effects to accomplish a fatigue in the rhythmic contractions of the digestive organs involved. Professor W. B. Cannon writes: "Hunger, in other words, is normally the signal that the stomach is contracted for action; the 134 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS unpleasantness of hunger leads to eating; eat- ing starts gastric secretion, distends the con- tracted organ, initiates the movements of gastric digestion, and abolishes the sensation." Now the curious thing to note in this sensation is that the stimulus is not the stomach, nor the empty stomach, but the qualitative and quan- titative character of the movements of that or- gan. If the introspector says that hunger is nonsense when reduced to movements, (just as he would say ether vibrations are a silly sub- stitute for yellow), the reply is that the sensa- tion hunger is the object and what it will do, just as with every other sensation in the con- scious cross-section. Only the experience of hunger is just another qualitative attribute of just such movements and nothing else; for the physiologist from whom I have just quoted would likewise be the last man to say that when the stomach contracts all one has in mind are the graphical results of the manometric meas- urements. 45. The other internal sensations we shall not consider in detail. Except in diseased con- ditions the intestinal organs can be burned, pricked, cut or pinched without any result for focal consciousness. The peritoneum and diaphram, on the other hand, as far as experi- 135 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ment has gone, show extreme responsiveness; yet the various attributes of sensation have not been systematically studied in them. Thirst and nausea are usually localized in the mouth and throat. As a usual thing we are not con- scious of the action of the heart and lungs, any more than we are of the other viscera, and, in- deed, only by those feelings known as aches and pains do we become at all aware of the unconscious backgrounds of focal conscious- ness. And these aches and pains are frequent- ly intensities, summations, extensities, durations and the like of coenaesthetic disturbances, con- stituting the with-for relation of general and specific defense against disease and thwarting. The psychology of these things, when thorough- ly investigated, will prove of interest to all hands, but their special study is for the pathol- ogist rather than for the student of general psy- chology. 2. Cutaneous Senses 46. The next group of sensations we shall consider are those functioned for by organs in the epidermis. These are commonly called touch, pain, warmth, cold, the pilomotor reflex, tickle, roughness, smoothness, and the like, — some of which are fusions and summations of other sensations. The area known as the "sur- 136 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS face of the b«rdy" is defined as extending as far within the apertures of the body as the nor- mally "skin-senses" can be aroused. In con- nection with all these dermal senses two things must be diligently kept in focus: first, the char- acter of the mechanical or other stimulus used, and second, the various layers of organs of sensibility beneath the skin surface. As said before, sensations are objects, and there are not sensations of these objects; so that later on, when we come to the possibility of arousing a sensation of warmth by a cold file the student will have no need of invoking the artifacts to help him over the seeming difficulty. In this connection it will be seen just how important the nature of series becomes in the science of the conscious cross-section. 47. The organs for the cutaneous senses are in general bulb-like. In and about every hair follicle fine nerve fibres wind, thus making the organs for superficial touch, — that is, the char- acteristic sensation aroused by a pin-head or a medium-sized bristle moderately applied. The formation of the touch-bulb is not unlike a rather amateurish piece of splicing. Cold is functioned for by other end-bulbs, of a round- ish appearance, while warmth is transmitted by a cylindrical organ, deeper in the layers of 137 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the skin than that for cold. Other disc-like or- gans have been located in the deeper tissues, whose function is not as exactly definable as that of the others. Pain is connected with the sensorial functioning of the free nerve endings, and has no specialized organ, insofar as evolu- tionary shaping is concerned. The skin does not respond to thermal, mechanical and elec- trical stimuli homogeneously, but is a mosaic of tiny areas, some of which respond to touches, others to temperatures, and still others to punc- tures and the like. But the interesting thing about the integumental sense field is that the same areas or spots remain constantly of the same character, so that we can factually say: "Once a touch spot always a touch spot," and so on. Of these spots, those responding pain- fully are the most numerous, cold and touch spots come next, while the warmth spots are the fewest. Punsters might infer from this condition both that "man was made to mourn," and also that nature had some hand in the size of the coal bill. Exploration of the entire in- tegument has also shown that these spots are unequally distributed, in general the most sen- sitive parts being over the joints and upon those areas uncovered by clothing. Special articles on these points will have to be referred to by 138 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the student for further and exacter informa- tion. 48. As a signal example of clean and sig- nificant experimentation upon the skin surface, is to be mentioned the work of Drs. Rivers and Head, as recorded in "Brain," Nov., 1908, in an article called "A Human Experiment in Nerve Division." 1 cite this article also for the purpose of showing that naive experiments per- formed in laboratories result in findings con- trary to those which appear in text-books, be- cause of lack of definition in the materials used and the method employed. Dr. Head found three separate sets of organs located in the dermal layers, each of which behaved quite differently upon the application of the same stimuli. And in this case, as before, one must be ready to resign his old idea of the nature of sensation, and distinguish between the p ijsical nature of the stimulus, the functional nature of the neural release, and the nature of ivhal the organism is doing in the presence of the en- vironment. For while we get yellow when look- ing at the sun as a conscious content, we get touches, colds, warmths and pains when the same shaped stimulus in diiferent physical series is applied to the skin. Only persons who are eye-minded think of needles when their 139 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION skin is punctured. The thing known as pain is not the essence of needledom; for the abstract- ing of a hair from the skin will also cause pain, just as the tapping of a cold spot often arouses the sensation called cold. We shall speak of the identity of series in these various contents and processes after the following brief sum- mary of this article cited above. 49. There is an area of deep sensibility, in- dependent of cutaneous nerves, which functions as follows. Tactile (pin-head) pressure is pres- ent in it, which even deep freezing by ethyl chloride does not abolish; but the application of cotton wool and the pulling of hairs outwards produces no focality in consciousness. Sudden jars and slight gradual pressures, however, are each differently responded to, thus indicating that the content of consciousness subtends re- spectively the different kinds of intensity in- volved. Roughness is well functioned for by this deep-lying system of nerves. Pressure, which to a normal hand would be painful, is present in consciousness as an ache, while needle pricking and electric pain arouse nothing there at all. Local sign is curiously prominent, even after freezing, but two compass points as far apart as 6 cm. laid longitudinally to the axis of the arm are not distinguished. Yet upon the 140 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS application of the points successively no such results are obtained. Temperature is wholly absent, only numbness being reported after the application of cold silver tubes and freezing solutions. The point to be finally made is that in the above experiment, "the peculiar aptitude possessed by a part innervated solely by the atierent receptor fibres of a muscular nerve, is the appreciation of all stimuli which produce deformation of structure." 50. Some time after such an operation, pro- topathic sensibility is present, or the sensibility appearing in the first stages of a lesion. In this condition, pain is distinctly felt, but "any ther- mal sensation produced by an adequate stim- ulus to a protopathic area tends to be widely diffused and to be referred into remote parts. In the attempt to estimate the relative intensity of two stimuli, a less cold object covering a larger area of the skin may evoke a more vivid sensation than one of smaller size but of lower temperature." In this stage, also, the hair is insensitive to all stimulation. (As long after the operation as 86 days.) The hairs do not respond with the characteristic "touch" sensa- tion, but bring about a tingling and diffused one, which "tends to be referred to parts remote from the point stimulated. Moreover, the re- 141 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION turn of this form of sensibility (protopathic) does not bring to the skin after shaving any power of reacting to stimulation with cotton wool." 51. In the later stages of a lesion, epicritic sensibility is manifest. Tactual sensations abound in almost the normal amount; localiza- tion is good, as are pointedness and relative sizes; and while thermal sensitivity is acute, the compass points are responded to with much irregularity. The touch of cotton wool on a shaven area is clearly appreciated, and the hair clad parts react both to pulls and pushes. The irregularity of the compass tests, however, does not include the item of eccentric reference, and Head believes that spacial discrimination is primarily a function of the epicritic sensibility. 52. The pilomotor reflex, commonly known as "goose-skin," is principally a function of the protopathic sensibility. "The exact date of the return of this reflex was not noted; but we gradually became aware that pricking the skin, pulling the hairs, or the application of the cold tube would occasionally give rise to a condi- tion of "goose-skin" within the area we were testing. "As protopathic sensibility increased, this reflex could be evoked more easily from the 142 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS affected area than from the normal skin. , . . Even brushing the hairs with cotton wool in this stage of recovery would start a pilomotor reflex. "With the gradual return of epicritic sen- sibility to the forearm, this increased response died away . . . "Whilst engaged on these experiments, we discovered that the 'thrill' called forth by aesthetic pleasure is accompanied by erection of the hairs ... He [the subject] could evoke the reflex by reading aloud some favorite poem." (Head, op. cit.) 53. As to the differences between these sys- tems of cutaneous sensibility in adapting to warm and cold, it is reported that, "Over normal parts, the neutral point of thermal sensibility shifts according as the hand is adapted to heat or to cold. "Over protopathic parts, no such change oc- curs . . . "It follows that some innervation other than protopathic must exist in the normal skin . . . and that this mechanism is capable of adaptation within a wide range. ". . . protopathic parts are incapable of adaptation to any material extent," but "parts in a condition of defective sensibility" are "ren- 143 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION dered apparently more sensitive to the specific stimulus of cold." (op. cit.) 54. "Accurate tactile localization is possible even M^hen the part is supplied with deep sen- sibility only, provided the pressure is sufficient to stimulate the deep afferent system. ". . . the recognition of two compass points applied simultaneously to the skin, is im- possible in the absence of epicritic sensibility, except at distances enormously in excess of the normal. "The existence of epicritic impulses inhibits the tendency to refer into remote parts. "Localization is in all probability the sum of two sets of sensations, one of which arises from deep, the other from cutaneous stimula- tion." 55. The attribute of intensity is found to have the following bearings upon the case: "Parts in a condition of protopathic sensi- bility respond more vividly than the normal skin to all stimuli capable of evoking a sensa- tion." [I should rather say "content."] "This ... is usually more intense and always of much greater extent than over normal parts. "For all effective stimuli, the threshold is 144 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS high in a protopathic area, and ... is one of defective sensibility. "An effective protopathic stimulus of low in- tensity, but covering a larger area, may produce a sensation of greater apparent intensity than a more restricted stimulation of greater strength. "The usual psychological view that an in- creased sensory reaction corresponds to a low- ered threshold must be readjusted. It is true in the strict sense only of epicritic and deep sensibility." (The italics in the above are mine.) 56. As to punctuate sensibility, Head furth- er reports: "The skin is supplied by two anatomically distinct systems which . . . regenerate at different periods after complete nerve division. Moreover, a part of the skin may be supplied by one of these systems only. "Protopathic sensibility depends upon spe- cific end-organs gathered together within the skin to form sensory spots; the spaces between are insensitive to cutaneous stimuli, if the part is endowed with protopathic sensibility only. "Owing to the sparseness of the heat spots, their characteristics can be easily demonstrated; cold spots are more numerous and correspond- 145 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ingly difficult to investigate. The pain spots are so closely distributed throughout the skin that it is impossible to study them with the [same] accuracy [as in the case] of the heat heat and cold spots; but the character of their response, and the period at which they regen- erate, show that they belong to the same order. "Whenever the skin is supplied with proto- pathic end organs only, any sensation evoked radiates widely and tends to be referred to re- mote parts. These are the same, whichever kind of spot be stimulated, so long as it lies within the same area of the skin. "Radiation and reference are abolished as soon as the part becomes sensitive to cutaneous tactile stimuli and to intermediate degrees of temperature. "All protopathic sense organs have a high threshold. All epicritic organs have a low thres- hold. . . . When the normal skin is stim- ulated, the defects of protopathic sensibility are corrected and compensated by the simultaneous activity of the low-threshold epicritic system. . . . The epicritic mechanism is highly adapt- able. The threshold for painful sensations is the same over normal and over highly proto- pathic parts, but on the normal skin the ap- proach of pain is preceded by the sensation of 146 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS contact with a pointed object. This is absent over protopathic parts. The power of recogniz- ing the pointed nature of the stimulating ob- ject . . . belongs to that group of sensations by which we estimate relative size." 57. It can thus be seen that "touch" instead of being one sense, as handed down in popular mythology, is more exactly ten or eleven senses, shared among three sets of nerve fibres. For example, we can "physically" touch the skin with wool, sandpaper, pin points and heads, or with wooden skewers that deeply deform it, — all touchings, if you will, and yet the conscious content is qualitatively different each time. Quantitative equality in these cases is something that does not exist for psychology, — the intensity is in each case prime; and these quantitative se- ries in psychology possess severally but one term, the term of specific qualitative intensity. However, in their relations to other series, an other than the prime relation exists in those se- ries constituting the separate dermal sensations. The case of paradox-cold is one to which too great emphasis cannot be drawn, for it means that some of the series making up sensation in- tersect, just as two lines intersect. To be able to arouse a cold sensation with the use of a hot rod means precisely that as much of the cold 147 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION sensation as is thus aroused is identical with the as yet unnamed complex of heat-touch-nerve- touch-organ, called by virtue of surprise, the paradox-cold sensation. It is something more than this; for in these two above-named com- plexes, there exists a common part. Further- more, this concept of the common part is ex- hibited in the case of arousing tickle with cot- ton wool and with a fine bristle attached to the tine of a tuning fork vibrating against the skin. The eccentric reference of sensation by the pro- topathic system to which Head refers is also but a case of common parts in the two series of stimulus-organ-response complexes. It also means for the student of physiology that the response was inhibited along one, its accus- tomed, final common path, and found its way out by another less blockaded. 58. It is almost needless to say, that the pro- hibition we declared against the use of popular terminology in the first chapter is more than justified by this rather exhaustive account of the nature of touchings and other dealings with the skin. Impacts, which have been the glory of physics to reduce to formulae, have almost no meaning in psychology. For impacts branch and flower at the gateway of the nervous system in such a surprising manner, that a new con- 148 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ception of their significance must react even on the study of physics. For physics should be that area of study in which sensations are exhaustively analysed. Again, in the tempera- ture senses, what we call warmth, heat and cold, are all within a very small range of the possible and actual temperatures. The series is short in psychology, bordered by the series of numb- nesses below the lower threshold of cold, and by burnings above the upper threshold for heat. Ice is way beyond our limit of cold imagina- tions, and the fusion point of even lead bank- rupts our sense-imagery. But, having lived so long under the dominion of hyperbole and ex- clamation points, we flatter ourselves that the range of the imagination is unlimited. We for- get that we substitute sensation thresholds for what lies beyond, and thus in the dust of the wheel utter many statements whose meaning corresponds exactly to that of flapdoodle and galoozalum. 59. Nevertheless here is a point where something other than sensational consciousness enters in. The thermometer, by which we measure temperatures accurately, and trans- cend our sensible appreciation of cold and heat, is in fact just a detachable organ, whose busi- ness is temperature affectiveness, but whose 149 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION efferent (sensory) nerve is not in the skin, but in the eye. That is, we do not sense trans-sen- sational thermometric temperatures, but per- ceive them. And at this point we shall leave the attribute-thing complex called sensation and go to the part-whole complex called per- ception, at least, as far as dermal sensitivity allows us. 60. When a single compass point is placed on the skin, and we merely react with "there," indicating that a touch of some kind was re- ceived, it is called sensation. When, again, the two compass points are placed on the skin, and we, with eyes closed as before, say "there," we have again merely sensational content. But if we are asked to tell whether in the second case there are two points rather than one touching us, and the twoness is manifest, we are on the road to perception. Especially is this true if we notice, by instruction, whether the points are placed in a certain dermographic relation to each other. Then, if we so locate them, or, if we discriminate the single point as having position relative to a certain other point or a part of the hand, we are perceiving along with our sensing, — ^they both getting simultaneously into the language reaction (common part). This is perception: sensations having structure, 150 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS sensations organized into some relationships and mentioned by the use of nothing necessarily more than prepositions and conjunctions. Drag a point along the skin, likewise, and if the re- port includes terms in relation, the conscious- ness is perceptual. Bear in mind, also, that these relations are not "material." Now the perception of cold or heat beyond the thresholds of these senses is vicariously accomplished by the observation of another set of changes than those of temperature proceeding side by side with the sensational alterations. Before the threshold of cold or heat is passed, several sets of changes are simultaneously present, one in the modality specified above, and the other in another modality, say that of sight. The first modality may be in focal, the second in co-con- sciousness. Then, when the threshold of the first modality is passed, the second modality comes into focality, and func- tions for both of them without apparent loss to fused consciousness of the mo- dality which has actually ceased to be present. For in such a case, our own responses keep marking time while the physical changes keep mounting their series,— the result being that the very condition of duration in one sense field coupled with alterations in another produces 151 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the fusion or summation effect of the sense im- agery adequate to the vicarious functioning of the trans-liminal series. 61. Thus perception is, so far, not a "mental act" by which we grasp the data obvious to us. It is, so far as dermal things are concerned, based entirely upon local sign, duration, exten- sity, intensity, fusion, contrast and after-image. For by the use of these alone, plus the responses of the neural organisation to relations, percep- tion is made clear and unmysterious. And if one asks here, as is inevitable, "how do we re- spond to relations?" the answer is that all neural functioning is, ipso facto, a series of effects and as such is a set of terms in relation. And these relations correspond with the relations between the objects they function. Furthermore, two compass points are, when not fused in touch, psychologically present as (1) "there," (2) "there," and (3) "something re- lating the two theres" as content. It is like- wise with all other relations and terms. Fur- thermore, when the content is loosely knit, they stand more clearly manifest the longer it en- dures; while when the content is welded and blent together, it has to be of longer duration to allow the relations to be perceived, and even then the various familiar parts must be allied 152 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS and compared with other things. This also is the door-step to logical-mindedness, as a little reflection will show. 62. It remains to speak somewhat in de- tail of certain attributes of dermal sensation. Of qualities there are only a few as compared with auditory and visual contents. In touch, there are light touch, superficial touch, granular touch, and the contents characteristic of moving objects on the skin. Intensity has been suf- ficiently treated in the quotations from Head. The latent period of touch is relatively long, varying from 1/6 to 1/4 sec, depending some- what upon the rate of impact employed. The threshold of touch is determined by the amount of pressure required to arouse the organs, and varies somewhat for different spots. The dura- tion of the touch sensation is connected with the matter of after-image, exhaustion, adapta- tion, and one or two other attributes, as follows. If the impact is forcible, say a dab with a pen- cil eraser on the forehead, suddenly withdrawn, there is very little longer duration to the main sensation than to the maintenance of the stim- ulus. But immediately afterwards, rings of throbbing or resurgence will arise from the smitten area as a center and pass off centri- fugally. These are after-images, and may ex- 153 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ceed five in number as well as exceed the in- tensity of the original impact as felt. They will be also more extensive than the original "sen- sation." Again, subliminal pressures will sum up into an effective stimulation, whose quality is often itchy or even painful and diffuse. Furthermore, the persistent stimulation of a live touch spot by supra-liminal pressures may ex- haust it, so that not even by looking at it and suggesting to oneself that it "ought" to feel touched, can we reaffirm the content above the threshold. Nevertheless, in the case of adapta- tion, the relating of the subconscious or co-con- scious elements of the sensation with other fo- cal contents will suffice to reinstate it among the series of appreciable intensities. Fusions in touch we have already illustrated by refer- ence to the compass points; curious simultane- ous and successive contrasts are often obtained by the use of compass points along with an in- strument giving single touches. Even when the compass points are beyond or within the two- point threshold, they may be felt as one or two as contrasted with single touches. Clearness is well illustrated in the above case as well as in that of diffuseness and pointedness being pres- ent at the same time; while lightly brushing a hair-clad surface will show that "intensity" (as 154 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS an impact phenomenon) is not required for fo- cal vividness. Feeling-tones in touch are beau- tifully illustrated with the aid of various text- ures, though touch blends operate here rather than single sensations. 63. As a last word on touch, I wish to cite an experiment upon the difference between the relative percentages of after-images derived from various modes of stimulating the skin, as reported in the "Psychological Monograph" for September, 1912, by M. H. S. Hayes in a thesis on "Cutaneous After-Sensations." The quota- tion I shall make will also serve to show the nature of the after-image series for dermal sen- sitivity. The general percentage of after-sen- sations, both those outlasting the application of the stimulus, and those reappearing after a sub- conscious interval is as follows: "Areal Cold 94.8% Punctiform Pain 93.5% Areal Heat 89.3% N. B. Areal Pressure 88.4% Punctiform Cold 84.7% N. B. Punctiform Pressure 79.3% Punctiform Heat 79.3% Radiant Heat 74.5% Radiant Cold 67.9% Electric Cold 59.3% 155 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION Electric Heat 58.3%" As to latent intervals, they are found most frequently with pressure, and less and less so with pain, heat and cold. Punctiform stimuli function them better than areal; whereas the briefer latent intervals are connected with heat, while longer ones are evident in touch and cold. The author concludes the article by saying, fur- thermore, that "cutaneous after-sensations are real phenomena, and not explainable by imagi- nation, oscillating attention, or the presence of skin and muscle [ ?] sensations ordinarily pass- ing unnoticed." 64. In connection with heat and cold, or better, warmth and cold,— for heat is a curious blend of cold and warmth, with slight admix- tures of pain at times, — one needs to notice that the range of temperatures which the skin right- ly appreciates is very limited. We shall speak of this range as those temperatures functionally effective for focal consciousness. But just as "physically" there is only "colder" and "warm- er," rather than true "cold" and "warm" or "hot," — thus offering no objection to the notion that temperature series in psychology overlap and possess common parts, — so in psychology, the sensational value of a thermal stimulus is dependent upon its temperature relative to 156 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS that of the human body. Notice this, further- more, — that we say we feel comfortable, that is, neither warm nor cold, when we mean that there are no noticeable thermal sensations, while yet the temperatures of mouth, nose, and ear, for example, are quite a few degrees dif- ferent from each other. To this contrast con- dition, there is only unconscious response. As a "warm" background for sensations, the skin behaves curiously: for we feel a cold stimulus as cold, even while the temperature of the skin affected is rising, — something the physicist would scarcely expect. Other curious phenom- ena of temperature are the paradox-cold and paradox-heat sensations, while even tapping a temperature spot sometimes arouses the tem- perature sensation. A similar curiosity is dis- covered in touch, where the diffuse sensation of light wool can be inhibited by touching with a pencil point the center of the responding area. But all these phenomena, and many others of a like character, merely show that the dermal senses are to be best thought of schematically, but schematically only as comparable to a net- work of intersecting lines and planes, which cannot, however, be reduced to the ordinary tri-dimensionality of Euclidian space. 65. Pain is not the same as unpleasantness, 157 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION for aches and pains can at times possess a curi- ous agreeability. Pain and pleasure, which common sense makes antithetical, have no such opposition in psychology: for pain is a sensa- tion, while pleasure is an attribute of any sen- sation. It is to be noted, in regard to pain, that it has an unusually long latent-period. The child whose cries do not come immediately after its being hurt, can thus be whisked out of the pain series if another class of sensations be properly presented to it. Extremes of tem- perature are called painful, but they do not be- come pains any more than a red becomes yel- low; the common part of both series is the basis for this apparent change in the conscious con- tent. Furthermore, pain-producing spots, though the most numerous of dermal organs, normally function less often than do the others, as result of both long latent-periods and habits of avoiding the adequate stimulus for this sen- sation. 66. If tickle can be aroused by stimulating a hair-clad surface with wool or by drawing a pencil lightly across it, this sensory content is a blend of subliminal touches. Tickle can also be aroused on hairless surfaces, where touch organs thickly abound, and in some cases seems to be interpenetrated with slight, unpleasant 158 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS pain. Other touch blends will be taken up un- der Kinaesthetic Sensations. The point I wish to keep in mind here is that if a rapidly vibrat- ing bristle and other things will arouse tickle, psychologically a spacial numerousness over a large area is the same as a temporal numerous- ness over a smaller one. For psychology, then, numerousness or periodicity is a prior category to space or time. And numerousness is a prop- erty of the cardinal number system, and not a "mental" or "physical" object. Questions on the Dermal Senses. 1. Describe fully both the physical and psychological events in producing some form of touch sensation. Make a list of the attributes exhibited and relate them one at a time, as ac- curately as you can, to the physical stimulus operating. 2. Slowly immerse the hand in cold water, and notice that the more surface that becomes stimulated by the liquid, the colder the con- sciousness becomes. Do the same with hot water and mark the corresponding effect. Then completely cover the hand with dry sand; or better, slowly immerse it in mercury and no- tice carefully that something else happens than in the case of the other two liquids. Enumerate all the attributes of sensation involved in the 159 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION three parts of this experiment, and state psy- chologically the different effects obtained. Kinaesthetic Sensations. 67. We have seen that a point moving over the skin can be sensorially appreciated. This phenomenon includes, however, the items of in- termittence and resistence, which are also pres- ent when we move the skin over a fixed stim- ulus; and these two situations are identical in their cutaneous effects. Now, movement is not a function of the touch organs, and neither is it dependent upon the muscular condition, for there are no muscular sensations, heavy and deep pressures being functioned by the cutane- ous system of deep sensibility, and by organs located in the joints and tendons. 68. The quality known as strain which we find as content in pushing, pulling, long stand- ing and the like is derived from an environment upon which the tendinous sense is contrasted. The spindles of Golgi furnish the specific organs for this response. It will be noted here, also, that strains as sensations are identical with strains in physics. Content and function here coincide. The strain sensation has common parts with certain members of the pain and warmth series in overexercise, while in buoyant health the "springy" step we experience is due 160 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS to the presence of the attributes of clearness and vividness, quite independent of the thres- hold. Strain has an obviously precise local sign in some cases, while in others eccentric refer- ence allies it to the protopathic system in touch. 69. Joint sensations have much the same quality as certain touches, especially the deep- er ones. To the functions of the end-organs of articular cartilages are due these joint or artic- ular sensations. If, before we push a heavy object, we "set" the joint, the subsequent sen- sations are largely tendinous. Now the state- ments in regard to movement are almost never indicative of sensations, but rather of percep- tions. To report that a limb has moved, — just moved, — is of course a sense report, but to say that its relation to the rest of the body or to an- other limb is altered, is no longer a matter of sensation, but of perception. This can be built up out of after-images of former position, united with the present sensory datum, or can be di- rectly related, — but in either case, we more properly speak of perceptions of movement, since the situation contains parts, rather than bare attributes. 70. When one feels a rough or smooth sur- face, not only is touch present, but a certain amount of intermittence and resistence also. 161 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION The reason we do not ordinarily call these con- tents perceptions, is because, if the eyes are closed, we are uncertain as to the physical na- ture of the stimulus, and the loose organization of parts is scarcely sufficient to avoid misnaming the stimulus. So we call them touch-blends in- stead. They are, more exactly, cases of inter- sensational fusion and summation, and as such have many common parts with each other as we shall presently see. For with all move- ments, or with all situations in which the ten- dinous and articular senses are involved, in- sufficient orientation with the rest of the con- scious cross-section produces a condition, the type of which the following illustration will render clear. In the first place, we never know our nerves, and never have any focal conscious- ness of the release of energy into the effector organs. It is impossible to think of the move- ments we go through in terms of specific excita- tion of the moving member, — arm, leg, eye, tongue, etc. We know only late in the game that they have moved beyond the place that is in focal consciousness. Former theorists on the nature of the will have turned over in their graves several times since this was made evi- dent, but it has so far done little good. Active and passive movements alike are unaccom- 162 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS panied by this experience of energy in the con- sciousness they produce. Furthermore, foot- rules are not part of the furniture of the nervous system; and our blind estimation of how far, or how much further we have moved a member this time in comparison to the last is very in- accurate. It takes a whole orgy of sensations to make a satisfactory perception of movement, and even then the part-whole complex they con- struct is often top-heavy with eccentric refer- ence of one of the elements. For with all the senses active, — movement, sight, hearing, touch, and the like, — one expects that his body will be- come an efficient geometer. But in psychology, there are no unequivocal calibrations. The quadrants, sextants, slide-rules, meter sticks, and so forth, which we make and use, are again ad- justable touch, movement, and sight organs, de- rived from countless comparisons with and con- tradictions of data obtained by the naive sense organs, as well as made under conditions in which the natural forces themselves inscribe their periodicities upon receiving surfaces. In comparison to the accuracy of these records, almost all naive perceptions might be termed blends, for as true perceptions they are serious- ly unstable. 71. I shall quote E. B. Titchener's account 163 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION of touch blends, as found on pages 171-2 of his "A Text Book of Psychology," since it seems both thorough and quite in line with the view of sensation as propounded in this book. "The difference between hard and soft, for instance, is mainly a difference in degree of resistance offered to the hand; and this means a difference in the degree of pressure exerted by the one articular surface upon the other. The distinc- tion thus belongs to the joints rather than to the skin. Again, the difference between smooth and rough is a difference, first, between con- tinuous and interrupted movement, and sec- ondly between uniform and variable stimula- tion of the pressure spots of the skin. The dis- tinction thus belongs to joints and skin to- gether." "Sharp and blunt differ, primarily, as pain and pressure: a thing is sharp if it pricks or cuts, blunt if it sets up diffuse pressure sensa- tions." . . . "Wetness is a complex of pres- sure and temperature. It is possible, under ex- perimental conditions, to evoke . . . wet- ness from perfectly dry things, — flour, lycopo- dium powder, cotton wool, discs of metal; and it is possible, on the other hand, to wet the skin with water and to evoke the perception [ ?] of a dry pressure or a dry temperature. Not 164 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the moistening of the skin, but the fitting dis- tribution of pressure and temperature sensa- tions, gives rise to the perception [?] of wet- ness. Other modes of distribution of the same sensations produce the perception [?] of dry- ness. "Clamminess is a mixture of soft and cold: the cold sensations and the pressure elements in the softness must be so distributed as to give the perception [?] of moisture. The clammy feel of a wet cloth may be got by laying the finger on a loosely stretched rubber membrane, and sending a puff of cold air over it at the moment of contact. Oiliness is probably due to a certain combination of smoothness and re- sistance; movement seems to be necessary to its perception [?]. Clinging, sticky feels may be obtained from dry cotton wool." If, then, an identical conscious content can be provoked by two or more differing mechanical means, we can but say that they have common parts: they coincide in the effects they produce. We have noticed this item in connection with the phenomenon of a "touch" becoming "pain- ful," and have dealt with the error involved in such a statement. Further illustrations of the same thing will occur profusely in, for ex- ample, the sense of sight, but we only need 165 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION prophesy here that no "red" ever became a "yellow," as will turn out after the whole band- age has been removed. Taste and Smell. 72. These two senses are very intimately connected in the conscious cross-section by vir- tue of the fact that they blend together so in- veterately. But psychological analysis separ- ates them with ease, and their definite connec- tion with chemicals is quite complete. The taste organs are taste buds, which are calyx-like structures in the papillae of the tongue, parts of the soft palate, the larynx, and a few other places. There are taste buds also in children on the inside of the cheeks, and in the center of the tongue, which, in adults lacks responsive- ness to taste. There are but four primary qual- ities of taste, — sweet, salt, bitter, and sour, — all others being smell-taste mixtures, or compensa- tions and rivalries either in one sense or the other, or between them both. Oscillations are also frequent between tastes of a high intensity. In general, the adequate stimulus is a solution, which is part of the function of the salivary re- flex. Besides, chemical salts taste salty, sugars taste sweet, alkaloids bitter, and the acids sour. However, there are some chemical salts that taste sweet, others bitter, while quite a few are 166 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS tasteless. Too, some few acids taste sweet, some are tasteless, while one, hydrocyanic acid, gives bitter. Very salty solutions slightly burn, and very sour things become astringent or pain- ful. Likewise, sweets in saturated solutions prickle or burn the tongue, while bitters often have a fatty as well as a burning quality. Only solutions taste, whether the solvent be solid, liquid or gaseous, but just as there are salts which do not taste salty, so there are some solu- tions which are tasteless. 73. Taste is easily localizable, being un- equivocally in that complex of solution- tongue. But in taste, one must carefully dis- tinguish between the quality of the taste and the quality or intensity of the solution as well as other things. An apple, let us say, tastes either sweet or sour; but as something eaten, as something in the mouth, there is much more to be considered than the bare taste quality. There are, for instance, the elements of pres- sure, movement, and duration, any or all of which give us the characteristic perception of eating this or that thing. It is known that a jaded palate is more often appeased by altera- tions in duration and pressure concerned in "re- ducing the contrary material to submission" than by alterations of the specific taste ele- 167 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ments themselves. The most interesting attri- butes of taste are fusion, adaptation, inhibition, and contrast, especially as they occur in cook- ing. Lemonade is both sour and sweet, and also a partial fusion of these two qualities. Sweets taste "smooth" and acids "rough," and thus lemonade is a complex of five, if not of six separable things. We sweeten bitter coffee and tea, — nature not having consulted with us in planning the woodside order of these bever- ages. Salads are another case of the "search for happiness" (?), in which concoctions sugar offsets the salt, while both either inhibit or en- hance the oil and vinegar to a slight degree. A strong sweet and a salt make an insipid com- bination, but neutralize each other into a vapid blend, if weak. And so on. The contrast ef- fects of tastes may be either simultaneous or successive, and subliminal sweets often sum up into something focal, which, if based on bare quantity, plots an unexpected series of relations between the two thresholds thus obtained. The latent period of taste, from long to short, runs as follows : bitter, sour, sweet, and salt. But in taste mixtures, this order does not follow the combinations made on a quantitative basis. For while the neutralizations (inhibition) are best in the order: sweet-bitter, sour-salt, salt- 168 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS bitter, sweet-sour,— following slightly the laws of color mixture,— yet new series are developed in the mixing which have their bases in some- thing other than chemistry or physics. Even the time relations of tastes would suffice to de- velop "newness" in the gustatory cross-section. Contrast in taste is more marked than adapta- tion, and adaptation to one sort of solution al- ways leaves the other three intact. Liminal sour on one side of the tongue applied at the same time as a subliminal sweet on the other, may bring the latter to some sort of focality; while subliminal bitter, when applied with an- other taste, is usually present as sweet, if at all. 74. Taste is a difficult sense to study, as one can easily imagine. The mouth must be bul- warked with cotton, and the tongue wiped dry incessantly, while the experimenter, with a fine camel's hair brush stimulates the various pa- pillae. But by dint of patience, the following general facts are well established: the back of the tongue senses bitter, the edges sour, the tip sweet, while salt is sensed by nearly every part of it. Some of the individual taste buds re- spond to all stimuli, while others to but one or two; continued touching of the papillae also ex- hausts their functioning power. The threshold, as might be expected, varies with the amount 169 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION of the liquid taken, but for equal quantities of solution, a 0.27( solution of sulphuric acid, a 0.4% solution of salt and a 1.2% solution of sugar is sufficient to effect a focality of taste. Curiously enough, also the electric current tastes, — doubtless due to ionization, — while with the ears full of warm water in which electrodes are bathed, a sour taste in the mouth results. However, inasmuch as the nerve supply of the tongue is functioned by the vagus, lingual and chorda tympani, such a phenomenon is not al- together anomalous. 75. The curious common parts in the der- mal senses have already been intimated. Chem- ically, there is apparent evidence for allying the various tastes more effectively than there is physically for allying the senses of warmth and cold. The so-called III, IV, and V groups of chemical series are generally sweet-tasting, while the "inorganic, bitter-tasting substances are derived from positive ionization of the I and II groups, and from the negative elements of the VI and VII groups." On this basis the sweet-generating molecule is also potentially a generator of bitter. But much clean experi- mentation is yet to be done upon this sense field. 76. Smell, like taste, is a chemical sense, 170 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS but smell is peculiarly a land and ground sense, used by man only for its nutritive and protec- tive value, and not for such purposes as are em- ployed by those animals in whom it is best de- veloped. We find our food by appointment and not by odor. The organ for this sense is not the total nose, but is a very small, brown patch of mucous membrane high up in the whorls of the anterior part of the head cavity, ciliated and bathed in liquid. The cilia waft forward, also, thus driving those odors ordinarily un- noticed in eating, which rise through the pos- terior nares, out toward the forward apertures, and in this way function a sort of extra sentry- duty upon our food. The cells in this patch of mucous are similar to the taste cells, and the olfactory nerve, which supplies them, is the shortest in the body. Part of the region con- cerned is also supplied by the trigeminous nerve, and there is unusual sensitivity to cold, heat and pain in that area of the body. It is thus doubtful whether one should call the organ of smell and its environs inside or on the sur- face of the skin. 77. Contact is essential for smell, and either vapors or particles can stimulate. The local sign of an object of smell is given by virtue of its position in the cone-shaped area defined by 171 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the apertures of the nose downwards. In gen- eral, those substances which whirl while dis- solving in a liquid can be smelled, but not quite all whirling substances are odorous, nor do all smellable things whirl in solution. Again, some substances must be applied in solution to the brown patch directly, in order to be sensed by this organ. Furthermore, the brown patch is not on the main line of conduction from the front to the back of the nasal passage, but the odors drift and are wafted thither by the cilia instead. In spite of this fact, the threshold is very low, being given as one millionth of a milli- gram of mercapton dissolved in a cubic deci- meter of washed air. There has been some at- tempt to relate the chemistry of smell to the psychology of it, but no one has plotted the series very far or very assuredly, since smell is even a more diflicult thing to test than taste on account of sudden exhaustion and adaptation. 78. While there are but four original tastes, there are several hundred smells, sometimes ar- rangea in classes, but without well determined bounds. Aromatic odors certainly differ from the vapors of dried fish, but in psychology, there is frequently as much "difference" between the near together as between the far apart. This may be politely analogous to the status of rela- 172 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS tives and strangers. Some smells also taste sweet, others bitter, while some are instantly painful withal. Some arouse tingling, some tears, and not a few nauseate. The inessential attributes of smell largely constitute the sensa- tion, since adaptations, fusions and inhibitions are especially frequent and potent. The curve of qualitative intensity falls with exceeding rapidity during the first few seconds, as every boudoir enthusiast knows. But smell mixtures are possible in smell in a way not quite known in taste. There are two brown patches, one in each nose, and the nasal passages do not unite that far forward in the head; thus one smell can be led to one nostril and another to the other, so that there can be an effect produced for consciousness not referable to the single, separable organs alone. The "position" of smells, therefore, is not necessarily in the space of our forefathers. Smells will also mix in the same nostril, just as tastes on neighboring pa- pillae. But smell mixtures are less stable than color mixtures, and there is also no clear cut antagonism in this field as there is in sight. Smell is lacking in the negative after-images we find in the temperature senses and in taste, a phenomenon that allies it likewise with the do- main of sound. Peculiarly special in this sense 173 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION field also is the case of the elevation of the threshold for discrimination after partial adap- tation, thus making contrast here a derivative of one of the temporal attributes of neural release. Hearing. 79. In connection with this modality, it will be requisite that the student have access both to enlarged models of the ear and to charts showing the various dimensions in outline, for a verbal account of so intricate an organ is usual- ly misleading and often fails to flatter the de- scriptive powers of an author. We shall speak, then, of the functions of the various parts, pre- suming some slight anatomical knowledge of the terms employed. Every one of the attrib- utes of sensation is clearly illustrated in connec- tion with audition, and the importance of this sense field being so obvious, it will be advan- tageous to keep in mind the schematization of sensation given in the introductry paragraphs of this chapter, as well as to note carefully the differences between the aural functions and con- tent, and those of the previously discussed sen- sory fields. 80. To begin with, there are three main groups of auditory qualities: tones, noises and voices. The adequate stimulus for audition is air or other vibrations which reach the ear. 174 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS Sound is not all due to air vibrations, for the sound of a tuning fork placed on the crown of the head or on the teeth will be conducted to the receptive surface by means of bony bridges; but vibrations of some sort must set the ap- paratus in motion for there to be a functioning in sound. It must be observed that an air or bone vibration is not a blank flutter. Cases of vibration are cases also of the frequency of the impacts, the amplitude of the wave motion and the form or regularity of the disturbance of the particles of the transferring medium. Each of these has an important finger in the auditory pie. For while the number of the vibrations means pitch, high or low, while the amplitude of the vibrations means loudness, and while wave form is a specifically differentiating element in tones, noises and timbres; yet all high tones are intrinsically loud, and low tones intrinsical- ly weak. Also, by a figure, we call the former bright or thin and the latter dull and broad by virtue of the fact that we habitually see the means of their production. Again, while the wave form is what we mean physically when we speak of clarionets and French horns, we also have the expression "tone color," by which is meant the pitch, "size" and intensity of a cer- tain given tone. Within these three groups,— 175 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tones, noises and voices, — there are exceeding- ly many separate qualities, clear from the lower limit of audibility (pitch) to the highest tone which can become focal in consciousness. These two extremes are called, respectively, the lower and upper thresholds of pitch. The au- dible range extends from about 12 to 40,000 vibrations per second, but the recognized musi- cal scale is between 40 and 8,000 vibrations only. The letter "s," which occurs so frequent- ly in language, is almost at the upper limit of hearing, as can be made manifest by compari- son with notes on a Gallon whistle. There is also another very important threshold in sound, and that is the duration threshold. Any note, to be heard distinctly in its physical pitch, must be represented by at least two vibrations before it has value in the diatonic scale. Otherwise it will not set into operation the mechanism of the ear sufficiently to arouse a tone sensation rather than one of noise. For noises are crowds of still-born tones. 81. The function of hearing is partly ac- complished by a mechanical apparatus of the following kind. The outer ear, or concha and external meatus, are together a funnel for re- receiving sound. They together form an unob- structed opening into the head, the external 176 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS meatus ending at the tympanum, or drum. This drum is a tough membrane of fibres radiating from the center, and performs an adaptive function as well as its function in hearing. It is likewise protective, especially in its collabora- tion with the action of the Eustachian tube, for we prevent rupture of the ear drum by keeping our mouth open in the presence of sharp explo- sions, thus equalizing the pressure of the air on both sides of the drum. By means of at- taching a very small convex mirror to the tym- panum and observing the play of reflected beams of light cast on the surface of the mirror, ob- servers have been able to detect with sureness just what part the tympanum plays in the hear- ing of certain sounds. The tensor tympani, — a small muscle attached to the hammer bone, which acts torsionally upon the tympanum, — is observed to contract with the increasing in- tensity of the tone. This function does not op- erate in connection with pitch, except insofar as the highest tones are intrinsically intense, as noted above. At a sharp sound there is in- stant contraction of the membrane, barring of course the latency required for such adjust- ment. After the drum is "set" for a certain intensity, it vibrates as a whole sympathetical- ly to the number of vibrations in the generating 177 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION body, and even vibrates in partials when the overtones of the stimulus note are relatively strong. We speak here particularly of notes in the middle register of the musical scale. Not only does the drum vibrate pro tanto with the stimulus, but the small bones in the ear do like- wise; for clear to the oval window the separate vibrations can be traced along the bony chain, which has been especially studied in the vibra- tions of the stapes when the tympanum is en- tirely absent. The general function of the or- gans of the middle ear is to vibrate freely as a whole to moderately low and mildly intense sounds. But the higher in pitch and the greater in intensity the sounds become, the tighter be- come all the loose parts in the external and middle ears. Thus the function of hearing some things is partly accomplished without ref- erence to anything but a mechanical apparatus, insofar as the transfer of sound vibrations half- way into the organ is concerned. Nevertheless, the one-to-one correlation above indicated is but brief in the series of sounds, and the disor- ganization of our expectancy begins even at the tympanum. For here vibrations of a relative- ly great amplitude and slight strength are turned into ones of smaller amplitude and greater strength. Furthermore, the tympanum, 178 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS when stretched, becomes a functioner of entire energy rather than pitch, for the amplitude of its vibrations in this case is very much de- creased; while if the tensor tympani is cut, the vibrations of the hammer head are considerably increased. These two additional items must also be noted : first, that if a sound is led to but one ear, the other ear functions it by conduction through the bones of the head and the Eustach- ian tubes, and second, that persons who lack the ossicles, still hear very high and very low tones. 82. Before taking up the interesting mass of material in audition which better concerns the psychologist than most of the discussions about what becomes of the vibrations after they are prodded into the oval window by the foot of the stapes, we had better outline in brief the general nature of neural functions in regard to periodicities in general. For the concept of periodicity includes not only such things as air- vibrations, but also such things as roughness, smoothness and a few other phenomena in the dermal modalities. We saw in connection with the senses hitherto considered, that if one be- came frightened as to how in the world the qualities of sensation managed to get into con- sciousness, there was nothing to do but to in- 179 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION voke the general mysteries of nature, or necro- mantically squeeze the nervous system until something like a reality oozed out. With hear- ing, as in the other senses, we shall not have any need to waste wonder over how the vibra- tions get heard: vibrations do not get heard, — they get counted. Vibrations are not all there is to tones, noises or voices: the vibrations are the part of these phenomena which are open to the investigations of physics. The part not specifically physical, but specifically psycholog- ical— (and call it psychological and nothing else, if the grumbling spirit moves you) — consists of things we call tones or other qualitative audi- tory phenomena, which, insofar as they are cor- related by the physicist, are said to be dependent upon vibrations; but which, as apprehended by the psychologist, are something else than this. Besides, it is not up to the psychologist to tell how he hears, but literally only what he hears. As for the physiologist, he may clip his tensor if he wishes, but if he does, it is no gauntlet thrown down to the physicist or the psycholog- ist: it is his own boomerang. The central fact of psychological data is the principle of order, — what I have elsewhere called series, — and it has been shown that the attributes of sensation are series for the most part of no temporal or 180 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS spacial character. The name in physics for these series or orders is periodicity of vibra- tions, while the physiological name for them is electro-chemical waves of neural discharge or release. However this does not make the nar- row strip of territory between physics and physiology called Psychology a petty and in- digent principality doing homage forever to its aggrandizing neighbor kingdoms. For only a few even of the mathematical sciences can claim to be based upon series which have a full quota of members. In physics, in chemistry, in physiology as well as in psychology, there are many series which cannot muster all the terms inferred from their point of origin and their subsequent development. Nevertheless, in this connection the point to be made is that not all things are physical nor chemical, nor yet "men- tal," but whatever partial orders there are in these and the other sciences, they frequently exhibit the phenomena of the common part. Here it is that many curious things often hap- pen in science on account of the hasty desire of theorists to rigidly apply throughout a science a principle that is exhibited only a little ways in the data they have honestly observed. 83. Thus the only reputable theories of hearing, of sight, of emotion and any other phe- 181 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION nomena are bare enumerations of the facts ar- ranged according to whatever principles of or- der are manifest. As is the case with other sciences, the data of psychology define their own dimension, and as observed before, neces- sitate the use of a system of terms in need of no apology in the presence of the other sciences. If, then, one asks how hearing is functioned, the answer is that the orders or series of audible things are partly correlated with physical vibra- tions, partly with neural periodicities, which are not vibrations of the nerves at all, but waves of neural release corresponding to the period- icity of the impacts of the stimulus. The con- nection is functional; whether there be identity now and then is neither a case for exultation nor alarm. Within the ear, then, we have seen that the organs in the air-filled spaces of it have a definite functional as well as mechanical re- lation to the sounding stimulus; but in the liquid chambers of that organ, the case has not been altogether facetiously called "a watery cor- relation between hearing and hammering"; for the action of the basilar membrance with its "harp of a thousand strings" is itself the definer of a new order of relations between stimulus and content. For this membrane, directly an element in the neural tissue, translates the phys- 182 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ical impacts into neural releases of such a char- acter that the content of consciousness is iden- tical with the qualitative character of the sounding and vibrating stimulus. The sound may be in the head, by virtue of bone or even air and nerve conduction, but it does not origin- ate in the head, nor is it hurled from the brain as a sort of by-product. The sound may be in the head, in the ear,— in fact anywhere you please,— but it is IN whatever is stimulus as well as content of consciousness. For the conscious cross-section includes the knowledges of every- thing, whether it be the introspection upon our poor relations, or our observations of and in- cluding the librations of the moon. 84. To give exactly the relation between tones, noises and vowels (voices), I shall cite the unusually significant and clean experimen- tation of Jaensch. He placed a selenium cell in the circuit of a telephone which was illum- inated by an arc lamp whose light was varied in its continuity and steadiness by the revolutions of an obstructing disc. This disc, moreover, was so cut about its edge that the variations in the length of its radius corresponded with the variations in height of any sound form-curve. By means of this apparatus he demonstrated that (a) a constant rate of vibration produces 183 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION a tone (e. g. mean variation of zero), (b) the same average rate of vibration produces a vow- el-like sound if the mean variation from the average is still small, but (c) with the further increase of the mean variation the sound, after passing into the vowel character, passes again out of it, until, with the mean variation being very great, nothing but noise is produced. Thus he showed that the average rates of vibration of the letter sounds, m, ii, o, a, e, i, s and ch are very nearly octaves of each other in an ascending series. But this octave connection is not in- clusive of the fact that the vowels are neces- sarily to be identified with certain tones, even if the prolongation of a vowel at a steady pitch always necessitates its being based upon some note in the musical scale. Thus vowels are something of tones and something of noises, though no octave connection exists between noises. Noises can be produced with striking resemblance to the musical scale, by the drop- ping of sticks of uneven length upon a flat sur- face. Orchestra players know very well that the "attack" required in sforzando passages is an actual noise. The relation between these three sorts of auditory qualities can be further elaborated by saying that with the increase of variation in the number of vibrations per sec- 184 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ond, there is a corresponding decrease in the definiteness of the pitch. But this scheme is best at about 1000 vibrations per second, for it waxes as one ascends or descends the pitch series, ceasing altogether at both 32 and 32,000 vibrations. 85. The physical analysis of sound waves shows two main patterns of vibration: periodic and non-periodic. A periodic wave is one in which the same movements are repeated, how- ever complex, during equal periods of time, however long. A non-periodic wave is wholly devoid of regularity. The periodic waves are subdivided into two lesser classes, pendular and non-pendular, these terms referring to the sim- plicity of their form. Thus the pendular waves represent pure tones, such as are produced by bottles and tuning forks, the form of the wave being a sine curve; while the non-pendular represent such tones as are produced on musical instruments, being accompanied by a series of overtones or partials. Voices and noises thus are composed of non-periodic sound waves, dif- fering in their percentage of regular interrup- tions as indicated previously. 86. Every contained volume of air as well as every more or less regularly (or orderly) shaped physical object, whether solid or hol- 185 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION low, has its own specific rate of vibration, which can be aroused not only by mechanical impacts, but by the surrounding air being thrown into suitable vibration. The vibrations which act thus as a stimulus, however, need not be the same in number as that of the sounding body of air or wood, for example, but must be related to it according to the laws of overtones with whose series it has a common part. We shall illustrate this in the following manner. When the low C string of a Cello is vigorously struck, not only is that particular tone sound- ing, but a great number of harmonic tones, gen- erated by its automatic division into halves, thirds, fourths, fifths, sixths, etc., in which case the tone of the string may be compared to the base of a veritable pyramid of sound, the har- monics being fainter the higher they are in pitch. They all appear simultaneously, of course, their number and intensity being part- ly dependent upon the intensity with which the ground-tone is struck, though a few of them are implicit in the fact of their being any ground- tone at all. If the low tone be C, its first over- tone, being generated by the string vibrating in halves, will be a note of the same name, but its pitch will be an octave above the generating tone; the second one will be G, one fifth above 186 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the first, being generated by the string vibrating in thirds, and so, as in the table following: Amount of string Tones and Over- Name of Note vibrating to tones produce it Ground tone c Entire string First overtone c half Second g third Third c fourth Fourth e' fifth Fifth s' etc. Sixth b' flat* Seventh c" Eighth d" Ninth e" Tenth t" sharp* Eleventh S" Twelfth a'"* Thirteenth b'" flat* Fourteenth b" " natural Fifteenth c Now mark well this sign (*) in the above scheme. For where it occurs it means that the notes so designated are all too flat to be used in the diatonic scale, even though they were generated out of "pure nature" and represent the natural development of overtones from a low, generating string. Even a Stradivarius or Guarnerius Cello will fail to produce anything more available for music than these, which sim- ply means that the "natural" order of tones as above developed is but one of the tone-orders, coincident at some points with the order of presentable music, but diverging from it at many others. In other words, we use only cer- tain special tones of the "natural" note series in the chromatic scale, discarding those which would clash with some of the harmonic tones generated from certain other ground-tones. 187 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION For when we want an f-sharp that will give keenness to the tonality G, — as the note b-nat- ural does to the tonality C, — we do not select nature's f-sharp as derived from C, (as in the above scheme), but we derive it from a ground- tone D, in which case it will be generated as the fourth overtone of that series. And not only is the whole keyboard scale of the piano made in this careful, searching manner, but even then, the various scales are tempered to each other, so that transitions from one key to another will be possible enharmonically. That is we employ the note midway between G and A, for instance, as either G-sharp or A-flat, depending upon the tonality about to be en- tered or passed through. This account may briefly suffice to give a hint as to the intricate nature of the series of tones, whether due to pendular or non-pendular vibrations. The point to be made in passing is, that just as the lowest string of the Cello arouses its popula- tion of overtones, so will any sounding body tend to throw into vibrations any other body within effective range, whose natural rate of vibration is the same as its fundamental or the same as one of its partials. But we shall meet with a corollary to this law in connection with difference tones, 188 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS 85. Strictly psychological is the matter of tonal intensity. Two notes, equally intense, when played together, will not produce a re- sultant of double the intensity. If one asks whether it is 3/4, 4/5, or any other fraction of it, no answer can be given. It is not less, to be sure, nor is it twice as much, but as hinted at before, the intensity series rarely consists of anything but primes. We met with much the same situation in connection with the dermal senses. The eccentric reference of a local- sign as exhibited there is paralleled in one of our responses to notes which are near the low- er limit of audible pitch. If the note 30 vibra- tions be produced on the Ebbinghaus acoustical apparatus, and carefully attended to, it will ap- pear to have a recognizable pitch, and be heard in its proper place in the series. Now let the note of 60 vibrations be sounded, noticed, and followed by the previous lower tone, and the observer will detect that the lower note was formerly heard too high, thus indicating that the straight, linear series of tones in physics, became curved at its end to the unaided ear, so that almost any note between 25 and 32 vibra- tions per second would have appeared of the same pitch. Here then would be a case of un- changing sensory content with changing stimuli, 189 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION a thing not so very different, so far as series are concerned, from the phenomenon of various means producing the tickle sensation, or the sense of pain. 86. We have mentioned so far three thres- holds of pitch. There is now a fourth to be considered in connection with the phenomena of fusion, summation, contrast and the like. This is the threshold of pitch difference, and it has been just treated in one of its aspects in the previous paragraph. Pitch differences are determinable both by a simultaneous and a successive presentation of the sources of sound. In physics, they are settled by recourse to graphic and other methods, but in psychology they are referred to the ears, for it is by them alone that we gain criteria for the use of tones in the realm of art. To come closer to the point, a pedantic physicist would hold up his hands in horror at the use of certain tonal arid harmonic effects in an orchestral symphony. Nevertheless, the physics of sound does not include the element of the esthetically satisfac- tory character of the resolution of a dissonance. However, the series of objects which have standing in psychology are just as empirical as those in any other science, as the reader who has followed me is well assured. An orchestra 190 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS or chorus frequently inhibits many a serious tonal error by the dynamic qualities produced by its ensemble. 87. The physicist is acquainted with inhibi- tions in the action of interference tubes. An- other kind of inhibition is found in the phe- nomenon of beats. Beats are a function of the difference in the vibration rates of tones simultaneously sounding. If we have two sources of sound, one of which vibrates 100 and the other 102 times per second, there will be 2 beats per second. Which is to say that twice each second the two wave systems will coincide and produce a maximum sound (mu- tual reinforcement), and twice they w^ll be half a wave length apart, and then the sound will all but disappear. Now physically, we might expect there would be as many audible beats of the same character as the numerical difference between the vibration rates of the notes simultaneously sounding to produce them. However, a significant divergence at once ap- pears in the qualitative aspect of the increasing difference between the generating tones. For there are four well-marked qualitative stages in beats, which are a psychological series rather than a physical one, whereby it is again seen that various kinds of quantities and intensities 191 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION may be co-present in any conscious content. Between two notes from one to six or seven vibrations apart, the beats have a well-marked "swell"; when the vibration difference is be- tween eight and twenty, a "sudden rise, pointed- ness or thrust" is manifest; at a difference of twenty to thirty, a rattling effect is produced; while the roughness that characterizes a dif- ference of about forty vibrations disappears entirely at some fifty vibrations per second between them. What then appears is con- sonance, rather than dissonance, and we have fusion in the result as opposed to the previous effect. Again, if we keep increasing the dis- tance between the two tones, some roughness constantly appears until another musical in- terval is reached, and so on, as far up the scale within an octave as we care to go. Thus the musical intervals might be considered in one aspect as primes in the beat-series, for no graphical record of them would give a hint as to the places where fusions of consonance pop up as it proceeds. Of psychological inter- est, again, is the differing qualitative and quan- titative character of the fusion value of the various intervals generated by the beat series. This is evidenced by the fact that the musical intervals which in linear series are the unison, 192 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS second, third, fourth, fifth, and so on are not better and better fusions in this order, but in another one entirely, — this again not deducible from the physical aspect of tones. Let me indi- cate in a table the relations between the two series. I. Order of appearance II. Order of fusion of of intervals in the the same intervals: beat series: Minor second Major second Minor third Major third Fourth Augmented fourth Fifth Minor sixth Augmented fifth Major sixth Natural seventh Major seventh Octave Octave Fifth Fourth Major third Major sixth Natural Seventh Minor third Minor sixth Augmented Fourth Augmented fifth Major seventh Major second Minor second The second column above is a trifle individual, but even then it represents the matter fairly. The series of fusions thus given appears once more to form quite an independent series, a series which may be exactly termed the second derivative of beats, but which again in a strik- 193 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ing manner harks back to physics in this way, — that these intervals are the same as those derived from the harmonic notes of the "nat- m-al" vibrations of strings. The simpler the ratios of the above intervals, furthermore, the sooner they appear in the natm-al system of overtones. 88. But yet another set of empirical data is to be presented. Beats produced between two very high notes, say about 1,000 vibrations per second, show only one stage of the above four qualities: they chirp rather than rattle or roughen. Again, the two lowest strings of the Cello when sounded together in the seemingly consonant interval of the fifth, produce beats; just as any two low notes, no matter how con- sonant, (barring the octave and unison), lack the smooth character of the same intervals in the middle register of the scale. Beats can also be produced by two dissonant tones when each is led through a tube to either ear, even when the separate tones are inaudible. This phe- nomenon is due to the action of the bony ap- paratus of the middle ear, and is termed "bi- naural beats". Substantially the same phe- nomenon is met with in many other modalities besides sound, but oftener as a fusion-resultant than as a case of inhibition. There is at pres- 194 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ent some inclination among students of tone to consider pitch as equivalent to local-sign, and to regard the musical intervals in the same way as the fusion of two touches or colds upon the skin surface. Accordingly, if only a few beats per second were present, there would be an intermediate locus for the beat-tone of three or four vibrations per second, but insofar as the musical scale is concerned, its "position" would be assimilated by one of the generating notes. Following this, the concept of tones as a linear series would have to include the attrib- ute of bi-dimensionality. Hints as to the prob- able correctness of this view will appear in the general treatment of the psychological nature of the scale, soon to follow. As a matter of fact, beats are heard as "fluctuations of a single tone, whose pitch is indistinguishable from that of the generators". Upon increasing the difference between them, the number of beats actually functions a tone quality, recog- nized as an intermediate tone, "which at first lies near the lower generator, and gradually rises in pitch until it approaches the upper", granting the ever-widening distance between the two generators. At the point where the beats become rough, however, the tonality of 195 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the intermediate tone which carries them is lost, and we hear only its noisy aspect. 89. Another singular datum is the differ- ence-tone. When two notes in the medium or upper register thirty or more vibrations apart are sounding together, there will be heard an entirely new tone, very deep in pitch, of as many vibrations as the arithmetical difference between those of the generators. This might well be called the undertone, in distinction to the overtones previously described. Under fa- vorable conditions, also, as many as four or five of these undertones can be produced, whose pitches coincide with the following scheme. Let a be the vibration rate of the upper generating tone, and / be the vibration rate of the lower, and Dl, D2, D3, D4, D5 be the sym- bols for the various undertones, then Dl= u —I, D2 = 2/ — u, D3 = 3/— 2u, D4 = 4/ — 3li, and D5 = 4iz, — 5/, etc. The final important tonal phenomenon to be mentioned is the interruption tone, which has strong alliances with the item of beats. The number of times a tone is interrupted, as espe- cially evidenced on the siren, — but not the siren that deceived Ulysses, — becomes the vibration rate of a new tone, whose difference from noise is significantly correlated with the periodicity 196 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS of the interruptions. The tone interrupted may also combine with the interruption tone in two ways; either as a summation efitect, evidenced by a note of the combined pitches, or by making a difference tone, in the manner Jillustrated above. In the case of both difference tones and sunmiation tones, it is to be kept in mind that they are often generated within the ear, and localized furthermore within the head, at a point midway between the two tympani. This corresponds to the eccentric reference men- tioned in connection with the protopathic sys- tem of the touch organs. By the use of resona- tors, however, some of them can be made the subject matter of physics as well as of psy- chology. 90. The musical scale presents an impor- tant problem in psychology, independent of the mechanical system which produces it. Two tones in unison and two tones an octave apart are more fused than any of the intermediate intervals of the scale. It has been previously shown that both beats and musical intervals are produced by steadily increasing the differ- ence between two generating tones; but what the nature of the scale, as a case of order with- out exclusive regard for physics is, has not been settled. The intervals of the scale, as fusions, 197 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION are not in the same series as they are in the series of increasing pitch differences, for the interval of the fifth, for example, which is mid- way in this latter series, occupies the second place in the fusion series, and the second and seventh, as musical intervals, both lie at the upper end of the series of fusions. The other intervals, likewise, are dispersed in the transi- tion from physics to psychology. They are of course, both in the conscious cross-section, in- asmuch as we know their separate character- istics, indeed, almost better than we can speak it out. But physical instruments of measure- ment, in addition to being detachable sense or- gans, respond usually by means of the efferent nerve of a different sense than the one they were constructed to be an adjunct to. Espe- cially is this so in the case of sound, where the best we can get from physics is a graphical record and not an improved psychological ear. So that when one asks what the scale and the fusion intervals constitute as an organized sys- tem for psychology, he must consider all the data investigated, and find his ultimate order in what we are as psychologists often led to call our favorite interpretations of the facts. At the same time in strict logic we discover that they are often those principles from which 198 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS all the data originate, whether they be the stuft" of physics or of any other realm of investiga- tion. Let us then consider the grounds for regarding the scale as something other than a simple, linear series in but one dimension. The pitch rises, to be sure, and as it does so, the scale ascends to the octave of the original note. Yet in so doing, it ends, from the standpoint of fusion, where it began, or at least nearer to that position than at any other in the physical order. Schematically, then, it loops back to a point on the perpendicular erected upon the starting point, but in the transition, it extends farther from the perpendicular at the interval of the second and seventh, than it does at the fourth and fifth, making also other curious twists and returns before the whole gamut is passed through. 91. It is not my intention to state any solu- tion for this intricate problem, but only to show why it cannot be regarded as a serious one. There are other orders than the rational, other dimensions than those handed down as a leg- acy from Euclid, and the fusion order of the musical intervals does not perplex any one who understands the havoc time plays with deduc- tion, as already illustrated at every place where opportunity afforded. Some problems are 199 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION solved by sheer brute force, others by the appli- cation of analogies, and still others by being dropped. Expectancy is not the cue to the cor- rectness of an answer, and in regard to this question of the "rationality" of the fusion in- tervals of the scale, it can be readily shown why the order of preferences takes precedence over the order of vibration ratios and their geometri- cal relations to each other. This is the evidence : (1) To determine the fusion values of the various intervals, one must ask for preferential judgments from musical subjects. (2) Likewise, one must ask unmusical sub- jects whether they hear one or two notes in the interval, and how clearly they hear them: fu- sion being a case of partial inhibition. (3) Judgments of the amount of fusion are within the realm of "psychological quantity", — a series, by the way, which is as likely to contain all primes as it is to contain other integers of an ordinal relationship. (4) While the intervals of the octave, fifth, fourth, third, and the like are correlated with the mathematical ratios of 1/2, 2/3, 3/4, 4/5, 3/5, 5/6, 5/8, and so on, and while the geomet- rical ratios between them may be exactly specified, the simplicity of these ratios does not compare with the simplicity of the conscious 200 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS content produced by them. Besides, no constant geometrical ratio exists between the ratios of these intervals, unless they are arranged in a series conflicting with them as a series of pref- erences. Even then it is poor. 1/2 is 3/4 of 2/3, 2/3 is 8/9 of 3/4, 3/4 is 15/16 of 4/5,— so far very well; but nothing whatever can be done with such ratios except to lay hold of their simplicity as an evidence that fusion has evident mathe- matical correlates. But this is saying nothing more than that correlative simplicities are found between physics and psychology. This is good news, to be sure, yet it requires nothing beyond psychology to tell us that a fusion is a psychological simplicity. Search for all other information is quite unnecessary, and the in- sistence that physics and psychology should co- incide at every point is but a symptom of fatuous hankering after causes. The fusion series is, whatever else it may be, psychological, and as such exhibits the independent status of some of the data of psychology. That it is em- pirical, and open to any investigator who cares to inspect it, goes without saying. For be it well remembered that nothing was ever taken out of the public universe by its being called "mental", the mental for all practical purposes being only the "not yet mentioned". And some- 201 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION thing specific has been said on a previous page in regard to unformulated statements, which does not need repetition here. 92. It will be sufficient, in the brief space yet to be devoted to sound, to indicate only a few cases in which the attributes of sensation particularly apply to this modality in a way not evidenced in the other sense fields. The strictly qualitive character of intensity has been shown in connection with intervals, and it as well applies to chords of three or more notes. The latency of sound is very short, muscular reactions to auditory stimuli being the quickest of the sensori-motor releases. Sounds made on musical instruments with many and strong overtones have a roominess (extensity) greater than that of the sounds produced by such in- struments as the flute, which is weak in over- tones. Duration and after-image concern us in the question of the discrimination of pitch differences. If two tones are successively given to us to distinguish as to pitch, the interval be- tween their presentation, the length of presenta- tion, and the character of the after-image will all determine whether by a good ear they shall be judged to be the same or different. Ordi- narily, 64.0 vibrations is in this way just dis- tinguishable from 64.15 vibrations per second; 202 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS and 2048.0 from 2048.36 vibrations. In an ex- periment performed by Dr. H. T. Moore in The Harvard Psychological Laboratory on Conson- ance and Dissonance, it was shown that after listening to the prolongation of two tones a dissonant interval apart, the two generating tones became inaudible after four or five min- utes, — nothing being heard thereafter except the rattling of the intertone localized within the ears. This illustrates the attribute of exhaus- tion. Adaptation is too well known, as in cases of the street cars and city clocks, to need further comment. In symphonic music is ex- hibited to a striking degree many phases of the phenomena of fusion, contrast and clear- ness. Vividness is well illustrated in the case of the exceedingly low degree of intensity required to elevate the bel canto passages of music into focality. Fusions furnish a hint as to one function of consciousness underlying the feeling-tone of sounds, while the pleasantness or unpleasantness of human voices are directly referable to the status of their owners in the social self. Local sign will be especially treated in the sections on space perception. In this connection, also, the vestibular organs of the ear will be functionally related to the responses of orientation. 203 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION Questions on Audition. 1. State briefly, and in the order of their importance, the significant diff"erences between the physics and the psychology of sound. 2. Which of the attributes of sensation appear first in a melody (succession of single notes), as contrasted with those appearing in a harmonized melody (two — , three — , or four- part combination of tones) ? Vision. 93. The gross structure of the eye can easily be demonstrated by means of models, charts, and by the dissecting of a specimen. Structure need concern us only in its connection wdth function, to which we at once turn. It will be sufficient at the start to indicate merely the course of a beam of light upon entering the eye and its various effects upon that organ. The cornea is of interest chiefly in cases where it is misshapen, — in astigmatism, — that has to be corrected by the use of eyeglasses which, according to the laws of optics, make up for its lack of regularity. Behind the cornea is the aqueous humour, and behind that is the iris, which acts as an accommodation apparatus, functioning the intensity of light. It thus en- larges or reduces the size of its aperture accord- ing to the diminution or increase of intensity, 204 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS unless inhibited from doing so by drugs. Its latency is long, as everyone has experienced when going suddenly from a sunny room to a dark one, and vice versa. The lens, which lies behind the iris, possesses a unique accommoda- tion apparatus, likewise, and functions the distance of the stimulus. Muscles at its edge pull it flat or push it into a thickened form, with somewhat less latency than occurs in the iris reflex. However, loss of the lens through an operation for cataract does not preclude the possibility of vision, for a certain correctly- made artificial eye-glass lens will restore the visual function nearly to its normal. In the case of wearing such an adjustable sense organ in front of the eye, it is ditficult to draw the line between the physiological and the physical, functionally construed. Similarly, in the use of tele-, micro-, stereo-, and pseudo-scopes, the eye does not end at the cornea, inasmuch as the conscious content we obtain by the use of these instruments is functioned for by the com- plex of eye-instrument, and not by the use of the eye alone. The function of the lens of the eye is the same as that of any bi-convex lens, and by means of it the rays of light entering the eye are projected toward the retina. If the eye-ball is too long, and the incoming rays of 205 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION light do not reach the retina, a concave lens is used in eye-glasses to remedy this defect, known as near-sightedness; if the eye-ball is too short, as in far-sightedness, the rays focus behind the retina, and a convex lens is used instead. In either case, as before, the functioning eye is constituted out of all that goes to make up the vision apparatus in or about the head. 94. According to the laws of physiological optics, the stimulus for vision is the image of the object on the retina. But this is not a fair statement of the case in psychology. The stim- ulus for vision is the object which one sees, whether it be something one can also touch, or whether it be some impalpable object in a dream or an hallucination. Of these stimuli for vision, there are two: colors and shapes, which, as has been mentioned before, may be anywhere. By color I mean anything one sees which is not a shape, thus including those con- tents called grays, whites and blacks, as well as the usual spectrum effects. Insofar as the image on the retina is concerned, it is in and of the object, just as is the wave-length of solar light: just as we hear tones rather than vibra- tions, so we see colors rather than the numeri- cal status of their wave lengths. In the same manner we smell smells, which may be mem- 206 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS bers of the III, IV, and V groups in chemistry as well, and we feel cold and warmth without first determining their position on the ther- mometer scale. In pain, the distinction between stimulus and content is even more strikingly made. The history of experimentation upon vision is murky with the conclusions which have been drawn from half-baked tests upon the action of the eye, — cases of the experimenter knowing everything that was going on, and of the subject being interpreted as having only that knowledge which the experimenter chose to favor him with. Bishop George Berkeley showed that we never see depth, but this was only another case of the "unthinkable having been carefully thought out". By flashing a pencil of light into the eye at an oblique angle, Purkinje showed that one could see his own optical blood vessels out in space, for what reason and with what conclusions heaven only knows; while a certain Le Cat demonstrated, by means of a card and a pin held up before the eye inside of the focal distance that every- thing we see is upside down! From all these and similar tricks of opticians one needs to be emphatically warned. We may not see depth, but we perceive that some things are nearer or farther than are others; and groans need never 207 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION arise from the fact that the retinal image is inverted. The retinal image is not a datum in the psychology of vision, nor do we ever see or feel it. Furthermore, objects are seen right side up, indeed just as they are, for the psy- chological status of the retina is one of func- tional dependence, and psysiological optics holds mortgages on nothing in the eye except the bare physical aspect of the watery media, the cornea, and the lens. We saw, in connec- tion with sound, that certain series had com- mon parts in physics and psychology, while certain others did not at all. In vision, how- ever, we shall see that color sensations are even less tangential to the series of physical de- terminations than was true in the case of auditory qualities. What else can it be than a downright subtraction from fact to palm off on science a single insignificant phenomenon for the whole cross-section of vision, and to insist that the parts which make up a whole in physics are the only kind of parts with which men of empirical minds can have anything to do? 95. To cite another as well as a last case of artifact in vision, the images of objects fall- ing upon the retina are said by some to proceed to the brain, thence to be "projected" outward into the air into or on top of the object of sen- 208 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS sation in order that vision may be accomplished. This is not only absurd, but more than that, it is a contravention of the entire data involved. In the first place, the "image" never gets into the brain, no more than does the object which functions by it: the very last place where ob- jects sequester is the clammy inside of the skull. The "image", solely an optical datum, is scarcely more than a datum for the uncon- scious retinal mechanism; it is not a content of visual consciousness, — it is solely a content of inferred consciousness for the student of physiological optics. Nothing gets into the brain at all in vision: the stimulus, or object, sends light into the eye, and this light acts adequately upon the sensitive membrane known as the retina, thereby releasing the neural energy along the neural connections to whatever cerebral localities the function of vision may have specific reference. Objects outside of the head; releases within the head, — nothing more: the periodicity of light waves and the periodi- city of neural releases being functionally re- lated and that is all. The actual numerousness of the ether vibrations maij, indeed, be the actual numerousness of the pulses along the optic nerve, but that would never necessarily 209 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION make the optic nerve yellow or blue while functioning for those particular colors. 96. It is interesting to note that there are two axes of the eye. Where the optic nerve enters on the nasal side in either eye is the point which defines the origin of the optical axis. This does not coincide, however, with the visual axis, which is determined by project- ing a diameter through the center of the cornea and the center of the lens, thereby making it strike the retina farther from the nasal side than the optic nerve lies in its circumference. Both of these axes are important: the optical, for it defines the blind spot where there is no functioning for vision; the visual, for it defines the spot of clearest color vision, known as the fovea. Now the optic nerve, upon entering the eye-ball, spreads out in all directions, covering the inner surface of it, and is further formed into minute terminal organs, known by a simile as the rods and cones, which point not toward the light, but directly away from it. At the fovea there are only cones, and at some distance outwards they cease entirely; beginning at the periphery there are only rods, which decrease in number significantly toward the fovea, and ending at that point. The cones function for color and the rods for whites, 210 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS blacks and grays, as well as for the shapes of visible objects. Nocturnal animals have only rods, while diurnal animals usually have both: it is thought that birds and fowls in general have only cones. Nevertheless, these animals do not appear to distinguish what we specifically sense as spectrum colors. In human beings, it is to be remembered, there is a larger area covered by both rods and cones than the retinal space covered by either alone. 97. The following list of visual sensations are to be considered: (a) the chromatic, or spectrum color sensations, which are developed best by beams of light passing through prisms; (b) the white-black-gray series, or achromatic sensations, whose relation to the former are yet to be in all points determined; (c) the color sensations derived by mixing the chromatic and achromatic together; (d) the sensations derived from textures such as pigments produce in so- lution or spread out on surfaces; and (e) the shape sensations of objects stimulating the retina. One significant thing to be noted in connection with chromatic and achromatic sen- sations is the paucity of names for the various reds, greens, and grays that are constantly sensed. Another quirk in terminology comes with the determination of the elements one can 211 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION name m every color as distinguishable from each other. As a usual thing, hue is the term which means the point in the spectrum series we are referring to in our naming; tint or brightness applies to the likeness of the spec- trum color to pure white light; while chroma is taken to mean such things as "the blueness of the blue", and refers to the amount of gray or black not at the time stimulating the reiina. 98. Physicists have offered correlations for these three factors in color vision. Correlated with hue is the wave length of the ether vibra- tions. The longest wave lengths are at the red end of the spectrum, while the shortest are at the violet end, the wave lengths decreasing with ordinal steadiness from red to violet. On the other hand, the changes from color to color are not so steady. For instance, there is much more red than yellow in the spectrum, and much more violet than green, as any casual observer of the rainbow must have remarked. Again, there are many more distinguishable yellows and blue-greens packed into a small linear space than there are hues of any other color. This applies for a constant and equal spectrum intensity only, of course, but the independence of the physical and the psychological series here is nevertheless well marked. Again, even apart 212 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS from the fact that wave length is sometimes correlated with a difference in chroma, (as evidenced by the fact that the most naturally saturated colors are red and blue, and the least yellow and blue-green, — chroma thus being a correlate of wave length as well as of wave form), the wave length as it changes also brings a change of tint, or brightness, yellow being the lightest and violet the darkest color of the whole spectrum. According to a strict depend- ence upon physics, the correlation of energy should indicate red, rather than yellow as the lightest spectrum color, and blue should be much darker than is the case. As a last case of negative correlation, any sufficiently intensi- fied color is seen as white, and the minimum visibile, or the smallest area of stimulus pos- sible, is always seen in the achromatic series. Contrariwise, any sufficiently enfeebled color intensity is functioned as colorless, — on the dark side of the white-black series. This phenome- non applies for diminution of intensity, also, as well as for the extent of the chromatic surface. 99. If one fixates a spot of white on a gray background, while a disc of some color is brought in from the periphery to the center of the visual field, certain changes in the appear- 213 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ance of the stimulus will be noted. It will first appear doubtless as an amorphous gray, then as a disc of some color allied to the actual hue, and finally as a clear steady chromatic sensa- tion. For different colors, the results will be different; some of the hues will be sensed truly at first focal functioning, while others may pass through several curious stages. The upshot of such experimentation is to ally the extent of cone-covered retina with the functioning of the colors by the retinal apparatus in a very definite manner. The retina has zones of unequal sen- sitivity to the various hues : the inner zone func- tions for red and green, the next outward for yellow and blue, while the farthest zone, toward the periphery, sees everything as a series of light and dark grays. The spectrum, when thrown upon this outermost zone is likewise devoid of chromatic character. But these zones are not as distinguishable in function as the above statement might imply. They are weak, rather than blind to the colors they imperfectly function, because sufficient extent and intensity of a stimulus in the periphery can bring out the known hue perfectly well. In moving a patch of color from the fovea to the periphery of the field, it is found that it will keep its color longer than when the stimulation moves in the 214 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS opposite direction. High degrees of energy and brief periods of stimulation are more effective than those of low energy and long duration, which is a principle we found illustrated in certain phenomena of dermal sensitivity as well. But this correlation of intensity with threshold of clear color vision does not necessarily mean intensity as the physicist construes it, for the intensities one meets with in psychology were seen earlier in the discussion of sensation to be other than of a numerical status, — the in- tensity as well as the extensity of sensation being in a prime series. Vision offers full sup- port to such a scheme of empirical classification. 100. Among the numerous thresholds met with in vision, the following will suffice as a sample of their nature. The minimum visibile is a threshold, just as is the maximum visibile, or the largest patch of color or visual stimulus which can be seen at one time. These two thresholds would define one sort of series, — the bi-dimensional space series. Another threshold is the color zone threshold for each and all of the colors. The threshold of color identity, of identity in tint between any number of chro- matic or achromatic sensations, of the greatest differences in saturation, or the least; the threshold of shape discrimination in the peri- 215 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION phery of the eye, and similar phenomena are samples of the extent to which this attribute can be applied. Any terminus ad qiiem, how- ever defined, could without fancy be called by the same term name, 101. Now while the spectrum appears as a straight band of hues, psychologically it cannot be regarded as such, since various properties of color forbid such a looseness in terminology. In the first place, for every spectrum color, or hue, there is another spectrum color, which, if mixed with it, will produce an achromatic sen- sation. Thus red and blue-green, yellow and blue, and the like, when mixed together, neutral- ize each other. But hue, or spectral series reference is lacking in the resulting conscious content. Schematically, therefore, we shall have to regard the spectrum as some sort of a closed series, possibly ovoid rather than circular. The trans-sensational infra-red and ultra-violet se- ries need not be as "long" series as that of the visible hues, for since the spectrum is a dis- persion phenomenon, apparent distances in the spread of the dispersed light may be but one of the natural series, and not by any means the fundamental one. There is no need, on the other hand, of insisting that the logic of color, —the principle of color clarification, — be lim- 216 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ited to the ordinary concept of two or three dimensions. The properties of color mixture, color contrast, after-images, and the like point not to a fundamental principle which maintains the naive naming of colors as the ultimate basis of their existence. 102. Before stating that principle as it should be formulated, let us examine the phe- nomena which make it both necessary and in line with induction. As to color mixture, not only will certain pairs of spectrum colors pro- duce a gray, but two colors out of such gray- producing position in the spectrum series will produce a hue dependent upon the relative amounts and intensities of the two colors, with a variation in saturation or chroma from the originals due to their nearness or remoteness in the color series. Here one must keep in mind the facts of intrinsic intensity and saturation of the spectrum colors as outlined previously. Again, the double mixing of pairs of colors fol- lows the same laws. Two gray-producing colors will, if mixed with two other gray-producing colors, produce a third gray whose tint is usually the arithmetical mean of the two combinations. In the same manner, red and yellow, which give or are that hue we call orange, will, if mixed with a green-violet blend giving a blue of low 217 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION saturation, produce a purplish gray. The formu- lation of the laws of color mixture is easy within certain limits. For example, the first law can be stated: C= , in which gray(G) is derived c from any two complimentary colors, repre- sented by C and c respectively, — complimentary referring to position in the spectrum series. The second law can be stated in a formula as fol- lows: w.l.Ci + W.I.C2 ( Ci C.C,= 2 which reads: the mixture of any two non-com- plimentary colors (Cj.Co) will give a third color whose wave length (w. 1.) is intermediate be- tween the first two; in which combination, furthermore, the hue of one color (C^) will predominate over that of the other (C,) in proportion as its intensity and quantity (i, q) are greater. The third law of color mixture may be symbolically stated by the use of the expression, 103. Now, so far as psychology is concerned, identical contents, such as result from fusion (color mixture), are expressed in the same 218 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS terms, — that is, by expressions of identity. Many stimuli are painful, and many combinations give gray. And while psychological simplicity is never to be confused with logical simplicity, yet the "new" things in psychology are just as much terms in science as are the physical terms of the stimulus. For we saw that the fusion intervals in music were a series, just as were the vibration differences which produced them. Psychological simplicity, or naivete, must be sharply distinguished from the perception of prime relations between non-physical proper- ties; all we urge is that the chronogenetic order be not taken for the logical one without suffi- cient warrant. As it is, the two may sometimes coincide, but the point is that their coincidence has importance only after inspection rather than before it. 104. Color mixing is not only possible with lights, but with the use of rotating discs, con- taining various sizes of sectors of pigment colors spread out on various textures. If such a disc is fixated, while revolving, various phenomena will be observed. Suppose the disc to be equally divided between two colors, say yellow and blue, to the right and left of the vertical respec- tively. One vertical half of the retina will then be blue-stimulated, the other half will be yel- 219 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION low-stimulated. Upon rotation of the disc, that half of the retina formerly stimulated hy the blue will first be gradually and then completely stimulated by the yellow half of the disc, and so on, — the alternations of stimulation compar- ing with the spacial relations of the two rotat- ing colors. The colors are thus retinally mixed. However, a certain rate of rotation is required before complete fusion occurs. At a low speed only a flickering impression will be produced, which phenomenon is actually not one of hue as such, but of tint or brightness, — the speed required to abolish flicker being greater with the brighter colors. The "likeness to white" of the rotating colors is thus actually seen as a partially isolated element. When fusion is finally accomplished by the above means, it is due to the fact of positive retinal after-images, for if the blue sensation had lasted no longer than the blue stimulation, a gray resultant would never have been produced. Part of the stimulus lags behind the temporal duration of visual presentation, thus making one of the terms in color mixture which is independent of the physical nature of the stimulus. In mov- ing pictures and fireworks the same phenome- non of after-images is to be observed. The fol- lowing special aspect of flicker is also note- 220 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS worthy. Before the threshold of fusion is reached, two kinds of flicker are observable, — coarse and fine; and the brightness of the coarse flicker is even greater than that of the resulting, fused sensation. Besides, upon let- ting the impression of the rotating disc fall upon the periphery of the eye instead of directly upon the fovea, the number of rotations of the disc per second required to abolish the flicker is considerably greater. The function of the rods of the retina has been previously shown to account for this. If, now, one compares color fusions with tonal fusions, he will see a differ- ence between them on the side of physical quantity. For upon steadily increasing the dis- tance between two tones, after fusion is ob- tained, the consonance is at once exchanged for dissonance, after which, consonance once more appears, then dissonance, and so on in alternation. Whereas, after color fusion is ob- tained on a color wheel, no increase in the rotation rate will make any alteration in the character of the fusion so produced. Indeed most analogies of physical quantity have but slight value in psychology. 105. Fixation of a color does not always result similarly. We never adapt to the noon- day sun, on account of its intensity, but are 221 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION always exhausted by it. Besides, such fixation results in the provocation of negative after- images of long duration, the number of them which simultaneously occur being dependent upon eye movements which partially rest one part of the retina, only to be followed by the reappearance of the partially inhibited sensa- tion through irradiation and sympathetic induc- tion from neighboring, over-stimulated areas. For the retina is so sensitive that such a strong stimulation as naked sunlight becomes almost an inadequate stimulus, as is evidenced by the inability to make out the sun's form directly after the first instant of fixation upon it. The combination of intensity and extensity here passes one of the upper thresholds of visual sensation. Fixation of milder colors than the most intense, causes adaptation, by which we mean that every color in the middle range tends toward neutrality, — that is, grayness. But the color does not become grayer, any more than red ever becomes yellow: for all colors are a combination of hue, tint and chroma, and "fad- ing out" or "becoming yellow" is the naive name for the fact that either the total sensation is altered by exchanges of identity, or that some physical essential property got called by the name of a psychological inessential. Never- 222 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS theless, through adaptation, the color of blue or brown spectacles becomes less than focally conscious, and wall paper not faded by the sun looks less bright or colorful after a while than it did at first. The fixation of a colored field until it fades (incorrect expression!) followed by the fixation of a gray field, is accompanied by the negative after-image. But this is no enigma, as we shall presently see. 106. For when the eye fixates a colored field, and the after-image replaces the stimulus, both conscious contents are identical in some constituent element. The hues interchange, it is true, but the brightness or saturation remains constant. Color sensations thus oscillate about some identity in their component parts or at- tributes. The color blind person, who asserts that my red books are of the same color as my green ones, asserts for tint, perhaps, what I assert for that complex known as hue-tint, or even hue-tint-chroma. We saw that the laws of color mixture indicated the gray relation be- tween complimentary colors, and that the tint and chroma of colors are stated in terms of the gray-white-black series of sensations, which terms strictly apply to the fusion of colors into their neutral components. Similarly the laws of the mixture of non-complimentary colors 223 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION laid their main emphasis upon hue as modified by tint and chroma, specifying the intrinsically intense effect of the contributing elements. Now, whatever color may be, the hues as qualities refer also to positions in the spectrum series; which, as evidenced by its various phenomena, is neither linear, nor spacial, nor anchored irre- vocably to quantity. Mixing non-complimentary colors toward the red end of the spectrum series showed a numerical resultant that was half of that of the other two colors; while the mixing of red and black, for example, does not give a wave length one can find in physics in the same way. Bare numerical values give small aid here. The colors, called by simple names, — "experienced" if you please as undefinable states of consciousness, — hold an altogether dif- ferent relation to each other than either the physicist or the introspective psychologist have yet been able to discover. I propose to give that relationship as well as possible, in the brevity of space here available. 107. The intensity, or brightness of a color is its one essential attribute. Hue is incidental. This intensity is its psychological intensity, (correlated with its wave length or amplitude, outside of the realm of psychology as far as one pleases), and moreover not predicated of it 224 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS before we see the color, but afterwards. It is a variable corrolary and not axiomatic. The yellow and blue which give gray, give the gray w^hich results on account of the fact that inhibi- tory conditions between the hues abolish them, leaving the intensities to be algebraically sum- med into the resultant. Fundamentally, then, the spectrum is a logico-psychological artifact: its linear extent is in no wise indicative of the essential nature of color. The formula C= c points to the systematization of the various colors as schematically represented by a right triangle, whose hypothenuse is analogical with the result of mixtures. Schematically only, however, for there is nothing linear about color, nor spacial either, except as the shape series and the color series have compatible relations in tri-dimensional space. With eyes closed, we see a mean gray which is distinguished only in point of brightness, — the fundamental color attribute. Now that gray which we thus see may be equalled by any two complimentary colors, just as it may be equalled by a mixture of white and black. The hues are positions in the spectrum series, it is true, but their posi- tions are of no importance to the visual situa- tion. The correlating of wave length, wave 225 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION amplitude, and wave form with the properties of color is always done with more or less apology, and we may regard the physical vibra- tions and forms as quite incidental: the various series coincide only with the mathematics strapped for consistency. Certainly a rather tottering basis for color, this numerical fiction; and it is not for psychology to put on a straight- jacket to mollify this incompatibility. Let the two series be as incompatible as they will: apparent homogeneousness is the basis for naivete, — not for logical treatments of data. And yet the question will doubtless be asked, "are not the four so-called psychologically simple colors, red, yellow, green, and blue, more funda- mental than the attribute of intensity"? These four colors look to be unanalysable, while, or- ange, violet and the like, are certainly com- pounds, or at least can be compounded out of the others, whereas no such thing is possible with these four. But, if compounding is to be made the criterion, all compounding ends with the gray series, — gray being the terminus ad quern of intensity, adaptation, mixture and other color phenomena. Why stop with com- pounding at an irrational point? To the painter, the primary colors are red, yellow, and blue, pigments relegating green to a basis of mixture. 226 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS To the physicist, the primary colors are red, green, and blue-violet, yellow being a resultant of admixing the others. While for the physio- logist, the primary colors are whatever few colors can act as equilibrants upon the retinal apparatus, insofar as the color zones of the eye are concerned. Surely that cannot be unlim- itedly primary which in this and that field of fact changes its status so readily. Sciences are fields of functions as well as fields of interests, and if a fact is public property, it cannot vanish into subsidiary importance upon being ap- proached merely from a different angle. Now red, or one of the reds of the spectrum and "something bluish", are the only two colors that retain their primacy throughout the above lists of simple colors; but the basis for this is choice among a multitude rather than an attempt to get behind the spectrum as an ulti- mate series. That only a few of the colors are requisite for mixings by which the others may be obtained, is doubtless exactly the case; but here again psychological simplicity has gotten the upper hand. Red and green equilibrate about gray, and yellow and blue equilibrate about gray also, while all the other selections of primary hues have been made for the sake of finding the fewest spectrum positions which 227 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION will in summation satisfy all the requirements of color. Gray being that about which all these terms of color oscillate, the logical primacy of this intensity is in need of no more defending at present. 108. Color contrast exhibits certain inter- esting derivatives of the fundamental attribute of intensity. There are also two kinds of color contrast, — simultaneous and successive, — in which the temporal and spacial elements per- form their usual unique functions. When a complimentary color is induced during steady fixation, we have a case of simultaneous con- trast. When, again, the after-effect is con- nected with the fixation of a brighter or darker surface than the surface of fixation, the induced or equilibrating color will depend for its inten- sity upon the elements of the background. Often simultaneous induction occurs, — that is, the re- turn of the original brightness and hue during fixation. Successive contrast is shown in cases of fixation followed by eye movements, in which case the complimentary hue and brightness is induced in the after-image. Contrast is due to the mutual interaction of neighboring retinal areas and is a differentiating process. Adapta- tion, on the other hand, is a function of dura- tion and acts as a leveling process. The gen- 228 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS eral laws of color contrast are as follows : Con- trast varies with the degree of antagonism, and with the nearness of the juxtaposed colored sur- faces or lights; it is enhanced hy the elimina- tion of contours or boundary lines, is greater when there is no simultaneous light contrast, and increases not only with the saturation of the inducing colors, but also with equal tex- tures, as well as with very simple patterns. However, prolonged experimentation and use of large fields of comparison, both reduce the con- trast eiiects. There is therefore both a time and a space threshold in the phenomenon. This is new in psychology, and is something like the newness of fusion. For colors that are con- trasted as well as fused produce an effect not deducible from either naive acquaintance and expectation, nor yet from a study of color effects not involving contrasts and memories of them. 109. Another function of intensity is the Purkinje phenomenon. If we increase the amplitude of the light waves in the spectrum, gradually the yellow and the blue, with a light gray between them, will be the only hues vis- ible, while the orange and red will appear yel- lower and yellower, and the blue and violet become indistinguishable from a bluish green. But the whole spectrum shortens, both ends 229 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION losing their stimulating character. On the other hand, upon decreasing the light energy of the spectrum we get another series of effects. This time orange and yellow drop out entirely, the red gets very dark, while blue and violet fuse into a bluish-violet, with only the green retain- ing its place and hue. Furthermore, all that now appears is of dark tint and low chroma. The amount of physical change in intensity necessary to produce either one of this pair of phenomena is called the photochromatic in- terval. Besides, it occurs only to a dark-adapted eye, that is, one that has been accommodated to the dark room in which the Purkinje phe- nomenon is being exhibited. Neither will it appear when thrown into the eye on that col- ony of cones known as the fovea. There being no rods at the fovea, the evidence points to this phenomenon as being functioned by those organs. It might be added that the Purkinje phenomenon has the smallest photochromatic interval at the extremes of the periphery, — the permanently dark-adapted or nyctalopic part of the eye. The rest of the retina is hemeralopic, or normally day-adapted, — that is, suited for hue and mean degrees of brightness. Daylight and twilight vision are in evidence when we come suddenly from light to dark rooms, just 230 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS as adaptation is noticed in coming from the yellow lighted theatre after a matinee into the sunlight, where, by contrast, everything looks bluish until the equilibrating functions of the retina have readjusted the field. The colors in hangings and carpets are often selected for their day and night effects, and modern cloth shops sell by artificial light such goods as are to be worn under similar conditions. 110. Evidences point to the rods as the functioners of daylight and nightlight vision. And the specific sine qua non of this function- ing is a substance in the rods known as the visual purple, or rhodopsis. It is a reddish substance, reacting to intensities of light. Under a bright illumination it becomes first red, and then white. Immediately a pigment in the rods creeps up and covers the rhodopsis, thus throw- ing them out of action. When the light is dim- med, the pigment cells retract and the visual purple first yellows, and then whitens. In the owl, this photochemical substance is covered by day, while in the night it is uncovered. The owl having only rods, his day-blindness is thus accounted for. If one eye be kept closed while the other is receiving stimulations which affect its rhodopsis, the same effects will be produced in both eyes by sympathetic induction, — so uni- 231 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION fied are the functions of both retinae. Inasmuch as the bleaching is most quickly accomplished by green, and most slowly by red light, its con- nection with the functioning for intensities, and especially night and day vision, is indisputable. 111. Flicker and rivalry (oscillating inhibi- tion) may also be obtained binocularly. One eye may get a negative after-image of an object given only to the other. A black patch and a white patch, binocularly combined in the stereo- scope frequently produce a silvery lustre, in which case not only the white and black, but the textures of the surfaces bearing them have to be considered. Something like this we have previously met with in connection with the Purkinje phenomenon, — I mean the silvery gray in the green section of the spectrum series. Bin- ocular sensation in this case is combined from right and left eye sensory contents separately brought to focality, and thus binocular lustre is a prime in this series of eif ects. When .flicker is present by virtue of separate stimulations to the two eyes, it can be reduced by giving the same speed in the revolutions of the stimuli to both eyes separately as would be required with one eye directly. Two combinations of flicker separately given to the eyes take the same speed to reduce as is required for both 232 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS eyes together. But when one eye gets a flicker effect, while the other eye gets none, the flicker- ing efiect is considerably dampened in the total, semi-fused content resulting from inter-ocular functioning, even despite a considerable range of brightnesses in the flickerless half of the visual field. Another binocular phenomenon is found when, by giving two difli'erent bright- nesses in the visual field to the eyes separately, a brightness slightly above the mean of the single sensations is produced. This ceases, how- ever, when the original differences are very great, but rises significantly with dark adapta- tion. It is absent, again, when a dark field is presented first, and when the dark area is very small. Question on Vision. 1. Arrange the colors of the normal spec- trum according to greatest-to-least intensity, and then according to greatest-to-least satura- tion. Compare these two series, singly and to- gether, with the "natural" succession of hues from red to violet. How many points of iden- tity do you find in these three series? How many similar tendencies do you find? Discuss fully the psychology of color from the above standpoint. 233 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION Perceptions, Meanings, and Speech. 112. Perception differs from sensation in point of structure. Sensations, as representing the attribute-thing relationship, were seen to be cross-sections of series whose terms were to a large degree prime to each other. One might well have wondered what could be de- duced from their relationships, for so fre- quently were they isolated, that bare enumera- tion seemed the only introduction and farewell they permitted. Nevertheless, simple exhibi- tion is all the scientist owes to elemental prop- erties, and to treat as blunt matters of fact things which exist solely as neutral elements, is the only fair course to pursue with them. The elements of sensation are not mental, for one must go to them without presuppositions. And after one has deduced from them what seems to be their terminus ad quern, he must again frankly apply himself to the facts in order to eliminate the cavalier element from, his con- jecturing. On the other hand, perceptions are examples of the part-whole relationship, sub- sisting in a complex of simultaneously or suc- cessively existing sensations which have a defin- able logical structure or unity. It now being necessary to distinguish between attributes and parts, we shall first say that for psychology there 234 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS are more specific properties of a whole consti- tuted out of parts, than there are specific prop- erties of a thing made of attributes. There is, indeed, a geometrical increase of such proper- tics for wholes over what it is for things. Again, sensations refer principally to sensory recep- tiveness or sensory acuity; while perceptions refer more to the motor element in conscious- ness, — the multiplicity of possible responses to the same stimulus embedded in different con- texts. 113. Now the parts in a perception are both sensations and relations between sensations. A patch of red is held up before my eyes, and along with other reactions, I respond to the duration of the stimulus, whether by adapta- tion, exhaustion or what not. But if a patch of blue replaces it and gets noticed as blue, and if my consciousness becomes verbally expressed by, " 'red and blue' supervenes the conscious- ness 'red' ", with any additional relational con- scious content such as, "two after one", "one more", or "formerly one, now two", I am per- ceiving rather than sensing. Or, to take a more familiar example, "that black thing", or an object whose color quality alone is being func- tioned, would be a sensation, in contrast to "that black thing" as "my black silk hat", which 235 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION would be a perception. It is not a case of the intensity of stimulus that makes the diflerence, but of the relations between the sensations, and in this particular case, what I am going to do about the object stimulating my retinae. It is on the basis of the "with-for" relation that per- ceptions obtain a rank as focal, forwarding elements in consciousness, — a thing sensations never get. In sensation the time element is reducible to now, the space element to here; while in perception the time and space elements are never more simply expressed than by the compound expression "here and now", their relation of togetherness being for perception, at least, indissoluble. Not that the attributes of duration or extensity in sensation have to change clothes in order to be valid in percep- tion, but only when duration is present as some- thing partly focal and partly fading out of focality, has the lower threshold of perception been passed. Similarly, the spacial element, expressed by the word "here" means a sensa- tional element, if everything is equally "here." It becomes of a perceptual status, however, if, at the same time there is a "here," there is also another portion of the content better expressed by the contrasting term "there." Considerable warning needs to be assimilated at this point. 236 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS There may be in logic, but there is not in psy- chology' any necessary distinction between "here" and "there" when these terms are used isolatedly. Do not say that consciousness is the same as speech, for it is not; neither fall into the egregious blunder of verbalizing the item re- ferred to by verbal symbols. There is a logical consciousness, and there is also a verbal or speaking consciousness; just as there is func- tional consciousness, and a conscious content logically separable from it. Sensations are the warp and woof of perceptions, and perceptions are the stuff out of which logic is made, but that does not allow one to say that the series is symmetrical. Furthermore, the logical dis- tinctions cannot be applied to the sensational sources of consciousness as focal elements re- siding oginally in them, for the finished pro- duct is never the cause of the materials. Thus "here" and "now" as elements in sensation need have no relational status to what is not here or now. For "then" and "there" might never occur, and indeed, never do occur, to one not engaged in logical considerations, sensation being merely the present, immediate qualitative and quantitative consciousness, and as such out of relation to other and more complicated forms of consciousness. 237 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION 114. Space and time have had but slight consideration up to this point. Their relation to sensation and perception is rarely treated with candor. "How do we experience space?" and "What is the psychology of time?" are questions over which much obscurity has been indulged in. It is said, and with truth, that the retinal image of a square table-top viewed obliquely is by no means square. It is, in fact, a spherical surface, with four spherical angles, whose sum is greater than that of the four right angles of the table-top as a geometrical surface. In this case, we are told, memory is invoked, and expectation as well, and many a fatuous explanation as to how the table-top is perceived as square ensues. Likewise in the case of time. A half hour in the captivating theatre, as the classic example, is shorter psychologically than the half hour spent in listening to a ser- mon; and then we are slyly asked just how we gain an experience of time, with nothing more to depend on than such psychological data. Now let us frankly admit all these facts as well as many more. A person blind from early in- fancy, who, in later life, has his sight restored, cannot tell the difference between a cube and a sphere if he has nothing more than his retinae with which to function the object. Also, a 238 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS blindfolded subject wlio is asked to tap contin- ously an interval given only once or twice by auditory stimulations, will, in the course of the tapping, enlarge some intervals and con- tract some others, remaining steady and accu- rate only when the "indifference" period exists between the stimuli. But when all our senses are active, there is a geometrical increase of ac- curacy in space and time judgments, and so when the question of dermal, visual or auditory space and time perceptions is up for discussion, we always have to remember that a whole has properties not implicit in the properties of the parts; and also that while visual space, — audi- tory space, — and dermal space-perception, when occuring singly, are all poor, yet, that a summa- tion of space perceptions as given by all these means together is far more accurate than their combined effects would arithmetically indicate. Similarly, in the case of time. Besides, as spe- cifically mentioned before, we have some other means whereby to determine spaces and times than by our naive sense organs, either singly or in combination. Our physical instruments of precision, — mathematically true eyes and ears that they are,— not only function to correct the errors of naive perceptions, but even to cor- rect their own errors as well. Therefore, to 239 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION speak of space and time perceptions as being dependent solely upon the unmathematical sense organs is an example of deliberate self abasement and self delusion. 115. But let us nevertheless exhibit just the extent to which naive space and time are in need of correction. Let us also examine the data by which we ever got the hint for the de- velopment of self correcting devices in the at- tempt to infinitessimalize space and time. In every science, the taking of a set of measure- ments involves the determination of the result- ing value. "Only when" is the scientists' goal in an experiment, and not the goal determined by his expectation. Otherwise, Paddock calls, and careful analysis of the results always show a "trace" of faking. Control of the conditions without hindering the freedom of the function to be investigated, is all the experimenter can ask, though frequently some slight bonus for doing so is smuggled into the final reckoning. But whenever we wish to find some such datum as a threshold, let us say, we take not one, but many measurements. These measurements are not identical, to be sure, but they always group themselves about a common terminus ad quern, — about a standard, average, or mean, which may or may not be one of the recorded measure- 240 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ments. Now this grouping about an average is significant, in that it usually defines what is known as a curve of probability, or a Gauss curve. Such a curve represents a tendency of, rather than an identity between, the measure- ments, — just as we spoke of the threshold being a quantitative tendency. It is not something peculiar to psychological measurements, but is met with in every set of scientific determina- tions. Not only is this central tendency im- portant, however, but also is the percentage of deviations from it, as well as their amount pro rata; for often two averages, derived from two independent sets of measurements will be the same, while the deviations from these averages will be the only thing significantly describing their differences. It then becomes necessary to pause and see just what numbers mean in such a situation. The rougher or finer the work is done, the greater or less general deviation from the central tendency will usually occur; but in any case, the result sought for will have to be admitted to be not some such unvarying quantity, such as 8, but only a quantity greater than 7 and less than 9. And if any one be dis- appointed at this, his disappointment of course comes about through the fact that to infinites- simalize space and time, whether or no, involves 241 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the fallacy of regarding continuity of measuring as necessarily bound up with the discreteness of recorded measurements. Curved lines are not a succession of tiny straight ones, and the mean, or average of a set of determinations is quite useless without their average deviation from that average. This is also why we speak of the diameter of a circle as its most accurate dimension, since the circumference, which is in the prime relation of "tt" to it, is incommen- surable. 116. Of the many methods possible in ex- perimentation, I shall outline but three. The method of mean error consists in having the subject himself reproduce the quantity of the standard measurement as closely as he can. Given a vertical line on a card, whose length he is to reproduce in a horizontal line, for example, the time intervals between the exhibition of standards, and both the accuracy and time taken to reproduce the line are recorded. Exceed- ingly great variability appears in the results of such a method, as one might expect. The other two methods, the limiting and the constant, are more fruitful, — all the conditions being pre- scribed by the experimenter. The limiting method consists of presenting graded variables to the subject, who judges them in terms of each 242 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS other, giving such answers as "greater," "less," "equal," and the like. Now, in such a case, not only do simultaneity and succession play a big part, but such things as the Tightness or leftness of the standard from the variable. The num- ber of measurements often taken in such a case is enormous, in order to cover all the possible permutations and combinations. Furthermore, the threshold may be obtained in four ways: (1) by taking a variable greater than the stand- ard and decreasing the amount between it and the standard until no difference is observable; (2) to start with two equal stimuli and increase their difference until one is much greater than the standard; (3) to start again with two equal stimuli and decrease one below the value of the standard; and (4) to start with one variable way below the standard and approach it, as in the first case above, (1). The constant meth- od consists of an irregular presentation of vari- ables along with the standard, with no regular series of differences between the pairs as pre- sented. One reason why these various methods are all employed is that with different material different methods are desirable, so as not to interrupt the function to be investigated. Be- sides, too slight differences between the pairs of stimuli are deadly to the selective attention 243 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION of the subject, anaesthetizing him against the ability to discriminate. For when only contra- dictions and negations result, they are taken to mean that one is on the wrong tack. 117. This will give an indication, not only of the method employed to find thresholds and the like in sensation, but of the method to de- termine naive space and time estimation as well. If we wish to know what "similarity" in psychology means, we take stimuli in which there is something identical, as determined by all possible means, and present them to a sub- ject who has not yet made such a determina- tion. Whatever he takes or mistakes (no dis- tinction here) for identity, is made the basis of similarity. Without any slur on his intelli- gence, the subject in an experimentation has only to keep even-minded and naive, — it being the business of the experimenter to plan un- expectancies and keep from coaxing results. That is to say, the experimenter regards the data of the experiment as lying in several series, but the subject's responses are narrowed to the one series about which certain information is desired. They both know equally what is go- ing on, except that the subject is not prepared for the exact order of the presentations. 118. Psychological things have as much be- 244 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ing as have any other things. Strictly speak- ing, there are no illusions. The psychological order is not the only order into which things get, and by virtue of the world not being a charming and fragrant unity, we have contrasts, contradictions and incompatibilities. Thus the bent stick in water is both a bent and a straight stick, the refractive power of water being a perfectly empirical fact. The psychological (naive ocular) stick, and the physical stick ex- ist cozily together; the one that is bent being made both of wood and of the index of refrac- tion for water, and of certain properties of the eye, while the straight stick is made of wood only. If one be asked whether the stick is bent or not, the answer cannot be wrong, no matter how stated; for the question is put in ambiguous language, not specifying which stick is meant. Every so-called illusion is either due to a tricky question, or to the fact that but one sense is operative where normally all the senses giving data germane to the stimulus contribute to the perceptive consciousness. Naive space and time determinations are not therefore illusions, but merely and frankly terms of series exist- ing with, while being more or less opposed to, those determinations made with that set of de- 245 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tachable sense organs known as instruments of physical precision. 119. If the subject closes his eyes, and a pencil be drawn over the skin of his hand, and he be asked how long a line it traced, his an- swer will be naive and erroneous. Our skin is not pock-marked with calibrations, and hence we do not know such things as dermal inches or millimetres. Yet here naive dermal space and time are clearly exhibited. If a bristle be attached to the tine of a tuning fork and the fork is struck and laid on the skin, we cannot count the vibrations, though they may be sep- arately felt. This is the dermal perception of number. If the subject's arm is placed in a tilting frame and gently moved, the extent of the movement will be stated in terms on the basis of which no accurately calibrated scale could ever be made. A single point placed di- rectly in the visual axis of the eye and moved forward or back with reference to the subject, cannot be seen to have changed its position. If the eyes are closed and a clicking stimulus is sounded at various positions with regard to the head, those back and front will be interchanged in the report almost haphazardly, while those from side to side will get into series compatible with what the experimenter knows, and what 246 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the subject would too, if he did but open his eyes. With the James Artificial Waterfall one can get negative after-images of movement, and of course one asks whether the ribbed belt is actually reversing. The answer is that the physical belt as a whole is stationary, but that certain parts of it which have no position, (hav- ing any position whatever), need not be still. That much of our sea-faring friends as is func- tioned by our timidity, dies in every storm which sets us in a fear, while the ship bearing them may at the same time be making twenty knots in good, calm weather. As with sensa- tion, so with perception; an object is something that will stimulate, and naive perception is not one of the functions of the organism with ref- erence to the stimulus within the encasing en- vironment which can be summarily pushed aside. 120. Naive time perception is a function of several diiferent things. Owing to the na- ture of the sense organs, stimulation produces consciousness which continually alters as to its focus, unless reinforcements arc forthcoming from other means than the stimulus itself. I mean the environment within and without the body. The fading of a sensation out of focality is accompanied by the relational consciousness 247 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION of the change. It may not he called hy any suitable name, but is signalized hy a difference in focality, a wilting, and is accompanied hy a corresponding condition of consciousness name- able either as "hefore-now-after," "less-more," or "more-less," or some such non-mental ex- pression. Again, the wave of neural discharge rises and falls, while, for example, the pulse is beating, or the breath being drawn or re- leased. These general organic rises and falls are the physiological basis of naive time per- ception, and the word "now" means any neural continuity or equilibrium which is homogene- ously focal in consciousness. However, "now" or "the present" may be regarded as just as long as the uninterrupted neural discharge. When a writer says, "Let us now consider, etc.," he means that he wishes his readers to have a focal consciousness whose content is his ideas for just as long a time as it takes to peruse his statements. If the backgrounds of conscious- ness are steadily maintained, "now" is a func- tion of that maintenance. "Now" and "then" are also interchangeable: any reference to events in time past, taken as a whole, means a "then." But the sensorial "now," or the present time, is always short, while the perceptual or logical "now" may be as long as one pleases. 248 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS Tliat is to say, those things which are axiomatic and always dependable are timeless, being in- different to any special time or situation. 121. Time estimations concern such things as the following: the number of objects oper- ating in the sense field; the strength of the first impression, — or the strength of some one of the impressions as contrasted with the varying strength of the succeeding or simultaneous im- pressions; the contrast effects of the sucession of unequal intervals of solar time in a series of presentations; the alternation of sense fields in focality, and similar phenomena. Sometimes the expressions "filled" and "unfilled" time are spoken of, but this means that interest domin- ates the items in the content, and not that the time interval is quantitatively altered. One curious fact in this connection is the "indiffer- ence period." The motor repetition of certain time intervals will be erroneous unless the in- terval is some multiple of about 0.7 seconds. This particular naive "second" is remarkably accurate. Again, if one sits in a chair resting the tendon under the knee upon an elevation too high to allow the heel to be comfortably held on the floor, and starts to jerk the heel up and down, the ensuing reflex will continue in spite of all volitions to the contrary while re- 249 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION maining in that position, and the regularity of the interval thus maintained will be a close in- voluntary standard of time. The sub- and un- conscious always function more dependably than any one sense field, no matter how focal it is. Rhythm may be spoken of as the invol- untary grouping of regular stimuli into pat- terns, the basis of which grouping is in the sub- conscious action of the neural arcs. Multiple, rapidly recurring stimuli are not responded to separately, but they sum into releases as has been indicated before. The initial reflex and the after-discharge are veritable elementary constituents of the trochaic foot in poetry. And no rhythm whatever has been successful which demanded grouping contrary to the elemental properties of the discharge mechanism of the neural arcs. As certain geometrical figures are to lines, so rhythms are to time intervals; the basis for spacial grouping being extensity, that of temporal grouping being intensity. We shall treat of the other features of time in con- nection with space, with which we shall have considerably more to do. 122. The following psychological space- givers are usually enumerated: (1) the bi-dimensional field of the passive skin, 250 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS (2) the bi-diniensional field of the active skin, (3) the tri-dimensional field of the passive skin, (4) the tri-dimensional field of the active skin, (5) the bi-dimensional field of the passive, single eye, (6) the bi-dimensional field of the passive, double eye, (7) the tri-dimensional field of the single and double moving eye or eyes, (8) the bi-dimensional field of the ear, or ears. Smell and taste, as well as the organic sensa- tions, are spaceless, though not lacking in the attribute of extensity. By "spaceless" is here meant that they cannot be developed into per- ceptions that wall square with the readings of detachable sense organs. One dimension can be gotten easily from either the skin moving over a point or a point moving over the skin. But a square, circle or triangle outlined upon the skin is poorly judged to be a closed figure unless the stimulation is intense enough to leave definite after-sensations. Otherwise the first impression of the stimulus will give an eccen- tric spacial reference. A temporal threshold 251 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION must not be exceeded here either, for otherwise, the after-sensation will be excentrically re- ferred. Local-sign, duration, after-image and the like, thus pass over into perceptions. A geometrical figure in metal, when laid on the skin, will likewise require a certain intensity of application to be judged correctly as to its shape. If it has sharp corners, they are likely to arouse pain before its sides fully arouse touch, in which case all the elements in the per- ception of its size will be derived from the vari- ous systems of cutaneous sensibility rather than from superficial (or epicritic) touch alone. A warmed dollar feels larger and lighter than a cold one, if both are laid simultaneously upon corresponding parts of the body, this being due both to the engorgement of the capillaries through heat, and to the numbing of the skin through cold, thereby making the skin itself a tactual stimulus. If a heavy, blunt point moves across the skin surface at the same rate as a lighter, finer one, the judgment of rate of mo- tion will err in point of underestimating the speed of the second. In all these cases of der- mal perception, there must be considered the matter of the "pressure gradient." This refers to the deformation of the skin by the stinmlus. The hand immersed in mercury will respond 252 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS to a summation of touches only at the line of emergence from the liquid. Below that point it will function a mutual inhibition of them. This is due to the exceedingly unusual pressure of the liquid at that place as compared with the pressure of the air above it. Contrast is here the deciding factor. In cases of the pressure gradient, the distribution of pressures from the point of application becomes such that irradia- tion occurs, — a factor which accounts for some of the eccentricity of dermal local-sign, — for some of the outlying areas beyond the stimulus will be subliminally excited, and, by virtue of the lateral pressure of the deformed skin, the non-orthogonal character of the entire stimu- lation will be functioned erroneously in the judgment given. Pain, in its quick lancing down, and cold in its contrasting thrill, are bet- ter localized than those other sensations which have less instant contrast effects, regardless of latency or intensity. 123. Dermal perception of space is also ob- tained by the moving of one skin area over an- other. All three dimensions can be thus exhib- ited, — the vertical, the horizontal, and the third dimension called depth. But this almost always involves tendinous and articular ingredients, and while the threshold of bare movement is 253 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION low, judgments of the extent to which the legs or arms have moved, whether singly or in pairs, are usually quite inaccurate. For example, a slow movement seems longer than a rapid one of the same extent, while the judgment of a blindfolded subject, who determines his two arms to pass symmetrically through the same distance, errs. The movement of the limb mentioned, noticed and kept in focus is always overestimated, though the extent of successive movements is better judged than that of simul- taneous. Along with kinaesthetic sensations, there is usually present either coolness or warmth from the skin due to the fanning of the air by the moving member. This, however, often gives cues as to spacial differences in the resulting perception. Extents of movement, durations, and qualities, — that is, the local sign of the articular elements in toe, hip, shoulder, wrist and the like, together with the massive- ness of the fusions from the large joints, — these are determining elements in all cases of kinaes- thetic perceptions. Curious among the eccen- tricities of naive perceptions is the familiar "size-weight" illusion. If a subject is presented with two objects of similar shape, but of ex- actly the same weight, and takes them both simultaneously and lifts them, the smaller of 254 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the pair will appear heavier than the larger. Furthermore, the larger is not only "better pre- pared for" muscularly than is the smaller, but it gets lifted more steadily and, due to the mus- cular "surprise" provoked by the other weight, gets lifted more rapidly. Other things being equal, the more rapidly a lifted object ascends, the lighter it seems. The experiment is usually set to deceive, and could be called an illusory phenomenon only in point of the verbal report of the subject upon suffering the joke. Other- wise, it is but a case of co-conscious perception as functioned by movement on the basis of in- equality of visual responses to sizes. For the motor setting with which we approach such un- equal objects is usually derived solely from their space relations, and not from the in- tended movements giving a sub-focal, strain pre-sensation. There is such a thing as a yellow consciousness, an angry consciousness, but there is no such thing as a heavy consciousness: we function for weights only by strains. This point of pre-sensation, pre-perception and motor at- tunement will be further treated of in the sec- tions on "meaning." 124. Before elaborating auditory and visual space perceptions, I wish to outline the sensa- tional elements in all perceptions. Under the 255 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION concepts of the attribute-thing and part-whole relationships, sensations and perceptions are differentiated chiefly by the complexity and concatentation of their elements. Perceptions, being linked with motor responses of general orientation, in a way which sensations are not, illustrate the "with-for" relationship in its most significant aspect. The clearest consciousness is perceptual, not sensational or emotional, and the motor acts of the body are not only the sur- est, most maintaining, and least fatiguing, when the perceptual responses are dominant; but per- ceptions at once lead to organizations of activ- ity, judgments, reasonings, clear conceptions in a manner not ever approached by other kinds of responses. Now, those attributes of sensation which lead directly to perception are the fol- lowing: fusion, duration, intensity, local-sign, contrast, and after-image. I shall take them up separately. 125. Fusion in perception. Every whole has properties other than those of its parts, taken isolatedly. There may also be more prop- erties of the whole than the addition of those of the parts would indicate to be the case. Now insofar as fusion typifies wholeness, a fusion resultant manifests the specific properties of a whole. A fusion resultant, furthermore, is not 256 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the same as a simple sensation; for a fusion can be broken up into several sensations, while a simple sensation breaks up at once into at- tributes: besides, the elements of a fusion still have position in space and time, while the at- tributes of sensation do not. It is possible, also, for the "position" of the fusion resultant not to coincide with that of any of the constituting sensations. Nevertheless, fusions give us a clear example of the addition of one and one to make but one, — as is evidenced by the two compass points placed on the skin within the dermal threshold for twoness. In such a case of fusion, also, we have exhibited the fact of the submergence of some of the properties of the parts under the new quality of the whole, or resultant. If, again, such a fusion be gradually consummated and then gradually broken up, one may get a clear perception of change as well as of rate of change, — two factors both of which facilitate orientation in any recurrent meeting with either the elements in, or results of, such fusion. Lastly, identity and contrast may be obtained along with fusion, with the probability that each may supplement the per- ceptual value of the others. For instance, if tickling be produced first by light wool and later by a vibrating tuning-fork, while the sub- 257 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ject obtains both visual and dermal contents from the stimulus, he will dermally sense iden- tities but visually sense and perceive difTer- ences. This will automatically evoke contrast in the resulting consciousness and all of the elements here involved will make a perceptual pattern of larger dimensions than would other- wise be possible. Such an account will fail to satisfy the incurable introspector, — for he wants to know in all such cases how the object is re-presented in consciousness, — not what of the object is first of all just plain consciousness. But this is asking what the "mental" status of an object is,— an item we have long ago rele- gated to the vocabulary of metaphysical pro- fanity. 126. Duration in perception. The fading out, wilting, or sudden onset and release of a stimulus, accompanied by whatever content or process is functionally related to such things, brings with it, or has as part of it, the corre- sponding consciousness in point of duration and its relational aspects. The duration of a content or process means also the passing of a threshold of the perception of relations. This tem- poral attribute of sensations welds them to- gether into the causal or symmetrical relations of perception. It is a primitive and ultimate at- 258 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS tribute, and is to be correlated directly with the rise and fall of the neural releases. Duration, including simultaneity and succession of im- pulses, is a bi-dimensional field, and by virtue of temporal duration we are enabled both to sense together, and sense successively, as well as perceptually function the discrimination be- tween pairs of intensities, local-signs, durations, and so on. The overlapping of neural impulses is the physiological element operating here. 127, Intensity in perception. The more in- tensive stimulations usually capture the final common path, and thus get soonest organized into perceptions. If, also, there be differences of intensity in the conscious manifold, they will be functioned as a series of intensities in addi- tion to whatever other series the stimulations may exhibit. Were it not for differing levels of receptiveness, most objects would otherwise be recorded as "Blob No. 1," "Blob No. 2," etc. A series of psychological intensities in one mo- dality, however, may be contrasted with data from another sense field operating at the same time, and thus better balance and orientation may result. 128. Local sign in perception. The position of every sensory stimulus is more or less de- terminable, and the resulting sensation is func- 259 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tioned as being derived from some part of the spacial order; however, the Euclidian position and the reported position need not coincide. We saw in the case of touch, that when two compass points were placed on the skin within that distance known as the dermal threshold for twoness, that the local sign of the resulting sensation was either absorbed by one or the other of the points, or was referred to something like a mean position between them. Likewise, when only the deep sensibility is left after nerve section, successive, and not simultaneous double pressure alone remains. Now, whether local- sign be a quality peculiar to every direction of stimulation or not, there is soon derived with practice an increased sensitivity to location, and practice also improves spacial discrimination on that side of the body not exercised. In all cases of location, two senses are better than one, and differences of position are responded to better than are single positions. But, as said before, we are not calibrated as meter sticks are, and questions put to us in regard to the sensorial position of things have no right to be couched in terms of the experimenter to the disparage- ment of the subject. Any response is a respect- able datum in psychology. 129. Contrast in perception. Togetherness, 260 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS whether sinuiltaneous or successive, is accom- panied by partially balanced neural responses, and this balance is part of the basis for the per- ception of the pattern of stimulations func- tioned in consciousness. We sense dififerences rather than absolute magnitudes, and this fact has a cash value in perception. Gradual in- creases or decreases in intensity of the stimulus are not usually accompanied by equal slidings in the content of consciousness, but abrupt in- creases or decreases are the rule. The steady "stream of thought" is something which the writer, for one, knows nothing about. Instead of being continuous, consciousness is discon- tinuous, — arguments for continuity on the basis of anything but breath or pulse being incompre- hensible to him. In this connection, it is logical to distinguish between the perception of con- trast and the sensations that are contrasted to- gether; nevertheless, in psychology either may be now primaiy, and again derivative. 130. After-image in perception. Structures are also revealed by duration and other con- tinuing phenomena. The after-image is such a functioner of structure. Both positive and neg- ative after-images, insofar as perception is con- cerned, each add just another term in the series of possible contents derived by the sense or- 261 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION gan. Often in so doing they give common parts with the effects of other stimuli. Thus they relate things which might otherwise go unre- lated for a considerable time, and by lasting longer than the stimulus presentation, they af- ford contrast effects, whereby further bases for perception are established. 131. There is thus nothing mythical in the sensational contributions to the elements of per- ception. We have specifically dealt, however, only with the response side; but inasmuch as the sensation is the object and what it will do, we have only to indicate the way structure is first functioned, — for it is always the object which is a structural experience as well as structurally experienced. Indeed, the object sensed and the object perceived differ in only two respects, — namely, the structure of the neural releases, and the structure of the en- vironment in which it is being functioned. All these structural relations are logical and em- pirical, and have none of the odor of "mental- ity" upon them. 132. Now for space perception, especially as related to the eye and the ear. Let us first bear in mind the fact that the study of space with reference to the naive ear and eye is not a study of how space is made, space never having gone 262 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS through any mill or shop, but only how space and spaciality are functioned. For the study of psychology is principally an analysis of what we already well know, as well as how things get known; and it determines the properties of parts in a whole whose parts are not yet fully determined as to their contributing elements. Consider the following list of sense-fields : Visceral and coenaesthetic sensations. Taste, Smell, Touch, Kinaesthesis, Hearing, Vision. As named in the above order, they represent not only that order in which they are the worst- to-best space givers, but also that order in which they have, with one or two exceptions, the least- to-most structure. Not only this, but they have in this order an increasing number of qualities, and therefore exhibit correspondingly numer- ous instances of variation in the combination of attributes leading directly to perception. Ear Space. 133. The eyes converge and focus, but the ears do not. The tensor tympani contracts upon accomodation, and the tympanum func- 263 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tions sudden intensity in the manner previous- ly described. But ear space is obtained by the relative intensity with which sounds are gotten by the two ears, barring one notable exception, the human voice. This can be very well lo- calized front and back, while all other sounds are in need of being placed well within the lat- eral field of sound with reference to the coronal and sagittal planes of the head. The shell of the ear (concha) also acts as a resonator, and performs a localizing function. There is also a widespread and clearly manifest tendency to locate a relatively loud sound in front of, and a relatively weak sound behind, the head, but just what the zero of intensity (loudness or weakness) is, in such cases, has not yet been determined. Furthermore, the straining of the eyes to right or left causes a misplacement of the sound in that direction, and every reflex tendency of the head adds an element in the determination of space while the eyes are closed. Sounds full of overtones are naively localized nearer to us than sounds poor in over- tones, while the "flatter" of two sounds seems to be the farther away. Fusion in sounds offers an interesting analogue to fusion in touches. If two similar sounds be produced at certain dif- ferent positions with relation to the head, they 264 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS will invariably be heard as one, in spite of the fact that the subject knows there are two of them. The position of the fused resultant will be either, (a) the actual position of one of the stimuli, (b) at a point between them, or (c) eccentrically referred to an indeterminate po- sition. 134. Again, if an auditory stimulus is car- ried toward the head, the localization of it will be functioned with the same result as if, with the stimulus fixed, the head has been moved in the direction of the source of sound. It is the moving things of nature that give us our best cues of position, and ear space furnishes a field in which these operate. Within the internal ear lie the semi-circular canals, as well as two conjoined organs of spherical shape known as the saccule and utricule. The canals are set in the three geometrical dimensions, and are full of a liquid that gets impacts which develop wave forms in the tiny tubes of these canals when the head is moved. Extirpation of them impairs our perceptions of position; but one of each corresponding pairs of canals on either side may be removed without apparent loss of this function. Only when both vertical, or both horizontal canals, for example, are extirpated, will such perception be inhibited. The saccule 265 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION and utricule have on their internal surfaces tiny hairs upon which lie crystals, whose func- tion is thought to be to exert pressure during sudden movements of the head or body, and thus to arouse stabilizing reflexes. Deaf mutes very frequently have defective inner organs of the ear, and the common inability of these per- sons to locate themselves in under-water swim- ming, as to the surface and bottom of the pool, is correlated with this fact. Interesting side- lights upon dizziness are revealed by incidents in connection with our modern conquest of the air. One of the important things that has been shown is to how great an extent the environ- ment of the aviator may be rigidly defined by his aeroplane, with but little reference to the surrounding medium. Spiral somersaults are soon learned without any feeling of dizziness. From a recent magazine comes the following quotation: "A naval airman when flying sea- ward entered a thick white cloud and wholly lost his sense of direction. He only realized that he was upside down on finding that things were falling out of his pockets. ... At length he emerged from the cloud and saw the sea apparently over his head, but was able to right his machine and continue his flight." In rotating the body rapidly, we produce the phe- 266 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS noinenon known as dizziness, which might be classified under sensations of movement, as well as under perceptions of space. It is accom- panied by eye movements, nausea, and dis- placements of the viscera, which, — being less stable than the bones, — alter the center of grav- ity of the body when they are disturbed. In this case also undoubtedly the kinaesthetic or- gans of the internal ear function importantly. Looking in a mirror whose position is suddenly unsteadied will also give a sense of dizziness. Toe-dancers obviate the inevitable dizziness in- cident to their rapid rotation by fixating one object after another before they arrive directly in front of it; or else, with eyes closed and di- rected downwards, they attain the same end. When one observes the eyes of a person who has been rapidly rotated, without any of these precautions being taken, he sees an involun- tary rotary movement of the eyes, called nystag- mus. This nystagmus may be lateral, (that is, the eyes may jerk rapidly from side to side), or rotary, but it is rarely vertical. During rota- tion, there is a tendency to fixate any stationary object, but it soon gets left behind, and we look quickly forward to fixate another stimulus. During this look forward there is no vision. After slowing up, a contrary effect is produced; 267 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the eyes of the subject jerk quickly back and slowly forward, the general effect of this being being to function the surrounding objects as rotating around him as a center. Some people lose their sense of orientation while watching a waterfall, as this is a form of flicker, while in- toxicants, and strange eye glasses, as well as disturbances in the circulation all have common parts in this phenomenon of mis-orientation. Even to pass a galvanic current through the ears produces dizziness, and one may have sen- sations of falling toward the cathode pole in such a case. But neither this nor the oscilla- tions of the eyes accompanying it occur when the labyrinths are removed. 135. In all these cases of confusion, there are several significant things to be noted. In the first place, the organs of accomodation and adjustment act with longer latent periods than allow instantaneous readjustment to an envi- ronment whose relative positions are shattered; and the consciousness generated in such situa- tions is the situation itself pitted against the responses to that other environment which has no especially significant name, but which is mainly functioned by the tonic reflexes that react against all such disturbances. Further- more, while the perception of confusion may be 268 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS a confused perception, all of our responses at any one time need not be confined to those ele- ments which are focally conscious. A confused environment may lie within an unconfused one, and part of the stabilizing influences may come directly from the responses to this other en- vironment. But at the time, these responses are not focally conscious, and need not have any content; they may be treated of entirely in terms of the general somatic momentum, which after all is but a response to whatever stability is present. For human beings are constant functions of their environment, whether they be manifesting sensation, perception, volition, belief, or judgment. And if any one wishes to know what "mystery" lies behind these other stabilizing environments, the only reply is that the non-mental elements which make up both mind and matter have other orders than those into which they may be and are constantly or- ganized as sensory data; and being non-mental as well as non-physical, they have no age nor settled occupation. 136. Of all the modalities, sight is the one which figures principally in spacial perceptions. Not only are the combinations of sight and touch, sight and sound, sight and movement, better space givers than any such two-term com- 269 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION bination not including sight, but also our in- struments of precision are usually adjustable sight organs rather than organs co-functioning with the efferent nerves of other sense fields. Telescopes, transits, sextants, and range-finders, for example, are all visual apparatus, and even the physical measurements employed to deter- mine time and intensities are calibrated into scales which we read with the eye rather than perceive by the use of the other receiving or- gans of sense. The domination of all other spaces by sight space is apparent, and we even employ in more than a figurative sense the ex- pression "seeing is believing," when we are in doubt as to the factual status of the something under suspicion. The functional dependence of perception upon the eye is not difficult to make explicit. No other single organ can re- ceive so many impressions and group them, while at the same time it adjusts itself to their differences, as can the eye. For three sets of functions are implicit in its action, — movement of the entire organ by rotation within its socket; accomodation of the lens by the ciliary reflex; and the color and shape responses quite inde- pendent of these two. The amount of space re- sponded to by the eye so far exceeds that of any other sense organ, that, if by the expression 270 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS "higher sense" is meant the possibility of or- ganized and dependable perception, no modal- ity is in any way superior to vision. 137. Convergence and accommodation are two motor responses of the eye which aid sig- nificantly in space perceptions. Convergence accompanies accomodation, and any intense stimulus for vision will set going automatic ro- tation of the eyes to bring the object directly in line with the visual axis, as well as adjust- ment of the lens to the focal distance required for clear vision. The two eyes converge and accomodate as one, and by means of producing convergences and accomodations under arti- ficial circumstances, the distances of objects thus seen will be functioned by the extent of the automaticity of these processes. Exceed- ingly distant objects make no apparent con- vergence in the eyes: the axes are practically parallel, as is the case with persons asleep ; and the "far away look" of one in abstraction or in a condition of surplus eating is directly refer- able to the non-fixation of any sensory stimulus. Objects will appear then, in this connection, as far away as the sensations of reflexly excited accommodation and convergence function them. But we must also take into account the matter of visual distance, and what it means. When 271 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION things are found out to be nearer or farther than they appeared, it cannot be called a visual il- lusion. Depth or distance, visually speaking, is as great as it appears to be; but depth or dis- tance in terms of intended movement to reach the object, is as great as it is found out to be. Of course, in eye-consciousness, one must con- sider that there are many unequal linear ex- tents which are functioned exactly alike,— they have common parts,— and these visual identities are just as good data as any others. Let the cause of the eye, and not the eye itself be the emptor qui caveat. What we were set to do on the basis of regarding these common parts as in one series only, is the basis for error; and this is a case of contradiction in the resulting movements, not an error of the visual content. The exact basis for erroneously calling this a "visual illusion" is the violation of the part- whole relation, — that is, the making of the whole consciousness independent of its contrib- uting parts and relations. 138. The so-called retinal image, or, for our purposes, the extent of retinal stimulation, has an immediate bearing upon the functioning for extents and depths. According to physiological optics, the size of the stimulated retinal area is directly proportional to the size of the ob- 272 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS ject stimulating it; and thus whatever object can be made to stimulate a smaller retinal area than it normally would in its spacial context, is called more distant than normally. The clear- ness or faintness of the stimulated retinal area has much to do also with the visual estimation of size and distance. Irradiation of light on neighboring retinal areas brings an inevitable distance effect, as well as does the stimulation of the retina by objects in a fog. But here haziness causes us to function the objects as much nearer for vision than they are in motor terms, whereas their vagueness of outline makes them appear farther away than one would ex- pect. Moreover, objects nearer than the fixa- tion point seem larger, and those farther away smaller; while if there are two objects directly in the line of vision, and the eye first fixates the farther and then the nearer of them, there will be apparent a doubling of the object not fixated. Holding a meter stick directly in the line of sight, and looking first at one end, then the other, and then at the middle, will cause all the blurring which any mis-focussed optical appa- ratus is heir to under similar circumstances. 139. Before taking up this phenomenon of doubling in detail, let us consider one differ- ence between monocular and binocular vision 273 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION on the phenomenal side. If a ring is suspended before one with its diameter in the median plane of the head while one eye is closed, the task of thrusting a pencil quickly into the aper- ture of the ring will be far more difficult than when both eyes are open. But the error is not so much one of direction as of the amount of distance at which the ring is estimated to be. If the ring moves, and any co-ordination be- tween vision and intended movement is there- by obtained, the trials will result in far greater accuracy than otherwise. Nevertheless, the de- termination of the amount of movement the ring has to make before accuracy of thrust is obtained, is of slight account; for there would be no basis on which accuracy with both eyes open without movement of the ring, could be equated with accuracy with but one eye open while the ring is moving. These two situations are prime to each other, and psychological primes may all be substituted for each other or not, just as environmental and intentional con- ditions determine. But so much does movement enter into perceptions of depth, that the eye must be regarded primarily as a motor mechan- ism whenever we wish to refer the data of space getting to it. For if we produce experi- mentally an apparent monocular visual im- 274 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS passe, — unless it be flashed on and oft' instan- taneously to the subject, — involuntary accomo- dation and re-accomodation occur, since the eyes are almost never still, even though we in- trospectively judge them to be so. Again, the two retinae do not function singly, however in- dependently they may elaborate their stimula- tions antecedent to the full neural discharge ac- companying focality. So that while uniocular depth may be obtained, especially with move- ment, one must be warned against assuming that the closure of one eye is accompanied by the exclusion of unconscious binocular, accu- rate functioning of space. 140. As a matter beyond dispute, however, depth can be obtained in too short a time to al- low for any eye movements, and while just how great a depth is therein apprehended is not quite clear, any depth at all would be sufficient evi- dence of the fact that space is not a matter of what some psychologists incorrectly term ex- perience, for spacial content is one thing, while the study of the functions whereby we get that content is quite another. Furthermore, to find ourselves accurately and prudentially oriented among our surroundings often means that mo- tor habits have improved upon the sensory content of vision to a large degree. The lowest 275 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION levels of consciousness are devoid of content, but they are not on that account lacking in those functions out of which accurate judgments may still be made. To treat then of binocular space, we have to consider first the fact that when the eyes are focussed, this functioning defines the field of vision in terms of the point of focus. Everything beyond and nearer than that point fails to arouse the same sort of definite stimu- lations from the eye sockets; as well as it fails to open such co-ordinating pathways to in- tended movements as does the fixation reaction, to which all others are subsidiary. One cannot converge his eyes in the dark correctly, and exact fixation of its source is impossible after a light, once shown, is obscured. If we turn out the electric light before retiring, not only will the exact position of the lighting fixture be lost to consciousness, but, in a strange room, all movements of orientation wall be suddenly swamped out of the motor pattern except the vaguest remnant of our previous intention. "Groping in the dark" is just another way of saying that intended movements guaranteed in their integrity by the element of visual fixation have been geometrically decreased by the bare arithmetical loss of the guiding eye, in point both of accuracy and chain continuity. Now, 276 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS as a usual thing, one is led to believe that the physiology and psychology of vision have made an inseparable contract. The notion of the ex- act correspondence between the amount of con- vergence of the eyes and the apparent distance of the object from the observer emanates from the very bosom of physiological optics, as well as the impossibility of single vision when non- corresponding points are being stimulated. Previous to that notion there was much support given to a derivative of the laws of optics known as the projection theory. This fell out of that opaque philosophical era in which the mind was considered a mirror of the objects of the "external" world. And yet the mind was in the brain, though the brain, strange to say, was also external! These were also the days when the mention of certain unctious words was inevitably followed by the stupefaction of the non-elect. Now although every observation may contribute to science, and while the search for ordinal correlations is symptomatic of one form of an orderly mind, yet any one who ex- periments upon vision and tries to ordinally correlate every visual phenomenon either with one of the laws of lenses or the laws of phys- iological optics exclusively, will find that in- stead of obeying the laws of nature, he has but 277 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION obeyed the laws of the logic of intention. We do find, it is true, that objects falling on non- corresponding points of the retinae, — that is, upon points geometrically non-identical, — pro- duce usually double vision of the stimulus. As a matter of fact, however, we get too few dou- ble images for the theory of identical points to be unlimitedly applicable, and too many for the notion of projection to be entertained. Im- portant work is being done at present upon this very item of binocular vision, and the general tendency of writers is to be catholic in the use of conclusions. At present, also, depth or solid- ity is being explained by saying that it is func- tioned by retinal conditions which exhibit a half-way state between single and double vision. For while we never see double at the fovea, neither does the marksman see two targets, nor the microscopist two specimens, though both of his eyes are open. To say, furthermore, that the eye not at the slit of the gun nor at the eye piece of the microscope sees nothing, is perjury to the facts. 141. For, if explanations of vision are to be through and through optical, or physiological, — in order to satisfy some a-priori theory of mechanism, — then, of course, at inconvenient places some such psychological (!) factor as 278 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS "habitual neglect" of the disturbing fact must be solicited in the final reckoning. For even stereoscopic cficcts of depth persist not only when the eyes are converging, but even when they are parallel, and when they are diverging as well; and distances can be discriminated as far as twenty metres, when kinaesthetic factors or retinal disparity are negligible. "Neglect of the extraneous elements," — by which is usually meant some "mental" hocus which is invoked to lubricate the irritating fact, — will not serve as an explanation, unless it be allowed to serve whichever side such a factor as "habitual ne- glect" or "convenient explanation" may prag- matically be called upon to support. Other- wise, "experience" and "habit" might become terms of no meaning! "Neglect" or "experi- ence" have nothing to do with the laws of op- tics; but so hard put are any and all purveyors of the insurmountable duality of stimulus and content, that the convenient explanation be- comes the one of greatest validity. Now the eye, besides being the functioner of vision, is a spherical body, whose optical effects are there- by often translations of plane surfaces into sphericities. Let one consider along with this the phenomenon of irradiation, the fact of much more than foveal vision being functioned nei- 279 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ther as infra- or ultra-foveal perspective, tlie fact of some indisputable monocular depth, of some instantaneous depth, and many other phenom- ena, and he will be factually obliged not only to infer, but imply as well that the series of phys- ical phenomena, the series of physiologically- optical phenomena, and the series of psycholog- ical space phenomena are three series, each as empirical, each as independent, and each as likely to have as not to have copious common parts with the others. In brief, there is a re- lation of functional dependence rather than a numerically causal relation existing between all these terms; and only the barest, and one might almost say inessential, correlation exists between all the terms of any one series, and all the terms of any other. But here is the main point, that incompatible as all these various series may be, term by term, their summation in all functioning for space may become self- corrective of any discrepancies in the partial explanation which any one of them may aftord. Motor adjustment, on the basis of the cumula- tive effects of re-fixation, accompanied either by the eye itself moving or the stimulus being moved about, has, as a total complex in the cross-section, such a geometrically greater ef- fect than the simple arithmetical summation of 280 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS the separable data iiiight lead one to expect, that the question of how we get space is quite subsidiary to the question of how accurate is the space so gotten. And this question is final- ly answerable by reference those ultra-ocular instruments of precision mentioned before, — I mean by reference to the ability of two con- structing engineers to make their separate tun- nels meet in the middle of a mountain, or to the ability of the gunner to demolish a target whose position is relayed to him by monoplane, tele- phone, and the calculus. 142. The insufficiency of such an account of visual space may perhaps be condoned on the strength of a brief mention of certain geomet- rical figures which are always cited as evidence of the tattered character of optical impressions. I mean the Mueller-Lyer, the Poggendorf, the Zoellner diagram, and others of their kind. Likewise, "Mach's Book" is often cited as espe- cially telling evidence against the stability of space. One word only must suffice in our treat- ment of this and all similar material. The "illusory" character of all these figures consists in the questions asked of the subject who at- tends to them. For example, if one is asked which way "Mach's Book" is open, — toward one or away from one, — the answer is that it is 281 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION turned in either direction, just as it appears to be. It is equally either, since it contains the perspective elements of both,— zY is all common parts, and has no exclusive relation to one aspect or the other. I'll even wager that it was drawn with this very end in view. The Muell- er-Lyer figure, while depending largely upon the motor element in vision for its emphatic effect, is a figure about which only tricky ques- tions can be asked. "Tell which line is the longer," as a sample of the instructions given to the subject, should be replaced by "which figure gives the more contracted effect?" For the threshold of this contraction can be easily found by the rotation of the movable arrows about their axes, and the whole "illusion" de- pends upon the absorption of one set of local signs by another, — a thing we found in connec- tion with compass points and intertones, and which we are as likely to find again in still a different set of phenomena as well. 143. This ends our particular treatment of sensations and perceptions. Be it known, how- ever, that some of the attributes we found in sensation apply also to perception. For in- stance, the time elapsing between the presenta- tion of such an object as a marlinespike and the comprehension of it as a splicing instrument, 282 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS would be called the latent-period of perception. The latent-period ending, the threshold would be reached. Again, perceptions summate, as for example, when a commander surveys the intricacies of a general engagement, and decides upon the particular efficacy of bayonets or cav- alry sabres to turn the tide of affairs. We adapt to perceptions also. Indeed, one of the clear- est ways to define analytically the difference between sensation and perception is to enumer- ate the attributes which both exhibit, and to determine why not all of them are carried over into the structural content of perception. This is hereby submitted as a question for the stu- dent to answer. We now turn to motor attune- ment and meaning. 144. It will be recalled that the motor end of the neural arc was mentioned as a very im- portant functioner of sensation. Indeed, unless the whole arc is active, the focalities of con- sciousness do not transpire. Although there are several ways in which the full neural release may occur, the most obvious way is to be elab- orated in the case of the instincts and the emo- tions, where the reflex excitation is practically total for the whole organism. Another form of release is the bare maintenance of the arc in a state of low resistance to a low current, as in 283 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION cases of adaptation, when no obviously visible change in the motor aspect comes with con- tinued functioning. Other forms of the motor aspect of release are convergence and accomo- dation. The continued maintenance of bodily positions with regard to the stimulus is, like- wise, just as motor as was the initiation of such motor relations; and, likewise, just as motor as is the inhibition of unequilibrating tendencies from other motor complexes which might sup- plant them upon the slightest provocation. But by far the most significant sets of motor re- sponses are those, which, either following ac- comodation, following convergence, or follow- ing the inhibition of spreads and wiltings, lead to the further orientation of the organism in reference to its surroundings. It follows upon this that the stimuli are functioned in a pattern on the basis of which we may deal furtheringly with the pliable part of the environment. In such cases, also, the more closely related the exciting stimulus is to the chief furthering ele- ment in the environment, the more automatic- ally does the chain of reflexes run off', and the less focal does anything but the end effect to be reached, become. Now the body is an organ- ism, and as such is an example of parts func- tioning a whole. Likewise, the environment is 284 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS at times organized into a definite whole leading to some general effect into which the effects of the separate parts, for a time, to be submerged. The motor adjustment to an environment then will be a furthering one, just to the extent that the cue-sensation and the resultant motor re- sponse are co-ordinated with the possibilities of the developing environment. Otherwise, less than the low current required in adaptation and habit will be developed in the responsive organ- ism. For habit is first based on the ease with which a response is shot off, and second, upon the lack of focality plus the gain in friction- less orientation which the completed response entails. With mannerisms and unconsciously learned responses the chapter on the emotional complex will have to do. From the internal sensations as well as from the general tonic reflexes of the body we gain a momentum which is indisputably fundamental for the superstruc- ture of learned habits, perceptions of relation, and the more special extero-ceptive sensibilities. The motor attunement developed as we ap- proach maturity is always guaranteed, though not always directed, by the residual environ- ment and funded responses within the body. The general character of this bodily momentum is not introspectable, — it is physiological, and 285 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION unconscious. The environment which the un- conscious responses function, being largely un- observable, is not what one ordinarily means by his special environment, for this latter is usually unsteady, and by virtue of its shifts in and out of focality, has sometimes erroneously been called that environment in reference to which one is free. "1 can look or not," "I can close my ears to it,' "I can take it or leave it," are expressions not referred to the vegetative system, but to the focally sensorial environment of our organism. But whatever this may ulti- mately turn out to mean, one can never say that he is unresponsive to his surroundings, even though the sensorial environment is often made up of series which have many missing members, — a thing which partly accounts for the notion of freedom; while the perceptual content, — the environment of logical structure, of learning, of observable furtherances, and the like, — is much more continuous. And in this case it is often a matter of observation that the so-called "free- dom of choice" is due to the forgetting of the steps which lead to the present responses. 145. Meanings are implicit in any definable pattern of response. In psychology, at least, anything means what one perceives it to he, as well as what one is about to do in the presence 286 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS of it. Environmental pattern and motor pat- tern, — besides these two there is nothing to be said at the start. Meaning for logic is equiva- lence. When an author writes, "That is to say," or "I mean by this," he always gives an equiva- lent expression, to get his idea into those con- sciousnesses which may be somewhat oblique to his own, — his own having been satisfied by his first expression. Psychologically, this would be a case of the substitution of stimulus, and a re- cognition not only of the latent-period of per- ception in others, but also of the lack of any psy- chological congruence between his vocabulary and that of his readers. Again, when a sound is heard in the dead of night and some say "mouse," while others say "burglar," there is no equivalence in anything but the probability of either, and in the sensorial partial equiva- lence of both. On the other hand, when one says, "I mean that it shall take place," the strict- est psychological interpretation of this state- ment becomes, "focally no inhibitions are caus- ing my predictions to lose their pattern." But in either case there is motor readiness, — the urgency attendant upon a meaningful percep- tion. 146. This brings us to what we call pre-per- ceptions. The learned readiness to take one ele- 287 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ment of the stimulus for the whole, (the motor discharging upon any complex situation in terms of one of the specific elements), marks the so-called "intelligent" man, as distinguished from the imbecile. Stupidity is a complex of interminable latent-period and motor incoordi- nation. In such a case the chain reflexes lack automaticity, and the cue-stimulations have so many common parts that they fail to arouse any definite pattern of activity upon the environ- ment. This pre-perception or apperception, as it has been equivocally called, is not the same as the introspection upon what one is about to do. When a motor response has been nipped in the bud, or inhibited, and one is asked to re- port upon what he would have done, had not such interruption prevented, the report as given need not be taken as equivalent to what is uni- formly the case when no nipping occurs. For the report arises out of congested conscious- ness,— a thing quite different from freely func- tioned reactions. Of course, the introspection in such a case may be valuable in that it defines the introspection, for often by its means one can tell how unified is the personality from whom it proceeds. The difficulty with introspection in such a case is that it makes focal certain ele- ments which normally would never become so, 288 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS and as such subverts the elements involved. That which is brewed in introspection is usually only the unimportant non-focal material becom- ing focal, plus the grammatical effluvia incident to the symbolization of the former contents and processes by means of speech. Introspection is not only reduplicated consciousness, but it manifests characteristics which the original consciousness did not properly have. Pre-per- ception is potential consciousness, but pre-per- ception as reported in introspection may not be at all the same as it might have been. And the way to test the validity of pre-perception is by check experiments in the laboratory, or by out- side reference to the verbosity of the subject. Now potential consciousness is indefinable except in terms of what does actually happen without the interruption of introspection. Can this be told by speech? Evidently not. Intro- spection may now and then get a few of the overtones of consciousness, but introspection is a reversal of the general current of its data, and as such, is valuable for that sort of reversed data and none other. I neglect and disparage the word "apperception" because it is a term which implies that we make up our perceptions out of tag-rag sensations by adding to them from a "mental" storehouse. Things are summed and 289 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION get additional properties thereby, not out of a hypothetical "mental" storehouse, but by vir- tue of the interaction of the neural currents to function an interacting environment. The old idea of the soul being something that thinks and thereby adjudicates sensory content has been evaporated to its last whiff, and with it has gone every notion of dualism and duplicity, for these two are indeed twins. 147. Along with pre-perception comes pre- sensation. This is one of the cardinal items in memory. When, for example, upon the mere mention of the name of an object we obtain sen- sory contents of it, we are said to remember or to have pre-sensations of it. This comes about by virtue of the fact that we have gained identi- cal responses to the various elements in the ob- ject, so that its color, shape, name, and so on, are all functionable by the same response. Now, the qualities and properties of objects have no more rigidly defined geographical position than have their names, and pre-sensation is but a case of obtaining part of an object in sensory content from the motor response to that which for us is the "open sesame" to such content. 148. With a brief consideration of the na- ture of speech, this long chapter must close. So far as evidences are to be trusted, speech can 290 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS be traced evolutionally to cries of danger, coo- ings and purrings in the mating season, wait- ings, cacchinations and "burblings." Speech arose apparently from the needs of communica- tion, but seems also to be a derivative of self- amusement as well. From the first wild cries of savage life, — whether from anger, fear, affec- tion or other situations, — we have derived the potent elements of speech, these, later on, being added to out of the need of orientation to a more complex and tranquiller environment. Part of language is onomatopoetic, that is, the words are direct imitations of the sounds of the things referred to. The rest is quite arbi- trary and conventional. The vowel element in language appears to be more directly related to the primitive order of things than does the consonantal element; for in every situation in which language is used forcibly and emotional- ly, the pitch element takes precedence over all else, and with vowels alone these nuances of pitch are functionable. 149. Language is also geographical rather than hereditary. A child of Chinese parents, brought up from the beginning in the midst of people of a different nationality, will speak only the language of its foster parents. This is not accounted for by the shape of the mouth cavity, 291 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION even though the palatal arch of different peoples is of different height and form; but it is due to the extreme flexibility of the movable parts of the vocal apparatus. These are the tongue, the lips, the lower jaw, and the muscles of the throat. The extremely important socially or- ganizing part language has played in his- tory is attested both by the social amalgamation of races having a common language, and the political unions of people of a common tongue. But, over against this fact is the anciently re- ported historical event of a conquering people making the language of the conquered the po- lite language of their court. In these cases, however, the absorption of culture has gone hand in hand with the passion for knowing the language in which such culture was developed. 150. Language is also a reaction. To men- tion the name of something seen, heard or han- dled, is to deal with it twice; and such dealing involves diff'erent elements of consciousness, and consequently differing effects. Further- more, the voice, by virtue of its being produced in the head, has an advantage over other reac- tions in several ways. In the first place, the re- action to auditory stimuli is quicker than to al- most any other kind. Furthermore, the domi- nance which the head plays in personality, as 292 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS well as the fact that the face is far and away the focus of all social intercourse, makes the language of a person his piece de resistance in a majority of social matters. When one con- siders how largely information comes by way of words, the place that words have in human aftairs seems clearly the chiefest. Language, as a reaction, is thus a doubling of responses to the situations in which it is used. Very little of it is absolutely necessary, for most discussions end with the definitions of the terms first employed, and concerning which so many misunderstood statements were made. For words, as symbols, are not bound to follow the orders of the things symbolized, and as a result, evaporation of meaning frequently occurs. But it is undeniable that relations and functions could not have been mutually considered without their aid. 151. The order in which a child learns a language is curious. Contrary to the report of fond parents, the imitation by a child of the sounds and mouth movements of its parents is fiot flattering to the famous intelligence of the human race. The child responds to the stimuli of its teacher by the best way it can, but hard consonants, such as 'k,' 'f,' 't,' and the like are imitated by the use of their softer forms, 'g,' 'v,' and 'd.' Furthermore, it learns class names 293 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION or general terms, before it learns words of se- lective discrimination. It speaks of itself in the third person before it uses the pronoun I, for to all intents and purposes, it is thoroughly realistic in its absorption of all data. 152. Nevertheless, the importance of lan- guage does not lie in the factors of its origin. Language, as a quotidian commodity, gets used in certain ways not to be explained by reference to its source. Words slip their moorings and exhibit common parts whose existence was little suspected beforehand; besides, the perception of new relations in things does not always go with the invention of a new word, — instead, we put together the old ones and make them do a little longer. In fact, all the new words are either derived from dead languages, or are blurted out unexpectedly in slang and banter. These developments are not introspectable either. We speak by momentum, and mostly out of the co-conscious, when speaking, in our normal speed and confidence. In this point, language is exceptionally typical of all unhin- dered consciousness: to function speech and then to recall it is the same sort of manifesta- tion as seeing, hearing and the like, and then introspecting upon it. The alterations that oc- cur to us in point of what we would have better 294 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS said, is the same sort of consciousness as the introspective consciousness. For neither is speech ordinally correlated with the chrono- genetic order of our ideas, nor is it the same as later corrections of it would indicate to have been our exact meaning. It has, however, com- mon parts with both. The later correction indi- cates logical determinations, while its lack of correspondence with the play of ideas illustrates that things can get into another than the first or- der of cross-sectioning, 153. Now an idea is either an attribute of a thing, a part of a whole, the pattern of a thing or a part, or the terminus of such a pat- tern, functionally construed, and so on. Ideas are anything being functioned by a nervous sys- tem. Functioning is the same here as knowing, and the only reason we distinguish between things not yet known and things known at the present time, is because the stages of their being first functioned, spoken of, and logically or- dered, reveal in this order relations which through summation and fusion have been over- looked. We use the term idea also to indicate usually that some such development is in pro- gress, rather than that bare noticing is all that is being done. The language reaction helps sig- nificantly here, for by means of it we are en- 295 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION abled to select more elements for retention than otherwise, and to respond specifically to things to which speechless animals cannot be discov- ered to be at all tropistic. Consequently, the more accurately language is used, the more things can be enumerated, the more patterns and relations can be specified and filed away, and the more comparing of ideas can be accom- plished. Following this, the business of argu- ment reorders the data and reveals coinci- dences and contradictions. We thus obtain considerable positive information by the inter- play of language, quite apart from the phys- ical presence of the data to which it refers. It is due to the fact that language, apart from the things, may reveal relations not before noticed in the things themselves, that we have devel- oped the notion of ideas of things. For ideas, in that they are attributes of, parts of, plans of, and the like, imply on this account no duality between thought and thing. Insofar as they are turned into words, — auditory symbols, — they seem on this account to necessitate a cleft be- tween matters of another sense than that of sound, as, for instance, when we mention tastes and sights, and then, by momentum and pre- ponderance, to cover the whole of consciousness with this sort of debilitating predicate. Unless 296 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS "consciousness of" means that there are several orders in the cross-section into which things can get, it has no meaning; for besides this and se- lective response, nothing is fundamental upon which it can be based. 154. The parts of speech, actually disre- garded except in grammars, are significant for this treatment. Nouns are language-equiva- lents of things, principally, as well as of parts, and frequently of orders and patterns. But or- ders are equivalent to verbs whenever there is functional significance in them. Also, genetic- ally, nouns refer to sensation masses, while verbs refer to motor intention. Attributes of "things" are primarily adjectives, while the functional elements of "wholes" and "things" are adverbial. The noun is thus either made of adjectives, or made of verbs and other parts of speech. Relations are expressed by the use of prepositions, conjunctions, and verbs, while sud- den inhibitions are functioned by the interjec- tions. Of all the parts of speech, the personal pronoun is the latest in development. Its mer- curial character is a matter of even common notice, for besides referring to the cross-section equivocally for different spaces of time, it refers either to a very insignificant part of conscious- ness one moment, or to the dominant motive at 297 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION another. The intentional suppression of ideas, commonly called lying, is thus made exceedingly easy, for the pronoun I is a shifting center of reference at best, and all that is said about it must be said in terms of the elements contrib- uting to it as a center. Being guaranteed by its periphery, and not being something subtle and within, the pronoun I and what it means must always be omitted when the accuracy and truth of a matter is at stake. The reader is at liberty to indulge in all the implications in the above statements. 155. Language when printed, as in this pres- ent form, is to be distinguished from the utter- ances of steady speech. For if one wishes to be read, he must seek to present his words in such a form that as many common parts will be present as there are persons for whom the ut- terances are to be stimuli. And while conces- sions are always made, they are not to be thought of as concessions which betray the au- thor of a book into compromises. To be able to get a hearing on account of using motor terms, well-chosen illustrations, and the like, is not the same as sneaking up behind a person and making him consent before he is aware of what the drift of the matter is. Seldom is the flow of any person's ideas good enough to speak 298 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS or print without castigation and reordering, neither is any hard and fast plan in composition ever strictly adhered to. Likewise, in speech and writing we respond to the environment of the audience and the environment of the sub- ject matter, and seek to find and express com- mon parts in both environments, so that as many as we wish to stimulate may be shown the object, and have their threshold lowered by removing the inhibiting inessentials. In the plan of a book, however, there need be no conces- sions. The logical order of presentation is not either linguistic nor individual. 156. Sensation and perception in the con- scious cross-section are thus seen to be items whose structural differences are chiefest. We shall now turn to another set of responses in which we shall not find structure central, but rather disorganization, due to continual inhibi- tion, fusion and confusion. 1 refer to the emo- tions anci the instincts. To a large degree, also, we shall have to consider consciousness lateral- ly and developmentally in order to understand the status of any emotion in the cross-section. As it is, moreover, this book is but an outline, and sketches, rather than fills in, the patterns it em- ploys in passing. But it makes no attempt to explain away anything that is, unless, per- 299 THE CONCCIOUS CROSS-SECTION chance, it be certain beliefs in non-existent things, and this is not only within its province to do, but also its particular business not to leave undone. Bibliography I. General. Holt, E. B., "The Concept of Consciousness," especially Chapter XI, "Sensation and Percep- tion in the Conscious Cross-Section," and Chap- ter XV, "The Emancipation of Physiology from Philosophy." Sherrington, C. S., "The Integrative Action of the Nervous System," Lectures I to VII. II. Touch. Rivers, W. H. R., and Head, Henry, "A Hu- man Experiment in Nerve Division," in "Brain," November, 1908. Titchener, E. B., "A Text-Book of Psychol- ogy," especially pp. 143-159. Myers, C. S., "A Text-Book of Experimental Psychology," Chapters II and XVII. III. Smell and Taste. Titchener, E. B., op. cit. pp. 114-141. Myers, C. S., op. cit. Chapter VIII. IV. Kinaesthetic Senses. Titchener, E. B., op. cit. pp. 160-182. Myers, C. S., op. cit. Chapters V and XVI. 300 THE SENSITIVE AND PERCEPTIVE ORGANS V. Hearing. Titchener, E. B., op. cit. pp. 93-112. Myers, C. S., op. cit. Chapters III and IV. Mach, E., op. cit. "Sensations of Tone." VI. Vision. • Titchener, E. B., op. cit. pp. 59-92. Myers, C. S., Chapters VI and VII. VII. Space Perceptions. Titchener, E. B., op. cit. pp. 303-373. Myers, C. S., op. cit. Chapters XVIII to XXIII. Pierce, A. H., "Studies in Auditory and Vis- ual Space Perception." James, W., "Psychology, Briefer Course," Chapters XV, XVII, XX and XXI. Mach, E., op. cit. pp. 41-118. Holt, E. B., "The Place of Ilhisory Experience in a Realistic World," in the "New Realism." 301 CHAPTER IV. THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX 1. This chapter will consider emotions, in- stincts, and their derivatives. Strictly defined, both instincts and emotions are motor responses to disordered situations. Their stimuli are ob- jects consisting of series, many of whose terms are missing. Thus mal-adjustment of the or- ganism, and a disordered object are the func- tional and content sides of emotions and in- stincts. 2. Responses define environments, and thus the emotional reaction may be functioned by one organism in a situation which arouses no such reaction in another organism. On the oth- er hand, a disorderly environment may be flanked on all sides by an orderly one, and so arouse various types of orderly or disorderly reactions on the part of organisms confronting it, with the result that the ensuing motor dis- charges, and not the nameable sensory content, must often be taken as the criteria of "what the organism is doing." Environments alter and organisms change, and the steps by which these alterations and changes occur need not be or- dinally correlated. So that the mal-adjustment 302 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX of the organism to the situation is one, but not the only disturbing factor in emotional and in- stinctive action. Nevertheless, the usual effect of such mal-adjustment is cumulative, — it in- creases the disorder. The fusion we met with in sensation is antityped here in confusion, attend- ed by the instant arousal of general skeletal re- action and glandular secretion, usually resulting in entire translation of the whole body through space. Instinct is as sudden as reflex, and emo- tion as positionless as feeling-tone, and both in- stincts and emotions lack that element in per- ception known as pattern. They both arise in situations we are unable to grasp significantly, and consist of the suddenest and strongest out- goings of energy of which we are capable. They follow a complete chopping off of former focal consciousness and, instead of leading to further activities of profitable orientation, lead, unless brought to a close by exhaustion or mutual in- hibition, to a situation of tatterdemalion con- sciousness. 3. The term "emotional complex" is used to indicate that these reactions usually keep crowding, impelling, or inhibiting each other. Furthermore, they often get insufTiciently shot- off, and as a result become suppressed, — the un- shot residue smouldering away as an uncon- 303 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION scious readiness of neural response. The un- conscious has no content, but it constituted sole- ly of functions, and it is this condition which renders obscure the causes of the breaking loose of smothered emotions. When a form of con- sciousness has no content, it cannot be satis- factorily described by the use of nouns. Verbs and adverbs are alone to be used. This is even witnessed by the fact of the current terms for the emotions and instincts: fear, flight, pugnac- ity, wonder, — such terms are all basically verbs, and only made over into nouns to satisfy the pragmatic urgencies of speech. There is no object, fear; there are only persons fearing: nothing is flight; there are only legs animatedly decreasing the parallactic angle in the eyes of the observer. This is not to be taken, however, to mean that fears and anxieties, for example, are groundless. It means nothing of the sort. But in every case of emotion or instinct, one is functioning a content less definable than one finds to be the case with sensation or percep- tion. And just as one has a red sensation or a logical perception, so in the case of these disor- dered responses now being considered, one has a fearful or a pugnacious consciousness, and this consciousness always has an object. 4. Emotions and instincts, then, are the 304 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX names chiefly applied to the functional aspect of disorderly consciousness. The content of such consciousness may be composed of any ob- jects whatsoever. Thus we may be afraid of a green, a black, a tall, a hollow, or a scurrying object, each of which are yet green, black, or tall, etc., exclusive of their emotional status. We are emotional or instinctive toward anything at all. And it is on account of the lack of spe- cific arousers of these mal-adjustments that we have no terms which specifically differentiate the environment into special contents for this and that emotion or instinct. Our strictest defi- nition in this case will therefore concern the neural discharges incident to their appearance. Two main points are profitably noted here. The first of these is the phenomenon of irradiation of the generating impulse which arouses centers of functionation not normally stimulated by the object of emotion or instinct when it is in an- other environment. The second point is what is called the auto-catalytic character of neural release. The first of these, — irradiation, — is not exclusively a phenomenon of the neurology of instincts and emotions. We spoke of it in the first few pages of the last chapter as significant even for the simpler responses. Synaesthesia has also been defined as correlated with it. Like- 305 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION wise, pre-perception and pre-sensation are ir- radiation phenomena as well. What then, shall we say is idiomatic in the irradiation aspect of the mal-adjustment phenomena? Why, this: that the irradiation is of such a type as to arouse non-perceptual (i. e., non-stabilizing) re- flexes of the chain type. Thus it is that the as- pect of the total situation confronting the or- ganism is inseparable from a full account of the responses generating the cross-section, 5. Now for the second, — the auto-catalytic character of the neural releases. Auto-cataly- sis occurs when one of the products of a reac- tion acts as a catalyser, catalysers being those things (substances) which hasten reactions by their mere presence, without entering into the formula themselves. The friction of the match sets free the chemical energy of the powder in the magazine, but the friction is not an element in the formula. Again, the decomposition of hydrogen peroxide by platinum black is a case of catalytic action. From the best evidence we have today, it is safe to assert that neuronic re- lease is a type of catalytic action, especially in the matter of the establishment of settled dis- positions in the organism. For upon the very first functioning of a nerve, the nerve path be- comes sensitized, the threshold lowered, and 306 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX further stimulation rendered easier. Indeed, this fact might be said to be the neural basis of logical classification, and we might also add that the reception or rejection by the various organs of the body of nutriment and sensory contents is exactly what choice in its lowest terms means. The sensitization of the neural paths is indeed the formation of an asymmetric- al series. To return to auto-catalysis, the re- lease of reflex energy in the nerve cells is ac- companied by the accumulation of deposits that unite to form a veritable storage cell, "which is capable, under appropriate conditions, of being discharged and [thereby] restoring the same specific current by which it was produced." All the neural responses tend, indeed, to become of this general character, — that is, auto-catalysed, — but some paths, being traversed oftener, and more vigorously than others, (while at the same time producing vivid irradiation among their neighbors), get a momentum as well as a prom- inence in consciousness which the others do not have. Attention is just a clear pathway of per- ceptual neural response, or release, and is a derivative of acuity, threshold, interest, and other furthering ingredients. Between selective attention and restricted neural momentum 307 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION there is no one so wise as to be able to draw even a hair-sized line. 6. Neural momentum is also the dominant element in habit. Habit, unlike emotion, is us- ually unintrospectable. Unlike emotion again, it has a definite pattern, and serves, or can be made to serve some other set of responses than its own. Considering habit in general, it is nei- ther useful nor useless; but considering it from the standpoint of psychology, it is the adjust- ment of the organism to some constant feature in its environment with about the least friction possible. Contrariwise, emotions arise from mal-adjustments to the environment, and in their continuance lead to worse and worse ad- justment, for only by exhausting the organism, or by sudden changes of focality do they bring about any possibility of readjustment on an equable basis. Curiously enough, there is a lack of correspondence between neural momen- tums and the speech reaction they arouse. Neu- rally construea, greatest ease of function comes when the wonted impulses are traversing the paths; our statements, however, very often as- sert that we prefer a complete change of activ- ity. At the bottom of this lies the emotional complex, and the presence of emotions is usual- 308 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX ly indicative of some disorder in neural con- tinuity. 7. Now the disordered environment men- tioned above is but one of the environments en- veloping the organism. When General Wood purified Havana, and by so doing cut down the death rate prodigiously, he was not responding to the disease-making environment so much as he was responding to the scientifically prophy- lactic environment of bacteriological laborato- ries. Havana was but a perplexing term in his entire environment for which some reagent was to be supplied in order to neutralize it. The needs of Havana and the visible condition of that city were two terms prime to each other; but by responses to a third element, having chemical common parts with both, he was able to make the Cuban city a member of a series of other cities, a series defined by its high posi- tion relative to vital statistics. On the other hand, the Havanese had been responding solely to the disorder. Now, to perceive nothing but a disordered environment is not to perceive in the strictest sense at all; but to perceive a dis- order in the midst of a larger order is virtually to function the discrepancy between them. Thereafter the motor readjustment of the dis- crepancy will take place just as fast and just 309 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION as far as there are common parts between them, and as fast and as far also as there is unification among the perceptions and impulses of the re- ad justor. There are disordered minds in the presence of what to others appears order and positive pattern, but these minds are still func- tioning the residues of unshot impulses, — sup- pressions for which there has been no utilized outlet. In many such cases, the environment is well said to be within the body. It is here also that the doctrine of the soft soul had its source. 8. I take particular umbrage at the con- ventional treatment of instincts. As in many another case, obscurity of source has been made the basis of the tenacity of belief. For the in- stincts are generally treated as unlearned, sud- den tendencies to action; race habits, "designed to promote the welfare of the race," and they are furthermore said to be "uncontrolled by in- telligence." Volume after volume has been written on this subject of instinct, and the gen- eral treatment indicates that bibliography plays a larger role than does observation and clear insight. Much obscurity results from this meth- od of procedure, for the writers who employ it have their eyes only on the organism, and not on "what the organism is doing" in the midst of its environment. The insufficiency of such treat- 310 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX ment will at once appear if we consider any- thing more than the organism. Sensations are objects and perceptions are objects, and like- wise emotions and instincts cannot be severed from their exciting stimuli and remain in the system of things known as the psychological order. The statement that instincts are un- learned does not signalize them as unique among the events of the cross-section. In the first place, none of the tropisms are premeditat- ed, sedulously tried out, and stamped with the hall-mark before they become settled disposi- tions. Secondly, suddenness cannot be their distinguishing mark, for short latency is applic- able to more of the responses than they. And that all the individual members of a race do this or that is more indicative of gregariousness than of anything subtly orig- inal. Instinctive action only appears sud- den because of the diremption in percept- ual consciousness that goes with it, and instinctive actions are racial only in so far as the predicaments of the individuals of a race are identical. A race is a constant function of its environment, a derivative of circumstances, and it is the environment that shapes it. The ubiquity of instincts is no more special than the ubiquity of ears or eyelids. The instincts 311 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION are said to be "designed to promote the welfare of the race," — an expression which is supposed to possess splendid oratorical possibilities, — but which upon analysis turns out to have no mean- ing. For instinctive actions, arising from dis- ordered environments, lead to nothing stable until they are superseded by clear perceptions, the latter not being in any necessary way pre- ceded by disorderly functioning. Furthermore, self-preservation is said to be the kernel of every instinct. But upon examination it will appear that this means bodily preservation, not preservation of the self in its developed condi- tion, and so we have to narrow the concept "self" in order to satisfy such a definition. 9. 1 use the word instinct, then, not because there is any internal origin for it save mal-ad- justment to the situation met with, neither be- cause it could not be superseded by a more em- pirical expression, but merely in order to show that a realistic psychology is not obliged to leave anything out of its account of mind. The im- possibility of self-observing the instinctive reac- tions, and the general loss of focal mind which they entail have been the roots of the notion that some special, internal readinesses were bas- ic in each individual. There are response pos- sibilities in each individual, but to call these by 312 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX a name that implies a stage all set ready for the curtain to rise is as reasonable as saying that ordnance is cast with the ammunition inside ol it. 10. The truth of the opening thesis of this chapter and its consequent development is wit- nessed by certain modern cataloguing and ex- planation of what are still called the "original tendencies." I refer to the w^ork of James and Thorndyke, whose lists of "instincts" are so broad as to be subversive of the general idea underlying their construction. James' account may be found in his "l^rinciples of Psychology," Vol. 11., Chapter XXIV., while Thorndyke's is given in his "Educational Psychology," Vol. I. Now the exact diliiculty in these treatments is that when they were written, the Ego-complex was not so much as even heard of, — at least not assimilated by the writers of these treatises. The infant had been regarded as "trailing clouds of glory" for about five years and three months, and then as suddenly becoming sheared of his nimbus and mortgaged as are the rest of us with inhibitions and a tough environment. But the Ego-complex, or the evolution of per- sonality, has been traced quite a ways into the nimbus, and psycholog>^ now includes the study of cradles and cognate apparatus. With this 313 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION change, moreover, there has come the recogni- tion of the futility of regarding the so-called "in- stincts" as universals, or unlearned tendencies at all, and we are slowly coming to recognize that the environment begins to be specifically functioned with the first breath, and not after an indeterminate and subtle interval. On the basis of this, then, 1 make bold to define the in- stincts and emotions as mal-adjustments, and to select from the list of generally given original tendencies those which fall rightly under this category. The boldness of the venture is appre- ciated, and so finality of conviction rests upon its accustomed supports. 11. The most modern treatment of instincts and emotions appears in McDougall's "Social Psychology," and 1 shall quote his list in the order in which the terms follow the greatest-to- least condition of mal-adjustment of the organ- ism to its environment. As follows: Instinct. Emotion. Flight Fear Pugnacity Anger Repulsion Disgust Curiosity Wonder Self Display Positive Self-feeling Self Abasement Negative Self-feeling Parental Instinct Tender Emotion 314 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX Reproduction No one specific emotionality Gregariousness *Fear of solitude Acquisition *Various self-feelings and jealousies (The terms marked (*) are not found in Mc- Dougall.) The instincts and emotions appear usually together, the former being detected by the movements of the skeleton; the latter, by the amount of vascular disturbance summing into confusion and glandular secretion. Further- more, Sympathy, Suggestion and Imitation are enumerated, as well as Play. There is also a list of complexes of emotions both involving and not involving the existence of sentiments, these latter being an organized system of emo- tions about some object. 12. Let it now be understood, however, that these various manifestations enumerated in the above table are capable of many degrees of in- tensity, and when they lose their edge, are not classifiable among the seriously disturbing mal- adjustments. Particularly note the instinct of curiosity. When this appears alone, as it may, without wonder, it is often linked with interest and attention in such a way as to lose its non- perceptual character. Gregariousness, when 315 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION adapted, may also become a matter of very lit- tle disturbance, if the environment of other hu- man beings is quiescent and in order. Similar- ly, acquisition may become bare thrift, and as such be pacific in its motivation. The others, however, are not so readily soothed into fur- therances, as a little observation will readily show. This, however, as a last word here; that when the instinct and its attendant emotion oc- cur together, they are more likely to »e disor- derly responses than otherwise, and some of these pairs of responses cannot be adapted nor made subservient to dominant, furthering pur- poses. 13. Somewhat in detail, then, let us consid- er the above pairs of responses together. One cannot always use self-observation as a basis for studying them, for accurate self-observa- tion is only attained by considerable study; and to ask some one how he feels when he is afraid is to ask but for summation and fusion, rather than for a detailed analysis of the facts. Flight- fear occurs as early as any of the complexes of the list, and much has been written on it that is well worth reading. James' account in his "Principles of Psychology," Darwin's "The Ex- pression of the Emotions in Man and the Ani- mals," are typical of the best in this line that is 316 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX extant. Perhaps no other emotional complex than flight-fear involves such a shattering of fo- cal continuities in consciousness. The result of it is a general super-violent efferent discharge, resulting in either paralysis, or in the swift pro- jection of the whole body by running as far from the stimulus as possible. But the self-pro- tective character of this is only on the assump- tion that the deep sea and the devil are both in front of one, and that to run in the opposite direction is to obtain sanctuary. The running away, of course, is no guarantee of the percep- tion of safety at the terminus of flight, but the general utility of it lies in a fifty-fifty chance of stopping somewhere this side of the devil. Children are not afraid of everything strange, but principally of noises and situations intend- ed to upset them. Of lightning they are often unaccountably afraid; but of thunder, and of dark closets and bugaboos only in proportion as their parents threaten them by voice or atti- tude before introducing them to the stimulus. The parent is as much a part of the child's environment as are the furniture and milk bot- tles, and the part the parents play is too fre- quently and in ignorance excluded from an ac- count of the child's reaction to the stimulus. Besides, I have been told by military men with 317 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION medals that much of the rashness of ijravery is plain ordmary fear, — ^the soldier being in a pre- aicament, and one thing to him about as good as another. Now, by virtue of ideas having common parts with things, and by virtue of the fact that wholes can be vicariously functioned for by their parts, the emotions can be aroused by the presentation of any part of the original- ly exciting stimulus, provided it is bolstered up by effective helps. Most of our functioning anyway is due to the serial focality of the barest common parts. 14. The pugnacity-anger complex arises clearly in situations which are too much for us to manage, and starts, at least, a series of events whose other end is often the annihilation or hu- miliation of the object or person confronting us. Many authors regard the distortion of the lips during anger as a remnant of the animal habit of frightening one's prey by the sight of the teeth about to bite. At any rate, pugnacity differs from flight in the direction of bodily translation, and in anger we are conscious of our bodies as larger than we are in fear. Pro- fessor Cannon has done significant experiment- ation upon both of these complexes in point of their physiological concomitants. In the first place, he finds the peaceful tabby cat of a bet- 318 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX ter digestion than her cantankerous mate, as evidenced by the fact that "fear and anger. . . . are attended. . . .by cessation of the contractions of the stomach and intestines." Furthermore, the disturbances of digestion which outlast emo- tional excitement, (after-image), are correlated with the action of the ductless glands which se- crete adrenalin, a substance which, when cir- culated in the blood, causes glycosuria and oth- er significant disorders. "It seems to act as an antidote to muscular fatigue, and renders more rapid the coagulation of blood." Both of these concern the pugnacity-anger complex, as well as that of flight-fear; for the angry or fearful person often performs acts which seem fully beyond his normal strength. Likewise, our dis- regard of wounds and their sudden healing in many cases of violent emotion are accounted for. (See "Recent Studies of Bodily Effects of Fear, Rage and Pain" by W. B. Cannon, Jour. Phil., Psych., and Sci. Meth., March 12, 1914.) 15. Repulsion and disgust are more chem- ical than anything else. Certain bitter tastes and nauseating smells are both noxious and originally annoying. The sense environment in which they figure is out of balance, and mal-ad- justment at once supervenes. The first func- tioning to this sort of an environment is strictly 319 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION chemical in its character; later on, by analogy, these responses can be obtained in connection with a set of stimuli which are not primarily chemical at all. Sneers, scorns, and loathing, which we direct at persons rather than at chem- icals, are responses to disordered situations made on the basis of verbal common parts. Of course there are the unwashed and unscented to whom we respond chemically, but for a book to be loathsome, an analogical situation must supersede. Certain very expensive books are printed on a most ill-smelling paper, and yet the response is to the printing and other beauty about the book, — the publisher having betted on the long latent-period of the odor, and the inhibitory properties of the literature. 16. The curiosity-wonder complex is less disturbing than the two previously mentioned, and is the basis of the questions what, how, and why. But science only begins in wondering why; it ends in finding out. And after this is done, no mal-adjustment is present. Wonder as an element in philosophy is of the same character, and only mystics keep on wondering after they have gotten under the top crust of things. To say that the instincts are the springs of human action is but to speak half of the truth. They are not the regulators of human 320 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX action, for these are perceptions instead. The curiosity-wonder complex differs from the two others thus far discussed in that it involves sensory elements rather than motor, and so does not function the shearing off of focality as is the case with the more vigorous complexes. But that the object wondered at is in a series too prime for orientation, none will be able to deny. 17. Self-display and self-abasement, with their attendant emotions of positive and nega- tive self-feelings, are responses to social dis- turbances of an intricate character. They are inevitably related to shyness, bashfulness, mod- esty, vanity and other so-called psychological simples, involving certain sexual elements of which some mention must be made. Exhibition is a cardinal feature of the mating season of all creatures, and displays and abasements are used to increase mutual desire. When the exhibition complex outlasts the specific incident in which it arose, or becomes suppressed, as is often the case, it may crop out in very unusual situations. Thus the blushing reflex and the "sidelong glance" are suppressions being partly released. This is not to say that manifestation of an im- pulse goes necessarily with focality of the knowledge of its origin, for in regard to most of 321 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION our nature we are naively ignorant. The old Socratic maxim "know thyself" has recently been inverted into "knowing oneself is a func- tion of knowing others." Thus an item in con- sciousness of a sexual origin may not be accom- panied by the focality of the desire for repro- ductive relations with another of the species, although we may be able to show that normally such would be the case were no inhibiting per- ceptions present. The reproductive instinct is devoid of any specific emotionality, — it being usually a periodic function of certain glandular motivation, and only embellished by emotions in certain concrete situations. The disorderly element in this instinct is the fact of, what might be called upon analysis, its promiscuous char- acter. The insecurity attendant upon this con- dition leads to the above-mentioned emotional embellishments of display and abasement. Self display and self abasement also originate in an environment where the truth is suppressed, and reappear quickly whenever analagous situa- tions occur. Thus the general adornment of the body, as well as the humility of a pension- er, may be entirely asexual, but the adornment and humility are both calculated to affect fa- vorably the one at whom they are directed, and 322 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX as such are forms of those suppressed ideas known as lying. 18. The parental instinct, with its attendant emotion of tenderness, is a function of the help- lessness of the young over which the parent be- comes solicitous. The child's self help cannot be forced,— it must be slowly developed, and slowly strengthened. The realization of the discrepancy between its present condition and that of mature development, as well as the ne- cessity to do nothing but wait until such self help matures, constitute the disorder in the situation evoking this form of response. Not unfrequently is the parental instinct manifested as a form of scepticism, which is a selective re- sponse to the abstract disorder of the cosmos. Again, the background of tender emotion may become studded with all sorts of violent emo- tions. The extremes to which all creatures go in order to defend their young, the chastisement which sometimes gets meted out to children upon the most trivial occasions, and the alter- nations of imperiousness and fawning which parents bestow upon their offspring, illustrate the point. Under the spell of the tender emo- tion, perceptual distortion is the rule; the "cute" acts of one's own children may at the same time be equivalent to vandalism, and a "prank" 323 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION in one environment may be an evidence of con- cealed misanthropy in another. Later on, the confidence in the superiority of one's own chil- dren, — on account of parental joy in being a cause, — is the basis of the plebian dogma that no one is quite good enough to mate with them. All these events are mal-adjustments, and the nearsightedness which must go with such in- stinctive and emotional reactions appears to be incurable if treated strictly within its own terms. 19. Gregariousness is the social instinct par excellence. Only the few are hermits, the rest of us are beholders and beholden all the while to the rest of society. Perhaps no other in- stinct could be gotten along so poorly without, and yet no other instinct demands as its tax so much equilibration to render it harmless. In- deed, the virtues, so-called, are the taxes we have to pay for gregariousness. It arises out of the fear of solitude, the uneasiness we feel at being absent from our fellows. But I take it that it is not bound up with any affection for our fellows, for we do not necessarily like those with whom we prefer to be. The main discom- fort of solitude comes through the realization of unfilled spaces between our body and those of others. Cities, states, clubs, fraternities, 324 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX churches, and all other organizations are pri- marily social aggregations for the annihilation of solitude. Solitary confinement in prison is the rational psychological limit of punishment, since we are not so constituted as to systemati- cally punish a man by utter "cold shoulder." Were such the case, doubtless the person so re- jected would immediately put himself off. The jokes about bachelors and old maids are con- cealed scorn at a lack of gregariousness, regard- less of how dismal a predicament many of the "unclaimed blessings" so discriminated against, have escaped. This instinct, however, does not in any way guarantee that the satisfying person shall be met by the mere fact of there being other bodies in the vicinity, and as such it rep- resents again the general principles of disorder and absence of clear perception. 20. It is hard to draw the line between the play motive and the instinct of acquisition. We saw in the former chapter, that the movements of the stomach were gone through with regard- less of the presence of nutriment in that organ. Thus it is in many another situation with re- gard to the human body, — series, rather than reasons are the ultimate bases of situations. In play and acquisitiveness we find basic certain odd fumblings, manipulations, gatherings and 325 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION scatterings, apparently from an excess of ener- gies, though not a surfeit of them. Certain mo- tions can be gone through with at a low ex- penditure of energy without the slightest degree of exhaustion ensuing. Acquisition also arises out of fumbling, but the resulting conscious- ness, — predominantly motor, — of having things in a certain spacial and motor relation to the body, produces further stimulations to the same end, and we keep gathering rather than throw- ing away. When such occurs, we have a case of perception. For the word "mine" principal- ly means "that thing frequently responded to." Furthermore, thinking about the things we have so responded to is auto-catalytic in its charac- ter. At the basis of miserliness and wealth lies this instinct of acquisition, — both differing sole- ly in the co-presence of the instinct of self dis- play. But there is no evidence for believing that there is an intention behind this response, — those forever planning to become rich, rare- ly becoming so. On the other hand, let Socra- tes come up and ask the possessor of wealth why, or to what end he is accumulating, and he cannot for the life of him tell. No reason given is exclusively in the field of inquiry. In this connection one will observe that the instincts are not characterized by any specific, nameable 326 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX content. Hoarding and jealousy may become co-functioned, but hoarding and generosity may also appear together. The successful business man may dislike the whole scheme of his en- deavors, or the unsuccessful one be of the opin- ion that his plans cannot fail. In all such cases, the non-focality to the person himself of his ruling manifestation is indicative of the general principle of disorder as the basis of instinct. 21. Constriictiveness is frequently named among the instincts, but for our purposes only the random fumbling of objects preparatory to the possible ordering of them on the basis of perceptions, could be called by any such name as "original tendency." Furthermore, fumbling is typical of mal-adjustment, and appears to have no specific, attendant emotion. Psycholo- gists have never admitted that destractiveness is as "original" as is constructiveness, for they have steadfastly overlooked the fact that young children maltreat and destroy long before they ever build or construct. Constructiveness and destructiveness might be profitably treated of together, even if but for the diff'erences they show which are not manifest in the spelling of the words. For the first of these lacks those anger elements which the second possesses. Random fumbling, again, may be suddenly su- 327 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION perseded by the perception of order, and thus be brought to some sort of furthering conclu- sion; while destructiveness meets all orderly situations only to disregard their perceptual ele- ments, and to reduce them to disorder. Once more, certain successful achieving of a pattern is frequently followed by the loss of that pat- tern, and so the orderly and disorderly series may alternate with considerable frequency. Only in point of its intermittent clumsiness, then, do we call construction an instinct, for when a dominant pattern is attained and stead- ily functioned, the environment becomes stable, and the responses non-contradictory. On the other hand, destructiveness is functioned by a strabismic consciousness, that is to say, a cross- section in which many un-shot complexes are smouldering, whose functioning is anti-social in its tendency. Vandalism, the joy of produc- ing carnage, the antique postulate of a trans- temporal oven in which those not holding views tangent to our own were to be eventually kept at n degrees Centigrade, — such are common ex- amples of this response to internal disorder with its attending manifestations. Even to see one building torn down to replace another causes some orderly minds to avoid the sight, as well as to feel resentment at the act. And 328 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX there is perhaps validity in the legal status of those who butcher for an occupation, in that they are excluded from certain jury service on the basis of lacking perceptions of the orderly status of an organism amongst its kind. 22. Three other forms of complexes may suitably be presented here. These are sugges- tion, sympathy, and imitation. The first has to do with the inducing of a non-perceiving con- sciousness to function the ideas of another when put into w^ords calculated to appeal to his in- stincts or emotions; and also to formulate pre- maturely his motor functioning on that basis. Sympathy is the appeal to, or sharing of, the surface emotions of another, with or without attempting to stir up the background of sup- pressed and smouldering complexes. Imitation is either copying the motor responses of an- other, especially gross movements, or copying the effects produced by another, — all such copy- ing being virtual in its identity rather than fact- ual. No resident benefit lies in any of these three, considered as bare descriptions of what happens in cases where they are exhibited. Nev- ertheless they can be made subservient to al- most any purpose promulgated, and this is of large account in the educational world, as well 329 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION as in advertising and selling, and the general business of social organization. 23. McDougall's enumeration of the com- plexes of emotions falls into two groups. The first one does not necessarily imply the existence of sentiments, while the second one does. "Senti- ment" is taken to mean "an organized system of emotional tendencies centered about some object." In the first group there are the fol- lowing emotional complexes. (a) Admiration. This is a compound of wonder and negative self-feeling. (By com- pound is meant a simultaneous occurrence, sometimes in the form of partial fusion, some- times not.) (b) Awe. This is composed of admiration and fear. (c) Reverence. This is derived from a blend of awe and gratitude, both of the ele- ments of awe being clearly present. (d) Gratitude. This is composed of the tender emotion and negative self -feeling. (e) Scorn. A mixture of awe and disgust. (f) Contempt. Composed of scorn and positive self-feeling. (g) Loathing. A compound of fear and disgust. (h) Horror is the acme of loathing. 330 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX (i) Fascination. This is a mixture of loath- ing and wonder, fairly well balanced. (j) Hate is composed of anger, fear and disgust, while (k) Envy is derived from negative self- feeling and anger. It must be kept focal that the binary and tertiary character of these com- pounds is incapable of any such clear exhibi- tion or demonstration as is possible with sensa- tions and perceptions. And the "organized" character of them is little more than bare "with- ness." Structure they lack, and are thus re- sponses to situations involving disorder. But by virtue of possessing among themselves com- mon parts, or common functions, the transition from one to the other is readily made in the presence of the same exciting object. All it re- quires is that the object be in mal-adjustment, — the train of these complexes is then easy to fol- low. As a tacit verdict of humanity that these emotions are not solely referable to the body, we have the expressions, "loathsome sight," "fascinating woman," "hateful delay," "he treat- ed me with contempt," and the like; and this is one of the signal examples of naivete being acute, whether by intention or not, with per- ception or without it. But naivete is far more concerned with complexes than with the other 331 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION data of consciousness, and for this unexpected correctness it must not fail to have due credit. 24. The following are the complex emo- tions which do imply the existence of senti- ments. (a) Reproach. This is composed of anger and the tender emotion. (b) Jealousy. In this we find a painfully checked positive self-feeling plus an oscillation between revenge and reproach. (c) Vengeful emotion. This is a compound of anger and a wounded self-regarding senti- ment. By the latter expression is meant that the insults one receives, if not at once resented and paid for, lower one in the eyes of his fel- lows. And in this predicament, (manifesting a wounded self-regard), it is curious to note, that, no matter how many eyes are turned upon one, the social center of gravity is not thereby set- tled in the object of such regard, but way off, as it were, clear outside the situation. It is as if the terms "beholder" and "beholden" in this case had absolutely nothing in common. (d) Resentment. This is what becomes of the vengeful emotion when the insult is at once avenged. It is perhaps nowhere better illustrat- ed than in the treatment of a subjugated na- tion by its victor. I do not mean the payment 332 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX of indemnity, or the other material symbols of conquest, but the lasting desire of the conquer- ors to see the individuals of the losing nation humbled and browbeaten. It is as if on the material side an eye would pay for an eye, but on the sentimental side, a whole jaw^ were none too much to satisfy the loss of a tooth. Stir- ring a nation to patriotism, likewise, is often nothing more than arousing a feeling of injury by generalizing, and sentimentally magnifying some forgivable misdemeanor that was never meant to provoke the use of cartridges. (e) Shame. This is a struggle between self-display and self-abasement, with their at- tendant emotions of positive and negative self- feeling. Just why shame, as a weakening con- dition, should have been so largely used in mat- ters of moral significance, is easier to determine from a legal than from a psychological stand- point. The legalistic view of good and bad makes special use of this sentiment on the ground that the intensest subjugation is justifi- able. Psychologically, there is nothing to op- pose justifying the means by the end, if the end is worthy; but as soon as the question of which end is worthier is introduced, the status of the shamed individual must come in for its share of consideration. When the struggle be- 333 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tween self-display and self-abasement, as in shame, becomes reconciled by a blending of the two, we have, instead, (f) Bashfulness. (g) Remorse is shameful and angry regret, (h) Joy is separable into what is called the esthetic pleasure of contemplation, (with which we shall deal in the last chapter of this book), combined with sympathetically induced pleas- ure, the tender emotion, and positive self-feel- ing. (i) Sorrow, on the other hand, is not the negative of the above, but rather composed of a Daffled tender emotion, (such as occurs in death and the loss of the recipient of affection), pride and hope negated, and negative self-feeling. Sor- row and joy are usually spoken of as antithetic- al, but by analysis, only one term is seen to be logically negatived in passing from one to the other. Their antithetical character depends upon the motor possibilities which can be stim- ulated under their dominance of the organism. In this respect, psychological opposition and logical opposition have many interesting dif- ferences, which the student should carefully find for himself, inasmuch as erroneous infer- ence arises from the confusing of the two. (j) Pity, McDougall calls the tender emo- 334 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX tion, tinged with sympathetically induced pain. Pain in this sense, as well as pleasure as above used, never refers to what we meant in the first chapter by the sensation pain or the sen- sational attribute pleasure. For pain, one should here substitute unpleasantness, and in emotion- al complexes he should also regard it as much stronger than sensorial feeling-tone, inasmuch as emotional discharges are stronger than tro- pistic releases. Furthermore, when there is lacking the release of the suppressed energy in emotions, there is functioned both negative self- feeling, and that which McDougall, whom I have generally followed, means here by pain. (k) Happiness is enumerated at the close of the account, and it appears to mean a gen- eral bodily Duoyancy as a result of clear percep- tion and satisfactory functioning. But we are here on the border line of ethics, the psychology of which must be reserved for the following and final chapter. 25. Mood is hereby defined as a co-con- scious appearance of any emotion or sentiment. It may be strong or weak, and when linked wdth some specifically characteristic motor manifest- ation, it is called temperament. It is significant to note that both mood and temperament may be functioned side by side with certain further- 335 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ing perceptions, but this fact of togetherness does not make mood and temperament strictly perceptual in character. All suppression is ac- companied by the expenditure of energy, and whenever suppression occurs, it means both less than the normal amount of clear perception and less definite motor functioning on the basis of a furthering pattern. In all these sentiments, it is plainly seen that the thesis of this chap- ter in regard to the disorderly object or situa- tion as their stimulus, and a mal-adjustment to the situation as their motor aspect, need not be recanted. The Crowd. 26. The social order, in which we find our- selves irrevocably embedded all the while, is one of the environments to which we cannot help but respond. It is not the only one of this kind, however, and even though it be a dis- ordered object, it yet lies in the midst of an- other environment, called, for want of a parti- san term, the universe. Now the conscious cross-section not only contains responses to so- ciety, to sense data, and to perceptions; but we also respond to principles of order, and to things which are neither mental, physical, mor- al, social, or artistic, but which are the stuff or stuffs out of which these orders are generat- 336 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX 0(1, and into which they plunge more or less firm roots. This merely in passing, for the business of psychology, while concerned with responses, (and thereto with all the responses that an or- ganism makes), has not within its province the ordering of non-human responses and tenden- cies, but only of those which can be glued to pronouns of various calibre. And one of these pronouns which we shall straightway consider is the pronoun "we." 27. The pronoun we, with its other forms of they, us, ours, their, them, and the like, is symbolical of that domain known as the Crowd. In this connection the material here pre- sented is drawn from Gustave Le Bon's account of "The Crowd," all of which would amply re- pay perusal. The crowd is a curious organiza- tion. Its intended perceptions are swamped by instincts and emotions, and its deliberative pow- er is in inverse proportion to its size and the proximity of its members. A crowd may be any group of people in one area, in sight of or bod- ily contact with each other, or, it may be com- posed of spacially isolated individuals respond- ing to the same or duplicated stimulus. The crowded spectators of a base-ball game are a crowd, as well as the isolated readers of the morning paper at the breakfast table. There 337 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION are two main types of crowds, — heterogeneous, and homogeneous. The first of these consists of individuals casually and haphazardly brought together. No deliberation or choice exists on the part of the members of such a crowd, leading them to just that place, or expos- ing them to just those other human beings thus met. The heterogeneous crowd is of two sub- sidiary types, — anonymous and not-anonymous. Street crowds, base-ball crowds, circus crowds and the like, are anonymous; while juries, par- liamentary assemblies, college faculties, lodges, and church gatherings, are of the second type. 28. All such assemblies, whether suddenly congregated, or slowly agglutinized, are under the sway of unconscious sentiments. Every dif- ferent nation is typified in the manner in which groups of its individual citizens get excited and pledged to some cause or movement. A crowd will demand anything its leader emotion- alizes them to demand. But who is its leader? Not the speaker who happens to be addressing them or leading them on. Not the principles enunciated from a rostrum or the slogan into which he crystallizes their opinion. Their lead- er is rather the summation of their smothered emotions, their unformulated dissatisfactions; for the tiling for which they vote, cheer, or pour 338 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX out their energies may not l)e at all that which they, as individuals, in calm moments, might determine upon as something desirable. It is only the fact that something is presented to them as being in a like condition to what they imagine themselves to be which arouses their enthusiasm, and this vicariously functions the exhibition of emotions, sentiments and instincts in its behalf. All heterogeneous crowds are an example of co-conscious and unconscious func- tioning of a disorderly object. In all such groups there is a slight inclination toward anarchy and barbarism. 29. Homogeneous crow^ds are divided into these three groups, sects, castes, and classes, (a) Sects, wdiether political or religious. In all sects, the individual members may differ very much as to education, caste, or profession. But the unifying element in them is some principle which is of another series than their education or profession, and to which these make no dif- ference. Some belief is aroused, some need for its application is shown, and the rest follows. Further unification comes through the expendi- ture of motor energies to the cause; wealth is poured out, buildings are erected to house the assemblies of the members, and the strength or weakness of the belief in the principle of the sect 339 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION is manifested by the number of things they fur- ther in connection with their material develop- ment. A belief is a meaning, and therefore it is tested for its tenacity by what those function- ing it will do upon occasion or in a crisis. Its strength or weakness, and its truth or falsity need have no connection. The pragmatic test of history as to whether beliefs have held, and the logical analysis of their terminology and co- herence, are two separate and distinct items; the pragmatic test is an emotional one in this case, and the test of analysis is one of percept- ual character. The first is an example of in- formal logic, the second, of the logic of exact formulation. It need not surprise the student of exact logic to find that analysis usually dis- covers nothing stable in all forms of popular beliefs. It is only in the science of psychology that we find a complete account of erratic emo- tional functions. 30. (b) There are three chief castes among Anglo-Saxons, namely, the priestly, the military, and the host of occupations. In these we find the highest type of crowd organization. The labor unions, it is safe to say, represent the most unsettled type of caste, — the other two, the priestly and the military, represent more systematic stratification, with a resultant of sat- 340 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION isfaction and contentment with their lot. In heterogeneous races the vohitile and mercurial elements are necessarily predominant, and the era of strikes is unavoidahle in a people just coming into individuality. In such cases, the caste may be said to be crystallizing. On the other hand, where several generations of the same family follow the same occupation, — thus making a homogeneous race in point of com- pleted stratification, — no disturbance whatever is so emotionalized as that which threatens the downfall of such a caste system into which the individuals have been cemented. One might again point out the fact that no matter how- much we clamor at times for a change, the rec- ord of past events shows that those who clam- ored loudest, were the most unwilling recipients of it, as well as those who sank back the soon- est into their former condition. 31, (c) We usually enumerate three classes, — the peasant, middle, and aristocratic. The habits, education, and interest of the in- dividual members of each of these are very similar. Sometimes it is difficult to draw the line between the members of these three classes, there being many kinds of recognized aristocra- cies, such as those of wealth, of talent, of intel- ligence, and so on. In classifying classes, how- 341 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ever, the monetary test is usually applied, and the border line cases omitted. By this means, also, it is easy to see why these classes have the poorest form of organization of all crowds, whether heterogeneous or homogeneous; for all those in the peasant and middle classes who are struggling out of them do not want any organ- ization that solidifies their position in that class, and the rest are too busy maintaining their posi- tion to become organized. The noiweaii riche furnish in this instance curious hints of the mo- mentum which economic conditions give to functions of a social character, for their un- conscious complexes, becoming suddenly re- leased, indicate the disorder which the condi- tion of sudden wealth produces. 32. When a crowd functions some punish- able disorder, it becomes a criminal crowd, or mob. But no one person in a crowd is doing exactly what the whole crowd may be said to be doing in such a case. In fact, nobody is at the head of a crowd. It has no head, for it is only releasing collective complexes, only satisfying its collective grudges. The ringleaders are us- ually punished, because the law demands a vic- tim; but the ringleaders are often only those spacially in front of the others, and only seem- ingly more indecorous than those pushing from 342 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX behind. Thus when one asks, "who started the rumpus?", it is not altogether a joke when each suspected culprit avers to the contrary. But, as Lc Bon says, "All collectivities have it in them to develop to a high degree certain ferocious and tender instincts." For the collective mind is an accumulation of suddenly uncorked sup- pressions, and what is done by it is a function of the environmental possibilities of the situa- tion as well as of the individual complexes. The crowd usually demands some one to be its lead- er as well as some candidate for anathema or praise. If a crowd is witnessing a fire at night, when a rescue is attempted, it is sometimes pa- thetic, sometimes ridiculous, and again some- times terrifying to see how the crowd both ten- derly nurses along the rescue, and also threat- ens an unsuccessful rescuer with the death he failed to avert. It roars and defames, it weeps and cries, it groans; it uses the same words in a "sacred and hushed tone" as it does in yelling and shouting. Here the object eliciting the re- sponses is clearly a disordered one, though oft- en hard to name in exact terms. 33. Deliberative assemblies have worked out a system which substantiates my thesis in this chapter. Important measures are first pre- sented, then debated, then referred to a com- 343 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION mittee, and so on, in order for the emotional element to have its little part, if need be; but also in order for the measure to have its logical and perceptual inning as well. Often, indeed, a committee or a single individual drafts and ad- judicates a matter with but the scantest refer- ence to the collective body that finally passes on it. On this principle, absolute monarchy is worthy of some consideration, psychologically, as well as such forms of government known as oligarchies and aristocracies, in the strict sense of these terms. Popular government is baseci on the idea that the many think better than the few. Psychology has nothing to say about government, but only about crowd organiza- tions in point of which this further quotation from Le Bon is pertinent : "In any deliberative assembly, called upon to give its verdict about a matter not entirely technical, the intelligence of the individual members counts for nothing." 34. The jury is a heterogeneous crowd, formed on occasion into a deliberating body. Why twelve members should constitute it is re- ferable to informal logic. Juries are usually made up of strangers, and as such represent an organization in which the knowledge of other minds engaged in the same work as one's own is supposed to count for nothing. This may or 344 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX may not be so, but it is only for us to say here that after a jury gets into the jury room to con- sult and deliberate, the results show something quite irreconcilable with the notion that the jury does not behave as a heterogeneous crowd. Juries are not unimpressible by the prestige, wealth, beauty, widowhood, countenance, and so on, of those witnessing, or on trial before the bar; and their emotions are often the only hope of the lawyers functioning in the case. Even though argument and debate are indulged in in the jury room, the crowd character is never sujj-focal there. Stubborn men have also been Known to completely reverse the tendency of the first ballot, — it being a test of endurance rather than a careful, cool deliberation which decided the case. It is the opinion of more than the writer that all juries should be forced to taKe a cold bath before going into the jury room, ana should further be obliged to avoid all vaso- motor constrictions by whatever means would be safest and quickest at the same time. 35. The informal logic of crowd reasoning is evidence of the disordered environment which it is functioning. The most exaggerated and ingenious sentiments are indulged in. The crowd never distinguishes between the actual and the virtual, between the possible and the 345 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION impossible, or between the internal and external aspects of the thing presented to it. It de- mands "equality," or "liberty," or asks things which are entirely beyond its power to use. It scorns a feeble, but reveres a strong authority; a reported weakness in the government will raise a mob very easily, but the report of even iron-handed dealings will at once quiet their emotional unrest. "Might makes right" is act- ually crowd reasoning, whether it be also true, false, or absurd. Catch phrases, slogans, and shibboleths, are just the material out of which crowd reasoning is constructed. The orator who addresses the crowd on the street need say nothing rational, just so long as he speaks in terms which the crowd will interpret as being "w^hat it thought also." An emotional collec- tivity thinks and speaks anything at all, the more disconnected it is the surer is it of being emotionally functioned; and so such things as analogical reasons are cheered as the very acme of truth and right. Crowds are also impressed by the marvelous. They demand some author- ity, and in lieu of living governors of men, any dead hero or nebulous ancestor will do very nicely. National figures of the past century, traditions, the longevity of customs, the great- ness or decline of an institution, — all these 346 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX stimuli manifest a universal tyranny over all sorts of crowds in all sorts of nations and ages. "The one tyranny humanity has always been under is the memory of its dead." But shake once the confidence of a people in its past, and you will find that "the end of a belief is the beginning of a revolution." And it is not amiss at this point to recall the passages in this book on auto-catalytic action as the basis of neural momentum, with the other remark about the desire for change we so often function in speech. For the crowd is after all only a magni- fied individual, and in the midst of a crowd we can often detect more of our smothered emo- tions and tendencies than in any other situa- tion that ofil'ers itself. Neural unification is rare, while self contradiction, which is a function of chronic, unresolved neural inhibitions, appears to be not only one of the chief products of any and all instinctive and emotional manifesta- tions, but indeed their source. 36. Another form which the emotional complex takes is the dream. This normally oc- curs in sleep, and is the rearousal of forgotten or suppressed ideas which have not been func- tioned during waking hours. It is substan- tially the revelation of a wish, — by which may equally be meant the hope that something will 347 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION happen, as well as the fear that something might happen. But in either case a dream is an un- shot residue of emotional or instinctive func- tioning, — the back-water of consciousness. Be- fore entering into the physiological or ideation- al processes which give dreams their being, it will be profitable to consider briefly other forms of the rearousal of past consciousness, in order that comparison, contrast, and orientation may serve as means whereby they may be better understood. 37. These other forms are memory and imagination. Memory has until recently been considered as something which resided in cer- tain cells of the cerebrum, and which, by a process of irradiation or some such neural re- lease, got into consciousness. Both of these views, — that of its being a single process, and that of its being the dormant content of special brain cells, — are not to be upheld in this book. There have been found in laboratory investiga- tions not one but four dififerent modes of re- arousal of past events, none of which give mem- ory contents exactly identical with the original. Memory, far from being a reduplication of the object, is a tendency to approach the class of objects of which the sense datum remembered is but an instance, or a member, and when this 348 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX memory content is fully developed, we have concepts, rather than percepts or sensory de- tails. So that every remembered object is on the way to generalization or conceptual content. On the other hand, the four kinds of rearousal of the content differ much from one another. And there is always a gap, a latency, between the sensorial presentation and the recall, and what is going on in this gap escapes introspec- tion. We have seen the particular object, let us say, but when the rearousal comes, we shall then be visualizing only that general class of visual phenomena instead; and this gap or la- tency is the time in which the particularity of the content is being lost. But this is nothing outrageous, for the particular object was also a member of its class, particular in this case meaning only that certain specific members of the series constituting it were functioned togeth- er. And each of these members had affiliations, common parts,— functional or contential,— with many other members of those series. Such, indeed, is often the case even with sensation. The paradoxical cold and heat, the tickle sen- sation, the estimation of movement and so on, all differ at times from the mathematical and physical status of the stimulus in ways that are familiar enough to need no exclamation points 349 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION as we pass. So that while in the focal area of consciousness we function with the words "this particular one," the sub-focal areas of con- sciousness could be as well functioned by the expression, "one of those which has been func- tioned before," as by other words referring to focality. Thus it is that when the object is re- moved from sense focality, and we recall it, while mentioning it or not, what gets restored in after-imagery is that cross-section of the se- ries making the object, which will be normally functioned with the least effort possible. But mark, that an intense effort to recall something is always accompanied by a tension in the body, as well as by an effort to place our organism in the identical relation to the absent stimulus as it was to it while present. For ideas are func- tioned by the aid of bodily attitudes, just as emotions are functions of the general disturb- ance caused by our bodily mis-orientation with the situation. 38. The four ways of reinstating absent stimuli are these. 1. Perseveration, which means that, shortly after its disappearance, without any mediating focal ideas, there is a re- currence of the original idea. 2. Persistence, (which usually occurs in fatigue or exhaustion), w^hereby is meant that ideas become repetitive 350 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX because we no longer perceive differences, or react in a discriminating manner to the sensory present. 3. Iteration, or the random recur- rence of fleeting impressions, and 4. The free emergence of those things we have often func- tioned, especially motor habits. Now if any one wishes to know how the absent object gets reinstated, or past functioning repeated, the answer is that the pastness or absence of the object is one thing, and its non-dependence upon consciousness for its existence is another. An object is something that will stimulate, whether it be orthogonally disposed to the body and its sense organs or not. The time series is one series and the space series is another, but there are other series, neither in time nor space, as we pointed out in the first part of Chapter III. Things have position in the order of knowl- edge, as well as in Florida or the year 1914. Things also have position in space twice at the same time and even twice in the same space, if we but open our eyes to that fact. 39. Let this specifically serve as an exam- ple. When we hang a mirror on the wall of a room, and stand in front of it, we can see our- selves doubled, — literally projected through the wall into the space beyond. If the wall of the room is continuous wdth the sheer edge of a 351 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION precipice, we do not see the object mirrored behind the wall tumble into the chasm below, even though its position relative to us is beyond the threshold of safety. And yet the mirrored object is colorful, shapely, motile, almost every- thing that we are, — except that it has no weight. Bat neither have our shape, color, and motility any weight. So that the mirrored object is composed of all those qualities which are not physical objects. This is also the substance of ideas. This, likewise, is the substance of mem- ories. The mirrored object is faithful to the shape, color, and movements of the original, but the mirror merely analyses out the non-ma- terial properties, and is thus a logical instru- ment as well as a sense organ, strictly defined. If a man is standing in front of a mirror and shaves himself, the mirror, of course reversing every horizontal movement relative to the ob- server, will betray the slight abrasion that the "real" skin suffers. But while the man's face has a tiny drop of blood upon it, the mirror face has not, — it has only a drop of red, which is one of the essential properties of the contents of the capillaries. Again, "the painted hawser will hold the painted ship," but it takes a rope hawser to hold a wooden ship. And so on. Thus the point is well taken that the physical 352 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX order of things is not the only order into which they get, regardless of the status of those other orders. But certainly they are not in the same time and space, nor entirely under the same laws as are the physical orders commonly ap- pealed to for truth and validity. 40. This is not only an aside; it is a neces- sary prologue to the proper understanding of memory and other co- and sub-conscious phe- nomena. The rehabilitation of the object in some sort of sensory content, faint and unfaith- ful though it be, is no more mysterious than is the phenomenon of mirror space. Nor is the motor readjustment of the body to a situation in which some instinct or emotion is repeated by the mere mention of a word or the presen- tation of an idea, any more subtle than are the original orders of things which get cross-sec- tioned into sensation and perception. The ob- jects of memory and imagination have no po- sition, and may be anywhere, just as the quali- ties of sensation may be anywhere. And mem- ory that comes pat with the provoking stimulus is primarily a function of the bodily attitude. We are set for that recall by a definite motor pattern, — we have crystallized toward a certain set of perceptions, and the sensory or motor ele- 353 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION merits follow as readily as the water from the faucet when we turn it on. 41. Memory, like the word "experience," is used both as a noun and a verb. The distinc- tion is well taken in connection with sensory content, but when we come to the motor mem- ories, we have a more intricate matter to deal with. The memory (subconscious) of the oper- ations of dressing is both a content and a pro- cess, let us say; but just where one begins and the other ends is rather obscure. And the rea- son is, that the clothes we wear and therewith clothe ourselves in the morning, are themselves best defined by the things we do with them. A hat is something that is worn on the head, shoes are things that are worn on the feet, and so on throughout the wardrobe. So that, since these articles are of the class of attributes-things- functions, so are memories which involve their accustomed use. Emotions and instincts are also of this class of objects, curiously tangled and interwoven, so that we have called them functions of the body, not because they are in- side of the skin and ooze through the pores, but because their position is obscure. We thus re- fer to the body out of a desire to spacialize them and give them position somewhere. 42. Imagination differs from memory in 354 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX that it is just a more agile and less personal transformation of the elements of the ohjects reinstated. James rightly spoke of "the date in our past" which all remembered things have, while, on the other hand, the imagination con- tent was everybody's, being nobody's. But this little hint may serve to make the distinction clearer. Memory is the result of having a motor pattern congruous with more elements that have become ingrained in us than is the case with imagination. There is no difference in the con- tent, relative position, clearness, or other fea- tures in both of these rearousals, but only in the familiarity with which we greet them, and memory is called mine sooner than is imagina- tion; and mine in this case means both period- icity, ingraining, and readiness of motor func- tioning. 43. Now for dreams. Two main condition- ers are to be mentioned in this instance, — the physiological and the ideational. On the side of the organism as a contributing element, we find that sleep is the usual state in which dreams occur. Day-dreams resemble night dreams in that they demand a certain lack of motor focus in the body before they come, — a certain pre- ponderance of co-conscious elements. Sleep, by which we mean the condition of a tired body, 355 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION relaxed, unstimulated by sense data, and be- coming ineffectual with regard to its environ- ment, is principally accompanied (a) by a loss of blood to the brain and a gain to the extrem- ities, (b) by a relaxation of tone in the vaso- motor system, (c) by the retraction of the den- drites, and (d) by a diminution of the supply of oxygen in the brain. And yet, while the ma- jority of functions are dormant, the thresholds are not all high. A mother who wakes not at the thunder storm, but yet at the slightest stir- ring in the cradle, is set not for thunder but for the needs of her child, and her sleep is thus only partial. Indeed we all sleep thus partial- ly, unless the sleep be caused by intoxication. Let us at once state, furthermore, that this par- tial sleep is the physiological element in our dreams, 44. Let us clarify this further. If there are any suppressed ideas in our consciousness when we fall asleep, they usually get functioned in some manner not anticipated. Any slight stimu- lus will be sufTicient to arouse them, even if there is nothing more than an informal logical rela- tion between the conscious elements. We do not predict dreams, but we nevertheless infer their origin with surprising certainty. Psycho- analysis, which is usually misreported in popu- 356 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX lar accounts of it, has been the method by which dreams have been pinned to the objects which have stimulated them. This analysis con- sists in obtaining from the subject, either verb- ally or in his own writing, all of the ideas which leisurely come in train at the mention of one of the elements in his dream, — particularly those concerning which there is obscurity as to their place or meaning. The subject must be truthful and keep back nothing, regardless of its intimacy or scandal. From the few blessed regenerates who are willing thus to admit their human nature, we obtain valuable information in regard to dreams. 45. Such a train of ideas is called "free association," but I do not mean by this that it has anything to do with the notorious doctrine of association which every book on psychology seems to find virtue in repeating. According to it, ideas are said to follow one another in the same order as they have been together be- fore, by virtue of their similarity, contrast, con- tiguity in time, or contiguity in space. Titch- ener dealt this doctrine its first fatal blow in his reduction of these four categories to one only, — namely contiguity in space, which for him summarizes them all. I shall wipe even this one away. Very little that is temporally 357 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION or spacially together gets remembered, or even functioned. And the order of recall does not follow the order of presentation except when motor ingraining has thoroughly taken place. Ideas are, according to this doctrine of associa- tionism, not identical with, but rather complete- ly distinct, from things, and between the two God has put a gulf so wide that no one can cross it in less than two leaps. These ideas were said to come and go in the manner of visitors, and furthermore said to have laws of entrance, eti- quette, and exit. No such rationality disposes the ideas. Logic is no description of how we think, for thinking as independent of the prop- erties of objects is a downright fabrication on the part of those who must perforce provide something for the soul to do. Functional de- pendence is the law of the connection of ideas that have pattern and sequence relative to the objects of which they are a part; and such triv- ial categories as similarity and togetherness are wholly secondary. How much, indeed, of the temporal or spacial present gets recalled in com- parison with what never gets focally recalled? The proportion is almost painfully small. What gets recalled is what gets into the pattern of motor manifestations, so far as focal conscious- ness is concerned; and, on the other hand, inso- 358 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX far as the dream consciousness is concerned, the order of recall and presentation is just as random as the emotionality that functions it, while the vagaries of the dreamer are just those shreds and clippings which the release of his suppressions brings to some sort of focality. 46. The material of dreams is mostly de- rived from the day before the dream occurs. Dr. Sigmund Freud, the Viennese psychologist, who has rendered signal service in ferreting out dream material, divides it into two main parts, namely, the "latent content," or the whole thought-mass of the dream, and the "manifest content," or the part we recall and mention upon aw^akening. This manifest content is an allegory of the latent content, frequently con- taining imagery of the most unsuspected things. For example, wishes and emotions expressed in the dream may go by contraries. Suppose we have in waking life disliked some one ex- ceedingly. The dream may represent us as putting that person out of the way, and then being bitterly sorry for the deed. Or, we may be dreaming of saving his life as a sign that we wished him some, but not the extremest, harm. The important space and time values of the events of waking life may all become distorted, — the things occupying the smallest or largest 359 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION spaces in dreams usually being opposite to their size in the waking estimation. Again, two per- sons manifesting the same emotion in a dream usually are found to represent the same per- sonality. As a general thing, also, the concept enters in largely, — dreaming of an immigrant will typify strangeness, timidity, or the fear of a new venture, and so on. 47. Now all of this material comes from past life and not from some spook who inhabits the corners of the brain or the sleeping room. The sensory vividness of the dream usually re- fers to the events of the day before, while the rest of it is the releases of tension which social and other pressures have necessitated. Five main sources are to be mentioned in this con- nection, (a) Any interrupted thought not fin- ished at the time, (b) All unsolved problems, which will tend to be flashed again and again upon the dreamer's consciousness in kaleido- scopic form. (c) Rejected or suppressed trains of thinking, (d) Parts of co-conscious- ness aroused from the previous day's life, recol- lections of where we hid things, or inadvert- antly put them away, (e) Indifferent or float- ing impressions of things. The making of the dream out of these materials is accomplished in the following way. First, there is the principle 360 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX of condensation. Every element in the mani- fest content represents several things (not one) in the latent content. Common parts ahound. Many anxieties are crowded into one terrifying situation, which by itself, and taken singly, may have little reference to the past of the dreamer. Tlic second element in dream making is dis- placement. The intensity of an element in the manifest content is no index of its intensity in the latent content. Hyperbole is the name we apply to this in matters of spech in waking life. We dream that we are being slaughtered or pushed over a steep precipice. This may merely refer to former situations when some one unwittingly jostled us, or caused us a slight annoyance. The magnitude of the distortion, however, depends upon the emotionality and unification of the personality; the most out- w^ardly modest and pious people may have the worst dreams, but this modesty and piety are no index of their suppressions, which may be maintained in vanity as well as in sincerity. A third feature in dream making is dramatization. Curious anachronisms accompany this. Pres- ent and past are intermingled, and the here and the far are juxtaposeu. The absurd things of waking life become mocked instead, the proud person is given a sceptre, the humble is relig- 361 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION iously turned into a worm, the teacher who "flunked" us is made tlie fireman in a crema- tory, the girl who loved us becomes a superb angel. In the informal logic of dreams any- thing can be expected to happen, for almost anything does happen. We can analyse it after- wards, but not settle upon its course in advance. The fourth and last feature in dream making is regression. The abstract things become con- crete, and single attributes appear as things. On account of this fact, people have frequently been inclined to place large stock in the flying vagaries of their sensoi-y content during sleep. Indeed armies have been raised to conquer, vast sums of money been poured out, deprivation endured,^ — all because some enthusiast with a picturesque vocabulary narrated heatedly his visitations from the "other world." The "inner self" of dreams possesses no such attractiveness to the empirical student of psychology as the naive mind takes for granted to be the case. Dreams typify, and dreams elucidate, but dreams are indices of erratic refraction, rather than evidences of tangency to another cosmos than the one to which w^e are subservient. 48. Bodily postures during sleep or bodily happenings while we are supine make up a con- sideranle amo"P* of the stimuli to dreams. 362 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX Tickle the neck of an enthusiastic dreamer, and he will be likely to dream of being guillotined as not. Drop a little water on his forehead, and he will think the club of Herakles is de- scending with its usual velocity. Turnings over in bed, whether involuntary, or elicited by an experimenter, will usually have their effect in the dream content; while too much heat of the bed-clothes, as well as being uncovered while sleeping, will be dramatized into situations of burning or freezing. Dreams of flying and fall- ing are usually correlated with sexual and anx- iety complexes respectively, and so far have the students of dreams pursued their analysis, that it is but necessary to tell one of them his dreams and be psycho-analyzed with care, in order that these phenomena be tracked to their true stimuli, and in many cases quite eradicated from the future sleeping consciousness. 49. No sketch of the emotional life would be complete without some account of the soul. This word, I am convinced, has both a reputable as well as a vicious signification, and 1 shall try here to separate them. "Psychology without a soul" has been the vogue for some years, if not decades, and it is the abuse of the term which is responsible for this state of affairs. Private motives, "moral" reasons, and other traducing 363 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION factors have long been called into play when empirical evidences were lacking; and thus the soul, evaporating out of psychology, is men- tioned only by a certain few who lay no claim to its validity except on the grounds of custom and reverence for the past. The notion of the soul originated in untutored and uncritical per- sons, who were at a loss to explain certain phenomena of mental life, as well as in a hurry to get names for things. The names, however, swallowed up the things, and it took some time for this fallacy to be undermined. The dreams of the primitive man, his personification of the elements and forces of nature, his mysterious regard for everything he could not control, and similar functions of ignorance, brought out his naive beliefs into crystallization, with the re- sult that he knew not the difference between himself and the rest of nature. When such a situation occurs, unknowns are in the majority, and the unknowns are taken as the criteria of the Knowns. One of the products of such think- ing is faith, — a form of scepticism which disbe- lieves in the full manifestation of the universe at any one time, and is inversely proportional to the amount of true knowledge which the individual is willing to assimilate. Ideals are some of the products of faith, and these, by con- 364 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX taining an element of uncertainty, — a perpet- ually unrealizable end term, — are forms of the same scepticism. Religion itself is a theory of the soul, as well as a theory of the structure of the world, and the place which human activi- ties have in it. Of these three, its theory of the soul is perhaps the most important, for its meta- physics is frequently deduced from its psychol- ogisms, while its morality is a function of the changing customs of the era in which it flour- ishes. I shall offer the following theories of the soul, each of which has figured in the past, and each of which is as likely to figure in the future. (a) The soul as glandular secretion. All reference to the soul as being in the body is connected with some organ of the body in which it has its "seat." "The brain is the seat of the mind, has sometimes been uttered in rash mo- ments; and likewise the heart or the liver or the other organs of vegetation have been given the honor above specified. There is something both reputable and otherwise in this statement, for the body is both the center of the individ- ual's existence, as well as dependent for its sta- bility upon the cardiac, respirator>% alimentary and other functions. In all emotional states, likewise, there are certain well defined func- 365 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tions of the ductless glands, such as the supra- renal, the thyroid, and the like, causing the animal better to endure wounds and heal them than otherwise, or at other times. But the dif- ficulty with this theory is that it makes physi- ological processes fundamental without recog- nizing that they are physiological. The emo- tions are disorders, signs of abnormality, and to make the soul as an emotional state, the fundamental thing in human life, is to choose the worst and call it the best. That which was the obscurest, the least known, the upholders of the internal soul have made the cap-stone of their belief, a procedure which is to say the least of it, fatuous. Psychologizing, or the tak- ing of unanalysed psychological data as the fundamental thing in logic, or philosophy, or ethics, or metaphysics, is the name of the error which characterizes all accounts of an internal soul or psyche, which inhabits the interior of the body. Such a "gaseous vertebrate" as this form of soul would have to be, must be the one "unmentionable," and therefore reducible to zero for psychology, (b) The soul as all the functions of the bodij. This theory easily allies itself with the doctrine of "self-expression." One is said to express himself when he does anything that re- 366 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX veals his "inner nature." Being able to find no satisfactory meaning for these terms, I shall have to pass them by. But the doctrine of self- expression must turn out to mean that any and every act is an expression of a self, and thus one has to grade such actions according to some other standard, if the expression is to have any meaning. That which means everything means nothing. Now the soul, as the entire life his- tory of the person concerned, or the present personality, — manners, habits, acuities, emo- tions, memories, and everything one can name which the organism is doing, is a notion that has so far supplanted the previous one that we might consider it the present day tendency in souls. (c) The soul as a specific organization of functions toward a permanent type which con- stantly evolves the new and the beneficial. The writer holds that this view is the only one so far presented which requires a special term to dis- tinguish it from mind, personality, or the whole of the cross-section. For the whole gamut of functions of which we are capable is necessar- ily a developmental series, if there is to be de- duction and permanency to it. We saw that the cross-section is full of incomplete series. At- tributes come and go, and parts have a share in 367 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION many series. Now when a set of functions freely operates, and operates time and again, there is something more intimate and secure about it than w^hen only random sets of opera- tions transpire. For example, there is a vast difference between the person who always tells the truth, and the person who can never be calculated to tell it; for in the former there is a permanent response to the facts of the case, and a lack of inhibitions against the language reaction becoming a derivative of that function. Not only is there also a vast difference between these two persons in point of social or emotional rank, uut the former does not have a divided consciousness, while the latter has. The former has no complexes strong enough to traduce his speech, and the result is both a better organ- ization of his functions, and a chance to become a predictable person, — two things which are denied to the other. This is just a passing ex- ample, but it will suffice to give the evidence why such a person whose consciousness is uni- fied should be said to have a soul, rather than the person of whom the same things cannot be said. 50. No more than a bare outline of the emotional complex can be included in this chap- ter, and the student must look for special treat- 368 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX ments elsewhere. The extent to which com- plexes abound, hinder, and split our conscious- ness asunder is revealed in almost every situa- tion of life. The phobias on which venders of patent medicines thrive is but one example. Another is the New England conscience, or the notion that everything must be interpreted in terms of duty. The delusion of "feeling that the eye of God is upon one" occurs frequently among the slightly insane. The general awak- ening to the destructive eifect of such fears is evidenced in certain moral and religious prop- agandas of the past decade, for whatever ab- surd metaphysics or cosmology they teach, their general stimulus is a recognized need. And yet, most moral propagandas are based upon the fear of something to a large degree, rather than upon the unification of the personality under a positive principle of incremental benefits. In many a religious code the negative suggestibility is assumed, and certain fears are played upon in connection with sickness, dying and the like predicaments, on the ground that phobia and negative instruction are the fundamental mov- ers of human activity. 51. There are certain other matters con- nected with emotion and suppression which be- long partly in this chapter and partly not in it. 369 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION These are the items in the cross-section known as interest, purpose, and will. They are not nouns, however, but something else. Interest, I take it, is the manifestation of constant motor tendencies toward some one special group of objects, plus a satisfyingness at their develop- ment. But this satisfyingness is not necessarily emotional, or, if so, it is considered best as emo- tion arising after the results have been achieved. The success of the motor disposals toward ob- jects is often too much to be assimilated, and, in such a case, the disordered state supervenes. However, interest may be very quiet and not accompanied by glandular secretion or vaso- motor constriction. It has normally, the same character as feeling-tone, — a readiness to re- spond again by virtue of a lack of inhibitory tendencies. Curiosity, which enters into inter- est, was spoken of as one of the safest instincts, and interest is often stimulated by curiosity. A person is interested both in that in which he says his interests lie, and also in what he does most without restraint or forcing. When the personality is unified, these two coincide. One may be interested in what he groans to be re- leased from. Some occupation that is hated, some iteration that is disliked, may be the very thing he will voluntary return to after being 370 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX freed. In such a case the interest is certainly emotional, and as such is a symptom of dis- order. 52. Purpose is the maintaining of a motor pattern in the midst of various environments, each equally contributing to its maintenance. It includes the element of choice. This choice is free, when it operates without hindrance; it is not free when it is hindered: it is deter- mined when the end to be gained can be gained only that way; it is indeterminate when any end term is equally suitable. Along with these are usually considered intention, or that which one is functioning furtheringly; and motive, or the reason why one furthers it. This "why" is cau- sal, it being the chain of events which lead up to the intention. Introspective psychology was once said to furnish the means for determining all these matters, but it has signally failed. One determines them by observing the organism and what it is doing in the midst of its various en- vironments, and then one asks the doer what he is doing, and these two reports are carefully compared, and the result balanced. If the doer and the sayer conflict in their results, the per- sonality is said to be divided; if they agree, he is said to be unified, truthful, and predictable. 53. The will is characterized as the domi- 371 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION nant purpose in the individual. James has giv- en a scheme of the various kinds of wills, — de- liberative, explosive, drifting, and the like, — which are characterizations of emotional and temporal manifestations rather than descrip- tions of what the organism is first and foremost doing in the midst of its environments. For if we but analyse all cases of the will, we find that the thing done, the thing willed, is the most constant response to that environment of which the person is capable. The divided, inconstant person alone boasts of the freedom of the will that is inside of him. The rest of humanity are even now falling into the habit of desiring to be predictable. The honesty of the bank- ers, lawyers, merchants and other persons of the social mele is just this predictability of their actions before they are fully functioned. For when a person says that he has choice and can do whatever he cares to do, it means at the ut- most that he can function thus once and once only. We are never apprehended by tlie law until we step over the threshold of social peace. This threshold may be high one hour and low the next, but it is always a definite function of the environment and the organism within it. Freedom of the will has long been a most un- pleasant topic on account of its being talked of 372 THE EMOTIONAL COMPLEX and never carried out. For the carte blanche we each of us hold, — the privilege to do what- ever we please, — is not a return ticket Irom cer- tain destinations we could inscribe upon it. And those things we say we can do and choose are limited by, first, motor possibility, and second, by the desirability of the end. And this end, unless we are emotionally distorted, is one of the terms of a series already started, and not something which falleth like the Palladium from the blue. 373 CHAPTER V. MATTERS AND MINDS 1. In the foregoing pages I have endeav- ored to present the nature of the common oper- ations going on within a consciousness. Objects sensed, objects perceived, objects in an emo- tional complication, — these are the three chief disposals we make of the various series which meet one another to form quotidian things. The various series which get thus concatenated are the ultimate, neutral entities of the universe. When they are considered as being material for responses, they are called matters, and when they are being responded to, and thus united in the with-for relation, they are called minds. In other words, minds are what human bodies do with matters. Matters include minds, but if human beings are to speak in certain ways, the two expressions are required out of conveni- ence and logic. Whether it is underhanded or not, some matters are commanded by way of our being obedient to them, while again out of such dealings come new matters of an order scarcely predictable; for it is hardly likely that some things would have had the factual exist- ence which they do, had not human activities 374 MATTERS AND MINDS played upon their elements, and thereby found parts and functions possessing significant prop- erties of union and mutual furtherance. We ar- rive on the planet with an organic structure craving food, and clear from the first intake of fluid nourishment to the erection of grain elevators, the human neural response involved is basically the same; embroidered, to be sure, by the constructive functions necessitated by the vast social environment for and against which we strive. Similarly, from the first time we are modest and shy, to the adornment of our bodies with the smothering regalia of collegiate func- tions, the same kernel of impulse dominates the situation, and the wholesale manufacture of clothes and adornments is the organized social structure based upon it. Such a list could be wellnigh prolonged indeterminately, but these examples wlil suftice to make focal the manner in which the dominating responses of the hu- man organism not only limit the possibility of shattering the orders which now stand solid from the mold, but also reach beyond the brief present, and control the futurities of most that he call "mine" and "yours." 2. Nevertheless it would be fatuous to credit everybody with motives of a furthering and permanent character. It is contrary to 375 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION fact, and hopeless to find. As evidence of the truth of this thesis ; let me but cite how unusual it is to find a calm mind, or a creative mind, or a mind that is truthful, or unshattered by com- plexes. How few persons, when they close the house door and enter the street and its crowds, do not shut the door upon their permanent mo- tives! Their environments are largely wooden, stone, and wall-paper constructions; and their morality depends largely in the lack of an- noyances, rather than in the responses to the environments of neutral orderliness. Neverthe- less, it is quite possible that perceptions of or- der may be obtained in the midst of disorder, and since this is a matter germane to nothing else than psychology, here will be the place to outline its development. 3. One is allowed, it would seem, in dealing with those responses called interests, to take a broad perspective of the field they cover. Psy- chology, as the study of the conscious cross-sec- tion, has little need to merely throw its data out for inspection, without throwing out for inspec- tion as well the possibilities of their organiza- tion. And, if I mistake not, one of the requi- sites in stating a problem is to do it in such a manner that the solution will be hinted at in the first fornmlation. That which disturbs our 376 MATTERS AND MINDS perceptions is the emotional complex, and the first thing to do, if one is to have perceptions of order and motor responses of permanence, is to get rid of all the complexes he can. Death is supposed to do this at one clip, and while there are some complexes which are resolved only by that event, there also lies within the principle of common parts another solution which we are at liberty to investigate. The word "soul," which in the preceding chapter was retained in psycholog}^ on good grounds, is a word which should be meant to imply a min- imum of emotional complexes and a maximum of clear perceptual and motor furtherances; and it is this business of obtaining a soul, which is the present topic under consideration. 4. In William James' chapter on "The Self," he enumerates various selves which come and go in consciousness. The material and bod- ily selves he makes fundamental, and the self of the widest and solidest relations he makes the final flowering of neural responses. But the "passing thought," which James made "the thinker," — the Ego, — is not to be included in this present account, however much assistance I may have drawn from his pattern of personal- ity as outlined in that chapter. At once it can be stated that the permanency of the Ego, or 377 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION self, is the ordinal correlation of the responses of the organism to the permanent orders of the universe. The "passing thought" of James is only the speaking voice, and is over and gone as soon as it is vittered. Not that I would claim a permanence for the self beyond the rigidest empirical evidence, but the "now" of psychology is not necessarily that span of time which in- cludes the passing thought; for the "now" is as long as any permanent interest lasts, and may be years as well as minutes. The engineer who put the tubes under the East River may have planned them for years before they were finally laid, and it is so with such constructions that the permanence of the idea, and its focality in mind is unwavering during the time that the individual is functioning and furthering it. I should call such an idea the source of person- ality, and I should say also that the mind fur- thering it was just as permanent as that interest which he was developing was permanent. 5. The self has had a curious history in philosophy and psychology. Descartes was the first acute thinker to ally it with functional ac- tivity, for he decided that the phenomenon of inhibition was the fundamental element in a consciousness. Since then, less and less has the notion of a permanent spirit or spook been the 378 MATTERS AND MINDS ruling theory of the self. James was the last renowned Avriter to assert that "we were always aware of our selves, of our personal existence." This book upholds no such non-empirical prin- ciple. We are our functions, we are our en- vironments, and "consciousness of" thus turns out to be merely an expression by which we pay homage to the tyranny of language. Thus "our own personal existence" is a term which is quite incomprehensible when applied to any other things than bare organic functions, and the focality of them in our consciousness. While writing this page, I am not aware of my per- sonal existence, but of the readers who will re- spond to it instead. Fingers, pens, typewriter and paper are but the media, — the plan it has or lacks, and the receptions it will receive, are the things my mind is made of while perform- ing this function of publication. Even the per- sonal pronoun "I," which is used here from time to time, is the vocal instrument of this per- manent interest, and used solely on account of custom and convenience. 6. James speaks of the hierarchy of selves, and makes the material self, which consists of the body, clothes, relatives and property, that from which all the rest of the interests originate as well as depart. The responses of food-getting, 379 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION self-display, reproduction and acquisition are the elements which enter into this type of con- sciousness, and which have to he satisfied be- fore anything else can have any show at all. Next comes the social self, which is a product of gregariousness, and includes the desire to be approved, the desire to excel, together with the subsequent blames, honors, and satisfactions. Following this is the spiritual self, which ap- pears to be a certain sentimental attachment to one's entire tissue of conscious states. In all this there seems to be a wholesomeness and a catholicity of observation which deserves to be imitated by all those seeking to do justice to the material of psycholog^^ But in his later writings James appears to have laid down an- other set of principles which, far from contra- dicting his earlier ones, enlarges them, and his last statements are in almost entire harmony with this book. Consciousness, as a separable substance of permanent character, he denies to the realm of thinkables and existants. "the "I think," which to most persons means their soul, he reduces to the "I breathe," and regards consciousness as a function, and not as an ever- lasting pronoun. 7. I cite this much of biography in order to show that the present development of psychol- 380 MATTERS AND MINDS ogy runs tangent and not counter to the mat- ter of this book, for with what is now known in abnormal psychology added to the develop- ment of the old-line psychology, we have more than either of them could have furnished alone. And that more is the principle of the ridding ourselves of complexes by vicarious substitu- tion of the perplexing object. 8. Emotional complexes are usually mani- fested in fears and inhibitions of a well defined character. The situations in which they first arose may have been private or public. We may have been mistreated or shocked as chil- dren, and the recurrence of the situation ever kept arousing the same emotions as the orig- inal. We responded in a disorderly manner to the first disordered situation, and were either prevented from resisting it, or thrust more deeply into the mire. Thereafter, whenever enough of the elements of the original situation were present, they summed into a stimulus of the same character as the first, and provoked the same result. For instance, timidity is usually the product of the first few weeks' environ- ment, and timidity is a form of fear. It often happens, therefore, that the new as well as the not-yet-known will provoke the fear re- sponse. The child fears dark corners and 381 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION closets, the young man fears the examination, and the old man fears the executors of his will. Those who fear usually pre-respond to the sit- uation, — commonly called "anticipating trou- ble.' Now the prevalence of phobias, of hesi- tancies, of emotional anticipations, is too wide to need further comment. Once started, it can ramify to all situations having common parts with the originals. But this business of com- mon parts also shows the way out of such a fearing consciousness, for by virtue of perceiv- ing that the fears do not develop in certain spe- cial situations, certain other situations can be produced, in which more fearless than fearful elements predominate; and thereby this com- plex may be signally reduced if not eliminated altogether. 9. Again, the sexual complex, which Walt Whitman facetiously calls the "procreant urge of the world," is one that frequently dominates the organism. Besides being a need of certain vitalizing functions within the body, it is con- nected with shyness, bashfulness, modesty, the wearing of clothes, and many other less obvious social embarrassments. Before mating with an- other of the species, fanciful idealizations, love songs, homages, and various forms of extreme politeness, together, perhaps, with dreams and 382 MATTERS AND MINDS the like phenomena, furnish the only means of harmonizing this predicament with the rest of one's interests. Our acquaintanceships being at the best haphazard, and our friends being those persons we have inadvertantly met, (rather rather than being chosen from a catalogue, or by the mediation of a cosmic duenna), one is privileged to call this insurmountable diiiiculty of choosing the best permanent companion, the true social evil. But where more than trivial, physiological motives are present, and where the environment to which one responds in such a case is larger than the fanciful passion for ownership, the chances are better than other- wise that the error of rashness may be abro- gated. 10. Years ago there was established in the city of Boston what was known as the Lyceum. It was a Greek name, having a flavor of erudi- tion and the classical. Before the establish- ment of this form of amusement, — for the Ly- ceum was a sort of theatre, — the New England conscience would not permit itself to say that plays and entertainments should figure in the daily or weekly routine. But with the establish- ment of the Lyceum, the New England conscious was appeased. The bare change of name, with the feeling that something solid and honorable 383 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION was always to take place under its tutelage, suf- ficed to release the complex of prejudice against the theatre. Those puritanically inclined, hav- ing always secretly wished to go to places of amusement, (but being vexed with orthophobia, or the fear that they had not done right), were now permitted to enjoy themselves. For the Lyceum was nothing more than a theatre, and as such was not quite up to the standard of the better theatres of the country. Indeed, some of the productions were so much worse than those of the regular boards that the Puritans should not have been entertained by them. We now have a replica of this in the productions of non- theatrical entertainers, who furnish amusement under what are advertised as "special auspices." The moaern moving picture shows, which al- ways bear the seal of being "passed by the board of censorship,'' are another partial reso- lution of the complex against amusements. This account is introduced merely to show the way popular psychology has attempted to reduce certain disharmonies in society, but whether they are anything more than lame attempts the reader is urged to decide for himself. 11. Suppressed ideas also take the form known commonly as lying. In this case speech does not function for the facts of the environ- 384 MATTERS AND MINDS ment, but rather for the dominant motive which is in disharmony with the sensory and percept- ual environment. It is the business of ethics to decide whether there are justifiable lies, but it is the business of psychology to infer the sub- sequent harmony or disharmony of any such suppression. The effects of this sort of func- tioning are cumulative, and the full releasing of the complex often demands that one put aside dozens of acquaintances and almost iso- late himself from all those whom he knows. The fund of "conscience money" which now amounts to considerable in the United States Treasury, is the result of the voluntary release of this complex on the part of the contributors to that fund. That no publicity attaches to the reception of it by the government, is a sign of the general increase of sanity. For we are com- ing to know that it does not require an emo- tional orgy to release an emotional complex satisfactorily. The wilful or stubborn child, who may become so through the parental environ- ment of cruelty or ignorance, soon learns by imitation to accomplish his ends by means of rendering a false account of his doings. What- ever else four-year olds are, they are pcrccivers of suuterfuge and insincerity, and the "strange and unaccountable misbehavior" for which they 385 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION often get punished is nothing more than the naive responses to a false situation. To obvi- ate this, a genuine disgust at indiscretions on the part of the elders should take the place of verbal maltreatment; for unless this happens the situation will be one that gets complicated, rather than obviated, in the future. This is merely a hint as to what can be done under sin- cere conditions, for otherwise the sham is more obvious than the attempt to conceal it. Of course, one must be forewarned in all this by the dictum of Socrates, — "Virtue can be taught, but there are no teachers." 12, In certain cases, there is no other way to release emotional complexes than by the use off emotional situations. A consciousness in which only perpetual turmoil exists, — in which the complexes are too numerous to be released through calm considerations of the larger en- vironment habitually refused, — can perhaps be resolved into something harmoniously fiirther- ing by an emotional explosion of large propor- tions. This is one of the things which both tears and laughter accomplish. We do not point to these as ends, however, but only as second class means, for the consciousness that is only brow-beaten and humiliated is fit for nothing but the milder emotions which usually super- 386 MATTERS AND MINDS vene. Nevertheless, this form of release is found effective, for the release of all complexes is to be desired at almost any cost, though it some- times becomes a matter of choosing between the zero of stability, and the maximum of instabil- ity. In the large, there is less clear percep- tion than emotion in the common conscious- ness, and the predicament thus entailed is obvi- ous. I suppose the ethicist would say that what- ever enters curatively into such a situation is a good, but he is not urged thereupon to de- cide. Psychology of Value. 13. The phychology of value enters into considerations of the cross-section whenever we have dealings with the good, the true, and the beautiful. The first concerns the psychology of morality, the second the psychology of reason- ing, and the third the psychology of art. Val- ues are the permanent, non-contradictory sta- bilizers of social and personal interests. A value is, for psychology, then, the functioning of this stability and the satisfaction derived from the things thus stabilizing one. A thing is good when it stabilizes human relationships with re- sulting satisfaction, — in other words when nei- ther perceptions, motor responses, nor feeling tones involved are contradictory. A thing is 387 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION true when it compares with the observations, when it is not functionally opposed to the state- ments one would make in which those same ob- servations could not figure, and when it can be shared with other observers and makers of statements. The psychology' of this is contained in the perception of the facts entailed in the statements, and in the naming and arranging them in a connected discourse. Something is beautiful when it produces a harmonious state of mind. The criterion here is, however, the harmonious state in minds which are not rid- dled with emotions. Beauty can be measured. The structure of paintings, symphonies, came- os, pottery, is open to any investigator, and their order, which is the kernel of beauty, is amenable even to yard-sticks, and the machin- ery of physics. The psychology of beauty is the correlation between the balanced bodily state and the balance and order in the beautiful ob- ject. Now all these in slight detail. .4 14. If one asks how permanent a value must be, in order for it to be a cardinal value, no answer is obtainable from a psychologist. He is solely concerned with the continuance of the functioning of this more or less permanent thing on the part of the organism which is his study. It can be functioned for a fraction of 388 MATTERS AND MINDS a second, or for a lifetime. Indeed, some of the functioning in this manner is but analogous to after-images, — the existence of the value as a content of consciousness having ceased. Thus old customs and discarded slogans, to which many persons still attach a huge significance, are but functional after-images of stimuli which have evaporated. They are, then, only eccen- trically referred to an environment which, on the basis of emotion, has common parts with the residual functioning. 15. Morality is the realm of goodness, and the psychology of it is concerned with the per- ception and motor functioning of the stabilizers of society, whatever these may be. Instinctive and emotional actions, the ubiquitous crowd, the functioning of more interests than can be all at one time furthered, brings us either to the perception of order and plan, or to the brink of unsettledness and hesitancy. So that the good thing is either that which stabilizes before any disorder occurs, or which stabilizes afterwards. The words of Aristotle, "virtue is not virtue un- til it becomes pleasant," may be said to apply to the first case; while any response to an S. O. S. signal would be gruel for the second. In either case, the maintenance of an unbaffled in- terest, stable enough to tide one over the next 389 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION period of indecision, would have to be called one of the items in the psychology of morality. 1 he selection of a dominating mterest would be another item. The perception of its poss. I'es, its history, its likelihood of getting perma- nently functioned by the organism, would come in as the rational elements of the choice. Then the testing it out with all sorts of conditions op- erating, the acceptance of it with intentional en- thusiasm, with intentional scepticism, and with intentional neutrality, — in order to obtain a bal- ance, — all these enter in to the psychology of settling the problems of morality. And while this is but a sketch of the matter, it must suf- fice. 16. Truth is a hard matter to get taken se- riously in this century, chiefly because it has been taken too seriously heretofore. It is now generally conceded that the difficulty was sole- ly of language, — we were asking what truth was instead of asking what was true. It is thus with most of the old, large "mouth-filling words" which modern logic so closely scruti- nizes. Capital letters cannot make nouns out of casual adjectives and adverbs. We ask, then, what is the psychology involved in finding a true statement, rather than in finding out what is capital "T" Truth. Now the significant item 390 MATTERS AND MINDS to be considered at this point is, that we do not start to "think" logicalhj, hut only with the informal logic of scattered ideas. The pattern may be there, but the set terms that can be gen- erally understood, as well as the fixed expres- sions which are to embody them, are not what we get in the first functioning of the material of logic. The whole process can be well com- pared with that of distillation. The crude stutT is the mass of ideas with which any formulation starts out. Then comes the linguistic expres- sion, or the first thing refined out of the viscous mass. But this is frequently too individual, too private. It must be laid aside to cool, then taken up again, and redistilled, and spoken, then oriented among those terms in which it is to be embedded, scrutinized as to common parts, common functions, special importance in that environment, and so on, after which it is ready for publicity. This is the work of words, whose meanings lie in what others will do upon their being singly or serially uttered. Logic is not a study of how we think, but a study of the responses that a certain pattern of words will get in a certain environment. If one wishes to be imderstood, he speaks thus and so. Only when words are in such and such a pattern, will they be understood as meaning this and not 391 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION that; one must speak clearly if he wishes to be understandable. These are the elements of the psychology of logic, and logic has validity only after such a thing is accomplished. Any psych- ologist can tell us how he thinks. Random, in- choate, tattered terms or ideas are the first step. Anything whatever in the way of an idea will start it, — there is no one, identical, invariable way in which we start every logical utterance. For patterns that will do in logic are empirical- ly tried and disposed of in one way or another, and not cooked up in some dark mental abysm perpetually veiled so that none can enter and peer about it. Logic has nothing to do with how we think. Logic has only to do with how clearly and unequivocally we speak. The psychology of language is the closest field to logic, and thus the psychology of speech con- cerns the question of functioning one of the dominant motives in consciousness at the time, whether it be focal or sub-focal. For what the logicians, who have tried to describe the way we think, are after, is the vain goal of contents in the sub-conscious, — things which do not ex- ist. 17. The term "reason" and its derivatives have been used more often with a psychological import than with a logical one. "He acts rea- 392 MATTERS AND MINDS sonably," "it stands to reason," "rational thought," and similar expressions, do not always mean something logical. They more often re- fer to the connectedness, or the easily flowing character of the thing mentioned in that con- text. Coincidence is taken for intention, — a factor which is psychological rather than any- thing else. Now reason is not so much a noun, as it is a term which refers to the pattern of the expression that is used to convey a meaning. When judgments coincide in their salient fea- ture, there is said to be a case of reason. Again, where one can start a chain of expressions, — none of which need to be bristling with common parts of each other, but which all together make a system, — whence something can be further implied or inferred, there is said to be ration- ality in the connection. Judgments, on which these connections depend, are terms in relation, implying classification among terms, or correla- tion with relations or functions. The logical mind is the one which judges, tests, and form- ulates the position of one term within a con- text of other terms; tries every functional con- nection it has with all the terms of the series implied, and concludes, not that something must be true, but that some expression has been found in which every term is satified, and every 393 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION term of which can be exhibited. But logic is also concerned with any and all statements, true, false and absurd. "And thrice he slew the slain," is just as good an expression in logic as "And 3/4 he slew the slain," or "And 3.14159 he slew the slain." For the question of how often the slain can be slain, is a question for the logic and psychology of slaughter. When this is de- cided, if there is anything left of the statement, then logic can again take it up and decide its status. But slaying is not logic, — slaying is mo- tor reduction of splanchnic incoherence, — and thus logic is the arbiter of the formulation of expressions, and not of the source of them. 18. From the foregoing it can be seen that there may well be certain expressions which have nothing logical in them, even though the same expressions may be effectual for motor arousals. Take the case of a patriotic oration which bestirs its hearers to deeds of valor and sacrifice. The verbal contents of the oration may be, and indeed, nearl}^ always are, abso- lutely meaningless, insofar as strict logical an- alysis is concerned. Again, every national an- them, if reduced to prose, and tested by defini- tion, is found to be incoherent. 1 need not re- count favorite slogans or shibboleths in detail, but if one is interested in strict logic, let him 394 MATTERS AND MINDS examine the so-called "famous expressions of great [or excited] men," and he will see that many things which have proved "pragmatic" or effectual, are verbal responses to disorder, and nothing else. That they have moved sects or nations to attain certain ends, is not the point; the point is whether they have been worthy of the motivating influence they have had, for, as they stand crystallized into words, they deceive us. In every text-book of logic there are enumerated certain "fallacies," or in- correct ways of formulating one's statements, and these fallacies are all reducible to either in- coordinate or absurd speech. The emotional complex in the "fallacy of ad hominem," the in- coordination of perceptions in the "fallacy of lion seqiiitiir," the emotionalized pre-perception in the "fallacy of petitio principii," are more psychological than logical fallacies, since they have their roots in the primary functions of re- sponse. The strictly logical fallacies, on the other hand, are those which involve the resort- ing of data, and concern inexact formulation. 19. We must now briefly consider several forms of art, and take stock of the chief psy- chological elements therein. Arts are of two kinds,— the time, and the space arts. Of the first, we usually enumerate poetry and music as 395 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION the chief examples; while of the second, paint- ing, sculpture, and architecture are the most prominent. It is interesting to note that a "time" art is one that chiefly concerns hearing; while a "space" art concerns sight. The latter class also depends more upon the motor mani- festations of the hands than does the former, though this dependence is not exclusive. 20. Poetry is defined as rhythmical words. This does not mean that the words need have a connected meaning. Rhythms are sets of im- pulses which have a pattern, exhibiting con- trast effects correlated with organic impulses. A rhythm differs from a bare repetition in that it exhibits grouping. 3/4, 4/4, 5/4 time in music or poetry means, that the first note of the bar gets the only voluntary accent, the rest being functioned on the momentum of that one. No such momentum appears in a bare succession, and such a succession we call monotonnous. Professor Muensterberg calls monotony . any "succession that is hated," but such a definition does not exhaust it. For the monotonous is pri- marily that form of succession which fails to save energy in the organic responses we give to it, and thus it becomes irksome. Gummy bear- ings in machinery, and monotonies in succes- 396 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION sions of impulses are more than analogically related. 21. Poetry is characterized by something further than rhythmical language, however. The choice of fine-sounding words is of great im- portance. Only certain words will produce a poetic effect, by which we mean specifically a mood-complex, plus a rhythm. Now moods are co-conscious arousals of smouldering emotions, and thus poetry is not designed to effect a full focality of the idea involved in it, but rather to arouse a consciousness sympathetic to the com- plexes of the poet. Poetic words are thus not noted for their clarity, directness or specificity; they are musical elements, and not information- al. Further than that, the motor elements of the recitation, and the listening to poetry both evidence to what a large extent the co-conscious enters into art. My own investigations in poetry have led me to state that "euphony" is reduci- ble to "eu-kinaesthesis,"— any sound whatever being pleasant, whose utterance does not bring into focality the mouth movements of the one speaking it. One more fact in respect to the words in poetry: we often are enabled to read some works in a foreign language and get the idea of them without being able to tell exactly, word for word, what it differentiatedly means. 397 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION This is due to the co-conscious arousal of the mood by means of sounds alone, and the rest follows readily after; for just so long as the tones of the stimuli further the pattern once started, so long will the sufficient half-hints of meaning come, summate, and satisfy. 22. Rhyme and alliteration are musical ele- ments. They perpetuate a tonal locality, while they also produce a non-focality of concrete dis- course. If one repeats any word over and over again, and watches how the meaning slowly evaporates the while, until only the sounds re- main, he will have demonstrated the essential element of rhyme and alliteration. The pattern of rhyme having once become established, and the mood firmly fixed in the reader, almost any combination of words may get taken for its face value. Now the point to be stressed in all this is that poetry is not originally clear as to its meaning, and so whenever rhymes need to be completed, or rhythms filled in, the poet is not beyond the temptation of completing and filling in with whatever material he has at hand that will not interrupt the mood. Art of this form, in that it uses words, must be said to abuse them from the standpoint of logic, whenever such a sacrifice of sense to sound takes place. Ultimate judgment, however, is based upon the 398 MATTERS AND MINDS intention, plan, and etiect of the poetic mate- rial; and the what, how, and why of these is just as determinable by those not carried away by the poetry as much as by those who are. 23. The basic psychological elements in music are those of tone and rhythm. By not employing words, music is a purer form of art than is poetry, since it requires no reference be- yond itself for its means or ends. Now melo- dies are rhythms in the sense of possessing pat- tern. "The melody goes of itself," we some- times say, and by that phrase we mean that only the first impulse needs our undivided attention, after which the rest follows as a sort of mo- mentum. Another point to be noted is that mel- odies are affected by tonality in a way not de- ducible from the original presentation of them in one key. Certain musical compositions lose all their "character" if played in a strange ton- ality; even the composer Schubert was once en- tirely deceived as to the source of one of his own "Lieder" by this means. For dramatic ef- fect, nevertheless, a composer often changes key without changing the melody; and canonic and contrapuntal forms abound in similar features. Such a procedure effects the organic accom- paniments of music to such a large degree, that the lack of doubled intensity with doubled 399 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION parts is often counteracted by this means. Har- monization of a melody is actually the accom- paniment of one melody by other melodies, so that in listening to a rich harmony we are focal to but one or two of the melodies then operat- ing, and CO-, or even sub-conscious to the others. It is upon this that the mood-character of most music depends. 24. One form of musical composition, known as "program music" attempts to be ono- matopoetic. In such music there are melodic structures which are planned ahead for the ef- fect they will produce, and labeled by the com- poser, furthermore, as such. Certain instru- ments lend themselves very well to these things, and "storms," "pastoral scenes," "military events," and the like, are quite more than sym- bolized in this manner. Recently, however, (since 1840), there have been schools of com- posers who have attempted to portray anything at all by means of orchestral tone-color. That is, they have endeavored to equate musical phrases with poetic speeches. I cite this fact here particularly to show that art forms are not all developed out of the spontaneous moods of the artist, but can often be the result of deliber- ate intentions. For, while music may not be en- tirely reducible to physics and physiology, yet, 400 MATTERS AND MINDS if one physically studies a rhythm, and sees what it is composed of, he may, if he is astute enough, deduce a "new" form from it, which has value in art. But it is safe to say that the series of art forms which get constantly devel- oped, are asymmetrical, and single, linear ones, rather than bi-dimensional. They arise, uncon- sciously, from moods, and suddenly, rather than from plotting and planning. I do not think it rash, therefore, to say that the art that survives is a derivative of the co-conscious and the sub- conscious, and not something that came when bidden. 25. One word on the psychology of song. When a composer plans to set w^ords to music, or music to words, as is sometimes done, there is often plainly manifest a marked discrepancy between them, if exhibited independently. For while a set of stanzas, for example, changes its subject matter, grammatical form, and signifi- cant punctuation, so far as correlating each line in every stanza is concerned, the music which usually goes with it is uniform for them all. As a result, there are discrepancies which must not reach the threshold of focality, for if they do, the harmonious state of mind will be upset, and the art commence to evaporate. For art and beauty are present by virtue of their con- 401 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tributing elements, and when the elements are disturbed, the beauty is not there, — it ceases to be. If any one asks where it goes, the answer is that its position is implicit in the complex, and when this has no coherence, the beauty ceases. It does not go, not being in the dimen- sion of things that travel, — art being another in- stance of "only when," — and not a case of some- thing mysterious and hidden. Even in a famous song, the beauty present is present by virtue of there being a preponderance of co-consciously functioned pattern, despite the inevitable lack of co-ordination between the grammatical ele- ments and the rhythms of the music. On the other hand, the sentimental and so-called "fa- vorite" songs are examples of crowd conscious- ness, and their incoherent character points to something in their origin which cannot be art. In such a case, moreover, one can correlate the musical preferences of the organism with its preference for something that merely super- ficially satisfies. For the popular notion that music must make one weep in order for it to be choice, has many common parts with serious abnormalities. 26. In connection with the space arts, let us only consider what is meant by an artistic space, or beauty in the visual content. Con- 402 MATTERS AND MINDS sciousness being one with its object, one is per- mitted to speak not only of "a musical song," or "a musical performer," but "a musical con- sciousness" as well. It is the same with the other arts. We beautify a room, for instance, and this operation consists in making the space relations between the objects harmonize. Thus far, simple enough; and language here prom- ises much. But what is the beautifying of a room, or the harmonization of spaces? Omit- ting the norm, for the time being, let us say that the harmonious state of mind which is the goal of art, is the presentation of objects in such a way that (a) the center of reference will not be the observer, but the observed instead. In- deed, loss of self-consciousness is exactly what this means. The art object, to be brief, cannot be felt to be owned while it is felt to be beauti- ful. It is not "mine," nor "yours," nor "ours," but, if the rhetoric be permissible, we are its. (b) In the presence of such an object there will be no motor tendencies to do anything more than to preserve the situation in its original form. And (c) there will be a release of com- plexes in the presence of the situation, so that the latent-period of beauty, upon future presen- tations, will be shortened. Now in beautifying space, it is necessary that the fewest possible 403 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION motor tendencies which disturb the equilibrium be present, and one of the ways this is accom- plished is by balance and symmetry. Here again, something "new" enters in. Any figure, the less extended it is the better, but no matter how ungainly it is alone, will, if doubled on one of its axes, produce an effect of balance. Bal- ance on the horizontal and vertical axis, never- theless, will produce the most satisfying effect, and in many cases we can discover a threshold of harmony even here. For when a figure is doubled, there are balanced tendencies in the motor elements of vision, and through these the gateway to non-personal reference is reached. 27. Thus one factor in the beautifying of space is exhibited. Rhythms of space also serve the same effect. Rhythms of sound are in time, and as such cannot be exhibited all at once; while space-rhythm is presto in character, and the effects are those of fusion and summation, rather than of serial order in time, and sensa- tional continuity. There is also another differ- ence between these two types of rhythm. A row of columns in rhythm may contain far more members than a series of notes in music, and still be grasped in a pattern. For the most notes we ever grasp as a unit are five, or at the ut- most six; while we may get rhythm out of twen- 404 MATTERS AND MINDS ty coluiiins, which in space are presented at once. Rhythms are not only possible in pillars of the same length, but are equally elicited from unequal lengths. The receding into space of the more distant columns toward a point not specifically indicated in the scheme, produces co-conscious elements which balance the filled with the unfilled space. Such co-conscious ele- ments appear also in the framing of pictures, where the mathematical center of the canvas is not the center of the color and shape masses balanced within it. Indeed, for these two cen- ters to coincide is atrocious. 28. Colors will balance as well as will fig- ures. A small, dark color mass at one side of a picture can be brought into balance with a very much spread-out color mass on the oppo- site side, — intensities here functioning the ef- fect. Needless to say, all of the attributes of sensation are elements in all forms of art, and their varied exhibitions often produce effects of surprising newness. Indeed, centering seems to be most subtle of all the artist's nuances, and by the varied framing of certain pictures, ex- ceedingly varied balances and instabilities may be obtained. So unlimited is the color reser- voir, and so delicate is the threshold of effects, that, if one asks whether there are any exhaust- 405 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION ibles in art, the answer is in the negative. And be it finally noted, that the creative interest is largely co-conscious. Just as we have men- tioned the fact that we know our voluntary acts only after they have occurred, so we know that we have created, or put together things to make a beautiful object, only after the plastic mate- rials have left our hands for crystallization. As with the case of revising ideas for the printed page, so we find in art that our hands or voices have bettered our original plan; and this bet- tering is not accomplished except by non-self- consciousness, — that is, it is only attained by responding without personal reference to the stimulus. 29. Some passing mention must now be made of the psychology of the business world. Such things as advertising and selling imply the material self. Advertisements therefore exhib- it permanent needs in such a manner that the readers of them will be induced to puithase. This implies more than mere interest or curi- osity. It implies that motor manifestations shall transpire, with the result that the object shall be bought, and this requires that the operations of purchasing shall become focal. To bring this about, the feeling of one's lack must inhibit the wish to retain what one has already gotten, and 406 MATTERS AND MINDS this is the central factor in selling. Be it said, however, that psychology' may be used either to protect the unwilling buyer or to further the aims of the man selling a useless article. Any matter engaging the social self is psychology: whether we enter a store willing to buy any- thing that attracts us, or whether we go deter- mined to have nothing but the one small arti- cle that is in instant need, — these and all inter- mediate cases are examples of some feature in psychology, and our failure to recognize it as such is not complimentarj'. It may, however, not be systematic psychology, but only the psj'chology of inarticulate thinking; but even so, it follows all the laws which pertain to that special domain. The psychologist cannot, therefore, tell you in advance what will be a good advertisement, for that is determined only after the advertisement has brought business, and not before. But the psychologist can tell you why it was a good advertisement, for every- thing is equally analysable. It is thus seen that analysis and deduction are not necessarily func- tioned by the same protoplasm with equal or comparable success. 30. Selling is argiimeuta ad homincin. Business, while in general devised to supply personal and public needs, is yet so crowded 407 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION by competition that profits become functions of needless accessories. Very little of the profes- sional selling is addressed to persons who act- ually need the article. But the desire to have as much as others have, or to have better than others have, or to be the only one within a wide radius who possesses this or that prized article, is that which makes the salesman flourish. There is a literature today on advertising and selling, which unfortunately goes by the name "psychological," and which once promised to bankrupt everybody for the sake of the mer- chant. This literature is, fortunately, becoming decadent, for the reason that the general in- crease of appeals for sales has inhibited itself, — too much advertising, and too many "below cost" sales look suspicious. There is no need for letters six feet high for persons who still have to examine their change to see if they have lost any. Even at the present date, also, a well- known psychologist, and a gifted writer to boot, is preparing a book for the general public on "How to evade the salesman," or "How to see through the fallacy of advertisements," or some such title, and so the tide, even of psychology, is setting in against the inflated world of un- necessary buying and selling. 31. There is another matter in connection 408 MATTERS AND MINDS with the psychology of business which is some- what in the balance today, in spite of the recog- nition of it as worthy and desirable. I refer to the so called "efficiency" work which such men as Taylor and Gilbreth have made almost na- tional institutions. Efficiency work is time-, and motion-saving, — two things which very greatly interest the business man. It arose from the pressure which the labor unions brought to bear upon the large manufacturer, for, to the con- stantly decreasing hours of work, the utmost output is necessarily conjoined. It is as if the capitalist had said, "All right, work as short hours as you please, but you must work in the strictest pattern so long as you do work." And thus we have our motion studies, and our sci- entific management which eliminate the unfit by machinery. The psychological effect on the worker is various. In the first place, his mo- tions are studied, and he is made to perform rig- idly identical tasks, rather than random ones. He is thus perfected in the small thing he does rather than introduced to the whole pattern of the work he is furthering. Only time can show the full results of this, for while it seems to some to make him a mere machine, to others it seems to give him the satisfaction of becoming a specialist. In the second place, the condi- 409 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tions under which he works are studied by spe- cialists who know much more than does he as to what are the best conditions under which he he becomes most productive, (regardless of whether he "likes" the improvement or not). Moreover, some of his thinking is done for him better than he could do it alone. Our modern factories, no matter how much they may be said to crush the "soul" of the worker, are far clean- lier and healthier than the workmen would have ever evolved alone, if left to think out im- provements in after-hours, or while they were wasting motions and time. And lastly, the eco- nomic conditions which have made the modern factory what it is are evolutions, for the psychol- ogy of the crowd, as well as the psychology of general business have crystallized into this pres- ent form, and it is only due to the manners and minds of men that either the good or bad con- ditions of the present exist. 32. There are many other instances of psychology in every day affairs which could only have a smattering treatment in such an account as this. And so we shall omit them. Be it remembered, however, that whatever is human response to environment is material for psychology. He who has analytic insight will carry with him into every situation he meets, 410 MATTERS AND MINDS the ability to sort the data and see the trend of affairs, especially if he will add to that in- sight the knowledge afforded by a study of the science of psychology. That it is a science, one cannot safely deny. The only difference be- tween it and the so-called physical and mathe- matical sciences is, that there are more insta- ble variables in it than in the others. One can know the human mind as well as he can know the reactions of bases and acids, but he cannot predict human minds unless they are patterned in such a way as to plot a series with very few lost members. In this connection, let it be ad- mitted that we are close to the realm of value, for when one becomes predictable, he functions the permanent, and in so doing gets a logical consciousness. Otherwise, of course, one is pre- dictable only in the sense that he is independ- able, a case which also hints of value in the neg- ative sense. In this sense, psychology is a nar- row strip of existence, and as such seems cu- riously enigmatical until one learns to relax and allow it merely to be exhibited to him with- out a qualm. For all our knowledge is in the conscious cross-section, and this fact makes up for any apparent heterogeneity among those se- ries we find in strict psychology' to be unexpect- edly prime to each other. For as we but func- 411 THE CONSCIOUS CROSS-SECTION tion the universe, and nothing else, all that is complete, incomplete, valuable and valueless, as well as permanent and non-permanent is pri- marily of non-personal reference, and exists in- dependently of us, except insofar as it becomes content of consciousness. And knowing, or functioning, or mentioning any matter neither creates it nor alters its power or being. 412 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED This book is due on thd last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. 7 r^ h\r M c i" DURING -■ Ji.JAE!? r '* r ■;. j- c\ ' ' ■4 ^foJSrojI^r "»'-£si£s,.i. U C BEHKfcLFY LIBRARIES CD2TM2TMD7