i ,'' ;'» n' lit 1 jti 'ft # A BIOGRAPHICAL HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY A SELECTION FROM ROUTLEDGE'S POPULAR LIBRARY SERIES Uniform -with this Volume. MILL'S PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. MILMAN'S HISTORY OF THE JEWS. THE WORKS OF CHARLES LAMB. Poetical and Dramatic, Tales, Essays, etc. Edited by Charles Kent. BARTLETT'S FAMILIAR QUOTATIONS. EMERSON'S WORKS. With a Steel Portrait. ADAM SMITH'S WEALTH OF NATIONS. CRUDEN'S CONCORDANCE TO THE OLD AND NEW TESTAMENTS. Edited by the Rev. C. S. Carey. 'A BIOGRAPHICAL HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. BY G. H. LEWES LONDON: GEORGE ROUTLEDGE & SONS, LIMITED New York: E. P. DUTTON and CO. u Woo \ k o SERIES I. ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY 417307 PREFACE. To write the Biography of Philosophy while writing the Bio- graphies of Philosophers is the aim of the following work. The expression " Biography of Philosophy," though novel, may per- haps be pardoned, because it characterizes a novel attempt. There have been numerous histories of philosophical schools ; some of these learned and laborious chronicles being little more than a collection of fragments and opinions ; others critical estimates of various systems ; and others attempting to unite both of these plans. But the rise, growth, and development of Philosophy, as exhibited in these philosophical schools — in a word, the Life of Philosophy — has yet, I believe, had no bio- grapher. My conception of such a task, and the principles which have guided the composition of the present attempt, are stated in the Introduction. It is usual, in presenting to the public a work destined for instruction, to show that such a work is wanted ; and, if other works on the subject already exist, to express a proper dis- satisfaction at them, as an excuse for one's own audacity. So reasonable a practice invites imitation, even at the risk of appearing presumptuous. That a History of Philosophy is an important subject may be taken for granted ; and although I by no means claim for the present work that it should supersede others, I do think that existing works have not rendered it superfluous. Stanley's 1 Lives of the Philosophers/ the delight of my boyhood, though a great work, considering the era in which it was pro- duced, had long been obsolete when Dr. Enfield undertook his abridgment of Brucker; and, although the translation of X PREFACE. Ratter's * History of Philosophy ' has driven Enfield from the shelves of the learned, yet its cost and voluminousness have prevented its superseding Enfield with the many. Dr. Enfield was a man equally without erudition and capa- city, and he simply abridged the ill-digested work of a man of immense erudition. Brucker was one of the learned and patient Germans, whose industry was so indefatigable that his work can hardly become altogether superseded ; it must remain one great source whence succeeding writers will draw. But, although he deserves the title of Father of the History of Philosophy, his want of sagacity, and of philosophical, no less than literary attainments, effectually prevent his ever again being regarded otherwise than as a laborious compiler. Dr. Enfield's Abridgment possesses all the faults of arrangement and dulness of Brackets work, to which he has added no in- considerable dulness and blundering of his own. Moreover, his references are shamefully inaccurate. Yet his book has been reprinted in a cheap form, and extensively bought — it certainly has not been extensively read. Ritter's ' History of Philosophy ' is a work of reputation. This reputation, however, is higher in France and England than in Germany ; and the reason is apparent : we have so little ol our own upon the subject, that a work like Ritter's is a great acquisition. In Germany they have so many works of all degrees of excellence and in all styles, that the great advantage of Ritter — his erudition — becomes of very secondary import- ance, while his deficiencies are keenly felt. I have been so much indebted to Ritter, during the progress or my own work, that any depreciation of him here would be worse than ingratitude ; but let me hope that a calm and honest appreciation of his merits and demerits will not be misunder- stood. Ritter is the Brucker of the nineteenth century — not quite so learned, and not quite so dull ; also not quite so calm and impartial As far as honest labour goes there is no defi- ciency ; but where labour ends his merits end. His exposition is generally purposeless and confused ; his historical appre- ciation, when not borrowed from others, superficial in the extreme; his criticisms heavy and deficient in speculative ability, and the whole work wanting life and spirit. He never rises with the greatness of his subject, and perhaps the very worst portions of his book are those devoted to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle ; and this is the more remarkable because PREFACE. Xi he has diligently studied the writings of the two last. As a coi lection of materials for a study of the subject, his book is very valuable ; but it is only an improved supplement to Brucker. Beyond the above works I know of none whence the English reader can gain satisfactory information. Essays on distinct portions of the subject are numerous enough; and there have appeared, from time to time, articles in the Reviews, all of more or less ability. There was a connected view of ancient systems from Thales to Plato, given in a series of articles which excited attention in the ' Foreign Quarterly Review,' during 1843 and 1844; and I must also mention the masterly 1 Essay on Metaphysical Philosophy/ which appeared in the ' Encyclopaedia Metropolitana,' eloquent, ingenious, and pro- found. But all these are buried in voluminous works not always accessible. There still seemed to be an opening for something new, something at once brief and complete. The present work is not meant as a sketch. It is small ; not because materials for a larger were deficient, but because only what was deemed essential has been selected. It would have been easier to let my materials wander into the diffuse space oi bulky quartos or solid-looking octavos ; but I have a great dis- like to "big books," and have endeavoured to make mine small by concentration. It is no complete list of names that figure in the annals of philosophy; it is no complete collection of miscellaneous opinions preserved by tedious tradition. Its completeness is an organic completeness, if the expression may be allowed. Only such thinkers have been selected as repre- sent the various phases of progressive development; and only such opinions as were connected with those phases. I have written the Biography, not the Annals, of Philosophy. A word or two respecting the execution. I make no preten- sions to the character of a savant ; consequently, as a work of erudition this will appear insignificant beside its predeces- sors. It is so. But to such works as already exist the greatest erudition can add little, and that little of subsidiary value ; I have, therefore, a good excuse for wishing to be measured by a different standard. So little have I desired to give this work an erudite air, that I have studiously avoided using references in the foot-notes whenever their absence was unimportant. The reader will not be sorry to see my pages thus pruned ot the idle ostentation which disfigures so many works on this subject; and, if the History look more superficial in conse- Xli PREFACE. quence, it is some consolation to know that all who are compe- tent to judge will not judge by appearances.* Such as it is, the erudition is not " second-hand." The passages upon which I have relied, which I have quoted, or referred to, have all been scrupulously verified, when they were not discovered by me. Of course I have liberally availed my- self of the industry of others; but can conscientiously declare that in no case have I accepted a passage at second-hand with- out having previously verified it by the original, whenever that was possible. This is a part of the historian's duty, irksome but indispensable, and very rarely fulfilled even by the erudite. Let me say, then, once for all, that the List of Books drawn up at the end of this Preface comprises all those used by me in the writing of this Series : and, consequently, any citation from, or reference to, an ancient author not included in that List, is to be considered as derived at second-hand, for the exactitude of which I am not responsible. G. H. L. * It must not be supposed that I am insensible to the importance of exact references ; my own pages will testify to the contrary. I speak only of the abuse of citatic*. LIST OF WORKS USED IN THE COMPILA- TION OF THIS SERIES. Ritter and Preller : Historia Philosophic* Graco-Romana, ex fontium locis contexta. Hamburg, 1838. (A collection of all the scattered fragments of the early philosophers, arranged historically. A work of the highest utility to the critic and historian. Unfortunately I only possessed it after the com- pletion of my first volume.) Aristotle : De Melaphysicd. Ed. Tauchnitz. Leipsic, 1832. (There is a good French translation of this work by MM. Pierron and Z6vort, to the notes of which I have been sometimes indebted.) Aristotle : De Animd. Ed. F. A. Trendelenburg. Jena, (The commentary of Trendelenburg is erudite and useful; but I have not always been able to verify his references.) Aristotle : De Physicd. De Animd. De Cab. } Paris, 1561, De Generatione ei Corruption*. De Sensu. Diogenes Laertius. Ed. Tauchnitz. Lipsiae, 1833. (There is also a French translation by M. Chauffepie" ; but it cannot be trusted.) Sextus Empiricus : Hypotyposes, et Adversos Mathematicos. Folio, Paris, 162 1. (This is not a critical edition ; but it is the only one I possess. It is the first of the Greek text.) Karsten : Philosophorum Gracorum Operum Reliquiae. Pars Prima. Xenophanes. Brussels, 1830. (An excellent work.) Plato : Ed. Bekker. Berlin, 1828. (Also four dialogues : Protagoras, Gorgias, Phaedrus, and the Apology^ which were analysed in a masterly manner in the ' Monthly Reposi- tory ■ from March, 1834 to February, 1835. From these all extracti which occur in my work have been taken.) Xenophon : Memorabilia. Ed. Edwards, Oxon, 1785. XIV LIST OF WORKS. Hornius: Historia Philosophica, Batav., 1756. Brucker : History of Philosophy. Abridged by Enfield. London, 18 19. Brucker: Historia Critica Philosophic. Leipsig, 1767. Ritter : History of Ancient Philosophy. 3 vols. English Trans. Oxford, 1838-9. Hegel : Geschichte der Philosophic. 3 Bande. Ed. Michelet Berlin, 1833. (This is rather the Philosophy of History than the History of Philo- sophy. I have found it suggestive.) Zeller : Die Philosophie der Griechen : ihrer Character, Gang, Hauptmomente und Entwicklung. Erster Theil. Vor- sokratische Philosophie. Tubingen, 1844. (Useful. Rather a criticism on other historians than a history.) Tennemann : Manuel de r Histoire de la Philosophie. Par Victor Cousin. 2 vols. Paris, 1830. (A good abridgment of an able work.) Renouvier : Manuel de la Philosophie Ancienne. 2 vols. Paris, 1844. (A work of learning and acuteness.) Jules Simon : Histoire de PEcole d 1 Alexandrie. 1st voL Paris, 1844. Victor Cousin : Cours de Philosophie. 3 vols. Bruxelles, 1840. V. Cousin : Nouveaux Fragmens Philosophiques. 1 vol. Bruxelles, 1840. Encyclopcedia Metropolitana t — article, Moral and Metaphysical Philosophy. Bayle : Dictionnaire Historique. Wiggers : Life of Socrates. English Trans., 1840. De Gerando : Histoire Comparee des Syslemes de Philosophie. Paris, 1822. (This work enjoys considerable reputation, and deserves it. Clear, discriminating, and well written.) Van Heusde : Initio, Platonicoz. Trajecti ad Rhenam, 1827. (One of the most elegant and delightful works on the subject ; written in very pleasant Latin, with great enthusiasm and abundant know- ledge. A valuable introduction to the study of Plato.) INTRODUCTION. This work is intended as a contribution to the History of Humanity. Let us, therefore, at once define the nature and limits of this contribution, lest its object be mistaken. The History of Philosophy is a vague title, and should, properly speaking, include the rise and progress of all the sciences. As usually employed, the title is understood to refer to only one science, viz., the science called metaphysics. Though disap- proving of this restrictive sense of the word philosophy, we use it in compliance with general usage. As all the earliest philosophy was essentially metaphysical, there is no great impropriety in designating Greek metaphysics by the name of Philosophy ; but when Philosophy enlarged its bounds, and included all the physical sciences as its lawful subjects, then indeed the earlier and restricted use of the word occa- sioned great confusion. To remedy this confusion slight but ineffectual attempts have been made. The term metaphysics, and sometimes the expressive, but uncouth, term ontology* have been brought forward to distinguish a priori speculations not within the scope of physical science. In order to prevent confusion, and at the same time to avoid the introduction ot words so distasteful as metaphysics and ontology, we shall throughout speak of Philosophy in its earlier and more restricted sense ; and shall designate by the term Positive Science that field of speculation commonly known as Inductive, or Baconian, Philosophy. It is the object of the present work to show how and by what steps Philosophy became Positive Science; in other words, by what Methods the Human Mind was enabled *.The science of Being. XVi INTRODUCTION. to conquer for itself, in the long struggle of centuries, its present modicum of certain knowledge. All those who have any conviction in the steady development of humanity, and believe in a direct filiation of ideas, will at once admit, that the curious but erroneous speculations of the Greeks were necessary to the production of modern science. It is our belief, that there is a direct parentage between the various epochs ; a direct parentage between the ideas of the ancient thinkers and the ideas of moderns. In Philosophy the evi dences of this filiation are so numerous and incontestable, that we cannot greatly err in signalizing them. Having to trace the history of the mind in one region of its activity, it is incumbent on us to mark out the countries and epochs which we deem it requisite to notice. Are we to follow Brucker, and include the Antediluvian period? Are we to trace the speculations of the Scythians, Persians, and Egyp- tians ? Are we to lose ourselves in that vast wilderness the East ? It is obvious that we must draw the line somewhere ; we cannot write the history of every nation's thoughts. We confine ourselves, therefore, to Greece and modern Europe. We omit Rome. The Romans, confessedly, had no Philosophy of their own ; and did but feebly imitate that of the Greeks. Their influence on modern Europe has, therefore, been only indirect ; their labours count as nothing in the history of Philo- sophy. We also omit the East. It is very questionable whether the East had any Philosophy distinct from its Religion ; and still more questionable whether Greece was materially influenced by it. JTrue it is, that the Greeks themselves sup- posed their early* teachers to have imbibed wisdom at the Eastern fount. True it is, that modern Oriental scholars, on first becoming acquainted with some of the strange doctrines of the Eastern sages, have recognised in them strong resem- blances to the doctrines of the Greeks. But neither of these reasons are valid. The former is attributable to a very natural prejudice, which will be explained hereafter. The latter is attributable to the coincidences frequent in all specu- lation, and inevitable in so vague and vast a subject as Philosophy. Coincidences prove nothing but the similarity of all spontaneous tendencies of thought. Something more is needed to prove direct filiation. A coincidence is the historian's will-o'-the-wisp, leading him into deep and distant bogs. He has studied the history of W INTRODUCTION. Xvii Philosophy to little purpose who has not learned to estimate the value of such resemblances \ who has not so familiarized him- self with the nature of speculation as to be aware of their necessary frequency. Pantheism, for example, under some of) its shapes, seems to have been a doctrine entertained by mostj speculative nations ; yet it seems to have been mostly spon4 taneous. Again, the physical speculations of the Greeks often V coincide in expression with many of the greatest scientific 1 discoveries of modern times ; does this prove that the Greeks \ anticipated the moderns ? M. Dutens has thought so ; and ^ written an erudite, but singularly erroneous, book to prove it. The radical error of all such opinions arises from mistaking the nature of Positive Science. Democritus, indeed, asserted the Milky Way to be only a cluster of stars ; but his assertion was a mere guess ; and, though it happens to be correct, has no proof of certainty. It was Galileo who discovered the fact. He did not guess it. The difference between guessing and knowing is just the difference between assertion and science. In the\ same way it is argued that Empedocles, Democritus, Pythagoras, and Plato were perfectly acquainted with the doctrine of gravitation ; and, by dint of forced translations, something coincident in-expression with the Newtonian theory is certainly elicited. But Newton's incomparable discovery was not a vague guess ; it was a positive demonstration. He did not simply assert the fact of gravitation : he discovered the laws of its action.* From that discovery of the laws gigantic results have been obtained in a few years. From the antique asser- tion no result whatever was obtained during the whole activity of centuries. From the above examples, it appears that coincidences of doctrine in metaphysical matters are no proof of any direct relationship, but only proofs of the spontaneous tendencies of the mind when moving within a circumscribed limit. Coin- cidences of expression, on the other hand, between a meta- physical doctrine and a scientific doctrine, prove nothing whatever. It is impossible for a doctrine which proceeds from a metaphysical point of view, although apparently only occupied with physical phenomena, to coincide with any truly scientific doctrine, except in language. Nothing can be more opposite * Karsten expresses the distinction very happily : u Empedocles poeticse adumbravit idem quod tot seculis postea mathematicis rationibus demon- stration est a Newtono." — Xcnophanes, Carm. Reliquia, p. xii. XV111 INTRODUCTION. than the Pythagorean and Newtonian physics ; no bridge can over-arch the chasm which separates them. Philosophy and Positive Science are irreconcileable. This is a point which it is of the utmost importance to understand clearly. Let us briefly indicate the characteristics of each. Philosophy (metaphysical philosophy, remember!) aspires to the knowledge of Essences and Causes. Positive Science aspires only to the knowledge of Laws. The one pretends to discover what things are in themselves, apart from their appear- ances to sense, and whence they came. The other only wishes to discover their modus ope? andi ; observing the constant co- existences and successions of phenomena amongst themselves, and generalising them into some one Law.* In other words, the one endeavours to compass the Impossible ; the other knows the limits of human faculties and contents itself with the Possible. To take an illustration from a popular subject, how many ingenious efforts have been made to discover the cause of Life — how many theories respecting the Vital Prin- ciple ! All such have been frivolous because futile. The man of science knows that Causes are not to be discovered — knows that Life is a thing which escapes investigation, because it defies experiment ; when you would examine it, it is gone. Is Life, then, an enigma ? What it is may be safely pronounced an enigma; but in what ways, and under what conditions it manifests itself, may be discovered by proper investigations. Irreversible canon : whatever relates to the origin of things, i.e., causes ; and whatever relates to the existence of things, per se, i.e., essences, are the proper objects of Philosophy, and are wholly and utterly eliminated from the aims and methods of Positive Science. With so broad and palpable a distinction between the two, we may be prepared to find radical differences in the Methods by which they are guided. Philosophy and Positive Science are both Deductive. They * The reader who desires perfect conviction, and who desires, moreover, a clear idea of the nature and conditions of science, is earnestly recom- mended to make himself master of John Stuart Mill's incomparable 1 System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive,' a work we feel bound, on all occasions, to recommend to philosophical students, as doing more for the education of the scientific intellect than any work we are acquainted with INTRODUCTION. xix have this in common, that they are both occupied with deduc- ing conclusions from established axioms. But here the resem- blance ends. Philosophy is deductive d priori ; that is to say, starting from some d priori axiom, such as "All bodies tend to rest," or " Nature abhors a vacuum," the philosopher believes that all the logical conclusions deduced from the axiom, when applied to particular facts, are absolutely true of those facts ; and, if the axiom be indisputable, the conclusions, if legiti- mately drawn, will be true. Mathematics is the ideal of a deductive science; it is wholly d priori f and wholly true. Positive Science is deductive d posteriori. It begins by first ascertaining whether the axiom from which it is to deduce conclusions be indisputable, It experimentalises; it puts nature to the test of " interrogation." After much observation, it attains, by the inductive process, to the certainty of a Law, such as " Attraction is inversely as the square of the distance." A law equals an axiom. From this certain deductions are drawn. Positive Science commences ; and that science is pronounced perfect when it has reached the point at which it may be carried on further by deduction atone. Such a science is Astronomy. This then is the difference between the Methods of Philo- sophy and Positive Science : the one proceeds from d priori axioms — that is, from axioms taken up without having under- gone the laborious but indispensable process of previous verifi- cation ; the other proceeds from axioms which have been rigidly verified. The one proceeds from an Assumption, the other from a Fact. It is a law of the human mind that speculations on all gene- ralities begin deductively : and the only road to truth is to begin inductively. The origin of Positive Science is to be sought in Philosophy. The boldest and the grandest specula- tions came first. Man needed the stimulus of some higher reward than that of merely tracing the co-existences and succes- sions of phenomena. Nothing but a solution of the mystery of the universe could content him ; nothing less could tempt him to the labour of sustained speculation. Thus had Astro- nomy its first impulse given to it by astrologers. Nightly did the old Chaldeans watch the stars in the hope of wresting from them their secret influence over the destiny of man. Chemistry came from Alchemy ; Physiology from Auguriei XX INTRODUCTION. Many long and weary years, of long and weary struggles, were passed before men learned to suspect the vanity of their efforts. First came scepticism of human knowledge altogether. Next came scepticism of the Methods men had followed. Induction arose. Slowly and laboriously, but as surely as slowly, did this method lead men into the right path. Axioms were obtained : axioms that had stood the test of proof, that were adequate expressions of general facts, not simply dogmatical expressions of opinions. Deduction again resumed its office ; this time to good purpose : it was no longer guess-work. The position occupied by Philosophy in the History of Humanity, is that of the great Initiative to Positive Science. It was the forlorn hope of humanity which perished in its efforts, but did not perish without having led the way to victory. The present work is an attempt to trace the steps by which this was accomplished; in this attempt consists its originality and its unity. There are many who altogether deny the fact of progression ; who regard Philosophy as something higher and greater than Positive Science ; who believe that the reign of Philosophy is not yet finished. And they would point to Germany for con- firmation. Thousands of Germans, to say nothing of indi- vidual Frenchmen and Englishmen, are now struggling with the same doubts as those which perplexed the Greeks of old. It is very true ; " and pity 'tis 'tis true." We have no space, nor is this the occasion, to develop our views, nor to combat those of our adversaries. We content ourselves with pro- claiming our belief in the constant Progression of Science, which will finally sweep away into the obscure corners of indi- vidual crotchets all the speculations which Philosophy boasts of usurping. We cannot mistake the legible characters of History. If Germany is behind, humanity is marching far a-head, to great and certain conquests. Individuals may be retrograding : the race is steadily advancing. There is nothing to surprise, though much to deplore, in the number of eminent minds led into the swamps and infinite mists of metaphysics, even at the present day. Long after Astronomy had been a science, accepted by all competent investigators, Astrology had still its individual votaries. Long after Chemistry had become a science, Alchemy still tempted many. Long after Physiology had become a science, there were and are still arduous seekers after the Vital INTRODUCTION. xx i Principle. But as these individual errors do not affect the general proposition respecting the wondrous and progressive march of Science, so also the individual metaphysicians, how- ever eminent, form no real exception to the general proposi- tion, that Philosophy has gradually been displaced by Positive Science, and will finally disappear. Metaphysics has been defined Part de s'egarer avec tncthode : no definition of it can be wittier or truer. The nature of Philosophy, therefore, condemns its followers to wander for ever in the same labyrinth, and in this circum- scribed space many will necessarily fall into the track of their predecessors. In other words coincidences of doctrine at epochs widely distant from each other are inevitable. Positive Science is further distinguished from Philosophy by the incontestable progress it everywhere makes. Its methods are stamped with certainty, because they are daily extending our certain knowledge ; Decause the immense experience of years and of myriads of intelligences confirms their truth, with- out casting a shadow of suspicion on them. Science then progresses, and must continue to progress. Philosophy only moves in the same endless circle. Its first principles are as much a matter of dispute as they were two thousand years ago. It has made no progress, although in constant movement Precisely the same questions are being agitated in Germany at this moment as were being discussed in ancient Greece; and with no better means of solving them, with no better hopes of success. The united force of thousands of intellects, some of them among the greatest that have made the past illustrious, has been steadily concentrated on problems, supposed to be of vital importance, and believed to be perfectly suscep- tible of solution, without the least result All this meditation and discussion has not even established a few first principles. Centuries of labour have not produced any perceptible progress. The history of science on the other hand is the history of progress. So far from the same questions being discussed in the same way as they were in ancient Greece, they do not remain the same for two generations. In some sciences — Chemistry for example — ten years suffice to render a book so behind the state of knowledge as to be almost useless. Everywhere we see progress, more or less rapid, according to the greater or less facility of investigation. In this constant circular movement of Philosophy and con- Xxii INTRODUCTION. stant linear progress of Positive Science, we see the condemna- tion of the former. It is in vain to argue that because no progress has yet been made, we are not therefore to conclude none will be made ; it is in vain to argue that the difficulty of Philosophy is much greater than that of any science, and there- fore greater time is needed for its perfection. The difficulty is Impossibility. No progress is made, because no certainty is possible. To aspire to the knowledge of more than pheno- mena, their resemblances and successions, is to aspire to trans- cend the limitations of human faculties. " To know more we must be more." This is our conviction. It is also the conviction of the majority of thinking men. Consciously or unconsciously, they condemn Philosophy. They discredit, or disregard it The proof of this is in the general neglect into which Philosophy has fallen, and the greater assiduity bestowed on Positive Science. Loud complaints of this neglect are heard. Great contempt is expressed by the Philosophers. They may rail and they may sneer, but the world will go its way. The empire of Positive Science is established.* We trust that no one will suppose we think slightingly of Philosophy. Assuredly we do not, or else why this work? Philosophy has usurped too many of our nights and days, has been the object and the solace of too great a portion of our bygone lives, to meet with disrespect from us. But we respect it as a great power that has been, and no longer is. It was the impulse to all early speculation ; it was the parent of Positive Science. It nourished the infant mind of humanity ; gave it aliment, and directed its faculties ; rescued the nobler part of man from the dominion of brutish ignorance, stirred him with insatiable thirst for knowledge, to slake which he was content to undergo amazing toil. But its office has been fulfilled ; it is no longer necessary to humanity, and should be set aside. The only interest it can have is an historical interest. The leading feature of this work is one which distinguishes it from all others on the subject : the peculiarity of being a History of Philosophy, by one who firmly believes that Philo- sophy is an impossible attempt, that it never has had any cer- titude, never can have any. All other historians have believed * Let those who doubt this seek satisfaction in Auguste Comte's ' Couri de Philosophic Positive.' Let every one who takes an interest in philo- sophy master this opus magnum of our age. INTRODUCTION. xxiii in philosophy. They have sometimes been tree from me trammels of any particular system — (Brucker and Ritter were so;) but they have not suspected the possible truth of Philo- sophy : they have merely been free from any defined system. Hitherto no one but a metaphysician has seen interest enough in it to write the History of Philosophy ; besides, it could not et written without Jong acquaintance with the subject, and no sceptic of the possibility of the science could well have formed tnat acquaintance, unless, like the presen writer, he was a sceptic after having been many years a believer. We write therefore not in the interest of Philosophy, but as a contribution to the History of Humanity. Other historians may be divided into cwo classes : the erudite and the specu- lative. The one collecting the opinions of philosophers ; the other explaining those opinions. Our great aim is to trace the development of philosophy ; and we seek therefore to explain methods, rather than individual opinions, though the latter are of course necessary to our plan. Our plan is purely historical Our scepticism will secure impartiality : since, believing no one system to be truer than another, though it may be more plausible, we can calmly appreciate the value of every one. Impartiality is a requisite, but it is not the only one. Impartiality implies unbiassed judgment; but it does not imply correct judgment. We shall doubtless err, and shall thankfully accept any indication of our errors. Most of the ancient writers have come down to us in fragments. We have not even the skeleton from which to judge of the living figure. Nothing but a thigh-bone here, a jaw-bone there, an arm elsewhere. But as the comparative anatomist can often decide upon the nature and habits of an animal only from an inspection of its jaw-bone, being enabled, by his knowledge of the general animal structure, to fill up the outline; so should the historian be able to decide upon the nature and scope of any philosophical theory from a study of only a fragment or two. Now all historians who have attempted to explain the opinions of the ancient thinkers have been somewhat in this condition : they have either believed all animals to be of one specific type ; or they have believed that all animals were of one type, without having decided the nature of that type. Hegel is an illustra- tion of the former ; Ritter of the latter class. We also shall have to conjecture what was the nature of the Kdv INTRODUCTION. system, from a fragment of its skeleton. But we are free from the bias of any metaphysical theory. Our decisions will be founded on our knowledge of the human mind, and of the history of speculation ; as the comparative anatomist's decisions are founded on his knowledge of the animal structure. Where so much is conjectural, much will necessarily be erroneous. How far we have erred, it is for readers to decide. JFtrst 'Epodb. SPECULATIONS ON THE NATURE OP THE UN/VEPSB. BOOK I. THE PHYSIOLOGISTS * CHAPTER L THALES. Although the events of his life, no less than the precise doc- trines of his philosophy, are shrouded in mystery, and belong rather to the domain of fable, nevertheless Thales is very justly considered as the father of Greek Speculation. He made an epoch. He laid the first foundation stone of Greek philosophy. The step he took was small, but it was decisive. Accordingly, although nothing but a few of his tenets remain, and those tenets fragmentary and incoherent, we know enough of the general tendency of his doctrines to speak of him with some degree of certitude. Thales was born at Miletus, a Greek colony in Asia Minor. The date of his birth is extremely doubtful ; but the first year of the 35th Olympiad is generally accepted as correct. He belonged to one of the most illustrious families of Phoenicia, and took a conspicuous part in all the political affairs of his * We are forced, though unwillingly, to follow other historians in the use of the word physiology in its primitive sense. It has another and very different meaning in English, always signifying biology. But we have no other word wherewith to translate fvmoXoyoi, or M inquirers into external nature." 26 THE PHYSIOLOGISTS. country; a part which earned for him the highest esteem of his fellow-citizens. His immense activity in politics has been denied, by later writers, as inconsistent with the tradition, countenanced by Plato, of his having spent a life of solitude and meditation ; while, on the other hand, his affection for soli- tude has been questioned on the ground of his political activity. It seems to us that the two things are perfectly compatible. Meditation does not necessarily unfit a man for action ; nor does an active life absorb all his time, leaving him none for medita- tion. The wise man will strengthen himself by meditation before he acts ; and he will act, to test the truth of his opinions. Thales was one of the Seven Sages. This reputation is suffi- cient to settle the dispute. It shows that he could not have been a mere Speculative Thinker; for the Greek Sages were all moralists rather than metaphysicians. It shows also that he could not have been a mere man of action. His mag- nificent aphorism "Know thyself," reveals the solitary medi- tative thinker. Miletus was one of the most flourishing Greek colonies ; and, at the period we are now speaking of, before either a Persian or a Lydian yoke had crushed the energies of its population, it was a fine scene for the development of mental energies. Its commerce both by sea and land was immense. Its political constitution afforded the finest opportunities for individual development. Thales both by birth and education would naturally have been fixed there ; and would not, as it has often been said, have travelled into Egypt and Crete for the prose- cution of his studies. These assertions, though frequently repeated, are based on no trusty authority. The only ground for the conjecture is the fact of Thales being a proficient in mathematical knowledge ; and from very early times, as we see in Herodotus, it was the fashion to derive the origin of almost every branch of knowledge from Egypt. So little consistency is there, however, in this narrative of his voyages, that he is said to have astonished the Egyptians, by showing them how to measure the height of their pyramids by their shadows. A nation so easily astonished by one of the simplest of mathe- matical problems could have had little to teach. Perhaps the strongest proof that he never travelled into Egypt — or that, if he travelled there, that he never came into communication with the priests — is ihe absence of all trace, however slight, of any Egyptian doctrine in the philosophy of Thales which he THALES. 2? might not have found at home. To that philosophy we now address ourselves. The distinctive characteristic of the Ionian School, in its first period, was that of physiological inquiry into the consti- tution of the universe. Thales opened this inquiry. It is commonly said, " Thales taught that the principle of all things was water." On a first glance, this will perhaps appear a mere extravagance. A smile of pity will greet it, accompanied by a reflection on the smiler's part, of the unlikelihood of his having ever believed in such an absurdity. But the serious student will be slow to accuse his predecessors of extravagance. The history 01 Philosophy may be the history of errors ; it is not that of follies. All the systems that have appeared have had a pregnant meaning. Only for this could they have been accepted. The meaning was proportionate to the opinions of the epoch, and as such is worth penetrating. Thales was one of the most extraordinary men that ever lived, and produced a most extra- ordinary revolution. Such a man was not likely to have enun- ciated a philosophical thought which any child might have refuted. There was deep meaning in the thought ; to him at least. Above all there was deep meaning in the attempt to discover this first of problems ; although the attempt itself was abortive. Let us endeavour to penetrate the meaning of his thought ; let us see if we cannot in some shape trace its rise and growth in his mind. It is characteristic of most philosophical minds, to reduce all imaginable diversities to one principle. We shall see in- stances enough of this in the course of our narrative, to absolve us from the necessity of any demonstration here. We may, however, illustrate it by one brief example. As it was the inevitable tendency of religious speculation to reduce poly- theism to monotheism — to generalize all the supernatural powers into one expression — so also was it the tendency of early philosophical speculation to reduce all possible modes of existence into one generalization of existence itself. Thales speculating on the constitution of the universe could not but strive to discover the one principle — the primary Fact — the substance, of which all special existences were but the modes. Seeing around him constant transformations — birth and death — change of shape, of size, and of mode of existence, he could not regard any one of these variable states of exis- tence as existence itself. He therefore asked himself, What is i8 THE PHYSIOLOGISTS. that invariable existence of which these are the variable states t In a word, what is the beginning of things ? * To ask this question was to open the era of philosophical inquiry. Hitherto men had contented themselves with accept- ing the world as they found it ; with believing what they saw ; and with adoring what they could not see. Thales felt that there was a vital question to be answered relative to the beginning of things. He looked around him. On what he saw, he meditated ; the result of his meditation was the conviction that Moisture was the Beginning. Could any- thing be more naturally present to an Ionian mind than the universality of water? Had he not from boyhood upwards been familiar with the sea ? M There about the beach he wandered nourishing a youth sublime With the fairy tales of science, and the long result of time." When gazing abroad upon the blue expanse, hearing "the mighty waters rolling evermore," and seeing the red sun, hav- ing spent its fiery energy, sink into the cool bosom of the wave, to rest there in peace, how often must he have been led to contemplate the all-embracing all-en gulphing sea, upon whose throbbing breast the very earth itself reposed. This earth how finite ; and that welling sea how infinite ! Once impressed with this idea, he examined the constitution of the earth. There also he found moisture everywhere. All things he found nourished by moisture ; warmth itself he de- clared to proceed from moisture ; the seeds of all things are moist. Water when condensed becomes earth. Thus convinced of the universal presence of water, he declared it to be the beginning of things. Just what moisture is to the ground, it has well been said, necessary to its being what it is, yet not being the ground itself, just soch a thing did Thales find in himself, something which was not his body, but without which his body would not be what it is ; without which it would be a dry husk falling to pieces. + Thales would all the more readily adopt this notion from its harmonising with ancient opinions; such for instance as * Had historians said that Thales taught that moisture was the begin- ning of things, they would have greatly simplified the question ; our word " principle " has another meaning. Beginning is the correct word ; and is the one used by Aristotle, Btfwp ilvat r?)v Apxhv. — Met. i. 3. t ■ Ency. Merrop.' art. Moral and Metaph. Philos. THALES. 99 Hesiod's Theogony, wherein Oceanus and Thetis were regarded as the parents of all such deities as had any relation to nature. " He would thus have performed for the popular religion that which modern science has performed for the book of Genesis : explaining what before was enigmatical." * This remark leads us to the rectification of a serious error, which is very generally entertained. We allude to the supposed Atheism of Thales. It is sufficient to name the learned Ritter, and the brilliant, ingenious Victor Cousin, as upholders of this opinion, to show that its refutation is requisite. Because Thales held that water was the beginning of things, it is concluded that God or the Gods, were not recognised by him. The only authority adduced in support of this conclusion is the negative authority of Aristotle's silence. But it seems to us that Aris- totle's silence is directly against such a conclusion. Would he have been silent on so remarkable a point as that Thales be- lieved only in the existence of water ? We cannot think so. Cicero, when speaking of Thales, expressly says that he held water to be the beginning of things, but God was the mind which created them from water. We certainly object, with Hegel, to Cicero's attributing to Thales the conception of God as intelligence (vow?) ; that being the expression of more ad- vanced philosophy. Thales did not conceive any formative principle, either as Power or Intelligence, by which the primeval moisture was fashioned. He had no conception of a Creative Power. He believed in the Gods ; but, in the ancient mytho- logy, the generation of the Gods was a fundamental tenet ; he believed, therefore, that the Gods, as all things, were generated from water. Aristotle's account bears only this interpretation. — Met. i. 3. But this is not Atheism. Atheism is not of so early a date. Indeed, to believe in any Atheism at such a period of the world's history, is radically to misconceive the history of the human race. In conclusion, we may say that the step taken by Thales was twofold in its influence : — 1st, to discover the beginning, the prima materia of all things (rj apxrj) ; 2dly, to select from among the elements that element which was most omnipotent, omnipresent. To those acquainted with the history of the human mind, both these notions will be significant of an entirely new era. In our Introduction, we stated the law of the progress • Ben). Constant, ' Du Polyth6Ume Romaine,* p. i. 167. 30 THE PHYSIOLOGISTS. of science to be this : Starting with a pure deductive method, the human mind exhausted its ingenuity, in developing all possible theories, and, when satisfied with the vanity of its efforts, it followed another method, the inductive ; till by means of the accumulated treasures of this method it was again enabled to reason deductively. The position occupied by Thales is that of the Father of Philosophy ; since he was the first in Greece to furnish a formula from which to reason deductively. CHAPTER II. ANAXIMENES. Anaximander is by most historians placed after Thales. We agree with Ritter in giving that place to Anaximenes. The reasons on which we ground this arrangement are, ist, in so doing we follow our safest guide, Aristotle. 2dly, the doctrines of Anaximenes are the development of those of Thales ; whereas Anaximander follows a totally different line of speculation. Indeed, the whole ordinary arrangement of the Ionian School seems to have proceeded on the conviction that each disciple not only contradicted his master, but also returned to the doctrines of his master's teacher. Thus, Anaximander is made to succeed Thales, though quite opposed to him ; whereas Anaximenes, who only carries out the principles of Thales, is made the disciple of Anaximander. When we state that 212 years, i.e. six or seven generations, are taken up by the lives of the four individuals said to stand in the successive relations of teacher and pupil, Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, and Anaxagoras, the reader will be able to estimate the value of the traditional relationship. The truth is, only the names of the great leaders in philo- sophy were thought worth preserving ; all those who merely applied or extended the doctrine were very properly consigned to oblivion. This is also the principle upon which the present history is composed. No one will therefore demur to our placing Anaximenes second to Thales ; not as his disciple, but as his historical successor ; as the man who, taking up the speculation where Thales and his disciples left it, transmitted it to his successors in a more developed form. DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. 31 Of the life of Anaximenes nothing further is known than that he was born at Miletus, probably in the 63rd Olympiad ; and discovered the obliquity of the ecliptic by means of the gnomon. Pursuing the method of Thales, he could not satisfy himself with the truth of Thales' doctrine. Water was not to him the most significant element. He felt within him a something which moved him he knew not how, he knew not why ; some- thing higher than himself ; invisible, but ever present. This he called his soul. His soul he believed to be air. Was there not also without him, no less than within him, an ever-moving, ever-present, invisible air ? The air which was within him, and which he called Soul, was it not a part of the air which was without him ? And, if so, was not this air the Beginning of Things ? He looked around him, and thought his conjecture was con- firmed. The air seemed universal.* The earth was as a broad leaf resting upon it. All things are produced from it: all things are resolved into it. When he breathed, he drew in a part of the universal life. All things were nourished by air, as he was nourished by it. This was the central idea of his system. He applied it to the explanation of many phenomena in a way that would make the reader smile ; but, as this history is a record of Methods, and not a mere record of absurdities, we will not occupy our space by further detail. Compared with the doctrine of Thales this of Anaximenes presents a decided progress. As & physiolo- gical principle, air may be as absurd as water; but the progress is seen in the conception of a principle founded on the ana- logies of the soul, rather than, as with Thales, on the analogies of the seed. CHAPTER III. DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. Diogenes of Apollonia is the real successor of Anaximenes, although, from the uncritical arrangement usually adopted, he is made to represent no epoch whatever. Thus, Tennemann * When Anaximenes speaks of Air, as when Thales speaks of Water, we must not understand these elements as they appear in this or that determinate form on earth, but as Water and Air pregnant with vital energy and capable of infinite transmutations. S* THE PHYSIOLOGISTS. places him after Pythagoras. Hegel, by a strange oversight; says that we know nothing of Diogenes but the name. Diogenes was born at Apollonia, in Crete. More than this we are unable to state with certainty ; but, as he is said to have been a contemporary of Anaxagoras, we may assume him to have flourished about the 8oth Olympiad. His work on Nature was extant in the time of Simplicius (the 6th century of our era), who extracted some passages from it. Diogenes adopted the tenet of Anaximenes respecting Air as the origin of things ; but he gave a wider and deeper significa- cation to the tenet, by attaching himself more to the analogy of the Soul. Struck with the force of this analogy, he was led to push the conclusion to its ultimate limits. What is it, he may have asked himself, that constitutes Air the origin of things ? Clearly its vital force. The Air is a Soul : therefore it is living and intelligent. But this Force or Intelligence is a higher thing than the Air, through which it manifests itself; it must consequently be prior in point of time ; it must be the apxv philosophers have sought. The Universe is a living being, spontaneously evolving itself, deriving its transformation from its own vitality. There are two remarkable points in this conception, both indicative of very great progress in speculation. The first is the attribute of Intelligence, with which the apxv is endowed. Anaximenes considered the primary substance to be an ani- mated substance ; Air was Soul in his system ; but the Soul did not necessarily imply Intelligence. He conceived the Soul as the vital principle. Diogenes saw that the Soul was not only Force, but Intelligence ; the Air which stirred within him, not only pro7?ipted but instructed. He carried this analogy of his soul on to the operations of the world. The Air, as the origin of all things, is necessarily an eternal, imperishable sub- stance ; but, as soul, it is also necessarily endowed with con- sciousness : " it knows much," and this knowledge is another proot of its being the primary substance ; " for without Reason," he says, " it would be impossible for all to be arranged duly and proportionately ; and whatever object we consider will be found to be arranged and ordered in the best and most beau- tiful manner." Order can result only from Intelligence; the Soul is therefore the First (apxv)> This conception was un- doubtedly a great one ; but that the reader may not exaggerate its importance, nor suppose that the rest of Diogenes' doctrines DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. 33 were equally reasonable and profound, we must for the sake of preserving historical truth advert to one or two of his applica- tions of the conception. Thus : — The world, as a living unity, must, like other individuals, derive its vital force from the Whole : hence he attributed to the world a set of respiratory organs, which he fancied he dis- covered in the stars. All creation, and all material action, were but respiration and exhalation. In the attraction of moisture to the sun, in the attraction of iron to the magnet, he equally saw a process of respiration. Man is superior to brutes in intelligence, because he inhales a purer air than brutes who bow their heads to the ground. These 7iaive attempts at the explanation of phenomena will suffice to show that, although Diogenes had made a large stride, he had accomplished very little of the journey. The second remarkable point indicated by his system is the manner in which it closes the inquiry opened by Thales. Thales, starting from the conviction that one of the four ele- ments was the origin of the world, and Water that element, was followed by Anaximenes, who thought that not only was Air a more universal element than Water, but that, being the soul, it must be the universal Life : to him succeeded Diogenes, who saw that not only was Air Life, but Intelligence, and that Intel- ligence must have been the First of Things. We concur, therefore, with Ritter in regarding Diogenes as the last philosopher attached to the Physiological method ; and that in his system that method receives its consummation. Having thus traced one great line of speculation, we must now cast our eyes upon what was being contemporaneously evolved in another direction. BOOK II. THE MATHEMATICIANS. CHAPTER I. ANAXIMANDER OF MILETUS. " As we now, for the first time in the history of Greek Philo- sophy, meet with contemporaneous developments, the observa- tion will not, perhaps, be deemed superfluous, that in the earliest times of philosophy, historical evidences of the recip- rocal influence of the two lines either entirely fail or are very unworthy of credit ; on the other hand, the internal evidence is of very limited value, because it is impossible to prove a complete ignorance in one of the ideas revolved and carried out in the other ; nevertheless, any argument drawn from an apparent acquaintance therewith, is far from being extensive or tenable, since all the olden philosophers drew from one com- mon source — the national habit of thought. When indeed these two directions had been more largely pursued, we shall find in the controversial notices sufficient evidence of an active conflict between these very opposite views of nature and the universe. In truth, when we call to mind the inadequate means at the command of the earlier philosophers for the dis- semination of their opinions, it appears extremely probable that their respective systems were for a long time known only within a very narrow circle. On the supposition, however, that the philosophical impulse of these times was the result of a real national want, it becomes at once probable that the various elements began to show themselves in Ionia nearly at the same time, independently and without any external connection."* The chief of the school we are now about to consider was * * Ritter/ i. p. j6$. ANAXIMANDER OF MILETUS. 35 Anaximander, of Miletus, whose birth is generally dated in 43rd Olympiad. He is sometimes called the friend, and some- times the disciple, of Thales. We prefer the former relation ; the latter is at any rate not the one in which this history can regard him. His reputation, both for political and scientific knowledge, was very great; and many important inventions are ascribed to him ; amongst ' others that of the sun-dial and the sketch of a geographical map. His calculations of the size and distance of the heavenly bodies were committed to writing in a small work which is said to be the earliest of all philoso- phical writings. He was passionately addicted to mathematics, and framed a series of geometrical problems. He was the leader of a colony to Apollonia ; and he is also reported to have resided at the court of the Tyrant Polycrates, in Samos, where also lived Pythagoras and Anacreon. No two historians are agreed in their interpretation of Anaxi- mander's doctrines ; few, indeed, are agreed in the historical position he is to occupy. In offering a new view of the character of his philosophy, we call the reader's attention to this point, as a warrant for the attempt, and as an excuse for failure, if we fail. Anaximander is stated to have been the first to use the term apxr) for the beginning of things. What he meant by this term principle is variously interpreted by the ancient writers ; for, although they are unanimous in agreeing that he called it the infinite (to a-n-eipov), what he understood by the infinite is yet undecided.* On a first view nothing can well be less intelligible than this tenet: "The Infinite is the origin of all things." It either looks like the monotheism of a far later date,t or like the word- jugglery of mysticism. To our minds it is neither more nor less difficult of comprehension than the tenet of Thales, that " Water is the origin of all things." Let us cast ourselves back in imagination into those early days, and see if we cannot account for the rise of such an opinion. On viewing Anaximander, side by side with his great pre- • * Ritter,' i. 267. t Which it certainly could not have been. To prevent any misconcep- tion of the kind, we may merely observe that the Infinite here meant, was not even the Limitless Power, much less the Limitless Mind, implied in the modern conception. In Anaxagoras, who lived a century later, we find ro dirnpov to be no more than vastness. — See Simplicius, Phys. 33, b. quoted in 'Ritter.' 36 THE MATHEMATICIANS. decessor and friend Thales, we cannot but be struck with the exclusively abstract tendency of his speculations. Instead of the meditative Metaphysician, we see the Geometrician. Thales, whose famous maxim, " Know thyself," was essentially concrete, may serve as a contrast to Anaximander, whose axiom, " The Infinite is the origin of all things," is the ultimate effort of abstraction. Let us concede to him this tendency ; let us see in him the geometrician rather than the moralist or physiologist ; let us endeavour to understand how all things presented themselves to his mind in the abstract form, and how mathematics was the science of sciences, and we shall then be able to understand his tenets. Thales, in searching for the origin of things, was led, as we have seen, to maintain Water to be that origin. But Anaxi- mander, accustomed to view things in the abstract, could not accept so concrete a thing as Water ; something more ultimate in the analysis was required. Water itself, which, in common with Thales, he held to be the material of the universe, was it not subject to conditions ? what were those conditions ? This Moisture, of which all things are made, does it not cease to be moisture in many instances ? And can that which is the origin of all, ever change, ever be confounded with individual things? Water itself is a Thing ; but a Thing cannot be All Things. These objections to the doctrine of Thales caused him to reject, or rather to modify, that doctrine. The dpxn, he said, was not Water ; it must be the Unlimited All, to a-rrzipov. Vague and profitless enough this theory will doubtless appear. The abstraction " All " will seem a mere distinction in words. But, in Greek Philosophy, as we shall repeatedly notice, distinctions in words were generally equivalent to dis- tinctions in things. And, if the reader reflects how the Mathe- matician, by the very nature of his science, is led to regard abstractions as entities, and to separate for instance form, and to treat of it as if it alone constituted body, there will be no difficulty in conceiving Anaximander's distinction between all Finite Things and the Infinite All. It is thus only we can explain his tenet ; and it thus seems borne out by the testimony of Aristotle and Theophrastus, who agree, that, by the Infinite he understood the multitude of elementary parts out of which individual things issued by separation. " By separation " — the phrase is significant. It means the passage from the abstract to the concrete — the All ANAXIMANDER OF MILETUS. yj realizing itself in the Individual Thing. Call the Infinite by the name of Existence, and say, "There is Existence per se and Existence per aliud — the former is, Existence the ever-living fountain whence flow the various existing Things" In this way you may, perhaps, make Anaximander's meaning intelligible. Let us now hear Ritter, Anaximander is "represented as arguing, that the primary substance must have been infinite to be all-sufficient for the limitless variety of produced things with which we are encompassed. Now, though Aristotle expressly characterizes this infinite as a mixture, we must not think of it as a mere multiplicity of primary material elements ; for to the mind of Anaximander it was a Unity immortal and imperish- able — an ever-producing energy. This production of individual things he derived from an eternal motion of the Infinite? The primary Being, according to Anaximander, is unques- tionably an Unity. It is One yet All. It comprises within itself the multiplicity of elements from which all mundane things are composed ; and these elements only need to be separated from it to appear as separate phenomena of nature. Creation is the decomposition of the Infinite. How does this decomposition originate? By the eternal motion which is the condition of the Infinite. " He regarded," says Ritter, " the Infinite as being in a constant state of incipiency, which, how- ever, is nothing but a constant secretion and concretion of certain immutable elements ; so that we might well say, the parts of the whole are constantly changing, while the whole is unchangeable." The reader may smile at this logic ; we would not have him do so. True, the idea of elevating an abstraction into a Being — the origin of all things — is baseless enough ; it is as if we were to say, "There are numbers i, 2, 3, 20, 80, 100 5 but there is also Number in the abstract, of which these individual numbers are but the concrete realisation ; without Number there would be no numbers." This is precisely similar reason- ing : yet so difficult is it for the human mind to divest itself of its own abstractions, and to consider them as no more than as abstractions, that this error lies at the root of the majority of philosophical systems. It may help the reader to some toler- ance of Anaximander's error if we inform him, that two of the most celebrated philosophers of modern times, Hegel and Victor Cousin, have maintained precisely the same tenet, though somewhat differently worded : they say that Creation is God J8 THE MATHEMATICIANS. passing into activity, but not exhausted by the act ; in othei words, Creation is the mundane existence of God ; finite Things are but the eternal motion, the manifestation of the All. Anaximander separated himself from Thales by regarding the abstract as of higher significance than the concrete ; and in this tendency we see the origin of the Pythagorean school, so often called the mathematical school. The speculations of Thales tended towards discovering the material constitution of the universe ; they were founded, in some degree, upon an induction from observed facts, however imperfect that induc- tion might be. The speculations of Anaximander were wholly deductive; and, as such, tended towards mathematics, the science of pure deduction. As an example of this mathematical tendency we may notice his physiological speculations. The central point in his cos- mopceia was the earth : for, being of a cylindrical form, with a base in the ratio i : 3 to its altitude, it was retained in its centre by the aid and by the equality of its distances from all the limits of the world. From the foregoing exposition, the reader may judge of the propriety of that ordinary historical arrangement which places Anaximander as the successor of Thales. It is clear, that he originated one of the great lines of speculative inquiry, and that one, perhaps, the most curious in all antiquity. We will make one more remark. By Thales, Water, the origin of things, was held to be a real physical element, which, in the hands of his successors, became gradually transformed into a merely representative emblem of something wholly different (Life or Mind) ; and the element which lent its name as the representa- tive was looked upon as a secondary phenomenon, derived from that primary force of which it was the emblem. Water was the real primary element with Thales ; with Diogenes, Water (having previously been displaced for Air) was but the emblem of Mind. A similar course is observable in the Italian school. Anaximander's conception of the All, though abstract, is, nevertheless, to a great degree, physical : it is All Things. His conception of the Infinite was not ideal — it had not passed into the state of a symbol — it was the mere description of the primary fact of existence. Above all, it involved no conception of intelligence except as a mundane finite thing. His to airtipov was the Infinite Existence, but not the Infinite Mind. This later development we shall meet with hereafter in the Eleatics. PYTHAGORAS. 39 CHAPTER II. PYTHAGORAS. It will create some surprise, in those not already familiar with our plan, to see Pythagoras treated of in immediate connexion with Anaximander ; but, although for the strongest evidence we must refer to the next chapter, in which the Pythagorean doctrines will be considered, yet we may at once adduce some slight collateral proof. Anaximander resided at the court of Poly crates, at Samos, where Pythagoras also 'ived. So runs tradition. Now, although this tradition may be groundless, as a fact, yet it indicates a connexion between the two thinkers firmly credited by ancient writers, and fully confirmed by the spirit of the two systems. The life of Pythagoras is enshrouded in the dim magnificence of legends, from which the attempt to extricate it is hopeless. Many years ago we examined this subject in its minutest details, and consulted almost everything that had been written on it. Guided by no sound principles of historical scepticism, we were perfectly bewildered with the force of contradictory evidence. We are now inclined to think that these opposing testimonies are of equal value : that is, of no value whatever. Certain general indications are doubtless to be trusted ; but they are few and vague. We will endeavour to sketch a memoir from them. As a specimen of the trouble necessary to settle any one point in this biography, we will here cite the various dates given by Scholars, as the results of their inquiries into his birth. Bentley says 43rd Olympiad ; Stanley, 53rd Oly. ; Gale, 60th Oly. ; Dacier, 47 th Oly. ; Diodorus Siculus, 61st Oly. ; Lloyd, 43rd Oly. ; Dodwell, 52nd Oly.; Clemens Alex., 62nd Oly.; Eusebius, 63rd or 64th Oly. ; Thirwall, 51st Oly. ; Ritter, 49th Oly. ; so that the accounts vary within the limits of eighty-four years. If we must make a choice, we should decide with Bentley ; not only from respect for that magnificent scholar, but because it agrees with the probable date of the birth of Pythagoras' friend and contemporary, Anaximander. Pythagoras is usually classed among the great founders of Mathematics ; and this receives confirmation from what we know of the general scope of his labours, and from the statement that ♦o THE MATHEMATICIANS. he was chiefly occupied with the determination of extension and gravity, and measuring the ratios of musical tones. His science and skill are of course absurdly exaggerated ; as, indeed, is every portion of his life. Fable assigns him the place of a saint ; a worker of miracles, and the teacher of more than human wisdom. His very birth was marvellous ; some accounts making him the son of Hermes, others of Apollo : in proof of the latter, he is said to have exhibited a golden thigh. With a word he tamed the Daunian bear, which was laying waste the country ; with a whisper he restrained an ox from devouring beans. He was heard to lecture at different places, such as Metapontum and Tauromenium, on the same day and at the same hour. As he crossed the river, the river-god saluted him with •' Hail, Pythagoras ! " and to him the harmony of the Spheres was audible music. Fable enshrines these wonders. But that they could exist, even as legendary lore, is significant of the greatness of Pytha- goras. It is well said by Sir Lytton Bulwer, in his brilliant and thoughtful work on Athens, that not only all the traditions respecting Pythagoras, but the certain fact of the mighty effect that, in his single person, he afterwards wrought in Italy, prove him also to have possessed that nameless art of making a personal impression upon mankind, and creating individual enthusiasm, which is necessary to those who obtain a moral command, and are the founders of sects and institutions. It is so much in conformity with the mariners of the time and the objects of Pythagoras, to believe that he diligently explored the ancient religious and political systems of Greece, from which he had been long a stranger, that we cannot reject the tradi- tions (however disfigured with fable) that he visited Delos, and affected to receive instructions from the pious ministrants of Delphi.* It is no ordinary man that Fable exalts into its poetical region. Whenever you find romantic or miraculous deeds attributed to any man, be certain that that man was great enough to sustain the weight of this crown of fabulous glory. So with Pythagoras, we accept the evidence of Fable. But the fact thus indicated is to us a refutation of the ordinary tradition of his having borrowed all his learning and philosophy from the East. Could not so great a man dis- pense with foreign teachers ? Assuredly he could and did. • * Athens : it Rise and F^ll,' vol. ii. p. 412. PYTHAGORAS. 4 t But his countrymen, by a very natural process of thought, looked upon his greatness as the result of his Eastern educa- tion. It is an old proverb, that no man is a prophet in his own country ; and the imaginative Greeks were peculiarly prone to invest the distant and the foreign with striking attributes. They could not believe in wisdom springing up from amongst them ; they turned to the East as to a vast and unknown region, whence all novelty, even of thought, must spring. When we consider, as Ritter observes, how Egypt was pecu- liarly the wonder-land of the olden Greeks, and how, even in later times, when it was so much better known, it was still, as it is to this day, so calculated to excite awe by the singular character of its people, which, reserved in itself, was always protruding on the observer's attention, through the stupendous structures of national Architecture, we can easily imagine how the Greeks were led to establish some connexion between this mighty East and their great Pythagoras. But although we can by no means believe that Pythagoras was much indebted to Egypt for his doctrines, we are not sceptical as to the account of his having travelled there. Samos was in constant intercourse with Egypt. If Pythagoras had travelled into Egypt — or, indeed, listened to the relations of those who had done so — he would thereby have obtained as much knowledge of Egyptian customs as appears in his system ; and that without having the least instruction from the Priesthood. The doctrine of metempsychosis was a public doctrine with the Egyptians; though, as Ritter says, he might not have been indebted to them even for that. Funeral cus- toms and abstinence from particular kinds of food were things to be noticed by any traveller. But the fundamental objection to Pythagoras having been instructed by the Egyptian Priests, is to be sought in the constitution of the caste of Priesthood itself. If they were so jealous of instruction as not to bestow it even on the most favoured of their countrymen, unless belonging to their caste, how unreasonable to suppose they would bestow it on a stranger, and one of different religion ! The ancient writers were sensible of this objection. To get rid of it, they invented a story which we shall give as it is given by Brucker. Polycrates wns in friendly relations with Amasis, King of Egypt, to whom he sent Pythagoras, with a recommendation to enable him to gain access to the Priests, 4* THE MATHEMATICIANS. fhe king's authority was not sufficient to prevail on the Priests to admit a stranger to their mysteries. They referred Pythagoras therefore to Thebes, as of greater antiquity. The Theban Priests were awed by the royal mandate, but were loath to admit a stranger to their rites. To disgust the novice, they forced him to undergo several severe ceremonies, among which was circumcision. But he could not be discouraged. He obeyed all their injunctions with such patience, that they resolved to take him into their confidence. He spent two-and« twenty years in Egypt, and returned perfect master of all science. This is not a bad story : it has, however, one objection ; it is not substantiated. To Pythagoras the invention of the word philosopher is ascribed. When he was in Peloponnesus, he was asked by Leontius, what was his art ? "I have no art. I am a philosopher," was the reply. Leontius never having heard the name before, asked what it meant. Pythagoras gravely answered : " This life may be compared to the Olympic games ; for, as in this assembly some seek glory and the crowns ; some by the purchase or by the sale of merchandise seek gain ; and others, more noble than either, go there neither for gain nor for applause, but solely to enjoy this wonderful spectacle, and to see and know all that passes; we, in the same manner, quit our country, which is heaven, and come into the world, which is an assembly where many work for profit, many for gain, and where there are but few who, despising avarice and vanity, study nature. It is these last whom I call philosophers ; for, as there is nothing more noble than to be a spectator without any personal interest, so in this life the contemplation and knowledge of nature, are infinitely more honourable than any other application." It is necessary to observe, that the ordinary interpretation of Philosopher, as Pythagoras meant it, a *} lover of wisdom," is only accurate where the utmost extension is given to the word "lover." Wisdom must be the " be-all and the end-all here " of the philosopher, and not simply a taste, or a pursuit. It must be his mistress, to whom his life is devoted. This was the meaning of Pythagoras. The word which had before designated a wise man, was pr]v), and Desire (Ov/mos) ; the two last man has in common with brutes ; the first is his distinguishing characteristic. It has hence been concluded that Pythagoras could not have maintained the doctrine of transmigration ; his distinguishing man from brutes being a refutation of those who charge him with the doctrine, t Without disputing the ingenuity of this argument, we are wholly unconvinced by it. J The Soul, being a self-moved monad, is One, whether it connect itself with two or with three; in other words the essence remains the same whatever its mani- festations. The One soul may have two aspects ; Intelligence and Desire, as in brutes ; or it may have three aspects, as in man. But each of these aspects may predominate, and the man will then become eminently rational, or able, or sensual ; he will be a philosopher, a man of the world, or a beast. Hence the importance of the Pythagorean initiation, and of the studies of Mathematics and Music. " This soul, which can look before and after, can shrink and shrivel itself into an incapacity of contemplating aught but the present moment, of what depths of degeneracy it is capable ! What a beast it may become ! And, if something lower than itself, why not something higher ! And, if something higher and lower, may there not be a law accurately determining its elevation and descent ? Each soul has its peculiar evil tastes, bringing it to the likeness of different creatures beneath itself; why may it not be under the necessity of abiding in the condition of that thing to which it had adapted and reduced itself ?"§ In closing this account of a very imperfectly known doctrine, we have only further to exhibit its relation to the preceding philosophy. It is clearly an offshoot of Anaximander's doc- trine, which it develops in a more logical manner. In Anaxi- mander there remained a trace of physical inquiry ; in Pytha- goras science is frankly mathematical. Assuming that Number * Thus Aristotle expresses himself when he says that the Pythagoreans maintained the soul and intelligence to be a certain combination of numbers, to 8k roiovSi (sc. tuv apiOfitiv) ^v\t) icai vovg. — Met, i. 5. t Pierre Leroux, ' De l'Humanite,' vol: i. p. 390-426. X Plato distinctly mentions the transmigration to beasts. — Phadrus, p. 45. And the Pythagorean Timaeus, in his statement of the doctrine, ai expressly includes beasts. — Tinueus, p. 45. { 4 Ency. Metrop.' — art. Moral and Metaphy. Philos. PHILOSOPHY OF PYTHAGORAS. 55 is the real invariable essence of the world, it was a natural deduction that the world is regulated by numerical proportions; and from this all the rest of his system followed as a conse- quence. Anaximander's system is but a rude and daring sketch of a doctrine which the great mathematical genius of Pytha- goras developed. The Infinite of Anaximander became the One of Pythagoras. Observe, that in neither of these systems is Mind an attribute of the In£ nite. It has been frequently maintained that Pythagoras taught the doctrine of a " soul of the world." But there is no solid ground for the opinion ; no more than for that of his Theism, which later writers so anxiously attributed to him. The conception of an Infinite Mind is much later than Pythagoras. He only regarded Mind as a pheno- menon ; as the peculiar manifestation of an essential number. And the proof of this assertion we take to lie in his very doc- trine of the soul. If the Monad, which is self-moved, can pass into the state of a brute, or of a plant, in which state it succes- sively loses its Reason, povs, and its Intelligence, prjv, to be- come merely sensual and concupiscible, does not this abdication of Reason and Intelligence distinctly prove them to be only variable manifestations (phenomena) of the invariable Essence? Assuredly ; and those who argue for the Soul of the World as an Intelligence, in the Pythagorean doctrine, must renounce both the doctrine of transmigration, and the central doctrine of the system, the invariable Number as the Essence of things. Pythagoras represents the second epoch of the second Branch of Ionian Philosophy ; he is parallel with Anaximenes, BOOK III. THE ELEATICS. CHAPTER L XENOPHANES. The contradictory statements which, for so long, had obscured the question of the date of Xenophanes' birth, may now be said to have been satisfactorily cleared up. M. Victor Cousin's essay on the subject will leave few readers unconvinced.* We may assert, therefore, with some probability, that Xenophanes was born in the 40th Olympiad, and that he lived nearly a hundred years. His birth-place was Colophon, an Ionian city of Asia Minor ; a city long famous as the seat of elegiac and gnomic poetry, and ranking the poet Minmermus amongst its celebrated men. He cultivated this species of poetry from his youth upwards ; it was the joy of his youthhood, the consola- tion and support of his manhood and old age. Banished from his native city, from what cause is unknown, he wandered over Sicily as a Rhapsodist :f a profession he exercised apparently till his death, though, if we are to credit Plutarch, with very little pecuniary benefit. He lived poor, and died poor. But he, above all men, could dispense with riches, having within him treasures inexhaustible. He whose whole soul was enwrapt in the con- templation of grand ideas, and whose vocation was the poetical expression of those ideas, could need but little of worldly gran- deur. He seems to us to have been one of the most remark- able men of antiquity ; certainly one of the sincerest. He had * ' Nouveaux Fragmens Philosophiques,' Bruxelles, 184 1. — The critical reader will observe some mis-statements in this essay, but on the whole it is well worthy of perusal. Karsten's ' Xenophanis Carminum Reliquae ' is of very great value to the student. f The Rhapsodists were the Minstrels of antiquity. They learned poems by heart and recited them to assembled crowds and on the occasions of feasts Homer was a rhapsodist, and rhapsodised his own divine verses. XENOPHANES. 57 no pity for the idle and luxurious superstitions of his time ; he had no tolerance for the sunny legends of Homer, defaced as they were by the errors of polytheism. He, a poet, was fierce in the combat he perpetually waged with the first of poets ; not from petty envy; not from petty ignorance; but from the deep sincerity of his heart, from the holy enthusiasm of his reverence He who believed in one God, supreme in power, goodness, and intelligence, could not witness without pain the degrada* tion of the Divine in the common religion. It was not that he was dead to the poetic beauty of the Homeric fables, but that he was keenly alive to their religious falsehood. Plato, whom none will accuse of want of poetical taste, made the same objec- tion. The latter portion of the 2nd and the beginning of the 3rd books of Plato's ' Republic,' are but expansions of these verses of Xenophanes' : — " Such things of the gods are related by Homer and Hesiod As would be shame and abiding disgrace to any of mankind ; Promises broken, and thefts, and the one deceiving the other." He who firmly believed that " There's but one God alone, the greatest of Gods and of mortals, Neither in body to mankind resembling, neither in ideas," * could not but see, " more in sorrow fhan in anger," the gross anthropomorphism of his fellows: — *' But men foolishly think that Gods are born like as men are, And have too a dress like their own, ana their voice and their figure : But if oxen and lions had hands like ours, and fingers, Then would horses like unto horses, and oxen to oxen, Paint and fashion their god-forms, and give to them bodies Of like shape to their own, as they themselves too are fashioned." f * This is too important a position to admit of our passing over the original : — «Ic Bibq Iv re Qtolai nai avBpwtcoim /igyioroc ovti dtfiag QvtiToiaiv bfioi'iog ovt( vorjua. Fragm. i. Ed. KarsUn. Wiggers, in his ' Life of Socrates,' expresses his surprise that Xeno- phanes was allowed to speak so freely respecting the State Religion in Magna Graecia, when philosophical opinions much less connected with religion had proved so fatal to Anaxagoias at Athens. But the apparent contradiction is reconciled when we remember that Xenophanes was a poet, and poets have in all ages been somewhat privileged persons. t Fragments v. and vi. are here united, as in Ritter. The sense seems to demand this conjunction. But Clemens Alexandrinus quotes the second fragment as if it occurred in another part of the poem ; introducing it with rat rdXtv ^r/ai — " and again he says." — Karsien, p. 41. 58 THE ELEATICS. In confirmation of which satire he referred to the Ethiopians, who represent their gods with flat noses, and of black colour ; while the Thracians give them blue eyes and ruddy com- plexions. Having attained a clear recognition of the unity and perfec- tion of the Godhead, it became the object of his life to spread that conviction abroad, and to tear down the thick veil of super- stition which hid the august countenance of truth. He looked around him, and saw mankind divided into two classes ; those who speculated on the nature of things, and endeavoured to raise themselves up to a recognition of the Divine, and those who yielded an easy unreflecting assent to the easy supersti- tions which compose religion. The first class speculated ; but they kept their speculations to themselves, and to a small circle of disciples. If they sought truth, it was not to communicate it to all minds ; they did not work for humanity, but for the few. Even Pythagoras, earnest thinker as he was, could not be made to believe in the fitness of the multitude for truth. He had two sorts of doctrine to teach : one for a few disciples, whom he chose with extreme caution; the other for such as pleased to listen. The former was what he believed the truth ; the latter was what he thought the mass were fitted to receive. Not so Xenophanes. He recognised no such distinction. Truth was for all men ; and to all men he endeavoured to pre- sent it ; and for three-quarters of a century did he, the great Rhapsodist of Truth, emulate his countryman Homer, the great Rhapsodist of Beauty, and wander into many lands, uttering the thought that was working in him. What a contrast is pre- sented by these two Ionian singers ! contrast in purpose, in means, and in fate. The rhapsodies of the philosopher once so eagerly listened to, and affectionately preserved in traditionary fragments, are now only extant in briefest extracts contained in ancient books, so ancient and so uninteresting as to be visited only by some rare old scholar and a few dilettanti spiders; while the rhapsodies of the blind old bard are living in the brain and heart of thousands and thousands, who go back to them as the fountain-source of poetry, and as the crystal mirror of an antique world ! How is this ? Because the world presented itself to Homer in pictures, to Xenophanes in problems. The one saw existence, enjoyed it, and painted it. The other also saw existence, but questioned it, and wrestled with it. Every trait in Homer is sunny clear ; XENOPFIANES. 59 in Xenophanes there is indecision, confusion. In Homer there is a resonance of gladness, a sense of manifold life, activity, and enjoyment. In Xenophanes there is bitterness, activity, but of a spasmodic sort, infinite doubt, and infinite sadness. The one was a poet singing as the bird sings, carolling for very exuberance of life ; the other was a Thinker, somewhat also of k fanatic. He did not sing, he recited : "Ah ! how unlike To that large utterance of the early Gods ! " That the earnest philosopher should have opposed the sunny poet, opposed him even with bitterness, on account of the degraded actions and motives which he attributed to the gods, is natural ; but we must distinguish between this opposition and satire. Xenophanes was bitter, not satirical. The statement derived frorn Diogenes, that he wrote satires against Homer and Hesiod, is incredible.* Those who think otherwise are referred to the excellent essay of Victor Cousin, before men- tioned, or to Ritter. Rhapsodising philosophy, and availing himself, for that pur- pose, of all that the philosophers of his time had discovered, he wandered from place to place, and at last came to Elea, where he settled. Hegel questions this. He says he finds no dis- tinct mention of such a fact in any of the ancient writers : on the contrary, Strabo, in his sixth book, when describing Elea, speaks of Parmenides and Zeno as having lived there, but is silent respecting Xenophanes, which Hegel justly holds to be suspicious. Indeed the words of Diogenes Laertius are vague. He says: — "Xenophanes wrote two thousand verses on the foundation of Colophon, and on a colony sent to Elea." This by no means implies that he lived there. Never- theless, we concur with the modern writers who, from the various connexions with the Eleats observable in his fragments, maintain that he must actually have resided there. The reader is again referred to M. Cousin on this point Be that as it may, he terminated a long and active life without having solved * Ttypaipt 8k cat iv tirtotv, /cat LXtytiag, eat ianfiovQ Kara '\lai68ov tal 'Oprjpov. Here, says M. Cousin, the word iapfiovg is either an interpo- lation of a copyist, as Feuerlin and Rossi conjecture, or else it is a mis- statement by Diogenes. Iambics could never be the designation of hexa- meters ; and there is not a single iambic verse of his remaining. But is his hexameters he opposes Homer and Hesiod. as we have seen. 60 THE ELEATICS. the great problem. The indecision of his acute mind sowed the seeds of that scepticism which was hereafter to play so large a part in philosophy. All his knowledge enabled him only to know how little he knew. His state of mind is finely described by Timon the sinograph, who puts into the mouth of Xenophanes these words : — M Oh, that mine were the deep mind, prudent and looking to both sides ; Long, alas ! have I strayed on the road of error, beguiled, And am, now, hoary of years, yet exposed to doubt and distraction Of all kinds ; for, wherever I turn to consider, I am lost in the One and Ally — (etc \v tclvto re -nav avtXvtro.)* It now remains for us to state some of the conclusions at which this great man arrived. They will not, perhaps, answer to the reader's expectation ; as, with Pythagoras, the reputation for extraordinary wisdom seems ill justified by the fragments of that wisdom which have descended to us. But although to modern science the conclusions of these early thinkers may appear trivial, let us never forget that it is to these early thinkers that we owe our modern science. Had there not been many a " Gray spirit yearning in desire To follow knowledge, like a sinking star, Beyond the utmost bound of human thought," f we should not have been able to travel on the secure terrestrial path of slow inductive science. The impossible has to be proved impossible, before men will consent to limit their endea- vours to the compassing of the possible. And it was the cry of despair which escaped from Xenophanes, the cry that nothing can be certainly known, which first called men's atten- tion to the nothingness of knowledge, as knozuledge was the?i conceived. Xenophanes thus opens a series of thinkers, which attained its climax in Pyrrho. That he should thus have been at the head of the monotheists, and at the head of the sceptics, is sufficient to entitle his speculations to an extended consi- deration here. * Preserved by Sextus Empiricus: Hypot. Pyrrhon. i. 224 ; and quoted also by Putter i. 443. f Tennyson. THE PHILOSOPHY OF XENOPHANES. ti CHAPTER II. THE PHILOSOPHY OF XENOPHANES. The great problem of existence had early presented itself to his mind ; and the resolution of that problem by Thales and Pythagoras, had left him unsatisfied. Neither the physiological nor the mathematical explanation could still the doubts which rose within him. On all sides he was oppressed with mysteries, tvhich these doctrines could not penetrate. The state of his mind is graphically painted in that one phrase of Aristotle's : " Casting his eyes upwards at the immensity of heaven, he declared that The One is God?" Overarching him was the deep blue, infinite vault, immoveable, unchangeable, embracing him and all things ; that his heart proclaimed to be God. As Thales had gazed abroad upon the sea, and felt that he was resting on its infinite bosom ; so Xenophanes gazed above him at the sky, and felt that he was encompassed by it. Moreover, it was a great mystery, inviting yet defying scrutiny. The sun and moon whirled to and fro through it ; the stars were " Pinnacled dim in its intense inane." The earth was constantly aspiring to it in the shape of vapour, the souls of men were perpetually aspiring to it with vague yearnings. It was the centre of all existence. It was exist- ence itself. It was The One. The Immoveable in whose bosom the Many were moved. Is not this the explanation of that opinion universally attri- buted to him, but always variously interpreted, " God is a sphere ? " The Heaven encompassing him and all things, was it not The One Sphere which he proclaimed to be God ? It is very true that this explanation does not exactly accord with his Physics, especially with that part which relates to the earth being a flat surface whose inferior regions are infinite ; by which he explained the fixity of the earth. M. Cousin, therefore, in consequence of this discrepancy, would interpret the phrase as metaphorical. " The epithet spherical is simply a Greek locution to indicate the perfect equality and absolute unity of God, and of which a sphere may be an image. The «rv et seq. Plato, is npeaking of the vo«c, adds ecu tyvxn> — Craty., p. 400. 96 ANAXAGORAS. that The Many could never be resolved into One ; and, ah without One there could not be Many, and with the many only there could not be One ; in other words, as God must be The One from whom the multiplicity of things is derived, the necessity of admitting The One as The All and the Self- existent was proved. This reasoning was accepted by Anaxa- goras. He saw that there were Many things ; he saw also the necessity for The One. In so far he was an Eleatic. Up to this point the two doctrines had been at variance ; a chasm of infinite depth yawned between them. Zeno's inven- tion of Dialectics was a result of this profound difference. It was reserved for Anaxagoras to bridge over the chasm which could not be filled up. He did so with consummate skill. He accepted both doctrines, with some modifications, and pro- claimed the existence of the Infinite Intelligence (The One) who was the Architect of the Infinite Matter {homaomerice, the Many). By this means he escaped each horn of the dilemma ; he escaped that which gored the Ionians, namely, as to how and why the Infinite Matter became fashioned into worlds and beings ; since Matter by itself can only be Matter. He escaped that horn which gored the Eleatics, as to how and why the Infinite One, who was pure and unmixed, became the Infinite Many, impure and mixed ; since one thing could never be more than one thing : it must have some other thing on which to act; for it cannot act upon itself. Anaxogoras escaped both these horns, by his dualistic theory of Mind fashioning, and Matter fashioned. A similar bridge was thrown by him over the deep chasm separating the Sensualists from the Rationalists, with respect to the origin of knowledge. He admitted both Sense and Reason ; others had only admitted either Sense or Reason. These two points entitle Anaxagoras to a very high rank in the history of Philosophy ; and we regret to see that Aristotle uniformly speaks disparagingly of him, but believe that the great Stagyrite did not clearly apprehend the force of the doctrine he was combating. EMPEDOCLES. jjjj CHAPTER III. EMPEDOCLES. We are forced to differ from all historians we have consulted, except De Gerando, who hesitates about the matter, respecting the place occupied by Empedocles. Brucker classes him among the Pythagoreans ; Ritter amongst the Eleatics 1 ; Zeller and Hegel as the precursor of the Atomists, who precede Anaxagoras ; Renouvier as the precursor of Anaxagoras ; Ten- neman placing Diogenes of Apollonia, between Anaxagoras and Empedocles, but making Democritus precede them. Whence these differences ? Because a just historical method was wanting to all. Chronology supports our view ; but our method originated it. When we come to treat of the doctrines of Empedocles, we shall endeavour to show the filiation of ideas from Anaxagoras. Meanwhile it may be necessary to examine the passage in Aristotle, on which very contradictory opinions have been grounded. In the 3rd chapter of the 1st book of Aristotle's Metaphysics, after a paragraph on the system of Empedocles, occurs this passage : " But Anaxagoras, of Ciazomenae, being superior to him (Empedocles) in respect of age, but inferior to him in respect of opinions, said that the number of principles was infinite." By "superior" and "inferior" we preserve the anti- thesis of the original ; but it would be more intelligible to say, " older " and " inferior." There are two other interpretations of this passage. One of them is that of M. Cousin (after Hegel), who believed that the antithesis of Aristotle is meant to convey the fact of Anaxa- goras, although older in point of time, being more recent in point of published doctrine than Empedocles, having written after him. This is his translation : " Anaxagoras qui naquit avant ce dernier, mais qui e'crivit apres lui." The second is that adopted by M. Renouvier from M. Ra- vaisson, who interprets it as meaning that the doctrine of Anaxagoras, though more ancient in point of publication, is more recent in point of thought, i.e., more developed philo- sophically although historically earlier. Now, we believe both these interpretations to be erroneous. There is no ground for them except in the antithesis of Aris- G 98 EMPEDOCLES. totle ; and the real meaning of that antithesis we will examine in the Appendix,* the present not being the place for such critical inquiries. Chronology is on our side. Anaxagoras was born about the 70th Olympiad ; Empedocles, by general consent, is said to have flourished in the 84th Olympiad ; this would make Anaxagoras at least 64 years old at the time when Empedocles published his doctrine, after which age it is barely probable that Anaxagoras could have written ; and even this probability vanishes when we look back upon the life of Anaxa- goras, who was teaching in Athens about the 76th or 77 th Olympiad, and who died at Lampsacus, in exile, in the 88th Olympiad, viz., 16 years after the epoch at which Empedocles is said to have flourished. Trusting that the above point was not unworthy of brief discussion, we will now commence our narrative. Empedocles was born in Agrigentum, in Sicily, and flourished about the 84th Olympiad. Agrigentum was at that period in the height of its splendour, and a formidable rival to Syracuse. Empedocles, descended from a wealthy and illustrious family, acquired a high reputation by his resolute espousal of the democratic party. Much of his wealth is said to have been spent in a singular and honourable manner ; namely, in bestow- ing dowries on poor girls, and marrying them to young men of rank and consequence. Like all the early philosophers, he is supposed to have been a great traveller, and to have gathered in distant lands the wondrous store of knowledge which he displayed. Only in the far East could he have learned the potent secrets of Medicine and Magic. Only from the Egyp- tian Magi could he have learned the art of prophecy. It is probable, however, that he did travel into Italy and to Athens. But, in truth, we can mention little of his personal history that is not open to question. His name rivals that of Pythagoras in the regions of Fable. The same august majesty of demeanour, and the same marvellous power over nature, are attributed to both. Miracles were his pastimes. In prophe- sying, in medicine, in power over the winds and rains, his wonders were so numerous and so renowned, that when he appeared at the Olympic Games all eyes were reverentially fixed upon him. His dress and demeanour accorded with his reputation. Haughty, impassioned, and eminently disinterested *See " Appendix C EMPEDOCLES. 99 in character, he refused the tyranny of Agrigentum when freely offered him by the citizens ; but his love of distinction showed itself in priestly garments, a golden girdle, the Delphic crown, and a numerous train of attendants. He proclaimed himself to be a God whom men and women reverently adored. But we must not take this literally. He probably only " assumed by anticipation an honour which he promised all soothsayers, priests, physicians and princes of the people." Fable has also taken advantage of the mystery which over- hangs his death, to create out of it various stories of marvel. One relates, that, after a sacred festival, he was drawn up to heaven in a splendour of celestial effulgence. Another and more popular one is that he threw himself headlong into the crater of Mount ^Etna, in order that he might pass for a god, the cause of his death being unknown ; but one of his brazen sandals, thrown up in an eruption, revealed the secret. A similar uncertainty exists as to his Teachers and his Writings. Pythagoras, Parmenides, Xenophanes, and Anaxa- goras have all been positively named as his Teachers. Unless we understand the word Teachers in a figurative sense, we must absolutely reject these statements. Diogenes Laertius, who reports them, does so in his dullest manner, with an absence of criticism, remarkable even in him.* Considering that there was, at least, one hundred and forty years between Pythagoras and Empedocles, we need no further argument to disprove any connection between them. Diogenes, on the authority of Aristotle (as he says), attributes to Empedocles the invention of Rhetoric ; and Quinctilian (iii. c. i) has repeated the statement. We have no longer the work of Aristotle ; but, as Ritter says, the assertion must have arisen from a misunderstanding, or have been said in jest by Aristotle, because Empedocles was the teacher of Gorgias ; most likely from a misunderstanding, since Sextus Empiricus mentions Aristotle as having said that Empedocles first incited, or gave an impulse to Rhetoric (irpwrov KeiuvrjKa/ai. — Adv. Mat. vii.). Aristotle, in his 'Rhetoric/ says that Corax and Tisias were the first to publish a written Treatise on Eloquence. We feel the less hesitation in rejecting the statement of Dio- genes, because in the very passage which succeeds he is guilty * Diogenes is one of the stupidest of the stupid race of compilers. His work is useful as containing occasional extracts, but can rarely be relied oq fpr anything else. loo EMPEDOCLES, of a very gross misquotation of Aristotle, who, as he says, " In his book of ' the Poets ' speaks of Empedocles as Homeric, powerful in his eloquence, rich in metaphors, and other poetical figures." — Diog. viii. c. ii. § 3, p. 57. Now, this work of Aristotle, on the Poets, is fortunately extant ; and it pro- claims the very reverse of what Diogenes alleges. Here is the passage : — " Custom, indeed, connecting the poetry or making with the metre, has denominated some elegiac poets, others epic poets : thus distinguishing poets not according to the nature of their imitation, but according to that of their metre only; for even they who composed treatises of Medicine, or Natural Philosophy in verse, are denominated Poets : yet Homer and Empedocles have nothing in common except their metre; the former, therefore, justly merits the name of Poet ; the other should rather be called a Physiologist than a Poet." — De Poet., c. i. After this, and indeed on the strength of this very passage, we may reasonably accept the suspicion of critics, that the tragedies attributed to Empedocles were not the works of the philosopher. The diversity of opinion with respect to the position of Empedocles, indicated at the opening of this chapter, is not without significance. That men such as Hegel, Ritter, Zeller, and Tenneman should see strong reasons for different classifi- cation cannot be without importance to the Historian. They destroy each other ; but it does not, therefore, follow that they all build upon false grounds. Each of their views has a certain truth in it ; but, not being the whole truth, it cannot prevail. The cause of the difference seems to be this : Empedocles has something of the Pythagorean, Eleatic, Heraclitic, and Anaxa- gorean systems in his system ; so that each historian, detecting one of these elements, and omitting to give due importance to the others, has connected Empedocles with the system to which that one element belongs. Ritter and Zeller have, however, been aware of some of the complex relations of the doctrine, but failed, we think, in giving it its true position. Respecting human knowledge, Empedocles belongs partly to the Eleatics. With them, he complained of the imperfection of the Senses ; and looked for truth only in Reason, which is partly human and partly divine — in other words, partly clouded by the senses. The divine knowledge is opposed to the sen- suous knowledge ; for man cannot approach the divine, neither EMPEDOCLES. 101 can he seize it with the hand nor the eye. Hence Empedocles conjoined the duty of contemplating God in the mind. But he appears to have proclaimed the existence of this divine knowledge without attempting to determine its relation to human knowledge. In this respect he resembles rather Xeno- phanes than Parmenides.* We have no clear testimony of his having studied the works of Anaxagoras ; but, if we had, it might not be difficult to explain his inferior theory of knowledge ; for, in truth, the theory of Anaxagoras was too far in advance of the age to be rightly apprehended. Empedocles, therefore, adhered to the Eleatic theory. With Xenophanes, he bewailed the delusion of the senses and experience. Listen to his lament : — " Swift-fated and conscious, how brief is life's pleasureless portion ! Like the wind-driven smoke, they are carried backwards awl forwards, Each trusting to nought save what his experience vouches, On all sides distracted ; yet wishing to find out the whole truth, In vain ; neither by eye nor ear perceptible to man, Nor to be grasped by mind : and thou, when thus thou hast wandered, Wilt find that no further reaches the knowledge of mortals." These verses seem to indicate a scepticism of Reason as well as of the Senses ; but other passages show that he upheld the integrity of Reason, which he thought was only prevented from revealing the whole truth because it was imprisoned in the body. Mundane existence was, in his system, the doom of such immortal souls as had been disgraced from Heaven. The Fall of Man he thus distinctly enunciated : — " This is the law of Fate, of the Gods an olden enactment, If with guilt or murder a Dsemonf polluteth his members, Thrice ten thousand years must he wander apart from the blessed. Hence, doomed I stray, a fugitive from Gods and an outcast To raging strife submissive." But he had some more philosophical ground to go upon when he wished to prove the existence of Reason and of the Divine Nature. He maintained that like could only be known by like : through earth we learn the earth, through fire we learn fire, through strife we learn strife, and through love we * Having quoted (p. 68) Aristotle's testimony of the sensuous nature ol knowledge in the Kmpedoclean theory, we need only here refer to it ; adding that in this respect he ranks with Parmenides rather than Xeno- phanes. t An immortal soul. 102 EMPEDOCLES. learn love. If, therefore,* like could only be known by like, the Divine could only be known by Divine Reason; and, inasmuch as the Divine is recognised by man it is a proof that the Divine exists. Knowledge and Existence mutually imply each other. Empedocles resembles Xenophanes also in his attacks on anthromorphism. God, he says, has neither head adjusted to limbs like human beings, nor legs, nor hands : " He is, wholly and perfectly, mind ineffable, holy, With rapid and swift-glancing thought pervading the whole world." We may compare these verses with the lines of Xeno» phanes — " Without labour he ruleth all things by reason and insight." Thus far Empedocles belonged to the Eleatics. The traces of Pythagoras are fewer ; for we cannot regard as such all those analogies which the ingenuity of some critics has detected. f In his life, and in his moral precepts, there is a strong resemblance to Pythagoras ; but in his philosophy we see none beyond metempsychosis, and the consequent absti- nence from animal food. Heraclitus had said there was nothing but a perpetual flux of things, that the whole world of phenomena was as a flowing river, ever-changing yet apparently the same. Anaxagoras had also said that there was no creation of elements, but only an arrangement. Empedocles was now to amalgamate these views. " Fools ! " he exclaims, " Who think aught can begin to be which formerly was not, Or, that aught which is, can perish and utterly decay. % Another truth I now unfold : no natural birth Is there of mortal things, nor death's destruction final ; Nothing is there but a mingling, and then a separation of the mingled, Which are called a birth and death by ignorant mortals. § " * We are here thinking for Empedocles ; that is, we have no other authority for this statement, than that something of the kind is wanting to make out a plausible explanation of what is only implied in the fragments extant. The fragments tell us that he believed in Reason as the transcen- dent faculty ; and also that Reason did in some way recognise the Divine. All we have done is to supply the link wanting. f See them noticed in ' Zeller, Philos. der Griechen,' p. 169-173. X Compare Anaxagoras, as quoted, p. 89 : " Wrongly do the Greeks suppose that aught begins or ceases to be." § Compare Anaxagoras : " So that all-becoming might more properly be called becoming mixed, and all-corruption becoming separate/* EMPEDOCLES. 103 So distinct a relationship as these verses manifest towards both Heraclitus and Anaxagoras will account for the classifi- cation adopted by Hegel, Zeller, and Renouvier ; at the same time, it gives greater strength to our opinion of Empedocles as the successor of these two. The differences are, however, as great as the resemblances. Having asserted that all things were but a mingling and a separation, he must have admitted the existence of certain primary elements which were the materials mingled. Heraclitus had affirmed Fire to be both the principle and the element ; both the moving, mingling force, and the mingled matter. Anaxagoras, with great logical consistency, affirmed that 'the primary elements were homceomericz, since nothing could proceed from nothing, and whatever was arranged must, therefore, be an arrangement of primary elements. Empedocles affirmed that the primary elements were Four, viz., Earth, Air, Fire, and Water : out of these all other things proceed ; all things are but the various minglings of these four. Now, that this is an advance on both the preceding con- ceptions will scarcely be denied ; it bears indubitable evidence of being a later conception, and a modification of its antece- dents. Nevertheless, although superior as a physiological view it has not the logical consistency of that maintained by Anaxa- goras ; for, as Empedocles taught that like can only be known by like, i.e., that existence and knowledge were identical and mutually implicative, he ought to have maintained that what- ever is recognised by the mind as distinct, must be distinct in esse. With respect to the Formative Power, we see the traces of Heraclitus and Anaxagoras in about the same proportion. Heraclitus maintained that Fire was impelled by irresistible Desire to transform itself into some determinate existence. Anaxagoras maintained that the infinite Intelligence was the great architect who arranged all the material elements; the Mind that controlled and fashioned Matter. The great dis- tinction between these two systems' is, that the Fire transforms itself, the Nous transforms something which is radically different from itself. Both these conceptions were amalga- mated by Empedocles. He taught that Love was the creative power. Wherever there is a mixture of different elements Love is exerted. Here we see the Desire of Heraclitus sublimed into its 104 EMPEDOCLES. highest expression, and the Nous of Anaxagoras reduced to its moral expression, Love. The difficulties of the Heraclitean doctrine, namely, as to how Fire can ever become anything different from Fire, are avoided by the adoption of the Anaxa- gorean dualism ; while the difficulties of the Anaxagorean doctrine, namely, as to how the great Arranger was moved and incited to arrange the primary elements, are in some mea- sure avoided by the natural desire of Love (Aphrodite), But there was a difficulty still to be overcome. If Love was the creator, that is, the Mingler, what caused separation ? To explain this, he had recourse to Hate. As the perfect state of supra-mundane existence was Harmony, the imperfect state of mundane existence was Discord. Love was, therefore, the Formative Principle, and Hate the Destructive. Hence he said that — " All the members of God war together, one after the other" This is but the phrase of Heraclitus : " Strife is the parent of all things." It is, nevertheless, most probable that Empe- docles regarded hate as only a mundane power, as only operat- ing on the theatre of the world, and nowise disturbing the abode of the Gods.* For, inasmuch as Man is a fallen and perverted God, doomed to wander on the face of the earth, sky-aspiring, but sense-clouded ; so may Hate be only perverted Love, struggling through space. Does not this idea accord with what we know of his opinions ? His conception of God, that is, of The One, was that of a " sphere in the bosom of harmony fixed in calm rest, gladly rejoicing." This quiescent sphere, which is Love, exists above and around the moved World. Certain points are loosened from the combination of the elements, but the unity established by Love continues. Ritter is convinced that Hate has only power over the smaller portion of existence, over that part which, disconnecting itself from the whole, contaminates itself with crime, and thereby devolves to the errors of mortals. Our account of Empedocles will be found to vary consider- ably from that in Aristotle ; but our excuse is that furnished by the great Stagyrite himself, who is constantly telling us that Empedocles gave no reason for his opinions. This is true. Moreover, Aristotle makes us aware that his interpreta- tion is open to question; for, he says, that his interpreta- * An opinion subsequently put forth with great splendour of diction by Plato in the ' Phaedrus.' DEMOCRITUS. 105 tion can only be obtained by pushing Empedocles' premisses to their legitimate conclusions ; a process which destroys all historical integrity : for what thinker does push his premisses to their utmost limits? Empedocles was an original thinker; but he was certainly not a logical thinker, and we have no right to supply his deficiencies in that respect. The last sentence will, perhaps, be thought subversive of our avowed plan of supplying the connecting links in a chain of reasoning which tradition hands down to us in fragments. But in truth our endeavour has been to connect two or more fragments, not to lengthen the original chain. For instance, at page 101-2, we take an admitted doctrine of perception, and an admitted doctrine of the existence of the Divine, we bring the two together by means of a syllogism j but we add nothing in the shape of doctrine. CHAPTER IV. DEMOCRITUS. The laughing Philosopher, the traditional antithesis to Hera- clitus, was born at Abdera (the new settlement of the Teians after their abandonment of Ionia), in the 80th Olymp. His claim to the title of Laugher, 6 yeXaalvos has been disputed, and by moderns generally rejected. Perhaps, the native stupidity of his countrymen, — and they were renowned for abusing the privilege which men have of being stupid, — afforded him incessant matter for laughter. Perhaps he was by nature satirical, and thought ridicule the test of truth. We have no proof of his being a satirist, except the tradition : that may be false, but must have had some origin. Democritus was of a noble and wealthy family, so wealthy that it entertained Xerxes at Abdera on his return from Asia. Xerxes in recompense left some of his Magi to instruct the young Democritus. Doubtless it was their tales of the won- ders of their native land, and of the deep unspeakable wisdom of their priests, that inspired him with the passion of travel. "I, of all men," he says, " of my day, have travelled over the greatest extent of country, exploring the most distant lands ; most climates and regions have I visited, and listened to the io6 DEMOCR1TUS. most experienced and wisest of men ; and, in the calculations of line-measuring no one hath surpassed me, not even the Egyptians, amongst whom I sojourned five years." In travel he spent his patrimony ; but he exchanged it for an amount ot knowledge which no one had previously equalled. The Ab- derites, on his return, looked on him with vague wonder. The sun-burnt traveller brought with him knowledge which, to them, must have appeared divine. Curiosity encompassed him. He exhibited a few samples of his lore, foretold unexpected changes in the weather, and was at once exalted to the summit of that power to which it is a nation's pride to bow. He was offered political supremacy, but wisely declined it. It would be idle to detail here the various anecdotes which tradition hands down respecting him. They are mostly either impossible or improbable. That, for instance, of his having put out his eyes with a burning-glass, in order that he might be more perfectly and undisturbedly acquainted with his reason, is in violent contradiction to his very theory of the soul, to which the eye was one of the great inlets. We may credit the account of his having led a quiet sober life, and of his dying at a very advanced age. More we cannot credit. Respecting his Philosophy we have more certain evidence ; but even that has been so variously interpreted, and is in many parts so obscure, that historians have been at a loss to give it its due position in relation to other systems. Reinhold, Bran- dis, Marbach, and Hermann view him as an Ionian ; Buhle and Tennemann, as an Eleatic ; Hegel, as the successor of Hera- clitus, and the predecessor of Anaxagoras; Ritter, as a Sophist ; and Zeller, as the precursor of Anaxagoras. Of all these attempts at classification, that by Ritter is the worst : it is pitiable. Because Democritus has an occasional phrase im- plying great vanity — and those mentioned by Ritter seem to us to imply nothing of the kind — he is a Sophist. That is a sample of Ritter's arguing ! We are convinced that all the above attempts are erroneous, and for a similar reason to that which guided historians in their classification of Empedocles. Democritus is distinguished from the Ionians, by the denial of all sensible quality to the primary elements ; from the Eleatics by his affirmation of the existence of a multiplicity of elements ; from Heraclitus on the same ground ; from Anaxagoras, as we shall see presently ; and from Empedocles, by denying the Four Elements, and the DEMOCRITUS. IO ; Formative Love. All these differences are radical. The resemblances, such as they are, may have beet? coincidences, or derived from one or two of the later thinkers : Parmenides and Anaxagoras for example. What did Democritus teach ? This question we will endea- vour to answer somewhat differently from historians ; but our answer shall be wholly grounded on precise and certain evi- dence, with no other originality than that of developing the system from its central principles. We commence with Knowledge ; and with the passage of Aristotle, universally accredited though variously employed : " Democritus says, that nothing is true ; or, if so, it is not evi- dent to us. Nevertheless, as, in his system, the sensation constitutes the thought, and at the same time is but a change in the sentient being, the sensible phenomena (i.e. sensations) are of necessity true." * What does this pregnant passage mean ? It means that sensation, inasmuch as it is sensation, must be true : that is true subjectively ; but sensation, inasmuch as it is sensation, cannot be true objectively. M. Renouvier thinks that Democritus was the first to introduce this distinc- tion ; but our readers will remember that it was the distinction established by Anaxagoras. Sextus Empiricus quotes the very words of Democritus: "The sweet exists only inform, the bitter in form, the hot in form, the cold in form, colour in form ; but in causal reality (am>/)t only atoms and space exist. The sensible things which are supposed by opinion to exist have no real existence, but only atoms and space exist." — Adv. Mathem. vii. p. 163. When he says that colour, &c, exist in form only, he means that they are sensible images constantly emanating from things ; a notion we shall explain presently. A little further on Sextus reports the opinion, that we only perceive that which falls in upon us according to the disposi- tion of our bodies ; all else is hidden from us. Neither Condillac nor Destutt de Tracy have more distinctly identified sensation and thought, than Democritus in the above passages. But he does so in the spirit of Kant rather than that * We feel bound to quote the original : jjtoi ov9tv tlvai a\r)9tg r\ rjfiiv y'atiriXov. "OXwg 8k did to Dicdkapfiavttv, Qpovijoiv fiiv rrjv oXo9r\oiv, ravri)v d'elvai dWoiuxriv, to ) saw existed, and existed as they saw it. Then came others who began to question the accuracy of the senses; lastly came those who denied that accuracy altogether, and pronounced the reports to be mere delusions. Thus the question forced itself on the mind of Democritus : — In what manner could the senses perceive external things ? Once settle the modus operandi and then the real efficacy may be estimated. The hypothesis by which he attempted to explain percep- tion was both ingenious and bold ; and many centuries elapsed before a better one was suggested. He supposed that all things were constantly throwing off images of themselves (ctSwAa), which, after assimilating to themselves the surround- ing air, enter the soul by the pores of the sensitive organ. The eye, for example, is composed of aqueous humours ; and water sees. But how does water see ? It is diaphanous and receives the image of whatever is presented to it. This is a very rude and material hypothesis, we will confess ; but did not philoso- phers, for centuries, believe that their senses received impres- sions of things ? and did they not suppose that they had images of things reflected in the mind? Now this latter hypothesis is perhaps, less obviously fantastic and gratuitous ; but it is also less logical ; for, if the mind be a mirror reflecting the images of things, how comes it that the images vary with different minds, and with the same mind at different states r And how is it that we never know the nature of things, but only their appearances? But, more than all, how is it that the mind becomes a mirror reflecting the images? The hypothesis stands as much in need of explanation as the phenomenon it pretends to explain. The hypothesis of Democritus once admitted serves its pur- pose ; at least, to a considerable extent. Only the external \y surface of a body is thrown off in the shape of an ctSuAov or image, and even that only imperfectly and obscurely. The figure thrown off is not a perfect image of the object throwing it off. It is only an image of the external form, and is subject to variations in its passage to the mind. This being the case, the strictly phenomenal nature of all knowledge is accurately / / exhibited. The idols or images, being themselves imperfect, *s our knowledge is imperfect. With this theory of knowledge how could he exhibit the other greater question of Creation ? We shall see. It is said, that he rejected The One of the Eleatics, The Four of Empe. no DEMOCRITUS. docks, and the homceomerice oi Anaxagoras, and declared Atoms invisible and intangible to be the primary elements ; and that all things were but modes of one of the triple arrangements, viz., configuration, combination, and position. The atom being indivisible is necessarily one ; and, being one, is necessarily self-existent. By this hypothesis, therefore, Democritus satis- fied the demands of those who declared that the self-existent must be One ; and of those who declared that there were many things existing, and that the One could never be more than ^\J the One, never become the Many. He amalgamated the Ionian and Eleatic schools in his speculation, correcting both. He, doubtless, derived this idea from the homceomerice of Anaxagoras ; or, as those who place Anaxagoras later than Democritus would say, originated this idea. It becomes a question, therefore, as to which of these speculations bears the impress of greater maturity. On this question we cannot hesi- tate to pronounce. The idea of homceomerice betrays its more primitive nature in this : it attributes positive qualities to atoms, which qualities are not changed or affected by combination or arrangement. The idea of the atom divested of all quality, and only assuming that quality as phenomenal, when in combina- tion with other atoms, and changing its quality with every change of combination, is indubitably a far more scientific speculation ; it is also obviously later in point of development. From the axiom that only " like can act upon like," Anaxa- goras formed his homaomerice. Democritus accepted the axiom, but gave it a wider application. If only like can act upon like, said he, then must all things be alike in esse ; and the only differences are those of phenomena, i.e., of manifes- tation ; these depend on combination and arrangement. Atomism is homgeomerianism stripped of qualities. It is, therefore, Anaxagoras greatly improved. The Atomism of Democritus has not been sufficiently ap- preciated as a speculation. To us it appears one of the pro- foundest yet reached by human subtlety. Some proof of this may be seen in the fact of the great Leibnitz, many centuries afterwards, having been led to a doctrine essentially similar. His celebrated " Monadologie " is but Atomism, with a new terminology. Leibnitz called his Monad & force; and that to him was the prima materia. So also Democritus denied that atoms had any weight j they had only force, and it was the impulsion given by superior torce which constituted weight DEMOCRITUS. ill It is worthy of remark that not only did these thinkers concur in their doctrine of atomism, but also, as we have seen, in their doctrine of the origin of knowledge, a coincidence which gives weight to the supposition that in both minds one doctrine was dependent on the other. From what has already been said, the reader may estimate Ritter's assertion, that it would be in vain to seek for any profounder view in the theory of Democritus than that com- mon to all mechanical physiologists who sought to reduce everything to mathematical conceptions ; an assertion as pre- posterous as that which follows it, namely, that Democritus arrived at his atomic theory in the same way as modern physio- logists, — from a bias for the mechanical consideration of Nature. He here grossly contradicts himself. Having first declared that there was nothing in the Democritian theory but what the Ionians had previously discovered, he next declares that this theory is the same as that of the modern atomic theory. We are puzzled to which opinion we shall award the palm of historical misconception. The modern atomic theory is the law of definite proportions ; the ancient theory is merely the affirmation of indefinite combinations. Between the two there is precisely the difference of Positive Science and Philosophy.* They were neither arrived at in the same way, nor have they the same signification. Ritter's chapter on Democritus is one of the worst in his book. He has misrepresented almost every point, and even failed, we believe, to seize the meaning of the very text he quotes. For instance, he says, " Only one physical property was attributed to these atoms — weight." This is in defiance ol authority, + and the very passage from Aristotle which is quoted to maintain it, is, we believe, against it. The passage is this : "Atoms, indeed, are heavy according to excess" {Ka.ro. t^v virepoxnv.) Excess of what? Clearly excess of aggregation, i.e., of force. But if only heavy in excess, they cannot indi- vidually be heavy ; ergo, weight is not a property of each atom, but of a combination of atoms. We can enter into no further details. Attempts have been made, from certain expressions attributed to Democritus, to deduce an Intelligence, somewhat similar to that in the Anaxa- gorean doctrine, as the Formative Principle. We cannot sec • See our * Introduction.' t See ' Renouvier,' i. 245, 6. i is DEMOCRTTUS. our way on this path. Evidence is so small and so questionable that we refrain from pronouncing on it. Certain it is that he attributed the formation of things to Destiny; but whether that Destiny was intelligent or not is uncertain. In conclusion, we may observe that his system was an ad« vance on that of his predecessors. In the two great points of psychology and physics, which we have considered at length, k is impossible to mistake a very decided progress, as well as *Jhe opening of * new line in each department. TOtrto lEpocf). INTELLECTUAL CRISIS. — THE INSUFFICIENCY OF ALL ATTEMPTS TOWARDS A SOLUTION OF THE PROB- LEM OF EXISTENCE, AS WELL AS THAT OF KNOWLEDGE, PRODUCES THE SOPHISTS. THE SOPHISTS. The Sophists are a much calumniated race. That they should have been so formerly does not surprise us ; that they should be so still is an evidence that historical criticism is yet in its infancy. In raising our voices to defend them, we are aware that we shall incur the charge of paradox. But, looked at nearly, the paradox is on the side of those who credit and repeat the traditional account. In truth we know of no charge so unanimous, yet so parodoxical, as that brought against the Sophists. It is as if mankind had consented to judge of Socrates by the representation of him in " The Clouds" The caricature of Socrates by Aristophanes is quite as near the truth as the caricature of the Sophists by Plato ;* with this difference, that the one was wilfully, consciously caricaturing, the other unconsciously. On the Sophists we have only the testimony of antagonists ,• and the history of mankind clearly proves that the enmities which arise from difference of race and country are feeble, compared with the enmities which arise from difference of creed : the former may be lessened by contact and intercourse, the latter only aggravated. Plato had every reason to dislike the Sophists and their opinions : he, therefore, lost no occasion of slandering the one, and misrepresenting the other. Yet from Plato alone do writers draw their opinions of the Sophists * See in particular that amusing dialogue the 'Euthydemus,' which is quite as exaggerated as Aristophanes. H ii4 THE SOPHISTS. as a class : as thinkers, Aristotle, if the work be his, also mis- represents them. This may look presumptuous. We have nothing remaining of what the Sophists taught, except the opinions reported by others. These opinions we pronounce to be garbled. And why ? The Sophists were wealthy ; the Sophists were powerful • the Sophists_were_dazzling 1 rhetorical^ but shallow. Interro- gate human nature — above all the nature of philosophers — and ask what will be the sentiment entertained respecting these Sophists by their contemporaries ? Ask the solitary thinker what is his opinion of the showy, powerful, but shallow rhetorician, who usurps the attention of the world. The man of convictions has at all times a superb contempt for the man of mere oratorical, or dialectical display. The Thinker knows that the world is ruled by Thought ; yet he sees expression gaining the world's attention. He knows perhaps that he has within him thoughts pregnant with human welfare; yet he sees the giddy multitude drunk with the enthusiasm excited by some daring sophism, clothed in enchanting language, He sees through the sophism, but cannot make others as clear- sighted. His warning is unheeded. His wisdom is spurned. His ambition is frustrated. The popular Idol is carried onward in triumph. Now the Thinker would not be human if he bore this with equanimity. He does not bear it. He is loud and angry in lamenting the fate of a world that can so be led ; loud and angry in his contempt of one who could so lead it. Should he become the critic or historian of his age, what exactness ought we to expect in his account of the popular idol ? Somewhat of this kind was the relation in which the Sophists and Philosophers stood to each other. The Sophists were hated by some because powerful, by others because shallow. They were misrepresented by all. In later times, their antagonism to Socrates has brought them ill-will ; and this ill-will is strengthened by the very prejudice of the name. Could a Sophist be other than a cheat and a liar ? As well ask, could a Devil be other than Evil ? In the name of Sophist all odious qualities are implied : and this implication perverts our judgment. Call the Sophists Professors of Rhetoric, which is their truest designation, and then examine their history ; it will produce a very different impression. We said it was a paradox to maintain that the Sophists really promulgated the opinions usually attributed to them. And by THE SOPHISTS. "5 this we mean that not only are some of those opinions nothing but caricatures of what was really maintained, but, also, that in our interpretation of the others we grossly err, by a con- fusion of Christian with Heathen views of morality. Moderns cannot help regarding as fearfully immoral, ideas which, by the Greeks, were regarded as moral, or, at least, as not disrepu- table. For instance : the Greek orators are always careful to impress upon their audience, that in bringing a charge against any one, they are actuated by the strongest personal motives ; that they have been injured by the accused; that they have good honest hatred, as a motive, for accusing him. Can any- thing be more opposite to Christian feeling? A Christian accuser is just as anxious to extricate himself from any charge of being influenced by personal considerations as the Greek was of making the contrary evident. A Christian seeks to place his motive to the account of abstract justice; and his statement would be received with great suspicion were it known that a personal feeling prompted it. _The .reason is that the. Chris tian Ethics do not countenance vengeance ; the Greek Ethics not only countenanced vengeance, but very much re- probated i?iformers : consequently, whoever made an accusa- tion had to clear himself from the ignominy of being an in- former, and, to do so, he showed his personal motives. This example will prepare the reader to judge, without pre- cipitancy, the celebrated boast of the Sophists, that they could "make the worse appear the better reason." This was the grand aim of their endeavours. This was their avowed object To teach this art they demanded enormous sums ; to learn it enormous sums were readily given, and given by many. Now, understanding this object as moderns have understood it, and thereby forming our notion of the Sophists, let us ask : Is it credible that such an art should have been avowed, and, being avowed, should be rewarded, in a civilized state ? Let us think, for an instant, of what are its moral, or rather its immoral, consequences. Let us reflect how utterly it destroys all morality ; how it makes the very laws but playthings for dialectical subtlety. Then let us ask whether, with our opinions respecting its morality, any state could have allowed such open blasphemy — such defiance to the very fundamental principle of honesty and integrity — such demolition of the social contract ? Could any state do this ; and was Athens that state ? We ask the reader to realize for himself some notion of the Athe- u6 THE SOPHISTS. nians as citizens, not merely as statues ; to think of them as human beings, full of human passions, not simply as architects, sculptors, poets, and philosophers. Having done this we ask him whether he can believe that these Athenians would have listened to a man proclaiming all morality a farce, and all law a quibble — proclaiming that for a sum of money he could in- struct any one how to make an unjust cause appear a just one ? Would not such a proclamation be answered with a shout of derision, or of execration, according to the belief in his sincerity ? Could any charlatan, in the corruptest age, have escaped lapidation for such effrontery ? Yet the Sophists were enormously wealthy, by many greatly admired, and were selected as ambassadors on very delicate missions. They were men of splendid talents, of powerful connexions. Around them flocked the rich and noble youth of every city they entered. They were the intellectual leaders of their age. If they were what their adversaries describe them, Greece could only have been an earthly Pandemonium, where Belial was King. To believe this is beyond our power. Such a paradox it would be frivolous to refute, had it not been maintained for centuries. Some have endeavoured to escape it by maintaining that the Sophists were held in profound contempt, and certain passages are adduced from Plato in proof of this. But the fact appears to us to be the reverse of this. The great wealth and power of the Sophists — the very importance implied in Plato's constant polemic against them — prove that they were not objects of contempt. Objects of aversion they might be to one party ; the successful always are. Objects of contempt they might be, to some sincere and profound thinkers. But the question here is not one relating to individuals, but to the State. It is not whether Plato despised Gorgias, but whether Athens allowed him to teach the most unblushing and undis- guised immorality. There have been daring speculators in all times. There have been men shameless and corrupt. But that there has been any speculator so daring as to promulgate what he knew to be grossly immoral, and so shameless as to avow it, is in such contradiction to our experience of human nature as at once to be rejected.* * We are told by Sextus that Protagoras was condemned to death by the Athenians because he professed himself unable to say whether the Gods THE SOPHISTS. 117 It is evident, therefore, that in teaching the art of " making worse appear the better reason," the Sophists were not guilty of anything reprehensible to a Greek ; however serious thinkers, such as Socrates and Plato, might detest the shallow philosophy from which it sprung ; and their detestation was owing to their love of truth, which the Sophists outraged. It may not be easy to make the reader understand how such doctrines could be regarded as otherwise than moral. But we will try. If he is familiar with Mr. Macaulay's brilliant and searching article on Machiavelli, he will at once see how such doctrines might have been held by very virtuous men. If he has not already made himself acquainted with that masterly performance, the following extracts will be acceptable both in themselves and in reference to our present subject : — " Among the rude nations which lay beyond the Alps, valour was absolutely indispensable. Without it, none wxild be eminent, few could be secure. Cowardice was, therefore, naturally considered as the foulest reproach. Among the polished Italians, enriched by commerce, governed by law, and passionately attached to literature, everything was done by superiority of intelligence. Their very wars, more pacific than the peace of their neighbours, required rather civil than military qualifications. Hence, while courage was the point of honour in other countries, ingenuity became the point of honour in Italy. " From these principles were deduced, by processes strictly analogous, two opposite systems of fashionable morality. Through the greater part of Europe, the vices which peculiarly belong to timid dispositions, and which are the natural defence of weakness, fraud, and hypocrisy, have always been most dis- reputable. On the other hand, the excesses of haughty and daring spirits have been treated with indulgence, and even with respect. The Italians regarded with corresponding lenity those crimes which require self-command, address, quick obser- vation, fertile invention, and profound knowledge of human nature. " Such a prince as our Henry the Fifth would have been the idol of the North. The follies of his youth, the selfish and desolating ambition of his manhood, the Lollards roasted existed, or what they were, owing to the insufficiency of knowledge. Yet the Athenians are supposed to have tolerated the Sophists as they *re understood by moderns ! n8 THE SOPHISTS. at slow fires, the prisoners massacred on the field of battle, the expiring lease of priestcraft renewed for another century, the dreadful legacy of a causeless and hopeless war, bequeathed to a people who had no interest in its event, everything is for- gotten but the victory of Agincourt ! Francis Sforza, on the other hand, was the model of the Italian hero. He made his employers and his rivals like his tools. He first overpowered his open enemies by the help of faithless allies ; he then armed himself against his allies with the spoils taken from his enemies. By his incomparable dexterity, he raised himself from the pre- carious and dependent situation of a military adventurer to the first throne of Italy. To such a man much was forgiven — hollow friendship, ungenerous enmity, violated faith. Such are the opposite errors which men commit, when their morality is not a science, but a taste ; when they abandon eternal prin- ciple for accidental associations. " We have illustrated our meaning by an instance taken from history. We will select another from fiction. Othello murders his wife ; he gives orders for the murder of his lieu- tenant ; he ends by murdering himself. Yet he never loses the esteem and affection of a Northern reader — his intrepid and ardent spirit redeeming everything. The unsuspecting con- fidence with which he listens to his adviser, the agony with which he shrinks from the thought of shame, the tempest of passion with which he commits his crimes, and the haughty fearlessness with which he avows them, give an extraordinary interest to his character. Iago, on the contrary, is the object of universal loathing. Many are inclined to suspect that Shakspeare has been seduced into an exaggeration unusual with him, and has drawn a monster who has no archetype in human nature. Now, we suspect that an Italian audience, in the fifteenth century, would have felt very differently. Othello would have inspired nothing but detestation and contempt. The folly with which he trusts to the friendly professions of a man whose promotion he had obstructed, the credulity with which he takes unsupported assertions, and trivial circum- stances, for unanswerable proofs, the violence with which he silences the exculpation till the exculpation can only aggravate his misery, would have excited the abhorrence and disgust of the spectators. The conduct of Iago they 'would assuredly have condemned; but they would have condemned it as we con- demn that of his victim. Something of interest and respect THE SOPHISTS. H 9 would have mingled with their disapprobation. The readiness of his wit, the clearness of his judgment, the skill with which he penetrates the dispositions of others and conceals his own, would have insured to him a certain portion of their esteem. " So wide was the difference between the Italians and their neighbours. A similar difference existed between the Greeks of the second century before Christ, and their masters, the Romans. The conquerors, brave and resolute, faithful to their engagements, and strongly influenced by religious feelings, were, at the same time, ignorant, arbitrary, and cruel. With the vanquished people were deposited all the art, the science, and the literature of the Western world. In poetry, in philo- sophy, in painting, in architecture, in sculpture, they had no rivals. Their manners were polished, their perceptions acute, their invention ready; they were tolerant, affable, humane. But of courage and sincerity they were almost utterly destitute. The rude warriors who had subdued them consoled themselves for their intellectual inferiority by remarking that knowledge and taste seemed only to make men atheists, cowards, and slaves. The distinction long continued to be strongly marked, and furnished an admirable subject for the fierce sarcasms of Juvenal. 11 The citizen of an Italian commonwealth was the Greek of the time of Juvenal and the Greek of the time of Pericles, joined in one. Like the former, he was timid and pliable, artful and unscrupulous. But, like the latter, he had a country. Its independence and prosperity were dear to him. If his character were degraded by some mean crimes, it was, on the other hand, ennobled by public spirit and by an honourable ambition. A vice sanctioned by the general opinion is merely a vice. The evil terminates in itself. A vice condemned by the general opinion produces a pernicious effect on the whole character. The former is a local malady, the latter a constitu- tional taint. When the reputation of the offender is lost, he too often flings the remains of his virtue after it in despair. The Highland gentleman who, a century ago, lived by taking black mail from his neighbours, committed the same crime for which Wild was accompanied to Tyburn by the huzzas of two hundred thousand people. But there can be no doubt that he was a much less depraved man than Wild. The deed for which Mrs. Brownrigg was hanged sinks into nothing when compared with the conduct of the Roman who treated the public to a 120 THE SOPHISTS. hundred pair of gladiators. Yet we should probably wrong such a Roman if we supposed that his disposition was so cruel as that of Mrs. Brownrigg. In our own country, a woman forfeits her place in society by what, in a man, is too commonly considered as an honourable distinction, and, at worst, as a venial error. The consequence is notorious. The moral prin- ciple of a woman is frequently more impaired by a single lapse from virtue, than that of a man by twenty years of intrigue. Classical antiquity would furnish us with instances stronger, if possible, than those to which we have referred. "We must apply this principle to the case before us. Habits of dissimulation and falsehood, no doubt, mark a man of our age and country as utterly worthless and abandoned ; but it by no means follows that a similar judgment would be just in the case of an Italian of the middle ages. On the con- trary, we frequently find those faults which we are accustomed to consider as certain indications of a mind altogether depraved, in company with great and good qualities, with generosity, with benevolence, with disinterestedness. From such a state of society, Palamedes, in the admirable dialogue of Hume, might have drawn illustrations of his theory as striking as any of those with which Fourli furnished him. These are not, we well know, the lessons which historians are generally most careful to teach, or readers most willing to learn. But they are not, therefore, useless. How Philip disposed his troops at Chsero- nea, where Hannibal crossed the Alps, whether Mary blew up Darnley, or Siguier shot Charles the Twelfth, and ten thousand other questions of the same description, are in themselves un- important. The inquiry may amuse us, but the decision leaves us no wiser. He alone reads history aright-who, observing how powerfully circumstances influence the feelings and opinions of men, how often vices pass into virtues, and paradoxes into axioms, learns to distinguish what is accidental and transi- tory in human nature, from what is essential and immutable." We must refer also to the universal practice of ancient rheto- rical writers, who all inculcated this sophistical art. Even Aristotle, who certainly loved truth as much as any man, in his ' Organon,' after examining the means of investigating truth, adds what he calls the Topics, in which he teaches the art of discussion without any reference whatever to truth : indeed, he teaches what the Sophists taught ; but no one accuses him of being a Sophist. THE SOPHISTS. l2 i The Sophists taught the art of disputation. The litigious quibbling nature of the Greeks was the soil on which an art like that was made to flourish. The excess of the Greek love of lawsuits is familiar to all who are versed in Grecian history. The almost farcical representation of a lawsuit given by iEschylus, in his otherwise awful drama, 'The Eumenides,' shows with what keen and lively interest the audience witnessed even the very details of litigation. For such an appetite food would not long be wanting. Corax and Tisias wrote precepts of the art of disputation. Protagoras followed with disserta- tions on the most remarkable points of law ; and Gorgias composed a set accusation and apology for every case that could present itself. People, in short, were taught to be their own advocates. Let us look at home. Does not every Barrister exert his energy, eloquence, subtlety, and knowledge " to make the worse appear the better reason " ? Do we reprobate Serjeant Talfourd or Sir Frederick Thesiger, if they succeed in gaining their client's cause, although that cause be a bad one ? On the contrary, it is the badness of the cause that makes the triumph great. Now let us suppose Serjeant Talfourd to give lessons in forensic oratory ; suppose him to announce to the world, that for a certain sum he would instruct any man in the whole art of exposition and debate, of the interrogation of witnesses, of the tricks and turning points of the law, so that the learner might become his own advocate : this would be contrary to legal etiquette : but would it be immoral ? Grave men might, perhaps, object that Mr. Talfourd was offering to make men cheats and scamps, by enabling them to make the worse appear the better reason. But this is a consequence foreseen by grave men, not acknowledged by the Teacher. It is doubtless true that owing to oratory, ingenuity, and subtlety, a scamp's cause is sometimes gained ; but it is also true that many an honest man's cause is gained and many a scamp frustrated by the same means. If forensic oratory does sometimes make the worse appear the better reason, it also makes the good appear in all its strength. The former is a necessary evil, the latter is the very object of a court of Justice. "If," says Callicles, in defence of Gorgias, to Socrates, " anyone should charge you with some crime which you had not committed, and carry you off to prison, you would gape, and stare and would not know 122 THE SOPHISTS. what to say; and, when brought to trial, however contemptible and weak your accuser might be, if he chose to indict you capitally, you would perish. Can this be wisdom, which, if it takes hold of a gifted man, destroys the excellence of his nature, rendering him incapable of preserving himself and others from the greatest dangers, enabling his enemies to plunder him of all his property, and reducing him to the situa- tion of those who, by a sentence of the court, have been deprived of all their rights ? " If it be admitted that Serjeant Talfourd's instruction in forensic oratory would not be immoral, however unusual, we have only to extend the sphere to include politics, to represent to ourselves the democratic state of Athens, where demagogues were ever on the alert, and we shall be fully persuaded that the art of the Sophists was not considered immoral ; and, as further proof, we select the passage in Plato's ' Republic,' as coming from an unexceptionable source. Socrates, speaking of the mercenary teachers whom the people call Sophists, says : — " These Sophists teach them only the things which the people themselves profess in assemblies : yet this they call wisdom. It is as if a man had observed the instincts and appetites of a great and powerful beast, in what manner to approach it, how or why it is ferocious or calm, what cries it makes, what tones appease and what tones irritate it ; after having learnt all this, and calling it wisdom, commenced teaching it without having any knowledge of what is good, just, shameful, and unjust among these instincts and appetites; but calling that good which flatters the animal, and that bad which irritates it ; because he knows not the difference between what is good in itself and that which is only relatively good." * There is the usual vein of caricature in this description (which is paraphrased in the * Quarterly Review,' f and there given as if the undoubted and un exaggerated doctrines of the Sophists; but it very distinctly sets forth the fact that the Sophists did not preach anything contrary to public morals, however contrary to abstract morality. Indeed the very fact of their popularity would prove that they did but respond to a public want ; and because they responded to this want they received large sums of money. Some people believe that the distinguishing peculiarity of the Sophists was their demanding •■ Plato, 'Rep.,' vi. p. 291. f No. xlii. p. 289. THE SOPHISTS. ,23 money for their instructions ; and Plato constantly harps upon their being mercenaries ; but he was wealthy, and could afford such sarcasms. The Greeks paid their Musicians, Painters, Sculptors, Physicians, Poets, and Teachers in Schools; why therefore should they not pay their philosophers? Zeno of Elea was paid ; so was Democritus ; but both of these have been sometimes included amongst the Sophists. We see nothing, whatever derogatory in Philosophers accepting money, any more than in Poets ; and we know how the latter stipulated for handsome payment We believe ourselves entitled to conclude that where the Sophists taught the art of disputation, they taught nothing that was considered immoral by the Greeks. No doubt the serious disliked this tampering with truth ; no doubt the old men saw with uneasiness the Athenian youth exercising a dangerous weapon, and foresaw demagogues in all the Sophists' pupils ; but that they did not regard the Sophists as " corrupters of youth," and enemies of the State, is evident from this striking fact, — the Sophists not only escaped persecution, but were rewarded with wealth and honours ; whereas Socrates was tried, condemned, and executed on the charge of having corrupted the Athenian youth. We cannot accept Plato's account of his opponents. It is perfectly true that the later Sophists became a frivolous and shameless race; but the early masters were not so. Plato himself makes the distinction, and speaks of some of the elder teachers with more respect But he always misrepresents them. We admit that, at the time Plato wrote, there were still many and powerful Sophists living. It may therefore be argued that he could not have ventured to misrepresent their doctrines when there were living witnesses against him. This is an argument often used in other cases. It is extremely trivial. In the first place do we not daily see instances of gross misrepresentation of opinions, the authors of which are still alive ? Is not misrepresentation a thing which cannot be guarded against, being sometimes the effect of party spirit, sometimes that of legitimate dulness ? In the second place we have no proof that the disciples of the Sophists did not contradict Plato. It is assumed that they did not, because no works have been transmitted to us in which these contradic- tions are mentioned. But it might have been done viva voce. i«4 THE SOPHISTS. Plato's account of the Sophistical doctrines is on the face of it a caricature, since it is impossible that any man should have seriously entertained them. It is not what Protagoras and Gorgias thought ; it is the reductio ad absurdum of what they thought. Plato seizes hold of one or two of their funda- mental doctrines, and, i?iterpreting them in his own way, makes them lead to the most outrageous absurdity and immorality. It is as if Berkeley's doctrine had been transmitted us by Beattie. Berkeley, it is well known, denied the existence of the external world, resolving it into a simple world of ideas. Beattie taunted him with not having followed out his prin- ciples, and with not having walked over a precipice. This was a gross misrepresentation; an ignoratio elenchi: Beattie mis- understood the argument, and drew conclusions from his mis- understanding. Now, suppose him to have written a dialogue on the plan of those of Plato : suppose him making Berkeley expound his argument in such a way as he Beattie interpreted it, and with a flavour of exaggeration for the sake of effect ; and of absurdity for the sake of easy refutation : how would he have made Berkeley speak ? Somewhat thus : — " Yes ;*I main- tain that there is no such external existence as that which men vulgarly believe in. There is no world of matter, but only a world of ideas. If I were to walk over a precipice I should receive no injury : it is only an ideal precipice." This is Beattie's interpretation ; how true it is most men know : it is, however, quite as true as Plato's interpretation of the Sophists. From Berkeley's works we can convict Beattie. Plato we can convict from experience of human nature ; that experience tells us that no man, far less any set of men, could seriously, publicly, and constantly broach doctrines acknow- ledged to be subversive of all morality, without incurring the heaviest penalties. To broach immoral doctrines with the faintest prospect of success, a man must do so in the name of rigid Morality. To teach immorality, and openly to avow that it is immoral, was, according to Plato, the office of the Sophists ;* a statement which carries with it its own contradiction. It is absolutely necessary that the opinions attributed to the Sophists should undergo a thorough revision. There are so few data to be trusted that the task must be extremely delicate. * In the ' Protagoras ' this passage is often referred to as a proof of the shamelessness of the Sophists ; and sometimes of the ill-favour with which THE SOPHISTS. ti$ We will make a venture in a line where successors may be more fortunate. Our history, inasmuch as it concerns itself with tendencies rather than with individual opinions, will not greatly suffer from the deficiency of information respecting the exact opinion of the Sophists. Protagoras, the first who is said to have avowed himself a Sophist, was born at Abdera, where Democritus first noticed him as a porter, who showed great address in inventing the knot.* The consequence of this was, that Democritus gave him instructions in Philosophy. The story is apocryphal, but indicates a connection to have existed between the specula- tions of the two thinkers. Let us suppose Protagoras then to have accepted the doctrine of Democritus, with him to have rejected the unity of the Eleatics and to have maintained the existence of the Many. With this doctrine he also learned that thought is sensation, and all knowledge therefore jpheno- menal. There were two theories in the system which he could not accept, viz. the Atomic and Reflective. These two imply each other, in the Democritean system. Reflection is neces- sary for the idea of Atoms ; and it is from the idea of Atoms, not perceived by the sense that the existence of Reflection is proved. Protagoras rejected the Atoms, and could therefore reject Reflection. He said, that Thought was Sensation, and all knowledge consequently only individual. Did not the place of his birth no less than the traditional story lead one to suppose some connection with Democritus, we might feel authorized to adopt certain expressions of Plato, and consider Protagoras to have derived his doctrine from Heraclitus. He certainly resembles the last-named in the main results to which his speculations led him. Be that as it may, the fact is unquestionable, that he maintained the doctrine of Thought being Sensation. Now, what does this doctrine imply ? It implies that every thing is true relatively — every sensation is a true sensation ; and, as there is nothing but sensation, knowledge is inevitably fleeting and imperfect. In a melancholy mind such a doctrine would deepen sadness, they were regarded. It is to us only a proof of Plato's tendency to caricature. * What the real signification of r»X»| is we are unable to say. A porter's knot, such as is now used, is the common interpretation. Perhaps Prota- goras had contrived a sort of board such as the glaziers use, and which is still used by the porters in Italy. 126 THE SOPHISTS, till it produced despair. In Heraclitus it had this effect. In minds of greater elasticity — in men of greater confidence, such a doctrine would lead to an energetic scepticism or individual- ism. In Protagoras it became the arrogant formula of " Man is the measure of all things." Sextus Empiricus gives the psychological doctrine of Prota- goras very explicitly ; and his account may be received without suspicion. We translate a portion of it : — " Matter," said Protagoras, " is in a perpetual flux \ * whilst it undergoes augmentations and losses, the senses also are modified, according to the age and disposition of the body. He said, also, that the reason of all phenomena {appearances) resided in matter as substrata (tovs Xoyovs irdvrv (paivo- ficvwv viroK€tff$ai h ttj v\rj) \ so that matter, in itself, might be whatever it appeared to each. But men have different per- ceptions at different times, according to the changes in the things perceived. Whoever is in a healthy state perceives things such as they appear to all others in a healthy state : and vice versa. A similar course holds with respect to different ages, as well as in sleeping and waking. Man is therefore the criterion of that which exists; all that is perceived by him exists, that which is perceived by no man does not exist."t Now, conceive a man conducted by what he thought irresis- tible arguments to such a doctrine as the above, and then see how naturally all the scepticism of the Sophists flows from it. The difference between the Sophists and the Sceptics was this : they were both convinced of the insufficiency of all know- ledge, but the Sceptics contented themselves with the conviction, while the Sophists gave up philosophy and turned their atten- tion elsewhere. Satisfied with the vanity of all endeavour to penetrate the mysteries of the universe, they began to consider their relations to other men : they devoted themselves to politics and rhetoric.J If there was no possibility of Truth there only remained the possibility of Persuasion. If one opinion was as true as another, — that is, if neither were true — it was nevertheless desirable, for the sake of society, that * rr\v v\r\v pevar^v tlvai, an expression which, if not borrowed by Sextus from Plato, would confirm the conjecture above respecting Hera- clitus, as the origin ot Protagoras' system. t 'Hypoty. Pyrrhon,' p. 44. X See Plato's definition of the sophistical art, ' Sophista,' p. 146. THE SOPHISTS. 127 certain opinions shoud prevail ; and, if Logic was powerless, Rhetoric was efficient. Hence Protagoras is made to say, by Plato, that the wise man is the physician of the soul. He cannot indeed induce truer thoughts into the mind, since all thoughts are equally true ; but he can induce healthier and more profitable thoughts. He can in the same way heal Society, since by the power of oratory he can introduce good useful sentiments in the place of those base and hurtful.* This doctrine may be false ; but is it not a natural conse- quence of the philosophy of the epoch ? It may be immoral ; but is it necessarily the bold and shameless immorality attri- buted to the Sophists ? To us it appears to be neither more nor less than the result of a sense of the radical insufficiency of knowledge. Protagoras had spent his youth in the study of philosophy ; he had found that study vain and idle ; he had utterly rejected it, and had turned his attention elsewhere. A man of practical tendencies, he wanted a practical result. Failing in this, he sought another path. An admirable writer in ' Blackwood's Magazine ' said a few years ago that although metaphysics was an excellent study for young men, yet it was fatal to them if they had not settled their doubts before the age of thirty. Here also was a man firmly impressed with the necessity of having something more definite wherewith to enter the world of action. Plato would have called him a Sophist. Plato could see no nobler end in life than that of contemplat- ing the Being — than that of familiarising the mind with the eternal Good, the Just, and the Beautiful — of which all good- ness, justice and beautiful things were the images. With such a view of life it was natural that he should despise the scepticism of the Sophists. This scepticism is clearly set forth in the following translation of a passage from the speech of Callicles, in Plato's ■ Gorgias ' : — " Philosophy is a graceful thing when it is moderately cul- tivated in youth; but, if any one occupies himself with it beyond the proper age, it ruins him ; for, however great may be his natural capacity, if he philosophizes too long he must of necessity be inexperienced in all those things which one who would be great and eminent must be experienced in. He must be unacquainted with the laws of his country, and with the mode of influencing other men in the intercourse of lift, • * Theaetetes,' p. 228. 1*8 THE SOPHISTS. whether private or public, and with the pleasures and passions of men ; in short, with human characters and manners. And when such men are called upon to act, whether on a private or public occasion, they expose themselves to ridicule, just as politicians do when they come to your conversation, and attempt to cope with you in argument; for every man, as Euripides says, occupies himself with that in which he finds himself superior ; that in which he is inferior he avoids, and speaks ill of it, but praises what he excels in, thinking that in doing so he is praising himself. The best thing in my opinion is to partake of both. It is good to partake of philosophy by way of education, and it is not ungraceful in a young man to philosophize. But, if he continues to do so when he grows older he becomes ridiculous, and I feel towards him as I should towards a grown person who lisped and played at childish plays. When I see an old man still continuing to philosophize, I think he deserves to be flogged. However great his natural talents, he is under the necessity of avoiding the assembly and public places, where, as the poet says, men become eminent, and to hide himself, and to pass his life whispering to two or three striplings in a corner, but never speaking out anything great, and bold and liberal." The distinguishing characteristics of the Sophists were their protests against the possibility of science and their art of dis- putation. As orators, and as travellers they learned to prefer expression to truth : as orators, because it was their art ; as travellers, because in their visits to various cities they could not fail to remark the variety of laws and ordinances in the different States. This variety impressed them with a convic- tion that there were no such things as Right and Wrong by nature, but only by convention. This, therefore, became a fundamental precept with them. It was but a corollary of their dogma respecting Truth. For man there was no Eternal Right because there was no Eternal Truth ; to hUaiov koI to alo-xpov ov (frvai aX\a vofno : law was but the law of each city. " That which appears just and honourable to each city, is so for that city, as long as the opinion is entertained," says Protagoras in the 'Theaetetes' (p. 229). This denial of abstract Truth, and abstract Justice, is easily pushed to absurd and immoral consequences; but we have no evidence that such consequences were maintained by the Sophists. Plato often judges them by such consequences ; but independently THE SOPHISTS, 1*9 of the want of any confidence in his representations as faithful, we can often detect in Plato himself evidences of the exaggera- tion of his general statements. Thus, he on various occasion? makes the Sophists maintain that Might is Right. Moderns, who always accept him as positive testimony, have therefore unanimously repeated this statement. Yet it is obvious that they could not have held this opinion except in a very quali- fied form. And in the first Book of the Republic, Thrasy- machus the Sophist is made to explain his meaning ; viz., that Justice is the law ordained by the party which is strongest in the State. Thus, in a democracy the enactments of the people are the laws : these laws are for their advantage ; therefore just. Now, in this admission, by Plato, of a qualification of the abstract formula, " Might is Right," we see evidence of that formula never having been promulgated by the Sophists ; it was only an interpretation by Plato. What they meant was this : All law is but convention : the convention of each State is therefore just for it ; and, inasmuch as any such convention must necessarily be ordained by the strongest party, i.e. must be the will of the many ; so we may say that justice is but the advantage of the strongest It would occupy too much space to pursue our explanation of the Sophistical tenets. The foregoing will, we trust, suffice to show that the tenets attributed to them by Plato are caricatures, and admit of very different explanation. Well might Gorgias exclaim, on reading the Dialogue which bears his name, " I did not recognise myself. The young man, however, has great talent for satire." In summing up we may observe that the Sophists were the natural production of the opinions of the epoch. In them we see the first energetic protest against the possibility of metaphy- sical science. This protest, however, must not be confounded with the protest of Bacon — must not be mistaken for the germ of positive philosophy. It was the protest of baffled minds. The science of the day led to scepticism ; but with scepticism no energetic man could remain contented. Philosophy was therefore denounced, not because a surer, safer path of inquiry had been discovered, but because Philosophy was found to lead nowhither. The scepticism of the Sophists was a shallow scepticism, in which no great speculative intellect could be drowned. Accordingly with Socrates Philosophy again re- asserted her empire. I jfomti (Bpot% I NEW ERA OPENED BY THE INVENTION OP A NEW METHOD, CHAPTER I. THE LIFE OF SOCRATES. Whilst the brilliant but dangerous Sophists were reaping money and renown by protesting against Philosophy, and teaching the word -jugglery which they call Disputation, and the impassioned insincerity which they call Oratory, there suddenly appeared amongst them a strange antagonist. He was a perfect contrast to them morally and physically. They had slighted Truth ; they had denied her. He had made her his soul's mistress ; and, with patient labour, with untiring energy, did his large, wise soul toil after perfect communion with her. They had slighted Truth for Money and Renown. He had remained constant to her in poverty. They professed to know everything. He only knew that he knew nothing. They professed to teach everything, and demanded enormous sums in recompense. He denied that anything could be taught. Yet he believed he could be of service to his fellow- men, not by teaching, but by helping them to learn. His mission was to examine the thoughts of others. This he humorously explained by reference to his mother's profession, viz., that of a midwife. What she did for women in labour he could do for men pregnant with ideas. He was an accoucheur of ideas. He assisted them in their birth, and having brought them into light, he examined them to see if they were fit to live ; if true, they were welcomed \ if false, destroyed. And for this assistance he demanded no pecuniary recompense ; Ud steadfastly refused every bribe of the kind. THE LIFE OF SOCRATES. i%\ The Sophists were somewhat puzzled with their new anta- gonist. Who is he ? Socrates, the son of Sophroniscus. What does he ? Converse. For what purpose ? To expose error. The gorgeous Sophists, in their flowing robes, followed by crowds of eager listeners, treated the poor and humbly-clad Socrates with ineffable contempt. He was rude and ungainly in his movements ; unlike all respectable citizens in his habits. Barefoot, he wandered about the streets of Athens absorbed in thought, and sometimes standing still for hours, fixed in medi- tation ; or he strolled into the market-place and disputed with every one. In appearance he resembled a Silenus. His flat- tened nose, with wide and upturned nostrils, his projecting eyeballs, his thick and sensual lips, his squab figure and un- wieldy belly, were all points upon which ridicule might fasten. Yet when this Silenus spoke there was a witchery in his tongue which fascinated those whom his appearance had disgusted. And Alcibiades declared that he was forced to stop his ears and flee away, that he might not sit down beside Socrates and "grow old in listening to his talk." Let us hear Alcibiades describe him : — " I will begin the praise of Socrates by comparing him to a cer- tain statue. Perhaps he will think that this statue is introduced for the sake of ridicule ; but I assure you that it is necessary for the illustration of truth. I assert, then, that Socrates is exactly like those Silenuses that sit in the sculptors' shops, and which are carved holding flutes or pipes, but which, when divided in two, are found to contain withinside the images of the gods. I assert that Socrates is like the satyr Marsyas; that your form and appearance are like these satyrs, I think that even you will not venture to deny ; and how like you are to them in all other things, now hear. Are you not scornful and petulant ? If you deny this, I will bring witnesses. Are you not a piper, and far more wonderful a one than he ? For Marsyas, and whoever now pipes the music that he taught, for that music which is of heaven, and described as being taught by Marsyas, enchants men through the power of the mouth ; for if any musician, be he skilful or not, awakens this music, it alone enables him to retain the minds of men, and from the divinity of its nature makes evident those who are in want of the gods and initiation. You differ only from Marsyas in this circumstance, that you effect without instruments, by mere words, all that he can do ; for when we hear Pericles, or any 132 THE LIFE OF SOCRATES. other accomplished orator, deliver a discourse, no one, as it were, cares anything about it. But when any one hears you, or even your words related by another, though ever so rude and unskilful a speaker, be that person a woman, man, or child, we are struck and retained, as it were, by the discourse clinging to our mind. " If I was not afraid that I am a great deal too drunk, 1 would confirm to you by an oath the strange effects which I assure you I have suffered from his words, and suffer still ; for when I hear him speak, my heart leaps up far more than the hearts of those who celebrate the Corybantic mysteries ; my tears are poured out as he talks, a thing I have seen happen to many others beside myself. I have heard Pericles and other excellent orators, and have been pleased with their discourses, but I suffered nothing of this kind ; nor was my soul ever on those occasions disturbed and filled with self-reproach, as if it were slavishly laid prostrate. But this Marsyas here has often affected me in the way I describe, until the life which I lead seemed hardly worth living. Do not deny it, Socrates; for I well know that if even now I chose to listen to you, I could not resist, but should again suffer the same effects, for, my friends, he forces me to confess, that while I myself am still in want of many things, I neglect my own necessities, and attend to those of the Athenians. I stop my ears, therefore, as from the Syrens, and flee away as fast as possible, that I may not sit down beside him and grow old in listening to his talk ; for this man has reduced me to feel the sentiment of shame, which I imagine no one would readily believe was in me; he alone inspires me with remorse and awe ; for I feel in his presence my incapacity of refuting what he says, or of refusing to do that which he directs ; but when I depart from him, the glory which the multitude confers overwhelms me. I escape, there- fore, and hide myself from him, and when I see him I am overwhelmed with humiliation, because I have neglected to do what I have confessed to him ought to be done ; and often and often have I wished that he were no longer to be seen among men. But if that were to happen, I well know that I should suffer far greater pain ; so that where I can turn, or what I can do with this man, I know not. All this have I and many others suffered from the pipings of this satyr. " And observe how like he is to what I said, and what a wonderful power he possesses. I know that there is not one THE LIFE OF SOCRATES. 133 of you who is aware of the real nature of Socrates ; but since I have begun, I will make him plain to you. You observe how passionately Socrates affects the intimacy of those who are beautiful, and how ignorant he professes himself to be; appearances in themselves excessively Silenic This, my friends, is the external form with which, like one of the sculp- tured Sileni, he has clothed himself; for if you open him, you will find within admirable temperance and wisdom ; for he cares not for mere beauty, but despises more than any one can imagine all external possessions, whether it be beauty or wealth or glory, or any other thing for which the multitude felicitates the possessor. He esteems these things, and us who honour them, as nothing, and lives among men, making all the objects of their admiration the playthings of his irony. But I know not if any one of you have ever seen the divine images which are within, when he has been opened and is serious. I have seen them, and they are so supremely beautiful, so golden, so divine, and wonderful, that everything that Socrates commands surely ought to be obeyed, even like the voice of a God. " Many other and most wonderful qualities might well be praised in Socrates, but such as these might singly be attri- buted to others. But that which is unparalleled in Socrates, is that he is unlike, and above comparison, with all other men, whether those who have lived in ancient times, or those who exist now ; for it may be conjectured, that Brasidas and many others are such as was Achilles. Pericles deserves comparison with Nestor and Antenor ; and other excellent persons of various times may, with probability, be drawn into comparison with each other. But to such a singular man as this, both himself and his discourses are so uncommon, no one, should he seek, would find a parallel among the present or the past generations of mankind; unless they should say that he re- sembled those with whom I lately compared him ; for assuredly he and his discourses are like nothing but the Silen and the satyrs. At first I forgot to make you observe how like his discourses are to those satyrs when they are opened ; for if any one will listen to the talk of Socrates, it will appear to him at first extremely ridiculous ; the phrases and expressions which he employs fold around his exterior the skin, as it were, of a rude and wanton Satyr. He is always talking about great market-asses, and brass-founders, and leather-cutters, and skin- dressers ; and this is his perpetual custom, so that any dull 134 THE LIFE 0F SOCRATES. and unobservant person might easily laugh at his discourse. But if any one should see it opened, as it were, and get within the sense of his words, he would then find that they alone of all that enters into the mind of man to utter, had a profound and persuasive meaning, and that they were most divine ; and that they presented to the mind innumerable images of every excellence, and that they tended towards objects of the highest moment, or rather towards all, that he who seeks the posses- sion of what is supremely beautiful, and good, need regard as essential to the accomplishment of his ambition. "These are the things, my friend, for which I praise Socrates." This Silenus was to become the most formidable antagonist that the Sophists had encountered ; but this is small praise for him who was hereafter to become one of the most reverenced names in the world's Pantheon — who was to give a new im- pulse to the human mind, and leave as an inheritance to man- kind, the grand example of an heroic life crowned with a martyrdom to Truth. Everything about Socrates is remarkable ; personal appear- ance, moral physiognomy, position, object, method, life, and death. Fortunately his character and his tendencies have been so clearly pictured in the works of Plato and Xenophon, that although the portrait may be flattered we are sure of its resemblance. He was the son of Sophroniscus. a sculptor,* and Phaenarete, a midwife. His parents, though poor, managed, it is said, to give him the ordinary education. Besides which he learnt his father's art. Whether he made any progress in it we are unable to say; probably not, as he relinquished it early. There was a report, alluded to by Timon, that the Graces which Socrates had executed found a place on the walls of the Acropolis, close behind the Minerva of Phidias. If this were authentic, it would imply great proficiency in the art. The more creditable account, however, is that in Diogenes Laertius, on the authority of Demetrius. Crito, a wealthy Athenian, charmed with the manners of Socrates, is said to have withdrawn him from the shop, and to have educated him • Dr. Wiggers says, that Timon the Sillograph calls Socrates, with a «rteer, Xt0o£6oc, "a stone-scraper." He forgets that Xi0o$ooc was one of the names for a sculptor, as Lucian informs us in the account of his early life. THE LIFE OF SOCRATES. 135 (*va€u>s). But this is not all the passage : it continues thus : " In these speculations he sought the Abstract (to KaOoXov), and was the first who thought of giving defini- tions." Now in this latter portion we believe there is con- tained a hint of something more than the mere moralist — a hint of the metaphysician. On turning to another part of Aristotle's treatise (Met. xiii. c. iv.), we accordingly find this hint more clearly brought out ; we find an express indication of the metaphysician. The passage is as follows : " Socrates concerned himself with ethical virtues and he first sought the abstract definitions of these. Before him Democritus had only concerned himself with a part of Physics ; and defined but the Hot and the Cold. But Socrates, looking deeper (cvAoyws), sought the Essence of Things, i.e. sought what exists ! y Moreover, in another passage (lib. hi. ch. ii.) he reproaches Aristippus for having rejected science, and concerned himself solely with morals. This is surely negative evidence that Socrates was not to be blamed for the same opinion ; otherwise he would have been also mentioned. Had Socrates been only a moralist, it would be difficult to conceive Plato as his pupil. Socrates made Ethics the end and aim of his philosophy; and this has given rise to the 156 PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. notion of his being a mere moralist. But his rank in the history of Philosophy is due to him for his conception of science. Let it be remembered that the work of the Sophists had been to destroy all belief in science. They denied the validity of human testimony. They pronounced science to be impossible. It was imperative therefore on Socrates to remove this scepticism before he could proceed. He removed it by presenting a conception of science which was not open to the attacks of the Sophists. Instead of occupying himself with any particular sciences, he directed his attention to science in general — to Method. " Man is the measure of all things," said Protagoras ; " and, as men differ, there can be no absolute truth." " Man is the measure of all things," replied Socrates ; " but descend deeper into his personality, and you will find that underneath all varieties there is a ground of steady truth. Men differ, but men also agree : they differ as to what is fleet- ing ; they agree as to what is eternal. Difference is the region of opinion ; Agreement is the region of Truth : let us endeavour to penetrate that region." The radical error of all the pre-Socratic philosophy was the want of definite aim. Men speculated at random. They sought truth, but they only built Hypotheses, because they had r*ot previously ascertained the limits and conditions of inquiry. They attempted to form sciences before having settled the conditions of Science. It was the peculiar merit of Socrates to have proposed as the grand question of philosophy the na- ture and conditions of Science. His solution of that ques- tion was incomplete ; but it was influential. The reader may now begin to appreciate the importance of Definitions in the Socratic Method and may understand why Socrates did not himself invent systems, but only a Method. He likened himself to his mother, who, though unable to bring forth children herself, assisted women in their labours. He believed that in each man lay the germs of wisdom. He believed that no science could be taught ; only drawn out. To borrow the ideas of another was not to learn ; to guide oneself by the judgment of another was blindness. The Sophists, who pretended to teach everything, could teach nothing; and their ignorance was manifest in the very pretension. Each man must conquer truth for himself, by rigid struggle with himself. He, Socrates, was willing to assist any man when in the pains of labour • he could do no more. PHILOSOPHY OP SOCRATES. 157 Such being the Method, we cannot wonder at his having attached himself to Ethical, rather than to Physical specula, tions. His philosophy was a realisation of the inscription at Delphos — Know Thyself. It was in himself that he found the ground of certitude which was to protect him against scepti- cism. It was therefore moral science which he prized above all others. Indeed we have great reason to believe that his energetic denouncement of Physical speculations, as reported by Xenophon, were the natural, though exaggerated, conclu- sions to which he had been hurried by a consideration of the manifold absurdities into which they drew the mind, and the scepticism which they induced. There could be nothing but uncertainty on such subjects. Certitude was only to be gained in moral speculations. This is the meaning of the common saying, that Socrates brought Philosophy down from the clouds to domicile it upon earth, or, as Cicero expresses it, " devocavit e ccelo et in urbibus collocavit et in domos etiam introduxit et coegit de vita et moribusque bonis et malis quaerere." He turned the attention from speculations on cosmology to speculations on morals. This is in flagrant contradiction to the representa- tion of Socrates in * The Clouds.' There he is busy with physical speculations. A contradiction so glaring has led many to suppose that Aristophanes knew nothing whatever of Socrates, but only took him as an available comic type of the Sophists. To this there are several objections. Firstly, it is not usual in Satirists to select for their butt a person of whom they know nothing. Secondly, Socrates, of all Athe- nians, was the most notorious, and most easily to be acquainted with in a general way. Thirdly, he could not be a type of the Sophists, in as far as related to physical speculations, since we well know those persons scouted physics. Fourthly, he did occupy himself with Physics, early in his career ; and probably did so when Aristophanes satirised him. In after life he re- garded such speculations as trivial. " I have not leisure for such things," he is made to say by Plato ; " and I will tell you the reason : I am not yet able, according to the Delphic in- scription, to Know Myself ; and it appears to me very ridicu- lous, while ignorant of myself, to inquire into what I am not concerned in."» • «Phaedrus,' p. 8. 158 PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. Connected with the Socratic view of Science it is curious to remark how he, who is accused of being only a moralist, always considers Virtue to be identical with Knowledge.* Only the wise man, said he, can be brave, just or temperate. Vice of every kind is Ignorance; and involuntary, because ignorant. If a man is cowardly, it is because he does not rightly appre- ciate the importance of life and death. He thinks death an evil, and flees it. If he were wise, he would know that death is a good thing, or, at the worst, an indifferent one, and there- fore would not shun it. If a man is intemperate it is because he is unable to estimate the relative value of present pleasure and future pain. Ignorance misleads him. It is the nature of man to seek good and shun evil : he would never seek evil, knowing it to be such ; if he seeks it, he mistakes it for good ; if he is intemperate, it is because he is unwise. It would be superfluous to refute these positions. We may remark, however, that they are grounded on the assumption that man is solely guided by his intellect. The passions are completely overlooked ; yet it is their operation in the above cases which interferes with the directing power of the intellect. We must, in conclusion, say a word or two on that vexata quastio, the Daemon of Socrates. He taught, and what he taught he believed, that on all critical occasions, especially whenever any danger awaited him or his friends, he was fore- warned by a Daemon who always accompanied him. Respect- ing the nature of this Daemon critics are, and probably will remain, at issue. Some agree with Olympiodorus, that it only meant Conscience. But although the voice of Conscience will often seem to tally with the attributes of the Socratic Daemon, it will still oftener fail. The Daemon not only warned Socrates concerning his own affairs, but also concerning the affairs of his friends ; as we see in the * Theages ' of Plato. By others the Daemon has been held to be purely allegorical; 5y others to be a mystical expression for the operations of his soul. The most probable explanation we take to be this : Socrates was a religious man, and implicitly believed in supernatural communications. This explanation has been too simple for Jhe critics, who have insisted on one more recondite. Yet the * QpovqatiQ Sitro tlvai icaoaq rdc aptrdg. — Aristot. Ethic. Nicomach. t vi. 13. Piato, in the ' Meno,' makes him maintain that Virtue cannot be Science, cannot be taught. But this is not Socratic PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. 159 above is in perfect accordance with what Plato uniformly says of Daemons. Apuleius tells us that Plato declared there was " a peculiar Daemon allotted to every man, who is a witness and guardian of his conduct in life, who, without being visible to any one, is always present, and who is an arbitrator not only of his deeds, but also of his thoughts." This Daemon presides over the man inquisitively, participates of all that concerns him, sees all things, understands all things, and dwells in the most profound recesses of the mind.* Xenophon is equally explicit. "The Daemon," he says, "gave signs" to Socrates, who believed "that the Gods know all things, both those spoken and those done, as also those meditated in silence ; for they are present everywhere, and give signs (crqixavew) to men concerning human affairs." — Memor., i. c, i. Although Socrates was not the first to teach the doctrine of the immortality of the soul, he was the first to give it a philo- sophical basis. Nor can we read, without admiration, the arguments by which he was wont to prove the existence of a beneficent Providence. Listen to Xenophon : — " I will now relate the manner in which I once heard Socrates discoursing with Aristodemus, surnamed the Little, concerning the Deity ; for observing that he neither prayed nor sacrificed to the gods, but on the contrary, ridiculed and laughed at those who did, he said to him : — " Tell me, Aristodemus, is there any man whom you admire on account of his merit? Aristodemus having answered ' Many ' — Name some of them, I pray you. I admire, said Aristodemus, Homer for his Epic poetry, Milanippides for his dithyrambics, Sophocles for tragedy, Polycletes for statuary, and Xeuxis for painting. 14 But which seems to you most worthy of admiration, Aristo- demus — the artist who forms images void of motion and intel- ligence, or one who hath the skill to produce animals that are endued not only with activity but understanding? The latter, there can be no doubt, replied Aristodemus, provided the production was not the effect of chance, but of wisdom and contrivance. But since there are many things, some of which we can easily see the use of, while we cannot say of others to what purpose they were produced, which of these, Aristodemus, • See the whole passage, together with much other matter, in Professor Long's truly admirable translation of * Plutarch,' i. p. 258. Consult also Plato's 'Apologia,' « De Legibus,' x. p. 221, and 'Theages,' pp. 275-8. I6c PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. do you suppose the work of wisdom? It should seem the most reasonable to affirm it of those whose fitness and utility are so evidently apparent. 11 But it is evidently apparent that He who at the beginning made man, endued him with senses because they were good for him ; eyes wherewith to behold whatever was visible ; and ears to hear whatever was to be heard ; for say, Aristodemus, to what purpose should odours be prepared, if the sense of smelling had been denied ? Or why the distinctions of bitter and sweet, of savoury and unsavoury, unless a palate had been likewise given, conveniently placed to arbitrate between them and declare the difference ? Is not that Providence, Aristo- demus, in a most eminent manner conspicuous, which, because the eye of man is so delicate in its contexture, hath therefore prepared eyelids like doors, whereby to secure it, which ex- tend of themselves whenever it is needful, and again close when sleep approaches ? Are not these eyelids provided, as it were, with a fence on the edge of them, to keep off the wind and guard the eye? Even the eyebrow itself is not without its office, but, as a penthouse, is prepared to turn off the sweat which, falling from the forehead, might enter and annoy that no less tender than astonishing part of us. Is it not to be admired that the ears should take in sounds of every sort, and yet are not too much filled by them ? That the fore teeth of the animal should be formed in such a manner as is evidently best suited for the cutting of its food, as those on the side for grinding it to pieces ? That the mouth, through which this food is conveyed, should be placed so near the nose and eyes as to prevent the passing unnoticed whatever is unfit for nourishment; while nature, on the contrary, hath set at a distance, and concealed from the senses, all that might disgust or any way offend them ? And canst thou still doubt, Aristo- demus, whether a disposition of parts like this should be the work of chance or of wisdom and contrivance ? I have no longer any doubt, replied Aristodemus; and, indeed, the more I consider it, the more evident it appears to me, that man must be the masterpiece of some great artificer; carrying along with it infinite marks of the love and favour of Him who hath thus formed it. "And what thinkest thou, Aristodemus, of that desire in the individual which leads to the continuance of the species ? Of that tenderness and affection in the female towards her young, PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. 161 so necessary for its preservation ? Of that unremitted love of life, and dread of dissolution, which take such strong posses- sion of us from the moment we begin to be ? I think of them, answered Aristodemus, as so many regular operations of the same great and wise Artist, deliberately determining to pre- serve what he hath made. " But, farther (unless thou desirest to ask me questions), seeing, Aristodemus, thou thyself art conscious of reason and intelligence, supposest thou there is no intelligence elsewhere ? Thou knowest thy body to be a small part of that wide extended earth which thou everywhere beholdest; the moisture contained in it, thou also knowest to be a small portion of that mighty mass of waters, whereof seas themselves are but a part, while the rest of the elements contribute out of their abundance to thy formation. It is the soul then alone, that intellectual part of us, which is come to thee by some lucky chance, from I know not where. If so be, there is indeed no intelligence elsewhere ; and we must be forced to confess that this stupendous universe, with all the various bodies contained therein — equally amazing, whether we consider their magnitude or number, whatever their use, whatever their order — all have been produced, not by intelligence, but by chance. It is with difficulty that I can suppose otherwise, returned Aristodemus ; for I behold none of those gods whom you speak of as making and governing all things ; whereas I see the artists when at their work here among us. Neither yet seest thou thy soul, Aristo- demus, which, however, most assuredly governs thy body ; although it may well seem, by thy manner of talking, that it is chance, and not reason, which governs thee. " I do not despise the gods, said Aristodemus ; on the con- trary, I conceive so highly of their excellence, as to suppose they stand in no need either of me or of my services. Thou mistakest the matter, Aristodemus ; the greater magnificence they have shown in their care of thee, so much the more honour and service thou owest them. Be assured, said Aristodemus, if I once could be persuaded the gods take care of man, I should want no monitor to remind me of my duty. And canst thou doubt, Aristodemus, if the gods take care of man ? Hath not the glorious privilege of walking upright been alone bestowed on him, whereby he may, with the better advantage, survey what is around him, contemplate with more ease those splendid objects which are above, and avoid the numerous ills and 16a PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. inconveniences which would otherwise befall him? Othei animals, indeed, they have provided with feet, by which they may remove from one place to another ; but to man they have also given hands, with which he can form many things for his use, and make himself happier than creatures of any other kind. A tongue hath been bestowed on every other animal ; but what animal, except man, hath the power of forming words with it, whereby to explain his thoughts, and make them intelligible to others ? " But it is not with respect to the body alone that the gods have shown themselves thus bountiful to man. Their most excellent gift is that soul they have infused into him, which so far surpasses what is elsewhere to be found ; for, by what animal, except man, is even the existence of those gods dis- covered, who have produced and still uphold, in such regular order, this beautiful and stupendous frame of the universe ? What other species of creature is to be found that can serve, that can adore them ? What other animal is able, like man, to provide against the assaults of heat and cold, of thirst and hunger ? that can lay up remedies for the time of sickness, and improve the strength nature has given by a well-proportioned exercise ? that can receive like him information or instruction ; or so happily keep in memory what he hath seen, and heard, and learnt ? These things being so, who seeth not that man is, as it were, a god in the midst of this visible creation ? so far doth he surpass, whether in the endowments of soul or body, all animals whatsoever that have been produced therein ; for, if the body of the ox had been joined to the mind of man, the acuteness of the latter would have stood him in small stead, while unable to execute the well-designed plan j nor would the human form have been 6f more use to the brute, so long as it remained destitute of understanding ! But in thee, Aristo- demus, hath been joined to a wonderful soul a body no less wonderful ; and sayest thou, after this, the gods take no thought for me ? What wouldst thou then more to convince thee of their care ? " I would they should send and inform me, said Aristodemus, what. things I ought or ought not to do, in like manner as thou sayest they frequently do to thee. — And what then, Aristo- demus? supposest thou, that when the gods give out some oracle to all the Athenians they mean it not for thee ? If by {heir prodigies they declare aloud to all Greece — to all man- PHILOSOPHY OP SOCRATES. 163 kind — the things which shall befall them, are they dumb to thee alone? And art thou the only person whom they have placed beyond their care ? Believest thou they would have wrought into the mind of man a persuasion of their being able to make him happy or miserable, if so be they had no such power? or would not even man himself, long ere this, have seen through the gross delusion ? How is it, Aristodemus, thou rememberest or remarkest not, that the kingdoms and commonwealths most renowned as well for their wisdom as antiquity, are those whose piety and devotion hath been the most observable ? and that even man himself is never so well disposed to serve the Deity as in that part of life when reason bears the greatest sway, and his judgment is supposed in its full strength and maturity? Consider, my Aristodemus, that the soul which resides in thy body can govern it at pleasure ; why then may not the soul of the universe, which pervades and animates every part of it, govern it in like manner ? If thine eye hath the power to take in many objects, and these placed at no small distance from it, marvel not if the eye of the Deity can at one glance compre- hend the whole. And, as thou perceivest it not beyond thy ability to extend thy care, at the same time, to the concerns of Athens, Egypt, Sicily, why thinkest thou, my Aristodemus, that the Providence of God may not easily extend itself through the whole universe ? " As therefore, among men, we make best trial of the affection and gratitude of our neighbour by showing him kindness, and discover his wisdom by consulting him in his distress, do thou in like manner behave towards the gods ; and, if thou wouldst experience what their wisdom and what their love, render thy- self deserving the communication of some of those divine secrets which may not be penetrated by man, and are imparted to those alone who consult, who adore, who obey the Deity. Then shait thou, my Aristodemus, understand there is a Being whose eye pierceth throughout all nature, and whose ear is open to every sound ; extended to all places, extending through all time ; and whose bounty and care can know no other bound than those fixed by his own creation. "By this discourse, and others of the like nature, Socrates taught his friends that they were not only to forbear whatever was impious, unjust, or unbecoming before man ; but even, when alone, they ought to have a regard to all their actions, since the gods have their eyes continually upon us, and none 1*4 PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. of our designs can be concealed from them." — MemorabJia, book i. chap. iv. To this passage we must add another equally deserving of attention : — " Even among all those deities who so liberally bestow on us good things, not one of them maketh himself an object of our sight. And He who raised this whole universe, and still upholds the mighty frame, who perfected every part of it in beauty and in goodness, suffering none of these parts to decay through age, but renewing them daily with unfading vigour, whereby they are able to execute whatever he ordains with that readiness and precision which surpass man's imagination ; even he, the supreme God, who performeth all these wonders, still holds himself invisible, and it is only in his works that we are capable of admiring him. For consider, my Euthydemus, the sun which seemeth, as it were, set forth to the view of all men, yet suffereth not itself to be too curiously examined ; punishing those with blindness who too rashly venture so to do; and those ministers of the gods, whom they employ to execute their bidding, remain to us invisible ; for, though the thunderbolt is shot from on high, and breaketh in pieces what- ever it findeth in its way, yet no one seeth it when it falls, when it strikes, or when it retires ; neither are the winds discoverable to our sight, though we plainly behold the ravages they every- where make, and with ease perceive what time they are rising. And, if there be anything in man, my Euthydemus, partaking of the divine nature, it must surely be the soul which governs and directs him ; yet no one considers this as an object of his sight. Learn, therefore, not to despise those things which you cannot see ; judge of the greatness of the power by the effects which are produced, and reverence the Deity." — Memorabilia, book. iv. chap. iii. And this, together with the ideal character of his ethics, and the heroic character of his life, have been his great titles to fame. His Method, which constitutes his real philosophical importance, has long since been discarded. If, however, Science has discarded it, History gratefully remembers and immortalizes it. The discovery of to-day will be the common- place of to-morrow ; but it is not less a discovery. A Dwarf standing on the shoulders of a Giant sees farther than the Giant ; but, if he stood upon his own basis, he would scarcely see at all. It behoves him to remember that the Giant is a Giant. APPENDIX. Note A. TRANSLATION OF THE FIFTH CHAPTER OF ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. (The various disputes respecting the doctrines of the Pythagoreans we can scarcely hope to have settled ; but that the reader may have the benefit of the greatest authority, and the greatest intellect, on this subject, we translate here such portions of the fifth chapter of Aristotle as relate to Pythagoras.) "In the age of these philosophers (the Eleats and Atomists), and even before them, lived those called Pythagoreans, who at first applied them- selves to mathematics, a science they improved ; and, penetrated with it, they fancied that the principles of mathematics were the principles of all things. " Since Numbers are, by nature, prior to all things, in Numbers they thought they perceived greater analogies with that which exists and that which is produced (bfiOLWfiara 7roXXdt roic oiot icai yiyvo/itVotc) than in fire, earth, or water. So that a certain combination of Numbers was justice ; and a certain other combination of Numbers was the soul and intelligence ; and a certain other combination of Numbers was opportunity (Kaipog) ; and so of the rest. 11 Moreover, they saw in Numbers the combinations of harmony. Since, therefore, all things seemed formed similarly to Numbers, and Numbers being by nature anterior to things, they concluded that the elements (v TroXvKafticTtitv, Twt vooq avQpb>iroiv having reference only to the feet, whereas the simile in Parmenides is meant to apply to the whole man. The meaning of the verses is, therefore, that the intelligence of man is formed according to his many-jointed frame, i.e., dependent on his organi- zation. * Ch. Kenouvier, ' Manuel de la Philos. Ancienne,' i. p. 15a, who cite* ' Plutarch, Opia. das Philos.,' iv. 5. i68 APPENDIX, Note C. The original of this disputed passage is this : — 'AvaCayopac di 6 K\al£ofiiviOQ rij p.kv TjXtKHf irportpog atv rovrov, rote S'tpyoig Vortpog — which is rendered by MM. Pierron and Zevort : " Anaxagore de Clazomene, l'ain6 d'Empedocle, rietait pas arrive a un systeme aussi plausible" — La Metaphysique d' Aristotle, i. p. 233. This agrees with our version. We confess, however, that on a first glance M. Cousin's version better preserves the force of the antithesis ry fikv ijfXiicip irpdrtpog — roic 0' fpyoic varepog. But the reasons alleged in our text prevent a concurrence in his interpretation, and we must look closer. MM. Pierron and Zevort, in their note on the passage, remark : " Mais les mots tpyy, ipyoig, dans une opposition, ont ordinairement une signification vague, comme re, revera, chez lez Latins, et, chez nous, en fait, en realite"." The force of the objection does not strike us. If Anaxagoras was in fact, in reality, posterior to Empedocles, we can only understand this in the sense M. Cousin has understood Aristotle, and, moreover, MM. Pierron and Zevort here contradict their translation, which says that, in point of fact, the system of Anaxagoras was not so plausible as that of Empedocles. More weight must be laid on the meaning of vortpog, which certainly cannot be exclusively taken to mean posterior in point of time. In the eleventh chapter of Aristotle's fifth book, he treats of all the significations of 7rp6rtpoc and vortpog. One of these significations is superiority and : nferiority. In the sense of inferiority vortpog is often used by the poets. Thus Sophocles : — *Q fxiapbv tfQog, nai yvvaitcog vortpov. " O shameful character, below a woman ! " " Inferior " is the primitive meaning ; thus, also, we say, " second to none " for " inferior to none." This meaning of vortpog, namely, of inferiority, is the one always under- stood by the commentators on the passage in question ; none of them understood a chronological posteriority, irportpog indicates priority in point of time ; vortpog inferiority in point of merit. Thus Philopon : " prior quidem tempore, sed posterior et manens secundum opinionem," fol. 2a ; and the anonymous scholiast of the Vatican MS. : irporepoc yovv Ttp \povtp, &W vortpog Kal tWuirtav Kara T"qv SoZav : " first indeed in time, but second and inferior in point of doctrine. ' ' The only question -which now remains to be answered in order to estab- lish the proof of the foregoing interpretation of vortpog, is this : Did Aristotle regard the system ot Anaxagoras as inferior to that of Em- pedocles ? This question we can answer distinctly in the affirmative. The readei will remember our citation of the passage in which Aristotle blames Anaxa- goras for never employing his First Cause (Intelligence) except upon emergencies (see page 9 ). Aristotle continues thus : " Empedocles employs his causes more abundantly, though not indeed sufficiently." Kai 'EfiirtdoKXrjg iimrXtov \t\v rovrt^ xprjrat rolg alriotg, ov ya) ovrt 'ucavuig.—Met. i. 4. JFtftf) IBpoci). PARTIAL ADOPTION OF THE SO CR A TIC METHOD, CHAPTER I. THE MEGARIC SCHOOL : EUCLID. " Several philosophers," says Cicero, " drew from the conver- sations of Socrates very different results ; and, according as each adopted views which harmonized with his own, they in their turn became heads of philosophical schools all differing amongst each other." It is one of the peculiarities of a philosophical Method, to adapt itself indiscriminately to all sorts of systems. A scientific Method is confined to one : if various and opposing systems spring from it, they spring from an erroneous or imperfect application of it. On the Socratic Method various and opposing systems were elaborated, all of which were equally legitimate, though not equally plausible. On the Method of Descartes, the systems of Spinoza, Malebranche, Leibnitz, Locke, and Hume, were equally legitimate. But on the Method of Bacon only one tendency is legitimate ; only one result can be obtained — that, namely, of the reduction of many phenomena to one law. We must not be surprised therefore to find many contradic- tory systems claiming parentage with Socrates. But we must be on our guard against supposing, as is usually done, that this adaptation to various systems is a proof of the excellence of the Socratic Method. It is only a proof of its vagueness. It may be accepted as a sign of the great influence exercised upon succeeding philosophers ; it is no sign that the influence was in the right direction ; rather the contrary. As we said, Socrates had no school \ he taught no system l7o THE MBGARIC SCHOOL: He exhibited a Method; and this Method his hearers severalty applied. Around him were men of various ages, various tem- peraments, and various opinions. He discoursed with each upon his own subject. With Xenophon on Politics; with Theages or Theaetetus on science; with Antisthenes on morals; with Ion on poetry ; and so forth. Some were convinced by him ; others merely refuted. The difference between the two is great. Of those who were convinced were formed the so- called Socratic Schools ; those who were only refuted, became his enemies. But of the former some were naturally only more or less convinced; that is, were willing to adopt his opinions on some subjects, but remained stubborn on others. These are the imperfect Socratists. Amongst the latter was Euclid of Megara. Euclid, who must not be confounded with the great Mathe- matician, was born at Megara ; date unknown. He had early imbibed a great love of philosophy, and had diligently studied the writings of Parmenides and the other Eleatics. From Zeno he acquired great facility in dialectics ; and this continued to be his chief excellence, even after his acquaintance with Socrates, who reproved him for it as sophistical. His delight in listening to Socrates was so great that he frequently exposed his life to do so. A decree was passed, in consequence of the enmity existing between Athens and Megara, that any inhabitant of Megara found in Athens should forfeit his life; Euclid, however, braved the penalty. He frequently came to Athens at night, disguised as a female. The distance was twenty miles. At the end of his journey he was recompensed by the fascinating conversation of Socrates ; and he returned to meditate on the results of their arguments. Brucker's supposition that a rupture was caused between them in consequence of Socrates having reproved Euclid's dis- putatious tendency, is wholly without foundation, and seems contradicted by the notorious fact that, on the death of Socrates, Plato and the majority of the disciples retired to Megara, in fear of some popular outbreak of the Athenians, who were in a state of rage against all the philosopher's friends. Euclid received them well. Bound by the same ties of friendship towards the illustrious martyr, and sharing some of his opinions, the Socratists made some stay in Megara. Differences, however, arose ; as they will amongst all commu- nities of the kind. Plato, and some others returned to Athens EUCLID. & as soon as the state of the public mind admitted their doing so with safety. The rest remained with Euclid. " The character of the Megaric doctrine, so far as it is pos- sible to fix it in the defective state of our information, may be briefly given as the Eleatic view enlarged by the Socratic conviction of the moral obligation, and the laws of scientific thought"* We confess our inability to comprehend this. In Euclid we have no hint of " moral obligation " ; in Socrates we are unaware of the " laws of scientific thought" If, by the former, Ritter means that Euclid gave an Ethical and Socratic mean- ing to the Eleatic doctrine, he is correct ; if by the latter he means that Euclid adopted the Socratic Method of Induction and Definitions, he is hopelessly wrong ; and, if he does not mean that by " laws of scientific thought " we are at a loss to understand what he does mean. Euclid agreed with the Eleatics in maintaining that there was but One unalterable Being, which can be known by \ / Reason only. This one Being was not simply The One ;r neither was it simply Intelligence ; it was The Good . This One Being received various names according to its various aspects : thus it was sometimes Wisdom (p6vrjth the Eleatic and Socratic elements. The conception of . God as to ayaObv — the Good — is purely Socratic : and the [/ denial of any existence to things opposed to the Good is an explanation of that passage in Plato's ' Republic,' when Socrates declares God not to be the author of all things, but * . only of such as are good.+ The Megaric doctrine is therefore the Eleatic doctrine, with an Ethical tendency borrowed from Socrates, who taught that y> «£irtae*was not any partial cultivation of the human mind, but constitutes the true and entire essence of the rational man, and indeed of the whole universe. The identificati on of Virtue U- with Wisdom is also Socratic ' " • 'Ritter.* t 09 tdvTutv alriov top 0 ANTISTHENES AND DIOGENES i for a shirt he was told to fold his cloak in two ; he did so. A wallet and a huge stick completed his accoutrements. Seeing a little boy drinking water out of his scooped hand, he threw away his cup, declaring it superfluous. He slept under the marble porticoes of the buildings, or in his celebrated Tub, which was his place of residence. He took his meals in public. In public he performed all those actions which the connate decency of man has condemned to privacy. Decency of every kind he studiously outraged. It was a part of his system to do so. Everything, not in itself improper, ought, he said, to be per- formed publicly — a sophism which could not have deluded any one. Besides he was wont to annoy people with indecent gestures ; had he a philosophical reason for that also ? Doubts have been expressed respecting his Tub, which it is thought was only an occasional residence, and used by him as expressive of his contempt for luxury. We incline, however, to the tradition. It is in keeping with all we know of the man ; and seems confirmed by a passage in Aristophanes.* It is not difficult to imagine the effect created by the Cynics in the gay luxurious city of Athens. There the climate, no less than the prevailing manners, incited everyone to enjoyment. The Cynics told them, that the enjoyment was unworthy of men ; that there were higher and purer things for man to seek. To the polished elegance of Athenian manners, the Cynics opposed the most brutal coarseness they could assume. To the friendly flatteries of conversation, they opposed the bitter- est pungencies of malevolent frankness. They despised all men ; and told them so. Now, although we cannot but regard Cynicism as a very preposterous doctrine — as a feeble solution of the great problem of morals, and not a very amiable feebleness — we are quite prepared to admit that it required some great qualities in its upholders. It required a great rude energy ; a fanatical logi- cality of mind \ a power over self, diseased it may be, but still a power. These qualities are not common qualities; and therefore they command respect. Any deviation from the beaten path implies a certain resolution ; a steady and consis- tent deviation implies force. Now force is what all men respect. The power of subjugating ordinary desires to one remote but calculated end, always impresses men with a sense * 'Knights/ 791. The soldiers are there spoken of as having been forced to live in wine-casks and cellars during the war. THE CYNICS. i8i of unusual power. Few are aware that to reflate desires is more difficult than to subjugate them — requires greater power of mind: greater will; greater constancy. Yet every one knows that abstinence is easier than temperance : on the same principle, it is easier to be a Cynic than a wise and virtuous Epicurean. That which prevents our feeling the respect for the Cynics which the ancients seem to have felt, and which, indeed, some portions of the Cynical doctrine would otherwise induce us to feel, is the studious and uncalled for outrages on common decency and humanity which Diogenes, especially, perpetrated. All the anecdotes that have come down to us seem to reveal a snarling and malevolent spirit, worshipping Virtue only because it was opposed to the vices of contemporaries ; taking a pride in poverty and simplicity only because those around sought wealth and luxury. It may be well to raise an earnest protest against the vices of one's age ; but it is not well to bring virtue into discredit by the manner of the protest. Doubtless the Athenians needed reproof and reformation, and some exaggera- tion on the opposite side might have been allowed to the re- formers. But Diogenes was so feeble in doctrine, so brutal in manner, that we should prefer the debauchery of the first pro- tligate we met with in that profligate city, to the debauchery of pride which disgraced the Cynic. The whole character of the man is exhibited in one anecdote. Plato had given a splendid entertainment to some friends. Diogenes entered, unbidden, and stamping on the rich carpets, said, " Thus I trample on the pride of Plato;" whereupon Plato admirably replied, " With greater pride, O Diogenes." Diogenes, doubtless, practised great abstinence. He made a virtue of his necessity ; and, being poor, resolved to be osten- tatiously poor. The ostentation, being novel, was mistaken for something greater than it was ; being in contradiction to the universal tendency of his contemporaries, it was supposed to spring from higher motives. To us it seems a miserable mask worn by a mountebank. There are men who bear poverty meekly ; there are men who look upon wealth without envy, certain that wealth does not give happiness ; there are men whose souls are so fixed on higher things as utterly to disregard the pomps and shows of the world ; but none of these despise wealth, they disregard it; none of these display their feelings, they are content to act upon them. The virtue that I0t ANTISTHENES AND DIOGENES: is loud, noisy, ostentatious, and self-affirmative, looks very like an obtrusive egotism. And this was the virtue of the Cynics. Pretending to reform mankind, it began by blaspheming huma- nity; pretending to correct the effeminacies of the age, it studiously outraged all the decencies of life. Eluding the real difficulty of the problem, it pretended to solve it by unabashed insolence. In his old age Diogenes was taken captive by pirates, who carried him to Crete, and exposed hiin for sale, as a slave. On being asked what he could do, he replied : " Govern men : sell me, therefore, to one who wants a master." Xeniades, a wealthy Corinthian, struck with this reply, purchased him, and, on returning to Corinth, gave him his liberty and consigned his children to his education. The children were taught to be Cynics, much to their own satisfaction. It was during this period that his world-renowned interview with Alexander took place. The prince, surprised at not seeing Diogenes joining the crowd of his flatterers, went to see him. He found the Cynic sitting in his tub, basking in the sun. " I am Alexander the Great," said he. " I am Diogenes the Cynic," was the reply. Alexander then asked him, if there was anything he could do for him. " Yes ; stand aside from between me and the sun." Surprised at such indifference to princely favour — an indifference so strikingly contrasted with everything he could hitherto have witnessed — he exclaimed: "Were I not Alexander, I would be Diogenes ! " One day, being brought before the king, and being asked whom he was, Diogenes replied : " A spy on your cupidity ; " language, the boldness of which must have gained him universal admiration, as imply- ing great singularity as well as force of character. Singularity and Insolence may be regarded as his grand characteristics. Both of these are exemplified in the anecdote of his lighting a lamp in the daytime, and peering about the streets as if earnestly seeking something : being asked what he sought, he replied : "A Man." The point of this story is lost in the usual version, which makes him seek " an honest man." The words in Laertius are simply : avOpioirov tyrta — " I seek a man." Diogenes did not seek honesty ; he wanted to find a man, in whom honesty would be included with many other qualities. It was his constant reproach to his contemporaries, that they had no manhood. He said, he had never seen men; at Sparta, he had seen children ; at Athens, women. One THE CYNICS. 183 day, he called out : H Approach, all men ! n When some ap- proached, he beat them back with his club, saying : " I called for men ; ye are excrements." Thus he lived till his ninetieth year, bitter, brutal, ostentatious and abstemious ; disgracing the title of The Dog (for a dog has affection, gratitude, sympathy, and caressing manners), yet growling over his unenvied virtue as a cur growls over his meatless bone : for ever snarling and snapping without occa- sion. An object of universal attention ; and, from many quarters, of unfeigned admiration. One day his friends went to see him. On arriving at the Portico under which he was wont to sleep, they found him still lying on the ground wrapped in his cloak. He seemed to sleep. They pushed aside the folds of his cloak : he was dead. It was thought that he had committed suicide by holding his breath, — a physical impossi- bility. Other versions of the cause of his death were current in antiquity ; one of them seems consistent with his character : it makes him die in consequence of devouring a neat's foot raw. The Doctrine of the Cynics may be briefly dispatched. Antisthenes, as the disciple of Gorgias, was embued with the sophistical principles respecting Science, principles which his acquaintance with Socrates did not alter. He maintained, that Science was impossible. As to the Socratic notion of Defini- tions, he utterly rejected it. He said, that a Definition was nothing but a series of words (\6yov ^cucprfv, "a long dis- course") ; for which Aristotle calls him an ignoramus (a7rai8evros — Met. viii. c. iii.). To the Socratic notion of a Definition, as including the essence of a thing, he opposed the Sophistic notion of a Definition, as expressing a purely subjective rela- tion. You can only express qualities, not essences ; you can call a thing silver, but cannot say in wnat it consists. Your definition is only verbal : hence the first step in education should be the study of woras.* What was the consequence of this scepticism ? The conse- quence was, that the Cynics answered arguments by facts. When someone was arguing in support of Zeno of Elea's notion respecting the impossibility of movement, Diogenes rose and walked. Definitions might prove that there was no motion; but definitions were only verbal, and could be answered by facts. * Arrian, 'Epictet.,' Diss. i. 17, quoted in • Ritter and Preller,' d- «74- 184 'I HE CYNICS This refuge found in common sense against the assaults of logic, enabled the Cynics to shape a doctrine of morals which had some certain basis. As they answered arguments by facts ; so they made actions take the place of precepts. Instead of speculating about virtue, they endeavoured to be virtuous. Socrates had brought philosophy from the clouds ; the Cynics Endeavoured to bring it into daily practice. Their personal dispositions gave the peculiar colouring to their doctrine, as that of Aristippus had done for the Cyrenaic Sbfxtf) «port. COMPLETE ADOPTION AND APPLICATION OF THE SOCRATIC METHOD : PLATO. CHAPTER I. LIFE OF PLATO. Perhaps of all ancient writers Plato's name is the best known. Homer himself is unknown to many who have some dim notion of Plato, as the originator of the so-called Platonic love There is a great and wide-spread interest about the Grecian age. The young and romantic have strange romantic ideas of him. " The general reader " — especially if a dabbler in fashionable philosophy, or rather, in the philosophy current in fashionable novels — has a very exalted notion of him as the "great Idealist." The theological reader regards him with affection, as the stout and eloquent upholder of the doctrine of the immateriality and immortality of the soul. The literary critic regards him as the type of metaphysical eloquence ; and classes with him every vapoury, mystical, metaphorical writer of <: poetical philosophy." Now, except that of the theologian, these notions, derived at second hand, are all false. It would be idle to inquire how such extravagant opinions came into circulation. Enough for us that they are false. Plato was anything but "dreamy;" anything but " an Idealist," as that phrase is usually under- stood. He was an inveterate dialectician, a severe and abstract thinker, and a great quibbler. His metaphysics were of a nature to frighten away all but the most determined students, so abstract and so subtle were they. His morals and politics^ so fa' G? LIFE OF PLATO. y from having any romantic tinge, were the ne plus ultra of logical severity : hard, uncompromising and above humanity. In a word, Plato the man was almost completely absorbed in Plato the Dialectician ; he had learned to look upon human passion as a disease, and human pleasure as a frivolity : the only thing worth living for was truth. Dialectics was the noblest exercise of humanity. *<* ■ Even the notions respecting his style are erroneous. It is not the " poetical " metaphorical style usually asserted. It has unmistakeable beauties, but resembles no other writing we are acquainted with. Its immense power is dramatic power. The best dialogues are inimitable scenes of comedy. Character, banter, irony, and animation are there ; but scarcely any imagery, and that seldom beautiful.* His object was to refute, or to convince ; his illustrations are therefore homely and familiar. When fit occasion does arrive, he can be eloquent and poetical. He clothes the myths in language of splendid beauty; and the descriptions of sceiJc loveliness in the 1 Phaedrus' are perfectly ravishing. But such passages are as oases in the arid desert of dialectics. In truth, Plato is a very difficult, and, as far as regards matter, somewhat repulsive writer : this is the reason of his being so seldom read ; for we must not be deceived by the many editions. He is often mentioned and often quoted, at second hand; but he is rarely read. Scholars and critics usually attack one dialogue out of curiosity. Their curiosity seldom inspirits them to further progress. The difficulty of mastering the ideas, and their unsatisfactory nature when mastered, are barriers to any general acquaintance with Plato. But those who persevere believe themselves repaid ; the journey has been difficult, but it was worth performing. We have performed that journey, and can honestly cry " courage ! " to those who lag behind. Perhaps our brief ac- count of Plato and his writings may be some inducement and some preparation. * " Even upon abstract subjects, whether moral, metaphysical, or mathe- matical, the language of Plato is clear as the running stream, and, in sim- plicity and sweetness, vies with the humble violet which perfumes the vale." —Dr. Enfield, ii. p. 221. Whenever you meet with such trash as this be certain that ihe writer of it never read Plato. Aristotle capitally describes Plato's style as "a middle species of diction between verse and prose." It has rhylhm rather than imagery. LIFE OF PLATO. ,87 Aristocles, surnamed Plato (the broad-browed),* the son of Ariston and Perictione, was born at Athens or i^Egina, Olym. 87. 3, on the 7th Thargelion (about the middle of May). His youth consequently falls about the time of the Pelopon- nesian war, the most active and brilliant period of Grecian thought and action. His lineage was illustrious : on the maternal side connected with Solon. So great a name as Plato's could not escape becoming the nucleus of many fables ; and we find, accordingly, the later historians gravely repeating all sorts of miraculous events con- nected with him. He was said to be the child of Apollo, his mother a virgin. Ariston, though betrothed to Perictione, delayed his marriage because Apollo had appeared to him in a dream, and told him that she was with child. We have given one specimen of the fables, and may hence- forth leave them in peace. Plato's education was excellent; and in gymnastics he was sufficiently skilled to contend at the Pythian and Isthmian games. Like a true Greek, he attached extreme importance to gymnastics, as doing for the body what dialects did for the mind ; and, like a true Greek, he did not suffer these corporeal exercises to absorb all his time and attention : poetry, music, and rhetoric were assiduously cultivated, and with some success. He wrote an epic poem, besides some tragedies, dithyrambics, lyrics, and epigrams. The epic he is said to have burned in a fit of despair, on comparing it with Homer. The tragedies he burned on becoming acquainted with Socrates. The epigrams have been partially preserved. One of them is very beautiful : — dorcpac rfaa9pt?c, atrrtfp t/iog* el9e yevoip-rjv ovpavoQ, &>q iroWolg opftaatv «c at /3X«»rw. " Thou gazest on the stars, my Life ! ah ! gladly would I be Yon starry skies, with thousand eyes, that I might gaze on thee ! " f * Some writers incline to the opinion that ' Plato ' was the epithet of broad-browed ; others of broad-shouldered ; others, again, that it was ex- pressive of the breadth of his style. This last is absurd. The author of the article ' Plato ' in the ' Penny Cyclopaedia ' pronounces all the above explanations to be M idle, as the name of Plato was of common occurrence among the Athenians of that time." But surely Aristocles was not endowed with this surname of Plato without cause ? Unless he derived the name from a relation, he must have derived it from one of the above causes. t The above translation is by Mr. Swynfen Jervi*. i» LIFE OF PLATO. His studies of poetry were mingled with those of philosophy, which he must have cultivated early, for we know that he was only twenty when he first went to Socrates, and we also know that he had been taught by Cratylus before he knew Socrates. Early he must have felt " A presence that disturbed him with the joy Of elevated thoughts ; a sense sublime Of something far more deeply interfused, Whose dwelling is the light of setting suns, And the round ocean, and the living air, And the blue sky, and in the mind of man : A motion and a spirit that impels Ail thinking things, all objects of all thought, And rolls through all things." * A deep and meditative spirit led him to question nature in her secret haunts. The sombre philosophy of Heraclitus suited well with his melancholy youth. Scepticism, which was the fever of that age, had seized on Plato, as on all the rest. This scepticism, together with that imperious craving for belief which struggled with the scepticism, both found breathing room in the doctrines of Socrates ; and the young scholai found that, without impugning the justice of his doubts, he could escape them by seeking Truth elsewhere. He remained with Socrates ten years ; and was separated from him only by death. He attended his beloved master during the trial ; undertook to plead his cause ; indeed, began a speech which the violence of the judges would not allow him to continue ; and pressed his master to accept a sum of money sufficient to purchase his life. On the death of Socrates, he went to Megara to visit Euclid, as we mentioned before. From thence he proceeded to Cyrene, where he was instructed in mathematics by Theodorus, whom he had known in Athens, if we may credit the ' Thesetetus," where Theodorus is represented discoursing with Socrates. From Cyrene he went to Egypt, in company, it is said, with Euripides. There is very little authority for this visit, and that little questionable. Certain it is that his stay there has been greatly exaggerated. There is no trace in his works of Egyptian research. " All he tells us of Egypt indicates at most a very scanty acquaintance with the subject, and, although he praises the industry of the Priests, his estimate of their scientific attainments is far from favourable. "t • Wordsworth, 'Tintem Abbey.' f 'Ritter,' ii. 147. LIFE OF PLATO. 189 In these travels, the broad-browed meditative man greatly enlarged the Socratic doctrine, and, indeed, introduced antago- nistic elements. But he strictly preserved the Socratic Method. "Whilst studious youth," says Valerius Maximus, " were crowding to Athens from every quarter in search of Plato for their master, that philosopher was wandering along the winding banks of the Nile or the vast plains of a barbarous country himself, a disciple to the old men of Egypt." He returned at last; and eager scholars flocked around him. With a mind richly stored in foreign travel and constant medi- tation, he began to emulate his beloved master, and devoted himself to teaching. Like Socrates, he taught gratuitously. In the world-renowned grove of Hecademus he founded the Academy. This grove was planted with lofty plane trees, and adorned with temples and statues ; a gentle stream rolled through it, with " A sound as of a hidden brook In the leafy month of June, Which to the sleeping woods all night Singeth a quiet tune." It was a delicious retreat, " for contemplation framed." Tht longing thoughts of posterity have often hovered round it, and made it the centre of myriad associations. Poets have sung of it. Philosophers have sighed for it. " See there the olive grove of Academe, — Plato's retirement, — where the Attic-bird Trills her thick-warbled notes the summer long." In such a spot, where the sound " Of bees' industrious murmur oft invites To studious musing,' 1 one would imagine none but the Graces could enter; and, coupling this with the poetical beauties of Plato's ' Dialogues,' people have supposed that the lessons in the Academy were magnificent outbursts of eloquence and imagery upon philo- sophical subjects. Nothing can be farther from the truth. The lectures were hard exercises of the thinking faculty, and demanded great power of continued abstraction. Whatever graces might have adorned Plato's compositions, his lectures were not literary, but dialectical exercises. Over the door of his Academy he tqo LIFE OP PLATO. wrote : " Let none but Geometricians enter here" — a sufficiently explanatory programme of the nature of his lectures. Ritter thinks differently. He says : " His school was less a school of hardy deeds for all than of polished culture for the higher classes, who had no other object than to enhance the enjoyment of their privileges and wealth." This passage is characteristic of the loose writing of its author. It is composed of three statements, all three absurd. Plato's school " was less a school of hardy deeds," does this mean that Plato did not teach stoicism ? if so, it is a truism ; if not a falsism since what has Dialectics to do with " hardy deeds " ? We are then in- formed that it was a school of polished culture for the " higher classes." A mere assertion, and an absard one. The " higher classes," principally frequented the Sophists ; besides, Plato's lectures were gratuitous, and every free citizen might attend them on certain conditions. There were no aristocratical exclusives in Athens. There were no " polished circles," with a culture differing from that of the other citizens. Thirdly, we are told that their object was " to enhance the enjoyment of their privileges and wealth." How they were to do this by listening to speculations on essences and archetypal Ideas, we are at a loss to conceive ; the more so as Ritter himself tells us Plato's views of justice and honour were" wholly impracticable in the corrupt state of the Athenian constitution; and all empirical knowledge, such as is indispensable to a politician, was in his view contemptible."* In his fortieth year Plato made his first visit to Sicily. It was then he became acquainted with Dionysius I., the tyrant of Syracuse, Dion, his brother-in-law, and Dionysius II. With Dionysius I. he soon came to a rupture, owing to his political opinions, and he so offended the Tyrant, that his life was threatened. Dion, however, interceded for him ; and the Tyrant spared his life, but commissioned Pollis, the Spartan Ambas- sador, in whose ship Plato was to return, to sell him as a slave. He was sold accordingly. Anniceris of Cyrene bought him, * Some countenance seems given to the ordinary notion of Plato's Lectures by the tradition that even some women attended them. We confess this statement is to us suspicious, especially as it is also said that one woman disguised herself in man's clothes ; disguise, then, was neces- sary ? The fact, however, if correct, would only show the high cultivation of the hetaira (for such the women must have been) ; and, when we think of such women as Aspasia, we see no reason for supposing they could not follow the ftbstrusest lectures. LIFE OF PLATO. 191 and immediately set him free. On his return to Athens, Dionysius wrote hoping that he would not speak ill of him. Plato contemptuously replied that he had not " leisure to think of Dionysius." Plato's second visit to Syracuse was after the death of Dionysius I., and with the hope of obtaining from Dionysius II. the establishment of a colony according to the laws framed by himself. The colony was promised • but never granted. Plato incurred the Tyrant's suspicions of having been con- cerned in Dion's conspiracy ; but he was allowed to return home in peace. He paid a third visit ; and this time solely to endeavour to reconcile Dionysius with his uncle Dion. Finding his efforts fruitless, and perhaps dangerous, he returned. In the calm retirement of the Academy Plato passed the remainder of his days. Lecturing and writing were his chief occupations. The composition of those dialogues which have been the admiration of posterity, was the cheering solace of his life, especially of his declining years. He died at the advanced age of 83. Plato was intensely melancholy. That great broad brow which gave him his surname, was wrinkled and sombre. Those brawny shoulders were bent with thought, as only those of thinkers are bent. A smile was the utmost that ever played over his lips ; he never laughed. " As sad as Plato " became a phrase with the comic dramatists. He had many admirers \ scarcely any friends. In Plato the thinker predominated over the man. That great expansive intellect had so fixed itself upon the absorbing questions of philosophy that it had scarcely any sympathy left tor other matters. Hence his constant reprobation of Poets. Many people suppose that his banishing the poets from his t Republic ' was but an insincere extension of his logical principles, and that he really loved poetry too well to condemn it, — a mistake. Plato's opposition to poets was deep and constant. He had a feeling not unallied to contempt for them, because he saw in them some resemblance to the Sophists, viz., a&J&digerence tojtruth and a preference for the arts of expression. The only po^txy~PfcrtTjreverpraises is the moral poetry, which is in truth versified philosophy. His soul panted for Truth. Poets, at the best, were only inspired madmen, unconscious of what fell 19* PLATO'S WRITINGS. from their lips. Let the reader open the ' Ion ' (it has been translated by Sheiley) ; he will then perceive the real cause of Poets being banished from the i Republic' He had a repug- nance for poetry, partly because it was the dangerous rival of philosophy, partly because he had a contempt for pleasure.* It is true that he frequently quotes Homer, and, towards the close of the ' Republic,' some misgivings of having harshly treated the favourite of his youth, escape him ; but he quickly withdraws them, and owns that Truth alone should be man's object. There is something unpleasant in Plato's character, which finds its echo in his works. He was a great, but not an amiable man ; his works are great, but lamentably deficient in humanity. His ethics are the ethics of a logician, not of a man ; they are suited only to an impossible state of humanity. In bringing forward this view of Plato's character we shall doubtless shock many prejudices, and tilt against eminent men. We cannot help it. The Plato we have drawn, if not so romantic, is a truer figure than that usually drawn ; it is the only one consonant with what the ancient writers transmit. Let no one object to our assertion of his constant melancholy, on the ground of the comic talent displayed in his dialogues. The comic writers are not the gayest men. Moliere, whose humour is the most genial, overflowing, and apparently most sponta- neous, was one of the austerestof men. Comedy often springs from the deepest melancholy ; as if in the rebound. Besides, in Plato's comedy there is almost always some undercurrent of bitterness \ it is Irony, rather than Joyousness. CHAPTER II. PLATO'S WRITINGS : THEIR CHARACTER, OBJECT, AND AUTHENTICITY. Before attempting an exposition of Plato's doctrines, it may be useful to say something respecting the character and authen- ticity of his 'Dialogues.' Modern criticism, which spares nothing, has not left them untouched. Dialogues, the authen * Comp. ■ Philebttf,' p. t jt. PLATO'S WRITINGS. 193 ticity of which had never been questioned in antiquity, have been rejected by modern critics upon the most arbitrary grounds. We cannot enter into the details, we have no space ; and, had we space, we might be excused from combating the incft vidual positions, when we refuse to accept as valid the funda mental assumptions on which they are founded. Internal evidence is deceptive at all times ; but that sort of internal evidence supposed to be afforded by comparative inferiority in artistic execution, is utterly worthless. Some of Plato's dia- logues not being found equal to the exalted idea which his great works have led men to entertain, are forthwith declared to be spurious. But what writer is at all times equal to the highest of his own flights ? What author has produced nothing but chefs-d'oeuvre 1 Are there not times when the most brilliant men are dull, when the richest style is meagre, when the com- pactest style is loose ? The same subjects will not always call forth the same excellence ; how unlikely then that various subjects should be treated with uniform power ! The ' Theages ' could hardly equal the ' Theaetetus;' the ■ Euthydernus' must be inferior to the ' Gorgias.' No one thinks of disputing Shakspeare's claim to the ' Merry Wives of Windsor/ because it is immeasurably inferior to * Twelfth Night,' which in its turn is inferior to ' Othello.' Besides the dialogues rejected on account of inferior art, there are others rejected on account of immature or contradic- tory opinions. But this ground is as untenable as the former. No one has yet been able to settle definitively what what was Plato's philosophy ; yet opinions are said to be unworthy of that unsettled philosophy ! A preconceived notion of Plato's having been a pure Socratist has led to the rejection of what- ever seemed contradictory to Socratic views. But there is ahundant evidence to show that Plato was not a mere exponent of Socratic opinions. Moreover, in a long life a man's opinions undergo many modifications ; and Plato was no exception to the rule. He contradicts himself constantly. He does so in works the authenticity of which no one has questioned ; and we are not to be surprised if we find him doing so in others. It is somewhat amusing to observe the confidence of modern criticism on this point.* An Ast, or a Socher, or a Schleier- * " According as the deification has directed itself to this or that aspect of his character, the opinions raised as to the genuineness or falsity of his 194 PLATO'S WRITINGS. macher, reject on the most fallacious assumptions the authen- ticity of works quoted by Aristotle as the works of his master, Plato. Now really to suppose that Aristotle could be mistaken on such a matter is a great extension of the conjectural privilege; but, to make this supposition on no better ground than that ol internal evidence, derived from inferiority of execution, or variation in opinion in the works themselves, seems truly preposterous. The ancients themselves admitted the ' Epinomis,' the 1 Eryxias,' the ' Axiochus ' and the ' Second Alcibiades * to be spurious. The ' Epistles' are also now pretty generally regarded as forgeries. With these exceptions, we really see no reason for rejecting any of the dialogues. The ' Theages ' and the 'Hippias Major' are certainly as much in Plato's manner as ' Measure for Measure ' is in Shakspeare's ; indeed, the ' Hippias ' seems to us a remarkably happy specimen of his dramatic talent. But whether all the dialogues were the productions of Plato, or not, they equally serve the purpose of this history, since no one denies them to be platonic. We may therefore leave this question, and proceed to others. Do the ' Dialogues ' contain the real opinions of Plato ? — this question has three motives, ist. Plato himself never speaks in propria persona, unless indeed the Athenian in the ' Laws ' be accepted as representing Plato ; a supposition in which we are inclined to concur. 2ndly. From certain passages of the ' Phaedrus ' and the ' Epistles,' it would appear that Plato had a contempt for written opinions as inefficient for instruction. 3dly. On the testimony of a phrase in Aristotle it is supposed that Plato, like Pythagoras, had exoteric and esoteric opinions, the former being of course those set forth in his • Dialogues.' We will endeavour to answer these doubts. The first is of very little importance ; the second of greater ; the last of very great importance. That Plato adopts the dramatic form, and preserves it, is true ; but this form, which quite baffles us with Shakspeare, baffles us with no one else. It is easy to divine the opinions of Aristophanes, Moliere, or Schiller. It is still more easy to divine the opinions of Plato, because, unlike the works have fluctuated ; so that we might safely say, the more his writings have been examined, the more has the decision of their authenticity become complicated." — Ritter. PLATO'S WRITINGS. 195 dramatists, he selects his dialogue solely with a view to the illustration of his opinions. Besides, it is reasonable to suppose that Socrates represents Plato's opinions seen through the manner of Socrates. And, whatever the variations may be with respect to subordinate points, we find but one Method in all the ' Dialogues,' but one conception of science, in a word, we find an unmistakeable tendency which we pronounce to be Platonic. Respecting his opinion on the insufficiency of books to convey instruction, we may first quote what he says on the subject in the ' Phaedrus : ' — " Writing is something like painting • Uie creatures of the latter art look very like living beings ; but, if you ask them a question, they preserve a solemn silence. Written discourses do the same : you would fancy, by what they say, that they had some sense in them ; but, if you wish to learn, and there- fore interrogate them, they have only their first answer to re- turn to all questions. And when the discourse is once written, it passes from hand to hand, among all sorts of persons, those who can understand it, and those who cannot. It is not able to tell its story to those only to whom it is suitable; and, when it is unjustly criticised, it always needs its author to assist it, for it cannot defend itself. There is another sort of discourse, which is far better and more potent than this. What is it ? That which is scientifically written in the learner's mind. This is capable of defending itself, and it can speak itself, or be silent, as it sees fit. You mean the real and living discourse of the person who understands the subject; of which discourse the written one may be called the picture ? Precisely. Now, think you that a sensible husbandman would take seed which he valued, and wished to produce a harvest, would seriously, after the summer had begun, scatter it in the gardens of Adonis, for the pleasure of seeing it spring up and look green in a week ? Or, do you not rather think that he might indeed do this for sport and amusement; but, when his purpose was serious, would employ the art of agriculture, and, sowing the seed at the proper time, be content to gather in his harvest in the eighth month ? The last, undoubtedly. And do you think that he who possesses the knowledge of what is just, and noble, and good, will deal less prudently with his seeds than the husband- man with his ? Certainly not. He will not, then, set about sowing them with a pen and a black liquid ; or, (to drop the meta- 196 PLATO* S WRITINGS. phor,) scattering these truths by means of discourses which cannot defend themselves against attack, and which are incap- able of adequately expounding the truth. No doubt, he will, fot the sake of sport, occasionally scatter some of the seeds in this manner, and will thus treasure up memoranda for himself, in case he should fall into the forgetfulness of old age, and for all others who follow in the same track ; and he will be pleased when he sees the blade growing up green." Now, this remarkable passage is clearly biographical. It is the justification of Socrates' philosophical career. But it must not be too rigorously applied to Plato, whose voluminous writings contradict it ; nor must we, in consequence, suppose that those writings were designed only for amusement, or as memoranda for his pupils. The main idea of this passage is one that few persons would feel disposed to question. We are all aware that books labour under very serious deficiencies ; they cannot replace oral instruction. The frequent misappre- hensions of an author's meaning would in a great measure be obviated if we had him by our side to interrogate him. And oral instruction has the further advantage of not allowing the reader's mind to be so passive as it is with a book ; the teacher by his questions excites the activity of the pupil. All this may reasonably be conceded as Plato's opinion without at all affecting the seriousness of his writings. Plato thought that conversation was more instructive than reading ; but he knew also that reading was instructive, and he therefore wrote : to obviate as much as possible the necessary inconveniences of written discourse he threw all his works into the form of dialogue. Hence the endless repetitions, and divisions, and illustrations of positions almost self-evident. The reader is fatigued by them ; but, like Addison's tediousness, they have " a design " in them : that design is, by imitating conversation, to leave no position unexplained. As a book cannot be inter- rogated, Plato makes the book anticipate interrogations. The very pains he takes to be tedious, the very minuteness of his details, is sufficient to rescue his works from the imputation of being mere divertissements. He was too great an artist to have sacrificed his art to anything but his convictions. That he did sacrifice the general effect to his scrupulous dialectics no one can doubt, and we believe that he did so for the sake of deeply impressing on the reader's mind the real force of his method. PLATO'S WRITINGS. 197 Had critics seen Plato's real drift, they would have spared much of their censure, and hesitated before pronouncing against the genuineness of certain dialogues. For our own part, we can only reconcile the style of Plato with the above explanation ; that once adopted, all the vexata questiones disappear. The third division of our investigation may now be entered upon. Connected with Plato's expressions respecting the imperfection of written works, there is the passage in Aristotle referring to the a 8oy/xaTa probably meant his lectures, or as Ritter suggests, notes taken from the lectures by his scholars. At any rate there is no ground for supposing them to have been esoterical opinions ; the more so as Aristotle, his most illustrious pupil, never speaks of any such distinct doctrine, but draws his state- ments of Plato's views from published works. We are convinced that the ' Dialogues ' contain the real opinions of Plato, in as far as Plato ventured to express them. We make this reservation because it is pretty generally known that individual opinions were not of so much importance as Method, in the Socratic philosophy. It would perhaps be better to say, therefore, that the ' Dialogues ' exhibit Plato's real Method and tendencies. Certain it is that the Method and tendencies can only rightly be appreciated after a survey of all the 'Dialogues.' The ancients, we are told by Sextus * ' Phys.,' iv. c. 2, p. 53. Ritter, who refers to, but does not cite, the passage, gives us to understand that, in these unwritten opinions, " much was explained differently, or, at least, more definitively than in the ' Dia- logues.' " But no such conclusion can be drawn from Aristotle. There is no greater difference alluded to in the above passage that may frequently be found between one dialogue and another. If the written (published) opinions differ, surely those unwritten may be allowed also to differ from the written? If the 'Republic* differs from the 'Timaeus,' surely the " unwritten opinion " may differ from the ' Timaeus ? ' 1 98 PLATO'S WRITINGS. Empiricus,* were divided amongst themselves as to whether Plato was a sceptic or a dogmatist. Nor was the dispute irra- tional ; for, as some of the * Dialogues ' are expository and dogmatical, and others are mere exercises of the dialectical method — mere contests in which nothing is definitively settled — any one having studied only one class of these ' Dialogues' would think Plato either a sceptic or a dogmatist, according to the nature of those which he had read. Thus Cicero, an ardent admirer, says : " Plato affirms nothing ; but, after producing many arguments, and examining a question on every side, leaves it undetermined." This is true of such dialogues as the 1 Theaetetus,' or the ' Hippias Major ; ' but extremely untrue of the ■ Phaedo,' 'Timaeus,' ' Leges,' &c. This leads us to a consideration of the various attempts at classifying the dialogues. That some sort of classification should be adopted is admitted by all ; but no two persons seem to agree as to the precise arrangement. Any attempt at chro- nological arrangement must inevitably fail. Certain dialogues can be satisfactorily shown to have been written subsequently to some others; but any regular succession is beyond our ingenuity. We may be pretty sure that the ' Phaedrus ' was the earliest or one of the earliest, and the ' Laws ' the latest. We may be sure that the ' Republic ' was earlier than the * Laws,' because the latter is a maturer view of politics. But when the ' Republic ' was written, baffles conjecture. It is usually placed with the ' Timasus ' and the ■ Laws;' that is to say with the last products of its author. But we demur to this on several accounts. The difference of style and of ideas observable in the ' Republic ' and the * Laws ' imply conside- rable distance between the periods of composition. Besides, a man not writing for his bread does not so soon resume a subject which he has already exhausted. Plato had uttered his opinions in the * Republic' He must have waited till new ideas were developed before he could be tempted again to write; for, observe both these dialogues are expository and dogmatical j they express Plato's opinions ; they are not merely dialectical exercises. It strikes us also that there is but one safe principle to be applied to the testing of such points. Whenever two works exhibit variations of opinion, we should examine the nature of * « Fyrrho. Hypot.,' i. p. 44. PLATO'S WRITINGS. 19$ the variations and ask, which of the two opinions is the later in development— which must have been the earlier? Let us take an example. In the ' Republic,' iii. p. 123, he attempts to prove that no one can excel in two arts ; that the comic poet cannot be the same as the tragic, that the same actor cannot act in tragedy and comedy with success. In the 1 Amatores,' p. 289, he has the same idea, though there only mentioned briefly.* In the 'Symposium,' however, Plato's opinion is directly the reverse ; for, in a celebrated passage, he makes Socrates convince Agathon, that the tragic and comic poet are the same person. Now, it is not difficult to decide which is the earlier opinion : that in the ' Republic ' is the logical consequence of his premisses ; but that in the \ Sympo- sium \ is the opinion corrected by experience; for, in the poets of his own day he found both comedy and tragedy united ; and Socrates being made to convince Agathon proves that the former opinion was not uncommon, and looks like a retracta- tion on Plato's side. No one will deny that the former opinion is superficial. The distinction between tragedy and comedy is such that it seems to imply a distinct nature for the cultivation of each. But Shakspeare, Racine, Cervantes, Calderon, and very many others, confute this notion by their works. Perhaps, a still more conclusive example is that of the " crea- tion of Ideas " so expressly stated in the ' Republic,' and the " eternity and uncreated nature of Ideas " as expressly stated in the ' Timaeus.' So radical a difference in the most important position of his philosophy would at once separate the epochs at which the two dialogues were composed. And to this may be added the difference in artistic treatment between the * Republic' and the ■ Timaeus.' The former, although expository, has much of the vivacity and dramatic vigour of the early dialogues. The * Timaeus ' and the ' Laws ' have scarcely a trace of art. Ritter has well observed that u the excellence of the Platonic dialogues, as pieces of art, is twofold : the rare imitative powers exhibited in the dialogue, and the acuteness with which piloso- * According to Ritter's principle, this would prove the ' Republic ' to be later than the 'Amatores.' He maintains, and with plausibility, that, when a subject which has been developed in one dialogue is briefly assumed in another, the latter is subsequent in composition. — See vol. ii. p. 183. Yet, on this principle the ' Phaedo ' is earlier than the • Phsedrus,' inasmuch as the doctrine of reminiscence is developed in the former and alluded to in the latter. 2oo PLATO'S WRITINGS, phical matters are dialectically treated. No one will deny that these two qualities have only an outward connexion, and con- sequently that they cannot advance equally. With the philo- sopher the latter is manifestly the more important, whereas the former is of secondary importance. The degree of perfection therefore in any dialogue, as such, affords at most a very uncer- tain means for the determination of its date; whereas the greatest weight ought to be laid on the dialectical skill." In proportion as the dialectical skill became mature, it is natural to suppose that the dramatic imitation was less cared for. In proportion as Plato became settled in his convictions he became anxious solely for their clear exposition. He began life with a love of poetry ; but this he soon abandoned for philosophy. So his first work was the ' Phaedrus,' the most luxuriant in poeti- cal images ; his last were the ' Timseus ' and the ' Laws,' the most exclusively dogmatical, and the least ornate. The whole inquiry may seem idle ; but it is not so. Until something like a positive arrangement of his works can be made, there will be no end to the misconceptions of his opinions ; for it is preposterous to cite passages in support of a doctrine before having ascertained the date of the work whence the passages are drawn. Yet this is the way critics and historians draw up an imaginary outline of Plato's philosophy, and squabble amongst each other as to who is right. When it is said that Plato held such or such an opinion, it should be distinctly understood at what period of his career he held it ; because, in so long a career, and with so many changes of opinion, it is necessary to be precise. For our own part we can scarcely name an opinion held by him throughout his works. Even the Socratic idea of Virtue being identical with knowledge, con- sequently, Vice being Ignorance and therefore involuntary — even this idea — he learned in his old age to repudiate, as we see in the ' Laws,' book v. p. 385, where he calls incontinence, no less than ignorance (17 yap oY afiaOiav rj 81 aKparetav), the causes of vice. In the same sense, book ix. p. 138, after speaking of anger and pleasure as causes of error, he says : " There is a third cause of our faults, and that is ignorance " (rpCrov fxrjv ayvouxv r? A further sub-division might also be made of the agonistic dia- logues, into such as are purely polemical, and such as by means of polemics enforce ideas. Sometimes Plato only destroys ; at other times the destruction is a clearance of the ground which opens to us a vista of the truth: of this kind is the ' Theaetetus.' We are, however, firmly persuaded that one distinct purpose runs through all the 'Dialogues,' whatever may be their varieties of form or of opinion : one great and fruitful purpose, which may rightly be called the philosophy of Plato, and which we will now attempt to exhibit. CHAPTER III. PLATO'S METHOD. By some, Plato is regarded as a mere literary exponent of the Socratic doctrines ; by others, as the real founder of a new epoch and of a new philosophy. Both of these views appear to us erroneous ; but, really on the subject of Plato errors are so numerous, and we had almost said so inevitable, that no one who rightly appreciates the difficulty of ascertaining the truth, will be disposed to dogmatise. Although we claim the right of enforcing our opinions — a right purchased with no con- temptible amount of labour in the inquiry — we would be dis- tinctly understood to place no very great confidence in their validity. After this preface, we trust, we may speak openly, without incurring the charge of dogmatism. We are not enunciating ascertained truths : we are simply recording the results of study.* Plato we hold to be neither a simple Socratist, nor the creator of a new philosophy. He was the inheritor of all the * It has beeu a principle with us throughout to abstain from all unne- cessary references ; and we shall follow it in this account of Plato. To have quoted chapter and verse for every statement would have been endless. The absence of such references renders it the more needful for us to state that, previous to writing this section, we renewed our acquain- tance with Plato, by carefully reading all his works, with the exception of two of the minor ones. This section is the result of that study. sTa= Abstract ideas=Science. In the everchanging flux of Becoming, which was the object of Perception, there were traces of the immutable Being, which was the object of science. This distinction may be applied to Plato's own manifold works. We may say of them that the opinions on psychology, physics, ethics, and politics are con- stantly changing, uncertain, and of no value. But amidst all these various opinions there reigns one constant Method. He never wavers as to Dialectics. That is the Science. We may therefore fully understand the importance bestowed on Dia- lectics ; and we may also clearly see what is meant by identi- fying his Philosophy with Dialectics. The basis of the Platonic doctine therefore is Dialectics ; the subject-matter of Dialectics consists of Ideas; and the Method consists of Definitions, Analysis, Induction. CHAPTER VII. flato's theology and cosmology. Hitherto we have been occupied solely with the general Doctrine j we have now to descend to particulars. But, as so often remarked, particular doctrines have scarcely uny stability in the Platonic writings; what is advanced to-day is refuted to-morrow ; accordingly, critics and historians have squabbled about these wavering opinions, as if agreement were possible. One declares Plato held one opinion j and cites his passages in proof. Another thinks his predecessor a block- head, and cites other passages wholly destructive of the opinion Plato is said to have maintained. A third comes, and string- ing passages from one dialogue to passages from another, interprets the whole in his own way. Any consistent Theological doctrine will not therefore be expected from us : we can only reproduce some of the Pla- tonic notions, those especially which have influenced later thinkers. In the same way as Plato sought to detect the One amidst 324 PLATO'S THEOLOGY AND COSMOLOGY. the Multiplicity of material phenomena, and, having detected it, declared it to be the real essence of matter, so also did he seek to detect the One amidst the Multiplicity of Ideas, and, having detected it, declared it to be God. What Ideas were to Phenomena, God was to Ideas: the last result of generaliza- tion. God was thus the One Being comprising within himself all other Beings, the lv koX 7roAXa, the Cause of all things, celestial and terrestrial. God is the supreme Idea. Whatever view we take of the Platonic cosmology — whether God created Ideas, or whether he only fashioned unformed matter after the model of Ideas — we are equally led to the conviction, that God represented the supreme Idea of all Existence : the great Intelligence, source of all other Intelligences: the Sun whose light illumined creation. God is perfect, ever the same, without envy, wishing nothing but good ; for, although a clear knowledge of God is impos- sible to mortals, an approximation to that knowledge is possible ; we cannot know what he is, we can only know what he is like. He must be good, because self-sufficing ; and the world is good, because he made it. Why did he make it ? God made the world because he was free from envy, and wished that all things should resemble him as much as pos- sible. He therefore persuaded Necessity to become stable, harmonious, and fashioned according to Beauty. Yes, per- suaded 'is Plato's word: for there were two eternal Principles, Intelligence and Necessity, and from the mixture of these the world was made ; but Intelligence persuaded Necessity to be fashioned according to Beauty.* He arranged chaos into Beauty. But, as there is nothing beautiful but Intelligence, and as there is no Intelligence without a Soul, he placed a Soul into the body of the World, and made the World an animal. Plato's proof of the world being an animal, is too curious a specimen of his analogical or Inductive reasoning to be passed over. There is warmth in the human being ; there is warmth also in the world'; the human being is composed of various elements, and is therefore called a body ; the world is also composed of various elements, and is therefore a body; and, * pifiiyfuvrj ydp ovv ij rovSe rov Koopov ytvkaiQ «£ dvdyKijg n cat vov vwrrdviui iyyivvijOri, vov $k dvdyKtjg apxovroc ry ireiOttv avrrjv tup yiyrofuvuv rd jcKiiara ixi to fitXrioTov dyuv. — Timnsus, p. 56. PLATO'S THEOLOGY AND COSMOLOGY. ■ 225 as our bodies have souls, the body of the world must have a soul : and that soul stands in the same relation to our souls, as the warmth of the world stands to our warmth.* Having thus demonstrated the world to be an animal, it was but natural he should conceive that animal as resembling its creator, and human beings as resembling the universal animal, to rrav £wov. As soon as the World, that image of the eternal Gods or Ideas, that vast Animal, began to move, live, and think, God looked upon his work, and was glad.t But, although God in his goodness would have made nothing evil, he could not prevent the existence of it. Various dis- putes have been warmly carried on by scholars, respecting the nature of this Evil which Plato was forced to admit. Some have conceived it nothing less than the Manichsean doctrine. This much we may say : the notion of an antagonist principle is inseparable from every religious formula : as God can only be Good, and as Evil does certainly exist, it must exist inde- pendently of him ; it must be eternal. Plato cut the matter very short by his logical principle, — that since there was a Good, there must necessarily be the contrary of Good, viz., Evil. If Evil exists, how does it exist, and where f It cannot find place in the celestial region of Ideas. It must, therefore, necessarily dwell in the terrestrial region of phenomena : its home is the world ; it is banished from heaven. And is not this logical? What is the world of Phenomena but an imper- fect copy of the world of Ideas, and how can the imperfect be the purely Good ? When Ideas are " realized," as the pan- theists would say, when Ideas, pure immutable essences, are clothed in material forms, or when matter is fashioned after the model of those Ideas, what can result but imperfections ? The Ideas are not in this world, the Ideas are 6vto>s ovra not yiyvoixiva: in this world they are only in a state of becoming. Phenomena are in their very nature imperfect : they are perpetually striving to exist as realities. In their constitution, * « Philebus,' pp. 170-I. f 'Qf l\ Kivr)6iv avrb icai £wv lvtv6t)v ytyovoQ aya\pa b yttvrjaag Tcarijp, t)ynnOrj re xai (uQpavtitiq iiri fidWov opoiov irp'oQ to irapdcuypa iirtvoqatv aTftpyaoaoOai. — l^maus, p. 36. It is almost superfluous to refer the reader to ' Genesis.' P 226 . PLATO'S THEOLOGY AND COSMOLOGY. there is something of the divine : an image of the Idea, and some participation in it ; but more of the primeval chaos.^ Those, therefore, who say that Plato thought that " Evil was inherent in matter," though expressing themselves loosely, express themselves on the whole correctly. Matter was the great Necessity which Intelligence fashioned. Being Necessity and unintelligent it was Evil, for Intelligence alone can be good.* Now, as this world of phenomena is the region where Evil dwells, we must use our utmost endeavours to escape from it. And how escape ? By suicide ? No. By leading the life of the gods ; and every Platonist knows that the life of the gods consists in the eternal contemplation of truth, of Ideas. Thus, as on every side, are we forced to encounter Dialectics as the sole salvation for man ! From the above explanation of the nature of Evil, it will be seen that there is no contradiction in Plato's saying, that the quantity of Evil in this life exceeded that of the Good ; it exceeds it in the proportion that phenomena exceed noumena, that matter exceeds ideas. But although Evil be a necessary part of the world, it is in constant struggle with Good. What is this but the struggle of Becoming f And Man is endowed with Free Will and Intelli- gence : he may, therefore, choose between Good and Evil : -rijf$ $€ y€v«r«os ro iroiov rtvos dorJK* reus fiov\r}cr€v r« dyaOwv aWiav ilvai ^v\riv cat rutv ra/ca»v), it was neces- sary to have some other principle which should determine its direction. He therefore makes vovq (intelligence), the principle which determines the soul (whether the soul of the world or of man, it is the same) to good ; and avoia (ignorance — want of nous) which determines it to evil. PLATO'S VIEW OF THE BEAUTIFUL AND GOOD. 227 proved to exist by the very feeling of affinity to his nature which stirs within our souls. Such opinions as those above set down were certainly ex- pressed by Plato, at different times : but we again warn the reader against supposing them to have been his constant views. They are taken from works written at wide intervals, and bear- ing considerable difference of opinion; and in those very works there are occasional glimpses of an appalling doctrine, viz. that man is but the plaything of God, who alternately governs and forsakes the world. The first notion seems de- rived from Heraclitus, who said, that making worlds was the sport of Demiourgos. Plato's words are these : avOpmirov Be tfeov tl TraLyviov ilvai fitfxTjxavrjfiivov : and this is said to be man's greatest excellence.* The second notion is formally expressed in the ■ Politicus,' pp. 273-80. "God," he says, " alternately governs and forsakes the world; when he governs it, things go on well : it is the age of gold ; when he forsakes it, the world suddenly turns round in a contrary orbit — a fearful crisis takes place, all things are disordered, mundane existence is totally disarranged, and only after some time do things settle down to a sort of order, though of a very imper- fect kind." CHAPTER VIII. plato's view of the beautiful and the good; THE to KaXov kcu to ayaOov. So much has been written and talked in modern times of the rb KaXbvj " the Beautiful," as conceived by Plato, and this by persons who never read a line of his works, that we must devote a few sentences to it ; certain as we are, that of those who consult our pages, two-thirds would deem the omission unpardonable. The bond which unites the human to the divine is Love. And what is Love ? The longing of the Soul for Beauty : the inextinguishable desire which like feels for like, which the divinity within us feels for the divinity revealed to us in Beauty. • ' De Legibus,' vii. p. 32. 828 PLATO'S VIEW OF This is the celebrated Platonic Love, which, from having originally meant a communion of two souls, and that in a rigidly dialectical sense, has been degraded to the expression of hypocritical sentiment between the sexes. Platonic love meant sympathy; it means the love of a sentimental young gentleman for a woman he cannot or will not marry. But what is Beauty ? Not the mere flattery of the senses. It does not consist in harmonious outlines and resplendent colours : these are but the indications of it. Beauty is Truth. It is the radiant image of that which was most splendid in the world of Ideas. Listen to Plato's description of it in the ' Phsedrus ' : — " For, as we have already said, every human soul has actually seen the Real Existences, or it would not have come into a human shape. But it is not easy for all of them to call to mind what they then saw : those, especially, which saw that region for a short time only, and those which, having fallen to the earth, were so unfortunate as to be turned to injustice, and consequent oblivion of the sacred things which were seen by them in their prior state. Few, therefore, remain who are adequate to the recollection of those things. These few, when they see here any image or resemblance of the things which are there, receive a shock like a thunderbolt, and are in a manner taken out of themselves ; but, from deficiency of comprehension, they know not what it is which so affects them. Now, the likenesses which exist there of Justice and Temperance, and the other things which the soul honours, do not possess any splendour ; and a few persons only, with great difficulty, by the aid of dull, blunt, material organs, perceive the terrestial likenesses of those qualities, and recognise them. But Beauty was not only most splendid when it was seen by us forming part of the heavenly possession or choir, but here also the likeness of it comes to us through the most acute and clear of our senses, that of sight, and with a splendour which no other of the terrestrial images of super-celestial existences possess. They, then, who are not fresh from heaven, or who have been corrupted, are not vehemently impelled towards that Beauty which is aloft when they see that upon earth which is called by its name ; they do not, therefore, venerate and worship it, but give themselves up to physical pleasure after the manner of a quadruped. But they who are fresh from those divine objects of contemplation, and who have formerly contemplated them much, when they see a Godlike counten- THE BEAUTIFUL AND THE GOOD, 129 ance or form, in which celestial beauty is imaged and well imitated, are first struck with a holy awe, and then, approach- ing, venerate this beautiful object as a god, and, if they were not afraid of the reputation of too raving a madness, would erect altars, and perform sacrifices to it. "And the warmth and genial influence derived from the atmosphere which beauty generates around itself, entering through the eyes, softens and liquefies the inveterate indura- tion, which coats and covers up the parts in the vicinity of the wings, and prevents them from growing: this being melted, the wings begin to germinate and increase, and this, like the growing of the teeth, produces an itching and irritation which disturbs the whole frame of the soul. When, therefore, by the contemplation of the beautiful object, the induration is soft- ened, and the wings begin to shoot, the soul is relieved from its pain and rejoices; but when that object is absent, the liquefied substance hardens again, and closes up the young shoots of the wings, which consequently boil up and throb, and throw the soul into a state of turbulence and rage, and will neither allow it to sleep nor remain at rest, until it can again see the beautiful object, and be relieved. For this reason it never willingly leaves that object ; but for its sake deserts parents, and brothers, and friends, and neglects its patrimony, and despises all established usages on which it valued itself before. And this affection is Love. The reader is doubtless by this time familiar enough with the Platonic philosophy to appreciate this passage. He will see the dialectical meaning of this poetical myth. He will com- prehend, also, that the Platonic Love is naturally more appro- priate between two men — master and pupil — than between the two sexes ; because it is purer, and less disturbed by other feelings. Beauty is the most vivid image of Truth : it is divinity in its most perceptible form. But what is the Good ? The Good, to ayaObv, is God, but God in his abstract state. Truth, Beauty, Justice, are all aspects of the Deity; Goodness is his nature. The Good is therefore incapable of being per- ceived ; it can only be known in reflection. In the same manner as the sun is the cause of sight, and also the cause of the objects of sight growing and being produced, so also the Good is the cause of science, and the cause of being to what- ever is the object of science : and, as the sun itself is not sight, 830 PLATO'S JSTJff/CS. nor the object of sight, but presides over both ; so also the Good is not science, nor the object of science, but is superior to both, for they are not the Good, but goodly. CHAPTER IX. plato's ethics. Plato was a Socratist. Hitherto, however, we have seen him following his master only in his Method. The speculations on Ideas, Reminiscence, Metempsychosis, God, &c, were things he did not learn from Socrates, although the Socratic Method was his most powerful instrument. We have before seen that Socrates occupied himself almost exclusively with Ethics ; and it is in Ethics, therefore, that we shall expect to find Plato resembling him. Such is the fact ; and it will enable us to pass more rapidly over the subject than the importance of it would otherwise justify. But, although Plato's ethical opinions are mostly Socratic, yet even in them we see how the Dialectician was dominant : they are logical rather than ethical : that is to say, they are deductions from certain logical premisses, not from investiga- tions into human nature. There is, moreover, considerable contradiction in his various works on this, as on other points. In one place (' Timaeus '), he advocates Free Will; in another ('Hippias Minor'), Fatalism. Sometimes vice is involuntary, at other times voluntary. Sometimes — indeed, generally — vice is nothing but ignorance ; elsewhere, as we have shown, vice is said to be partly ignorance and partly incontinence. Virtue is said to be Science ; yet Knowledge alone does not constitute Happiness, nor can Virtue be taught. Although, therefore, many splendid passages may be quoted, in which morals are worthily spoken of, we cannot but regard as chimerical any attempt to deduce from them an ethical system. All that can safely be relied on, is general tenden- cies: such, for instance, as his subordination of Ethics to Dialectics. As M. de Gerando well observes, " he did not found his ethics on a principle of obligation, on the definition of duty, but on the tendency to perfection." In Plato's Ethics, the passions are entirely set aside ; they PLATO'S ETHICS. *3i are regarded as disturbances in the moral economy. Virtue is purely a matter of Intelligence. And the Intellect has there- fore not only a regulative office, but the supreme direction of all action.* Now, as Chamfort admirably said, " the Philo- sopher who would set aside the passions, resembles a Chemist who would extinguish his fire." We are all aware that it is very common " to know the right, and yet the wrong pursue"; that the passions not only disturb the regulative action of Reason, but positively triumph over it ; and that morals are our mores, our habits, rather than our beliefs. The Ethics of Plato might suit the inhabitants of another world ; they are quite useless to the inhabitants of this. His Politics are his Ethics applied to the State ; and labour under the same errors. But his Utopian Government, the * Republic/ has had too much celebrity for us to neglect it. The ' Republic ' is unquestionably one of the most interest- ing of his works, and so slow has been the progress of social science, compared with every other science, that many of the ideas Plato has there put forth, are still entertained by very serious thinkers ; whereas his ideas on physics, metaphysics, or morals, would barely find a defender. The weakness of Man is the cause that States are formed. As he cannot suffice to himself, he must live in Society. This society should be an image of himself. The faculties which belong to him must find a proper field of activity in Society ; and this vast union of intellects should form but one intelligence. Thus man's virtues are, I. fpovrjais, wisdom; II. avSp«a, fortitude; III. o-wjtpoovvrj, temperance; IV. SiKaiotrvvrj, justice. The State, therefore, must have its Rulers, the philosophers, who will represent wisdom ; its soldiers, who will represent fortitude ; its craftsmen and burghers, who will represent tem- perance. Justice is a quality which must be shared by all classes, as lying at the root of all virtuous action. In wisdom and justice we have the alpha and omega of Plato's doctrine : justice is wisdom in act. The office of the Rulers is therefore to ordain such laws as will effectually prevent all injustice in the State. * We cannot interrupt our exposition with any examples ; they are too numerous. But we have added in the ' Appendix ' a passage respecting the misery of the unjust man, from the ' Gorgias.' In it Plato endeavours to prove that he who does an injury suffers more than he who endures it. — See* Note B.' s$2 PLATO'S ETHICS. Their first care will be to instil into the minds of the citizens, just notions respecting the deity. All those who attribute to the deity the passions and imperfections of men, must be banished: hence the famous banishment of the poets, of which so much has been said. This Law, pushed to its rigorous conclusions, is the Law of fanaticism. Whatever the Rulers believed respecting Religion, was to be the Religion of the State. Strange that a pupil of Socrates should have advocated a law, the operation of which caused his master's condemnation ! But there were other causes for the banishment of the Poets besides their fictions respecting the gods. They enervate the soul by pictures of immoderate desires : they give imitations of the vices and follies of men : they overstep the limits of that moderation which alone can balance the soul. Even the Musicians were partly banished ; those at least who were plaintive and harmonious. Only the Dorian and the Phrygian music could be admitted; the one, impetuous and warlike, the other calm. There is a germ of Stoicism in Plato, and that germ here bears its fruit. A measured equability of mind was the ideal of human happiness, and anything which interfered with it was denounced. Thus poetry and music. Thus also conjugal love. As the State could not subsist without children, children must be begotten. But parents are foolishly fond ; they are avaricious for their children ; ambitious for them. Husbands are also foolishly fond. To prevent these disturbances of good order, Plato ordains community of wives, and interdicts paren- tage. Women are to be chosen for marriage as brood mares are chosen. The violent women to be assorted to the mild men ; the mild to be assorted to violent men. But the chil- dren belong to the State. They are, therefore, to be consigned to the State Nurses, who will superintend their early education. As children manifest different capacities, and, as Plato thought with St. Simon, each citizen should be ranked according to his capacity, the State would undertake to decide to which class the young man should belong. But, if domestic life is thus at a blow sacrificed to the public good, do not imagine that women will lose their occupations. No : women must share with men the toils of war and agricul- ture. The female dog guards sheep as well as the male; why should not the women guard the State?" And, as some few PLATO'S ETHICS. J33 women manifest a capacity for philosophy, those few will share with men the Government. With community of wives and children, it is natural that community of property should be joined, and the reason is similar. Property is the great disturber of social life; it engenders crimes and luxuries, which are scarcely better than crimes. Property, therefore, must be abolished. The State alone has riches. In one word, the Family, no less than the individual, is sacrificed to the State ; the State itself being an Abstraction. Like the Utopists of modern days, he has developed an d priori theory of what the State should be, and by this theory all human feelings are to be neglected : instead of developing a theory d posteriori, i.e. from an investigation into the nature of human wants and feelings. By thus reducing the ' Republic ' to its theoretical formula, we are doubtless viewing it in its most unfavourable light Its value, and its interest, do not consist in its political ideas, but in its collateral ideas on education, religion, and morals. But these are beside our present purpose. In the * Laws,' many of the above notions are modified ; but the general theory is the same. Willingly would we discourse upon these two remarkable books at greater length ; but, although we have only touched on a few points connected with Plato, we have already exhausted the space we could afford ; and we must close here this imperfect account of one of the greatest minds of antiquity. If we have assigned him his due position in the history of human development — if we have in some sort presented the reader with a clue, whereby he may traverse the labyrinth of that celebrated, but ill-understood doctrine — if we have suc- ceeded in conveying some impression of the man, more con- sonant with truth, than that usually accredited, we have performed our task. Sbttantif) <8pocft. PHILOSOPHY AGAIN REDUCED TO A SYSTEM: CLOSE OF THE SOCRATIC MOVEMENT. ARISTOTLE. CHAPTER I. LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. When Plato was leaving Athens for the journey into Sicily, of which we have spoken, and which occupied him three years or more, Aristotle appeared in that active city, then an active, restless youth of seventeen ; rich both in money and in know- ledge, eager, impetuous, truth-loving, and insatiable in his thirst for philosophy. Tidings of the wondrous men who made that city illustrious, and whose fame still sheds a halo round its ruins, had reached him in his native land ; tidings of the great thinkers and the crowded schools had lured him, though so young, to Athens. Aristotle was born at Stagira, a colony in Thrace, Olympiad 99 (b.c. 384). His father Nicomachus was an eminent physi- cian, who had written several works on medicine and natural history ; so that Aristotle's love of such subjects may be called hereditary. Losing his parents at an early age, he was con- signed to the care of a certain Proxenus, who had him in- structed in all the physical knowledge of the time. Proxenus died, and Aristotle then fulfilled his desire of seeing Athens. During the three years of Plato's absence Aristotle was not idle. He prepared himself to be a worthy pupil. His wealth enabled him to purchase those costly luxuries, Books — for there was no cheap Literature in those days — and in them he studied the speculations of the early thinkers, with a zeal and intelligence of which his own writings bear ample evidence. UFE OF ARISTOTLE. 335 There were also some friends and followers of Socrates and Plato still at Athens ; men who had listened to the entrancing conversation of the "old man eloquent," who could still re- member with a smile his keen and playful irony ; and others who were acquainted with some of the deep thoughts brooding in the melancholy soul of Plato. These Aristotle eagerly questioned, and from them prepared himself to receive the lessons of his future teacher. Plato returned. His school was opened, and Aristotle joined the crowd of his disciples, amongst whom the penetrating glance of the master soon detected the immortal pupil. Plato saw that the impetuous youth needed the curb ; but there was promise of greatness in that very need. His restless activity was characterized by Plato in an epithet: "Aristotle is the Mind of my school." Aristotle continued to listen to Plato for twenty years ; that is, till the death of the latter. But he did not confine himself to the Platonic philosophy ; nor did he entirely agree with it. And from this disagreement has arisen the vulgar notion of a personal disagreement between Master and Pupil : a notion, to be sure, propped up with pretended anecdotes, and knocked down with others equally authentic. Much has been written on this quarrel, and on what people call Aristotle's ingratitude. We place no reliance on it ; the same thing was said of Plato with respect to Socrates, and we have excellent reasons for treating that as calumny. In his writings Aristotle \ doubtless combats the opinion of Plato; but he always mentions him with respect, sometimes with tenderness. If that be ingrati- tude, it is such as all pupils have manifested who have not been slavish followers. It was a wise thought of Macedonian Philip to give his son Alexander such a preceptor as Aristotle. For four years was the illustrious pupil instructed by the illustrious master in poetry, rhetoric, and philosophy; and, when Alexander de- parted on his Indian expedition, a scholar of Aristotle's, one Callisthenes, attended him. Both from Philip and from Alex- ander, the Stagyrite received munificent assistance in all his undertakings: especially in the collection of natural curiosities, which were selected from captured provinces, to form the materials of the ' History of Animals.' After a long interval Aristotle returned to Athens and opened a school in the Lyceum : a school which eclipsed all the others 236 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. both in numbers and importance. It is curiously illustrative of his restless vivacious temperament that he could not stand still and lecture, but delivered his opinions whilst walking up and down the shady paths of the Lyceum, attended by his eager followers. Hence his disciples were called the Walking Philo- sophers : Peripatetics. His lectures were of two kinds : scientific and popular : acroamatic or acroatie, and exoteric. The former were for the more advanced students, and those who were capable of pursuing scientific subjects ; he delivered these in the morn- ing. The latter were afternoon lectures to a much larger class, and treated of popular subjects : rhetoric, politics, and sophis- tics. Much learning and ingenuity has been thrown away in the endeavour to determine the precise nature of these two kinds of instruction ; but we cannot stop to notice it. Those who conclude that the distinction between the esoteric and exoteric was a distinction of doctrine seem to us in error ; the distinction was, as above stated, purely that of subject-matter. Dialectics and Poetics are not addressed to the same hearers. He spent a long and laborious life in the pursuit of know- ledge, and wrote an incredible number of works, about a fourth of which it is calculated are extant; the division, arrangement, and authenticity of which has long been a pet subject of con- tention amongst scholars ; but, as no agreement has yet been effected, we may leave the question as it stands. CHAPTER II. aristotle's method. Plato and Aristotle may be said to contain all the speculative philosophy of Greece : whoso knows them knows all that Greece had to teach. It is not our plan to draw comparisons between the greatness of two great men, otherwise these two would furnish a happy subject. We have endeavoured to point out in what way Plato advanced the science of his age. We have now to do the same by Aristotle. Aristotle was the most learned man of antiquity, but this learning did not enervate the vigour of his mind. He studi- ARISTOTLE'S METHOD, 23? ously sought, both in books and in external nature, for mate- rials wherewith to build a doctrine. Before laying down his own views he examines the views of his predecessors with tedious minuteness ; and his own opinions often seem rather brought out in his criticisms than dogmatically affirmed. Hence some have declared his Method to be the historical Method ; a misconception, not to be wondered at when we consider the abundance of historical evidence, and the absence of any express definition of his Method in his writings. Unlike Plato, Aristotle never mentions the nature of his method; but he has one, and we must detect it. We may expect to find it somewhat resembling that of his master, with some modifications of his own. It is so. Plato, as Van Heusde remarks, stands as a middle point between Socrates and Aristotle. The Method of Socrates was one of Investiga- tion ; that of Aristotle was one of Demonstration. The Defi^ nition and Induction of Socrates were powerful but vague ; the Syllogism of Aristotle rendered them powerful and precise. Plato, as it were, fills up the gap between these two thinkers ; by the addition of Analysis and Classification he reduced the Socratic Method to a more scientific form, and gave it precision. Where Plato left it Aristotle took it up ; and, by still further modifications, all of which had but one aim, *.*., greater precision, he gave it a solidity which enabled it to endure for centuries. Wherein did Plato and Aristotle fundamentally differ ? Until the time of Hegel the universal explanation of this difference was briefly to this effect : Plato is an Idealist, Aris- totle a Materialist ; the one a Rationalist, the other an Empiric : one trusting solely to Reason, the other solely to Experience. This explanation Hegel crushed by showing, that although Aristotle laid more stress upon experience than did Plato, yet he also expressly taught that Reason alone could form science. Let us, then, try if we can penetrate the real difference. And to do so, we must first ask, What was the fundamental position ot the Platonic doctrine ? That question our readers can readily answer : the theory of Ideas, whereby Dialectics became science. If here Aristotle be found to agree with his master, there can be no fundamental difference between them ; if here he be found to differ, we shall be able to deduce from it all other differences. In truth, Aristotle radically opposed the Ideal theory ; and 338 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD, the greater part of his criticisms on Plato are criticisms of that theory. He does not deny to Ideas a subjective existence : on the contrary, he makes them the materials of science ; but he is completely opposed to their objective existence, and calls them empty and poetical metaphors. He says, that on the supposition of Ideas being Existences and Models, there would be several Models for the same Thing ; since the same thing may be classed under several heads. Thus, Socrates may be classed under the Ideas of Socrates, of Man, of Animal, and of Biped; or Philosopher, General, and Statesman. The "stout Stagyrite" not only perceived the logical error of the Ideal theory, but also saw how the error originated. He profoundly remarked, that Ideas are nothing but productions of the Reason, separating, by a logical abstraction, the particular objects from those relations which are common to them all. Aristotle saw that Plato had mistaken a subjective distinction for an objective one ; had mistaken a relation which the understanding per- ceived between two objects for the evidence of a separate existence. The partisans of the theory of Ideas Aristotle likens to those who, having to enumerate the exact number of things, commence by increasing the number, as a way of simplifying the calculation. In this caustic illustration we may read his whole criticism. What, indeed, was the Ideal theory, but a multiplication of the number of Existences? Men had before imagined that things were great, and heavy, and black or brown. Plato separated the qualities of greatness, weight, and colour, and made these qualities new existences. Having disproved the notion of Ideas being Existences, — in other words, of General Terms being anything more than the expressions of the Relations of individual things, — Aristotle was driven to maintain that the Individual Things alone existed. But, if only individuals exist, only by sensation can they be known ; and, if we know them by sensation, how is the Universal, to kolOoXov, ever known — how do we get abstract ideas ? This question was the more pertinent because Science could only be a Science of the Universal, or (to use the language of Positive Science) a science of general truths. Aristotle admitted, with Plato, that there could be no " science of sensation," no science which was not founded on ideas ; and it was needful, therefore for him to show how such ideas could be obtained. ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. 339 Plato's solution of the problem we before exhibited ; it was the ingenious doctrine of the soul's reminiscence of a former apprehension of truth, awakened by the traces of Ideas which sensation discovered in Things. / This solution, of course, did not satisfy Aristotle. He, too, was aware that reminiscence was indispensable ; but reminis- cence of previous experience, not of an anterior state of existence in the world of Ideas. By sensation we perceive particular things ; by induction we perceive the general in the particular. - Sensation is the basis of all knowledge : but we have another faculty besides that of sensation ; we have Memory. Having perceived many things, we remember our sensations, and by that remembrance we are enabled to discern wherein things resemble and wherein they differ; and this Memory then becomes an art whereby a general conception is formed : this art is Induction. Man alone has this art. The distinction between Brutes and Men is, that the former, although they have Memory, have no Experience; that is to say, have not the art which converts Memory into Experience — the art of Induction. Man is a reasoning animal. That Aristotle meant Induction by the art of which he speaks as furnished by experience, may be proved by one luminous passage of the Metaphysics. " Art commences when, from a great number of Experiences, one general conception is formed which will embrace all similar cases." * And, lest there should be any misunderstanding of his definition, he proceeds to illus- trate it " Thus : if you know that a certain remedy has cured Callias of a certain disease, and that the same remedy has pro- duced the same effect on Socrates and on several other persons, that is Experience ; but to know that a certain remedy will cure all persons attacked with that disease is Art : for Experi- ence is the knowledge of individual things (t£>v KaOeKatrra) ; Art is that of Universals (iw kcl06\ov)." " That strain I heard was of a higher mood ! ** The commencement of Positive Science — the awakening to an appreciation of the nature and processes of science, lies in that passage. In the Socratic conception of Induction we saw little more than Analogical Reasoning ; but in this Aristotelian * yivtrat di Ti% vr l orav t/c woXAa-v r^y ifAirtioiag ivvonparw kclB6\ow jita yivqrai rtpi *i>v bfioiuv iw 6\i)\pi<;. — 'Met.,' i. I. 340 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. conception we see the Collection of Instances, and the generali- zation from those Instances which Positive Science claims as its Method. Nor was this a random guess of the old Stagy- rite's : it was the logical deduction from his premisses respecting knowledge. Hear him again : " Experience furnishes the principles of every science. Thus Astronomy is grounded on observation ; for, if we were properly to observe the celestial phenomena, we might demonstrate the laws which regulate them. The same applies to other sciences. If we omit nothing that observation can afford us respecting phenomena, we could easily furnish the demonstration of all that admits of being de- monstrated, and illustrate that which is not susceptible of demonstration." * And, in another place, when abandoned in his investigation by phenomena, he will not hazard an assertion. " We must wait," he says, " for further phenomena, since phenomena are more to be trusted than the conclusion of reason." Had he always steadily held before his eyes this conception of Science, had he always been the Empiric which Germans so contemptuously call him, he would have anticipated Bacon — he would have been the father of Positive Science. But it was precisely because he did not — and, indeed, in that age could not — confine himself to Experience and the generalizations of Experience, that he could not effectually carry out his own scheme. His conception of Method was certainly a just one; but the application of such a Method could have led him only a short way, because there was not sufficient Experience then accumulated from which to generalize with any effect. Hence Aristotle's speculations are not always carried on upon the Method which he himself laid down. Impatient at the insufficiency of facts, he jumps to a conclusion. Eager, as all men are, to solve the problems which present themselves, he solved them d priori. He applied his Syllogism before he had ascertained the exactitude of his premisses. But the radical defect in his Philosophy is the notion that science can penetrate the mystery of existence. This made him en- deavour to create a metaphysical system ; and this metaphysical system is a sufficient disproof of the vulgar notion of his being a mere Experimentalist, an Empiric. The distinction between Aristotle and Plato is, that while • * Analy. Prior./ i. c. 30. ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC. S41 both admitted science only could be formed from Universals, Ta icdOoXov, Aristotle contended that such Universals had purely a subjective existence, i.e. t that they were nothing more than the inductions derived from particular facts. He, there- fore, made Experience the basis of all Science, and Reason the Architect. Plato made Reason the basis. The tendency of the one was to direct man to the observation and interrogation of Nature ; that of the other was to direct man to the contem- plation of ideas. The distinction between Aristotle and Bacon is, that while they both insist upon the observation and generalization of facts, as alone capable of furnishing correct ideas, Aristotle believed that he could observe those primary facts of Existence and Cause, which Bacon wisely declared beyond the human ken. While both insisted on the necessity of experience, while both saw that the science of the general must be framed from the inductions of the particular, they differed profoundly as to the nature of that * general.' Bacon endeavoured in particular facts to trace the general laws ; Aristotle endeavoured in par- ticular facts to trace the general ideas. To understand this, we must cast a glance at Aristotle's Logic, CHAPTER HI. aristotle's logic. It is often remarked that Aristotle's use of the word Dialectics differs from Plato's use of it. Indeed, with Plato, dialectics was the science of Being ; with Aristotle, it was no more than the instrument of Thought. But it is highly necessary that we should clearly understand the position occupied by Logic in the Aristotelian philosophy ; the more so as after ages have prized the Logic above all his other works. Logic is the science of Affirmation ; Affirmation is the active operation of the mind on that which sensation has presented to it ; in other words, Affirmation is Thought. Affirmations may be true or false : there can be no falsehood in Sensation. If a 4 3 Ak)STOTL&S LOGIC. you have a sensation of an object, it must be a true sensation . but you may affirm something false of it. Every single thought is true ; but, when you connect two thoughts together, that is when you affirm something of another thing, you may affirm that which is false. Everything therefore that you think about may be reduced to a Proposition ; in fact, your thoughts are a series of Proposi- tions. To understand the whole nature of Propositions — to understand the whole Art of Thinking— is the province of Logic. By a very natural confusion, Aristotle, thus convinced of the importance of language, was led to maintain that truth or false- hood did not depend upon things but upon words, or rather upon combinations of words — upon Propositions. Logic therefore to him, as to Plato, though in a different way, became the real Organon of Science. But, as John Mill remarks, " the distinc- tion between real and nominal definitions, between definitions of words and what are called definitions of things, though con- formable to the ideas of most Aristotelian logicians, cannot, as it appears to us, be maintained. We apprehend that no defini- tion is ever intended to explain and unfold the nature of the thing. It is some confirmation of our opinion that none of those writers who have thought that there were definitions of things have ever succeeded in discovering any criterion by which the definition of a thing can be distinguished from any other proposition relating to that thing. The definition they say unfolds the nature of the thing : but no definition can unfold its whole nature : and every proposition in which any quality whatever is predicated of the thing unfolds some part of its nature. The true state of the case we take to be this : All definitions are of names and of names only ; but, in some definitions, it is clearly apparent that nothing is intended except to explain the meaning of the word ; while, in others, besides explaining the meaning of the word, it is intended to be implied that there exists a thing corresponding to the word. Whether this be or be not implied in any given case, cannot be collected from the mere form of expression. ■ A centaur is an animal with the upper parts of a man and the lower parts of a horse ' and * a triangle is a rectilineal figure with three sides ' are, in form, expressions precisely similar; although, in the former, it is not implied that any ^/^conformable to the term really exists, while in the latter it is • as mav be seen by substituting, in both ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC 243 definitions, the word means for is. In the first expression, 'a centaur means an animal,' &c, the sense would remain unchanged : in the second ' a triangle means,' &c, the meaning would be altered since it would be obviously impossible to deduce any of the truths of geometry from a proposition expressive only of the manner in which we intend to employ a particular sign. " There are, therefore, expressions commonly passing for definitions which include in themselves more than the mere explanation of the meaning of the term. But it is not correct to call an expression of this sort, a peculiar kind of definition. Its difference from the other kind consists in this, that it is not a definition, but a definition and something more. The defini- tion given above of a triangle, obviously comprises not one, but two propositions, perfectly distinguishable. The one is, 1 There may exist a figure bounded by three straight lines : ' the other, ' and this figure may be termed a triangle.' The former of these propositions is not a definition at all : the latter is a mere nominal definition or explanation of the use and application of a term. The first is susceptible of truth or false- hood, and may therefore be made the foundation of a train of reasoning. The latter can neither be true nor false : the only character it is susceptible of is that of conformity or discon- formity to the ordinary usage of language. "There is a real distinction, then, between definitions of names and what are erroneously called definitions of things ; but it is that ;the latter, along with the meaning of a name, covertly asserts a matter of fact. This covert assertion is not a definition, but a postulate. The definition is a mere identical proposition, which gives information only about the use of language, and from which no conclusions respecting matters of fact can possibly be drawn. The accompanying postulate on the other hand, affirms a fact which may lead to consequences of every degree of importance. It affirms the real existence of things, possessing the combination of attributes set forth in the definition ; and this, if true, may be foundation sufficient to build a whole fabric of scientific truth."* This profound and luminous distinction was not seen by Aristotle, and his whole system was vitiated in consequence of the oversight. He thought that Logic was not only the Instru- ment of Thought, but, as such, the Instrument of investigating • « System of Lo^ic' vol. i. pp. 195-7. t44 ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC, Causes. In his Logic the first place was occupied by the cele- brated Categories. They are ten in number, and as follows : — oicria Substance. irooov Quantity. iroiov Quality. irpoQ n . • . . . . Relation. iroitiv Action. icaavriKof sense-experience, and at variance with his Method; but, as we before observed, the rigorous application of his Method was barely possible ; and, however excellent as a precept, it was so vague as to be almost inevitably vitiated in practice. The process of vitiation was this. Experience was necessary, as affording the materials for Reason to work with. Any rea- soning not founded on a knowledge of phenomena must be false ; but it by no means follows, that all reasoning founded on a knowledge of phenomena will be true. Here was Aristotle's mistake. He thought that Experience could not deceive. But, to make his Method perfect, he should have laid down the rules for testing that Experience — for "interrogating" Nature — for the discrimination of what was pertinent to the question in hand — for establishing a proper " experimentum cruets. 1 ' Thus " facts," as they are called, are notoriously valuable in proportion only to the value of the theory upon which they have been collected. People talk of " facts " as if facts were to produce irresistible convictions. The truth is, they are sus- ceptible of almost any explanation ; and, in the history of science, we do not find the facts, but the theories, changing; ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. a 49 that is to say, Nature has preserved one uniform course, her ordinary operations are open to all men's inspection ; and men have endeavoured to explain these operations in an endless variety of ways. Now, from a want of a proper knowledge of the conditions of Scientific inquiry, Aristotle's Method became fruitless. The facts collected were vitiated by a false theory ; his sense- experience was wrongly interpreted. It is time, however, to give his solution of the great meta- physical problem of Existence. Matter, he said, exists in a threefold form. It is, I. Sub- stance, perceptible by the senses, which is finite and perishable. This Substance is either the abstract substance, or the sub- stance connected with form, elSos. II. The higher Substance, which, though perceived by the senses, is imperishable ; such as are the heavenly bodies. Here the active principle (eve'pycia, actus) steps in, which, in so far as it contains that which is to be produced, is understanding (vovs). That which it con- tains is the purpose (to ov eve/ca), which purpose is realized in the act. Here we have the two extremes of potentiality and agency, matter and thought The often-mentioned entelechie is the relation between these two extremes — it is the point of transition between SJva/us and cvepyaa; and is accordingly the Cause of Motion, or Efficient Cause, and represents the Soul. III. The third form of Substance is that in which the three forms of power, efficient cause, and effect are united ; the Absolute Substance ; eternal unmoved ; God himself. God, as the Absolute Unmoved Eternal Substance, is Thought. The Universe is a thought in the mind of God. It is " God passing into activity, but not exhausted in the Act." Existence, then, is Thought : it is the activity of the Divine Reason. In Man the thought of the Divine Reason completes itself so as to become self-conscious. By it he recognises in the ob- jective world his own nature again ; for thought is the thinking of thought — Zarnv rf varjcris, vorjcrews, v6y] But from all these masters he could gain no solid convic tions; they gave him hints ; they could not give him Truth ; and, working upon the materials they furnishea, he produced a system of his own, by which we presume he justified his claim to being self-taught His early years were agitated and unsettled. He visited Athens at eighteen, but remained there only one year. He then passed to Colophon, Mitylene, and Lampsacus. He returned to Athens in his six-and-thirtieth year, and there opened a school, over which he presided till his death, Olymp. 127. The place he chose for his school was the famous Garden, a spot pleasantly typical of his doctrine. The Platonists had their Academic Grove ; the Aristotelians walked along the Lyceum ; the Cynics occupied the Cynosarges : the Stoics occupied the Porch ; and the Epicureans had their Garden. Here, in the tranquil Garden, in the society of his friends, he passed a peaceful life of speculation and enjoyment. The friendship which existed amongst them is well known. In a time of general scarcity and famine, they contributed to each other's support, showing that the Pythagorean notion of com- munity of goods was unnecessary among friends, who could confide in each other. At the entrance of the Garden they placed this inscription : "The hospitable keeper of this mansion, where you will find pleasure the highest good, will present you liberally with barley cakes and water fresh from the spring. The gardens will not provoke your appetite by artificial dainties, but satisfy it with natural supplies. Will you not be well entertained ?" The Garden has often been called a sty ; and the name of Epicurean has become the designation of a sensualist. But, in spite of his numerous assailants, the character of Epicurus has been rescued from contempt both by ancient and by modern critics. Diogenes Laertius, who gives some of the accusations in detail, easily refutes them by an appeal to facts ; and the modern writers have easily penetrated the motive of the ancient calumnies, which mostly proceeded from the Stoics. A doctrine like that of Epicurus would, at all times, lend itself to gross misrepresentation ; but, in an epoch like that in which it appeared, and contrasted with a doctrine so furiously opposed to it as that of the Stoics, we cannot wonder if the bitterness of opposition translated itaelf into bitter Sfe THE EPICUREANS. calumny. It is one of the commonest results of speculative differences to make you attribute to your opponent's opinions the consequences which you deduce from them, as if they were indubitably the consequences he deduces for himself. Your opinions are conducive to sound morality ; of that you are convinced ; and, being so convinced, it is natural for you to believe that contrary opinions must be immoral. Your opponent holds contrary, ergo, immoral opinions ; and you proclaim his imn orality as an unquestionable fact. In this, however, there s a slight forgetfulness ; viz., that your opponent occupies exactly similar ground, and what you think of him he thinks of you. The Stoics had an ineffable contempt for the weakness and effeminacy of the Epicureans. The Epicureans had an in- effable contempt for the spasmodic rigidity and unnatural exaggeration of the Stoics. That they mutually libelled each other follows of course ; but the libels against the Epicureans have met with more general credit than those against the Stoics, from the more imposing character of the latter, both in their actions and doctrines. Epicurus is said to have been the most voluminous of all Greek Philosophers, except Chrysippus ; and, although none of these works are extant, yet so many fragments are preserved here and there, and such ample testimony as to his opinions, that there are few writers of whose doctrine we can speak with greater certainty, the more so as it does not in itself present any difficulties of comprehension. t^k\ Nothing can be more unlike Plato and Aristotle than Epicurus; and this difference may be characterized at the mtset by their fundamental difference in the conception of ?hilosophy, which Epicurus regarded as the Art of Life, and not the Art of Truth. Philosophy, he said, was that power (ivipytuC) by which Reason conducted man to happiness.* The investigations of science he despised, because not only were they uncertain, but contributed nothing towards happi- ness ; and, of course, Logic, the instrument of science, found no favour in his sight. His philosophy was, therefore, only another form of Scepticism, consequent on mental dissatis- faction at previous inquiries. Socrates had taught men to * rfvot \6yoiq cat £ta\oyi* that he asked where such men were to be met with. At that moment Crates the Cynic passed by : the bookseller pointed him out to Zeno, and bade him follow Crates. He did so ; and became a disciple. But he could not long remain a disciple. The gross manners of the Cynics, so far removed from true simplicity, and their speculative incapacity soon caused him to seek a master elsewhere. Stilpo, of Megara, became his next instructor ; and from him he learned the art of disputation which he subse- quently practised with such success. But the Megaric doctrine was too meagre for him. He was glad to learn from Stilpo ; but there were things which Stilpo could not teach. He turned, therefore, to the expositors of Plato : Xenocrates and Polemo. In the Philosophy of Plato there is, as before remarked, a germ of stoicism ; but there is also much that contradicts stoicism, and so, we presume, Zeno grew discontented with that also. After twenty years of laborious study in these various schools he opened one for himself, wherein to teach the result of all these inquiries. The spot chosen was the Stoa, or Porch varie- gated with the pictures of Polygnotus, and which had once been the resort of the Poets. From this Stoa the school derived its name. As a man, Zeno appears deserving of the highest respect. Although sharing the doctrines of the Cynics he did not share their grossness, their insolence, or their affectation. In person he was tall and slender, and of weakly constitution. But he lived to a great age, because he was rigidly abstemious : living upon figs, bread, and honey. His brow was furrowed with thought, and this gave a tinge of severity to his aspect, which accorded with the austerity of his doctrines. So honoured and respected was he by the Athenians that they entrusted to him the keys of the citadel ; and when he died they erected to his memory a statue of brass. His death is thus recorded : In his ninety-eighth year, as he was stepping out of his school, he fell and broke his finger. He was so affected at the consciousness of his infirmity that, striking the earth he exclaimed : " Why am I thus importuned ? Earth, I obey thy summons ! " He went home and strangled himself Let us now bestow our attention on his doctrines. In the history of humanity there are periods when society seems fast dissolving ; when ancient creeds have f lost theii «*> THE STOICS. majesty, and new doctrines want sincerity : when the onlookei sees the fabric tottering, beneath which his fellow-men are crowded either in sullen despair or in blaspheming levity, and, seeing this, he feels that there is safety still possible, if men will but be bold. He raises a voice of warning, and a voice of exhortation ; he bids them behold their peril and tremble, behold their salvation and resolve. He preaches to them a doctrine they may have been unused to hear, or, hearing it, unused to heed ; and by the mere force of his own intense con- viction he gathers round him some believers who are saved. If the social anarchy be not too widely spread, he saves his country by directing its energies in a new channel ; if the coun- try's doom is sealed, he makes a gallant effort, though a vain one, and " leaves a spotless name to after-times." Such a man was Zeno. Greece was fallen ; but hope still remained. A wide-spread disease was fast eating out the vigour of its life : Scepticism, Indifference, Sensuality, Epicurean softness were the reigning doctrines, only counteracted by the magnificent but vague works of Plato, or the vast but abstruse system of Aristotle. All Greek civilization was fast falling to decay. A little time and Rome, the she-wolfs nursling, would usurp the place which Greece had once so proudly held — the place of vanguard of European civilization. Rome, the mighty, would take from the feeble hands of Greece, the trust she was no longer worthy to hold. There was a pres sentiment of Rome in Zeno's breast In him the manly energy and stern sim- plicity which was to conquer the world ; in him the deep rever- ence for moral worth, which was the glory of Rome before, intoxicated with success, she sought to ape the literary and philosophical glory of old Hellas. Zeno the Stoic had a Roman spirit; and this is the reason why so many noble Romans became his disciples ; he had deciphered the wants of their spiritual nature. Alarmed at the scepticism which seemed inevitably following speculations of a metaphysical kind, Zeno, like Epicurus, fixed his thoughts principally upon Morals. His philosophy boasted of being eminently practical and connected with the daily practices of life. But, for this purpose, the philosopher must not regard Pleasure so much as Virtue : and this Virtue does not consist in a life of contemplation and speculation, but in a life of activity ; for what is Virtue ? — Virtue is manhood. And what are the attributes of man ? Are they not obviously THE STOICS. i&j the attributes of an active as well as of a speculative being? and can that be Virtue which excludes or neglects man's activity? Man, Plato, and O Aristotle, was not made only to speculate : wisdom is not his only pursuit. Man, O Epicurus, was not made only to enjoy : he was made also to do somewhat, and to be somewhat. Science ? — It is a great thing, but it is not alL Pleasure ? — It is a slight thing, and, were it greater, could not embrace man's entire activity. The aim, then, of man's existence is neither to be wise nor to enjoy, but to be Virtuous — to realize his manhood. To this aim, Science is a means, and Pleasure may be also one : but they are both subordinate. But before we can t c taught to lead a Virtuous life, we must be taught what Virtue '$. Zeno thought, with Socrates, that Virtue wa s the Science of Good : and that Vice was. nothing but error. If to know the good were tantamount to the pur- suit and practice of it, then was the teacher's task easily defined : he had to explain the nature of human knowledge, and to explain the relations of man to the universe. Thus, as with Socrates, does Morality find itself inseparably connected with Science ; and more especially with psychology. A brief outline of this psychology becomes, therefore, necessary as an introduction to the stoical Morality. Zeno utterly rejected the Platonic theory of knowledge, and accepted, . though with some modifications, the Aristotelian theory. 'Reminiscence" and "Ideas" were to him mere words. Ideas he regarded but as the universal notions formed by the mind from a comparison of particulars. Sense furnished all the materials of knowledge : Reason was the plastic instru- ment whereby these materials were fashioned. But those who maintain that Sense furnishes us the materials of knowledge are hampered with this difficulty, — By what process does sense perceive ? What relation is there bet wee. i Sense and the sensible Thing ? What proof have we of those sensations being comformable with the Things ? This difficulty is a serious one, and early occupied specu- lators, as we have already shown. Indeed, this question may be pronounced the vital question of all philosophy: upon its solution depends to a great extent the solution of all other questions. Let us state it more clearly in an illustration. At the distance of fifty yards you descry a tower : it is round. What do you mean by saying it is round ? You mean that the a** the stoics. impression made upon your sense of sight is an impression similar to that made by some other objects, such as trees, which you, and all men call round. Now, on the supposition that you never approached nearer to that tower, you would always believe it to be round, because it appeared so. But, as you are enabled to approach it, and as you then find that the tower is square, and not round, you begin to examine into this difference. It appeared round at that distance; and yet you say it really is square. A little knowledge of optics seems to explain the difference ; but does not. At fifty yards, you say, it appears round; but it really is square. At fifty yards, we reply, it appears round, and at one yard it appears square : it is neither : both round and square are conceptions of the mind, not attri- butes of things : they have a subjective, not an objective exist- ence. Thus far the ancient sceptics penetrated ; but, seeing herein an utter destruction of all certainty in sense-knowledge, and compelled to admit that Sense was the only source of our knowledge, they declared all knowledge a deceit. The per- ception of the real issue whence to escape this dilemma — the recognition of the uncertainty of sense-knowledge, and the reconciliation of that theory with the natural wants of the specu- lative mind — reconciling scepticism with belief, and both with reason, was the work of after-times. Those who believed that the senses gave true reports of the Things which affected them, were driven to invent some hypo- thesis explanatory of the relation subsisting between the Object and the Subject, the thing and the Sense. We have seen how eidola, airy Images affluent from Things, were invented to choke up the gap, and to establish a direct connection between the Subject and the Object. Zeno, acutely enough, saw that an image detaching itself in an airy form from the Object, could only represent the super- fices of that Object, even if it represented it correctly. In this way the hypothesis was shown to be no more than an hypo- thesis to explain Appearances ; whereas the real question is not " How do we perceive Appearances ? " but, " How do we perceive Objects?" If we only perceive their superfices, our knowledge is only a knowledge of phenomena, and we fall into the hands of the sceptics. Zeno saw the extent of the difficulty, and tried to obviate it. Bui his hypothesis, though more comprehensive, was as com- THE STOICS. 269 pletely without foundation. He assumed that Sense could penetrate beneath Appearance, and perceive Substance itself. As considerable confusion exists on this point in the ordi- nary historians, we shall confine ourselves to the testimony oi Sextus Empiricus ; to us the most satisfactory of alL In his 7th Book— that, namely, directed against the Logicians* — he tells us, the Stoics held that there was one criterium of truth for man, and it was what they called the Cataleptic Phantasm (ttjv KaTaXypmKrjv avraaiav : i.e. the Sen- suous Apprehension). We must first understand what they meant by the Phantasm or Appearance. It was, they said an impression on the mind (rvirwris cv ijn>x*))' But from this point commence their differences ; for Cleanthus understood, by this impression, an impression similar to that made by the signet- ring upon wax, tov K-qpov tvttwo-iv. Chrysippus thought this absurd ; for, said he, seeing that thought conceives many objects at the same time, the soul must upon that hypothesis receive many impressions of figures. He thought that Zeno meant by impression nothing more than a modification (crepoiuio-is). Comparing the soul to the air, which, when many voices sound simultaneously, receives simultaneously the various alterations, but without confounding them. Thus the Soul unites several perceptions which correspond with their several objects. This is extremely ingenious. Indeed, distinguishing thus Sensation as a modification of the soul, is opening a shaft deep down into the dark region of psychology. But, if it lets in some of the light of day, it also brings into notice a new obstacle. This soul, which is modified, does it not also in its turn exercise an influence ? If you pour wine into water, you modify the water ; but you also modify the wine. There can be no action without reaction. If a stone is presented to my sight, it modifies my soul ; but does the stone remain unmodified ? — No; it receives from me certain attributes, certain form, colour, taste, weight, &c, which my soul bestows on it, which it does not possess in itself. Thus is doubt again spread over the whole question. The soul modifying the object in sensation, can it rely upon the truth of the sensation thus produced? Has not the wine become watery, no less than the water vinous ? These conse- quences, however, Zeno did not foresee. He was intent upon • Pp. i° T ^$ of Henry Stephen's edition. 2?o THE STOICS. proving that the soul really apprehended objects, not as eidola, not as the wax receives the impression of a seal, but in absolute truth. Let us continue to borrow from Sextus. The Phantasm, or Appearance, which causes the modifica- tion of the Soul which we name Sensation, is also understood by the Stoics as we understand ideas ; and in this general sense, they said that there were three Kinds of Phantasms : those that were probable, those that were improbable, and those that were neither one nor the other. The first are those that cause a slight and equable motion in the soul : such as those which inform us that it is day. The second are those which contra- dict our reason, such as if one were to say during the day-time: ,a Now the sun is not above the earth," or, during the night- time : " Now it is day." The third are those, the truth of which it is impossible to verify, such as this : " The number of the stars is even " ; or, " the number is odd." Phantasms, when probable, are true, or false, or both true and false at the same time, or neither true nor false. They are true when they can be truly affirmed of anything ; false if they are wrongly affirmed, such as when one believes an oar dipped in the water to be broken, because it appears so. When Orestes, in his madness, mistook Electra for a Fury, he had a Phantasm both true and false ; true, inasmuch as he saw something, viz. Electra ; false, inasmuch as Electra was not a Fury. Of true Phantasms, some are Apprehensive (cataleptic,) and others non-cataleptic. The latter are such as arise from disease or perturbation of the mind; for innumerable Phan- tasms are produced in phrenzy and hypochondria ; but these are all non-cataleptic. The cataleptic Phantasm is that which is impressed by an object which exists, which is a copy of that object, and can be produced by no other object. Perception is, elsewhere, said to be a sort of light, which manifests itself at the same time that it lights up the object from which it is derived. From the foregoing exposition may be seen how easy the task of criticism is compared to that of invention. Zeno dis- tinctly saw the weakness of the* theories proposed by others ; he failed, however, in establishing any better theory in their place. Sextus Empiricus may well call the Stoical doctrine vague and undecided. Can anything be more removed from scientific precision than the above theory ? How are we tQ THE STOICS. •?■ distinguish the true from the false in appearances ? Above all, how are we to learn whether an impression exactly coin- cides with the supposed object? This is the main problem, and Zeno pretends to solve it by a most circular argument. Thus : given the problem, How are we to distinguish the true impressions from the false impressions ? The solution offered is, — By ascertaining which of the impressions coincide with the real objects ; in other words, By distinguishing the true impressions from the false ? Such is metaphysics. Let us continue our exposition. Having a perception of an object is not knowledge ; for knowledge, it is necessary that reason should assent Perception comes from without ; assent from within : it is the free exercise of man's reason. Science is composed of perceptions so solidly established that no argumentation can shake them. Perceptions not thus estab- lished only constitute Opinion. This is making short work with difficulties, it must be con- fessed \ but the Stoics were eager to oppose something against :he Scepticism which characterized the age, and, in their eagerness to build, they did not sufficiently secure their foun- dations. Universal doubt they felt to be impossible. Man must occasionally assent, and that too in a constant and absolute manner. There are perceptions which carry with them irresistible conviction. There would be no possibility of action unless there were some certain truth. Where, then, is conviction to stop ? That all our perceptions are not correct every one is willing to admit. But which are exact and which are inexact? What criterium have we? The criterium we possess is Evidence. Nothing can be clearer than evidence, they said ; and, being so clear, it needs no definition. This was precisely what it did want; but the Stoics could not give it. In truth, the Stoics, combating the scepticism of their age, were reduced to the same strait as Reid, Beattie, and Hutcheson, combating the Scepticism of Hume : reduced to give up Philosophy, and to find refuge in Common Sense. The battle fought by the Stoics is very analogous to the battle fought by the Scotch philosophers, in the ground occupied, in the instruments employed, and in the enemy attacked, and the object to be gained. They both fought for Morality, which they thought endangered. 37? THE STOICS. We shall subsequently have to consider the Common-Sense theory; enough if we now call attention to the curious ignoratio elenchi — the curious misconception of the real force of the enemy, and the utter helplessness of their own position, which the Common-Sense philosophers display. The Sceptics had made an irresistible onslaught upon the two fortresses of philosophy, — Perception and Reason. They showed Percep- tion to be based upon Appearance, and Appearance to be only Appearance, not Certainty. They showed, also, that Reason was unable to distinguish between Appearance and Certainty, because, in the first place, it had nothing but Phenomena (Appearances) to build upon ; and, in the second place, because we have no criterium to apply to Reason itself. Having gained this victory, they proclaimed Philosophy no longer existent. Whereupon the Stoics valorously rise, and, taking their stand upon Common Sense, believe they rout the forces of the Sceptics ; believe they retake the lost fortresses by declaring that Perceptions are true as well as false, and that you may distinguish the true from the false, by — distinguishing them; and Reason has its criterium in Evidence, which requires no criterium ; it is so clear. This seems to us pretty much the same as if the French were to invade England ; possess themselves of London, Edinburgh, and Dublin, declare England the subject of France, and it was then supposed that they were to be driven home again by a party of volunteers taking their stand upon Hampstead Heath, displaying the banners of England, and with loud alarums proclaiming the French defeated ! But it is time to consider the Ethical doctrines of the Stoics , and to do this effectually we must glance at their conception of the Deity. There are two elements in Nature. The first is v\r) irgwrr^ or primordial matter ; the passive element from which things are formed. The second is the active element, which forms things out of matter : Reason, Destiny (iifiapneirr)), God. The divine Reason operating upon matter bestows upon it the laws which govern it, laws which the Stoics called \6yoi (rn-€pfutTLKoi i or productive causes. God is the Reason of the world. With this speculative doctrine it is easy to connect theTr practical doctrine. Their Ethics are easily to be deduced irom their theology. If Reason is the £reat creative law, tp THE STOICS. 273 live conformably with Reason must be the practical moral law. If the universe be subject to a general law, every part of that universe must also be duly subordinate to it The conse- quence is clear : there is but one formula for Morals, and that is, ** Live harmoniously with Nature," o/^oAoyo/xcVw? -nj vf our human organization to be susceptible of pain, it is only affectation to conceal the expression of that pain. Could silence stifle pain, it were well ; but to stifle the cry is not to stifle the feeling: and to have a feeling, yet affect not to have it, is pitiful. The Savage soon learns that philosophy ; but the civilized man is superior to it You receive a blow, and you do not wince ; so does a stone. You are face to face with Death, and you have no regrets ; then you are unworthy oi life. As a reaction against effeminacy, Stoicism may be applauded ; as a doctrine, it is miserably one-sided. It ends in apathy and egotism. Apathy, indeed, was considered by the Stoics as the highest condition of Humanity ; whereas, in truth, it is thelowest. It leads, also, to gross immorality and to unseemly extrava- gances. Declaring Reason to be the only true regulator of our actions, and, deducing from that the natural consequence of all actions being either conformable or non-conformable with Reason, they arrived at some curious conclusions. Thus, all actions conformable with Reason are good ; and not only all good, but all equally so. In like manner, all acticns not con- formable with Reason are bad, and all equally bad. The absurdities which this doctrine led them into are innumerable ; enough if we mention that one gravely repeated by Perseus, that to move your little finger without a reasonable motive is a crime equal to killing a man, since both are non-conformable with Reason. There is great difficulty in crediting such extrava- gances, but really there seems no limit to systematic errors. THE NEW ACADEMY. a 75 CHAPTER IV. THE NEW ACADEMY : ARCESILAUS AND CARNEADES. The New Academy would solicit our attention, were it only for the celebrity bestowed on it by Cicero and Horace ; but it has other and higher points of interest than those of literary curiosity. The combat of which it was the theatre was, and is, of singular importance. The questions connected with it are those vital questions respecting the origin and certitude of human knowledge which so long have occupied the ingenuity of thinkers, and the consequences which flow from either solu- tion of the problem are of the utmost importance. The Stoics, as we have seen, endeavoured to establish the certitude of human knowledge, in order that they might estab lish the truth of moral principles. They attacked the doctrines of the Sceptics, and believed they triumphed by bringing forward their own doctrine of Common Sense. But the New Academicians had other arguments to offer. They too were Sceptics, although their scepticism differed from that of the Pyrrhonists. The nature of this difference Sextus Empiricus has noted. " Many persons," says he, u confound the Philosophy of the Academy with that of the Sceptics. But, although the disciples of the New Academy declare that all things are incomprehen- sible ; yet they are distinguished from the Pyrrhonists in this very dogmatism : they affirm that all things are incomprehen- sible — the Sceptics do not affirm that. Moreover, the Sceptics consider all perceptions perfectly equal as to the faithfulness of their testimony ; the Academicians distinguish between pro- bable and improbable perceptions : the first they class under various heads. There are some, they say, which are merely probable, others which are also confirmed by reflection, others which are subject to no doubt u Assent is of two kinds. Simple assent which the mind yields without repugnance as without desire, such as that of a child following its master ; and the assent which follows upon conviction and reflection. The Sceptics admitted the former kind ; the Academicians the latter." These differences are of no great moment ; but in the history of sects we find the smallest variation invested with a degree * 76 THE NEW ACADEMY: of importance; and we can understand the pertinacity with which the Academicians distinguished themselves from the Sceptics even on such slight grounds as the above. In treating of the Academicians we are forced to follow the plan pursued with the Sceptics, viz., to consider the doctrines of the whole sect, rather than to particularize the share of each individual member. The Middle Academy and the New Academy we thus unite in one ; although the ancients drew a distinction between them, it is difficult for moderns to do so. Arcesilaus and Carneades, therefore, shall be our types. Arcesilaus was born at Pitane in 116 Olymp. He was early taught mathematics and rhetoric, became the pupil of Theo- phrastus, afterwards of Aristotle, and finally of Polemo the Platonist. In this last school he was contemporary with Zeno, and probably there began that antagonism which was so re- markable in their subsequent career. On the death of Crates, Arcesilaus filled the Academic chair, and filled it with great ability and success. His fascinating manners won him general regard. Hs was learned and sweet-tempered, and generous to a fault. Visiting a sick friend, who, he saw, was suffering from privation, he slipped, unobserved, a purse of gold underneath the sick man's pillow. When the attendant discovered it, the man said with a smile : " This is one of Arcesilaus's generous frauds." He was of a somewhat luxurious temper, but he lived till the age of seventy-five, when he killed himself by hard drinking. Carneades, the most illustrious of the Academicians, was born at Cyrene, in Africa, 141 Olymp. He was a pupil of Diogenes the Stoic, who taught him the subtleties of disputa- tion. This made him sometimes exclaim in the course of a debate : " If I have reasoned rightly, I have gained my point ; if not, let Diogenes return me the mina I paid him for his lessons." On leaving Diogenes he became the pupil of Hege- sinus, who then held the Academic chair; by him he was instructed in the sceptical principles of the Academy, and on his death he succeeded to his chair. He also diligently studied the voluminous writings of Chrysippus. These were of great value to him as exercising his subtlety, and trying the temper of his own metal. He owed so much to this opponent that he used to say : " Had there not been a Chrysippus, I should not be what I am," a sentiment very easy of explanation. There are two kind'', of writers : Those who directly instruct us in ARCBSTLAUS AND CARNEADES. tjj sound knowledge, and those who indirectly lead us to the truth by the very opposition they raise against their own views. Next to exact knowledge, there is nothing so instructive as exact error : an error clearly stated, and presented to you in somewhat the same way as it at first presented itself to the mind that now upholds it, by enabling you to see not only that it is an error, but by what process it was deduced from its pre- misses, is among the most valuable modes of instruction. It is better than direct instruction; better, because the learner's mind is called into full activity, and apprehends the truth for itself, instead of passively assenting to it Carneades was justified in his praise of Chrysippus. He felt how much he owed to his antagonist. He felt that to him he owed a clear conception of the Stoical Error, and a clear con- viction of the truth of the Academic doctrine ; and owed also no inconsiderable portion of that readiness and subtlety which marked him out amongst his countrymen as a fitting Ambas- sador to send to Rome. Carneades in Rome — Scepticism in the Stoic city — presents an interesting picture. The Romans crowded round him, fascinated by his subtlety and eloquence. Before Galba — before Cato the Censor — he harangued with marvellous unction in praise of justice; and the hard brow of the grim Stoic softened ; an approving smile played over those thin firm lips. But the next day the brilliant orator undertook to exhibit the uncertainty of all human knowledge; and, as a proof, he refuted all the arguments with which the day before he had supported Justice. He spoke against Justice as convincingly as he had spoken for it. The brow of Cato darkened again, and with a keen instinct of the dangers of such ingenuity operating upon the Roman youth, he persuaded the Senate to send back the Philosophers to their own country. Carneades returned to Athens, and there renewed his con- test with the Stoics. He taught with great applause, and lived to the advanced age of ninety. That the Academicians should have embraced Scepticism is not strange : indeed, as we have said, Scepticism was the in- evitable result of the tendencies of the whole epoch ; and the only sect which did not accept it was forced to find a refuge in Common Sense ; that is to say, was forced to find refuge in the abdication of Philosophy, which abdication is in itself a species of Scepticism. But it may seem strange that the Academy *7« THE NEW ACADEMY : should derive itself from Plato; it may seem strange that Arcesilaus should be a continuer and a warm admirer of Plato. The ancients themselves, according to Sextus Empiricus, were divided amongst each other respecting Plato's real doc- trine; some considering him a sceptic, others a dogmatist. We have already explained the cause of this difference of opinion, and have shown how very little consistency and pre- cision there is in the ideas of Plato upon all subjects except Method. Scepticism, therefore, might very easily result from a study of his writings. But this is not all. Plato's attack upon the theories of his predecessors, which were grounded upon sense-knowledge, is constant, triumphant. The dialogue of the ' Theaetetus,' which is devoted to the subject of Science, is an exposition of the incapacity of sense to furnish materials for Science. All that sense can furnish the materials for is Opinion, and Opinion, as he frequently declares, even when it is Right Opinion, never can be Science. Plato, in short, destroyed all the old foundations upon which theories had been constructed. He cleared the ground before commencing his own work. By this means he obviated the attacks of the Sophists, and yet refused to sustain the onus of errors which his predecessors had accumulated. The Sophists saw the weakness of the old belief, and attacked it. Having reduced it to ruins, they declared themselves triumphant. Plato appeared, and admitted the fact of the old fortress being in ruins, and its deserving to be so ; but he denied that the city of Truth was taken. " Expend," said he, " your wrath and skill in battering down such fortresses ; I will assist you ; for I too declare them useless. But the real fortress you have not yet approached ; it is situate on far higher ground." Sense- knowledge and Opinion being thus set aside, the stronghold of Philosophy was the Ideal theory : in it Plato found refuge from the Sophists. Aristotle came and destroyed that theory. What, then, remained? Scepticism. Arcesilaus admitted, with Plato, the uncertainty of Opinion ; but he also admitted with Aristotle the incorrectness of the Ideal theory. He was thus reduced to absolute Scepticism. Th? arguments of Plato had quite destroyed the certitude of Opinion ; the arguments of Aristotle had quite destroyed the Ideal theory. And thus, by refusing to accept one argument of the Platonic doctrine, Arcesilaus could from Plato's works ARCESILAUS AND CARNEADES. » 79 deduce his own theory of the Incomprehensibility of all things : the acatalepsy. The doctrine of acatalepsy recalls to us the Stoical doctrine of catalepsy or Apprehension, to which it is the antithesis. The Cataleptic Phantasm was the True Perception according to the Stoics ; and, according to the Academicians, all Perceptions were acataleptic, i.e., bore no conformity to the objects per- ceived ; or, if they did bear any conformity thereto, it could never be known. Arcesilaus saw the weak point of the Stoical argument. Zeno pretended that there was a Criterium, which decided between science and opinion, which decided between true and false perceptions, and this was the Assent which the mind gave to the truth of certain perceptions : in other words, Common Sense was the Criterium. " But," said Arcesilaus, " what is the difference between the Assent of a wise man, and the Assent of a madman ? — There is no difference but in name." He felt that the criterium of the Stoics was itself in need of a Criterium. Chrysippus the Stoic combated Arcesilaus, and was in turn combated by Carneades. The great question then pending was this : — What Criterium is there of the truth of our knowledge t We have seen the attempts of the Stoics to answer this question. Let us now see how Carneades answered the Stoics. The Criterium must reside either in Reason, Conception, or Sensation. It cannot reside in Reason, because Reason itself is not independent of the other two : it operates upon the materials furnished by them, and is dependent upon them. Our knowledge is derived from the Senses, and every object presented to the mind must consequently have been originally presented to the Senses : on their accuracy the mind must depend. Reason cannot therefore contain within itself the desired Criterium. Nor can conception ; for the same arguments apply to it. Nor can the Criterium reside in Sense, because, as all admit, the senses are deceptive, and there is no perception which cannot be false. For what is Perception ? Our senses only inform us of the presence of an object in so Car as they are affected by it. But what is this ? Is it not we who are affected — we who are modified ? Yes ; and this modi- 280 THE NEW ACADEMY: fication reveals both itself and the object which causes it. Like Light, which, in showing itself, shows also the objects upon which it is thrown. Like Light also in this, that it shows objects in its own colours. Perception is a modification of the soul The whole problem now to solve is this : Does every modification of the soul exactly correspond with the external object which causes that modifica- tion f This is the problem presented by the Academicians. They answered ; but they did not solve it. They left to their adver- saries the task of proving the correspondence between the object and subject. We may here venture to carry out their principles and endeavour to solve the problem, as it is one still agitating the minds of metaphysicians. We say, that in nowise does the Sensation correspond with the object, in nowise does the modification correspond with the external cause, except in the relation of cause and effect. The early thinkers were well aware, that, in order to attribute any certainty to sensuous knowledge, we must assume that the Senses transmit us Copies of Things. Democritus, who was the first to see the necessity of such an hypothesis, suggested that our Ideas were £idola, or Images of the Objects, of an extremely airy texture, which were thrown off by the objects in the shape of effluvia, and entered the brain by the pores. Those who could not admit such an explanation substituted the hypo- thesis of Impressions. Ask any man, not versed in such in- quiries, whether he believes his perceptions to be copies of objects — whether he believes that the flower he sees before him exists quite independently of him and of every other human being, and exists with the same attributes of shape, fragrance, taste, &c. — his answer is sure to be in the affirmative. He will regard you as a madman if you doubt it. And yet so early as the epoch of which we are now sketch- ing the history, thinking men had learned in somewise to see that our Perceptions were not Copies of Objects, but that they were simply modifications of our minds, caused by the objects. Once admit this, and sensuous knowledge is for ever pro- nounced not only uncertain, but absolutely false. Can such a modification be a copy of the cause which modifies ? As well ask, Is the pain occasioned by a burn a copy of the fire? Is it at all like the fire ? Does if at all exoress the essence of fire ? ARCESTLAUS AND CARNEADES. 281 Not in the least. It only expresses one relation in which we stand to the fire ; one effect upon us which the fire will produce. Nevertheless, fire is an Object, and a burn is a Sensation. The way in which we perceive the existence of the Object (fire) is similar to that in which we perceive the existence of other Objects : and that is in the modifications they occasion : in our Sensations. Let us take another instance. We say that we hear Thunder. In other words we have a Perception of the Object called Thunder. Our Perception really is of a Noise, which the elec- trical phenomena we call Thunder have caused in us by acting on the aural nerve. Is our sensation of this Noise any Copy of the Phenomena ? Does it in any degree express the nature of tfie Phenomena ? No ; it only expresses the sensation we receive from a certain state of the atmosphere. In these cases most people will readily agree with us : for, by * very natural confusion of ideas, whenever they speak of per- ceptions they mostly mean visual perceptions : because with sight is associated the clearest knowledge ; because also the hypothesis of our perceptions being Copies of Things, is founded upon sight. The same persons who would willingly admit that Pain was not a Copy of the Fire, nor of any thing in the nature of Fire, except in its effect on our nerves, would protest that the appearance of Fire to tneJEyewas the real appearance of the Fire, all Eyes apart, and quite independent of human vision. It all Sentient beings were at once swept from the face of the earth, the fire would have no attribute at all resembling Pain : because Pain is a modification, not of Fire, but of a sentient being, in like manner if all Sentient beings were at once swept from the face of the earth, the Fire would have no attributes at all resembling light and colour ; because light and colour (however startling the assertion) are modifications of the sentient being, caused by something external, but no more resembling its cause than the pain inflicted by an instrument resembles that instrument. Pain and colour are modifications of the sentient being. The question at issue is, Can a modification of a Sentient being be a copy of its cause ? The answer is clearly a negative. We may imagine that when we see an Object our sensation is a copy of it, because we believe that the Object paints itself upon the retina : and we liken perception to a mirror, in which things t83 THE NEW ACADEMY: are reflected. It is extremely difficult to divest ourselves of this prejudice ; but we may be made aware of the fallacy if we attend to those perceptions which are not visual — to the perceptions of sound, fragrance, taste, or pain. These are clearly nothing but modifications of our being, caused by external objects, but in nowise resembling them. We are all agreed that the heat is not in the fire, but in us ; that sweetness is not in the sugar, but in us; that fragrance is but an effluvia of particles, which, impinging on the olfactory nerve, cause a sensation in us. In all beings similarly constituted these things would have similar effects, would cause pain, sweetness, and fragrance ; but, on all other beings the effects would be different : Fire would burn paper, but not pain it ; Sugar would mix with water, but not give it the sensation of sweetness ; and so forth. The radical error of those who believe that we perceive things as they are, consists in mistaking a metaphor for a fact, and believing that the mind is a Mirror in which external objects are reflected. But, as Bacon finely says, " the human understanding is like an unequal mirror to the rays of things, which, mixing its own nature with the nature of things, distorts and perverts them." This is the process whereby we attribute heat to the fire and colour to the flower ; heat and colour really being states of our consciousness occasioned by the fire and the flower under certain conditions. What is Perception? — Perception is nothing more than a state of the percipient — i.e. a state of consciousness. This state may be occasioned by some external cause, and may be as complex as the cause is complex, but it is still nothing more than a state of consciousness — an effect produced by an adequate cause. Of every change in our Sensation we are conscious, and in time we learn to give definite names and forms to the causes of these changes. But in the fact of Con- sciousness there is nothing beyond Consciousness. In our per- ceptions we are conscious only of the changes which have taken place within us ; we can never transcend the sphere of our own consciousness ; we can never go out of ourselves, and become aware of the objects which caused those changes : all we can do is to identify certain external appearances with certain internal changes, e.g. to identify the appearance we name " fire " with certain sensations we have known to follow our being placed near it. Turn the fact of consciousness how you will, you can see nothing in it but the change of a sentient being operated ARCESILAUS AND CARNEADES. sfl3 by some external cause. Consciousness is no mirror of the world : it gives no faithful reflection of things as they Mt per se; it only gives a faithful report of its own modification as excited by external things. The world, apart from our consciousness, i.e. the non-ego qua non-ego — the world per se — is, we may be certain, some- thing utterly different from the world as we know it ; for all we know of it is derived through our consciousness of what its effects are on us, and our consciousness is obviously only a state of ourselves, not a copy of external things. How do you know that the world is different from what it appears to us ? This question is pertinent, and we will answer briefly. The world per se must be different from what it appears to us through consciousness, because to us it is only known in the relation of cause and effect World is the Cause ; our Con- sciousness the Effect. But the same world operating on some other organization would produce a very different effect. If all animals were blind there would be no such thing as light, be- cause light is a phenomenon made up out of the operation of some unknown thing on the retina. If all animals were deaf there would be no such thing as sound, because sound is a phenomenon made up out of whe operation of some unknown thing (supposed to be pulsations of air) on the tympanum. If all animals were without their present nerves, or nerves having the same dispo- sitions, there would be no such thing as pain, because pain is a phenomenon made up out of the operation of some external thing on the nerves. Light, colour, sound, pain, taste, smell are all states of con- sciousness, and nothing more. Light with its myriad forms and colours — Sound with its thousand-fold life — make Nature what Nature appears to us ; but they are only the investitures of the mind. Nature is an eternal Darkness — an eternal Silence. We conclude, therefore, that the World per se is in nowise resembling the World as it appears to us. Perception is an Effect; and its truth is not the truth of resemblance, but of relation, i.e. it is the true operation of the world on us, the true operation of Cause and Effect. But Perception is not the true resemblance of the world, Consciousness is no mirror reflect- ing external things. Let us substitute for the metaphor of a mirror the more abstract expression of " Perception is an Effect caused by an ««4 THE NEW ACADEMY. external object," and much of the confusion darkening this matter will be dissipated. An Effect, we know, agrees with its Cause, out it does not resemble it. An Effect is no more a Copy of the Cause than pain is a copy of the application of fire to a finger : ergo, Perception can never be an accurate report of what things are per se, but only of what they are in relation to us. It has been said that, although no single sense does actually convey to us a correct impression of anything, nevertheless we are enabled to confirm or modify the report of one sense by the report of another Sense, and that the result of the whole activity of the five senses is a true impression of the externa) Thing. This is a curious fallacy. It pretends that a number of false impressions are sufficient to constitute a true one ! The conclusion to be drawn from the foregoing premisses is this : There is no correspondence between the object and the sensation, except that of Cause and Effect. Sensations are not Copies of Objects; do not at all resemble them. As we can only know objects through sensation — i.e. as we can only know our Sensations — we can never ascertain the truth respect- ing objects. This brings us back to the New Academy, the disciples of which strenuously maintained that Perception, being nothing but a modification of the Soul, could never reveal the real nature of things. Do we then side with the Academicians in proclaiming all human knowledge deceptive ? No : to them, as to the Pyr- rhonists, we answer : You are quite right in affirming that man cannot transcend the sphere of his own consciousness, cannot penetrate the real essence of things, cannot know causes, can only know phenomena. But this affirmation — though it crushes Metaphysics — though it interdicts the inquiry into noumena, into essences and causes, as frivolous because futile — does not touch Science. If all our knowledge is but a knowledge of phenomena, there can still be a Science of Phenomena adequate to all man's true wants. If Sensation is but the effect of an External Cause, we, who can never know that Cause, know it in its relation to us, ix. in its Effect. These Effects are as constant as their Causes; and, consequently, there can be a Science of Effects. SUMMARY OF THE EIGHTH EPOCH. 385 Such a Science is that named Positive Science, the aim of which is to trace the Co-existences and Successions of Pheno- mena, ue. to trace the relation of Cause and Effect throughout the universe submitted to our inspection. But neither the Pyrrhonists nor the Academicians saw this refuge for the mind ; they consequently proclaimed Scepticism as the final result of inquiry. CHAPTER V. SUMMARY OF THE EIGHTH EPOCH. We have now brought our narrative to the second crisis in the history of speculation. The Scepticism which made the Sophists powerful, and which closed the first period of this history, we now behold once more usurping the intellects of men, and this time with far greater power. A Socrates ap- peared to refute and to discredit the Sophists. Who is there to refute and to discredit the Sceptics ? The Sceptics, and all thinkers during the epoch we have just treated were such, whether they called themselves Epicureans, Stoics, Pyrrhonists or New Academicians — the Sceptics, we say, were in possession of the most formidable arms. From Socrates, from Plato, and from Aristotle, they had borrowed their best weapons, and with these had attacked Philosophy, and attacked it with success. All the wisdom of the antique world was powerless against the Sceptics. Speculative belief was reduced to the most uncertain " probability." Faith in Truth was extinct. Faith in human endeavour was gone. Philosophy was impossible. But there was one peculiarity of the Socratic doctrine which was preserved even in the midst of scepticism. Socrates had made Ethics the great object of his inquiries : and all subse- quent thinkers had given it a degree of attention which before was unknown. What was the consequence? The consequence was that the Common Sense doctrine of the Stoics, and the Probabilities of the Sceptics, however futile, as scientific prin- ciples, were efficacious enough as moral principles. Common 286 SUMMARY OP THE EIGHTH EPOCH Sense may be a bad basis for Metaphyseal or Scientific reason ing ; but it is not so bad a basis for a system of morais. The protest, therefore, which Scepticism made against all Philosophy was not so anarchical in its tendency as the protest made by the Sophists ; but it was more energetic, more terrible. In the wisdom of that age there was no cure for it. The last cry of despair seemed to have been wrung from the baffled thinkers, as they declared their predecessors to have been hope- lessly wrong, and declared also that their error was without a a remedy. It was, indeed, a saddening contemplation. The hopes and aspirations of so many incomparable minds thus irrevocably doomed ; the struggles of so many men from Thales, when he first asked himself, Whence do all things proceed? to the elaborate systematization of the forms of thought which occu- pied an Aristotle — the struggles of these men had ended in Scepticism. Little was to be gleaned from the harvest of their endeavours but arguments against the possibility of that Science they were so anxious to form. Centuries of thought have not advanced the mind one step nearer to a solution of the problems with which, child-like, it began. It began with a child-like question ; it ended with an aged doubt. Not only did it doubt the solutions of the great problem which others had attempted ; it doubted the possibility of any solution. It was not the doubt which begins, but the doubt which ends inquiry : it had no illusions. This was the second crisis of Greek Philosophy. Reason thus assailed could only find a refuge in Faith, and the next period opens with the attempt to construct a Religious Philo- sophy. Ntnt!) lEpocij. PHILOSOPHY ALLIES ITSELF WITH FAITH. THE ALEXANDRIAN SCHOOLS. CHAPTER 1. ALEXANDRIA. Philosophy no longer found a home in Greece ; it had no longer any worshippers in its native country, and was forced to seek them elsewhere. A period had arrived when all problems seemed to have been stated, and when none seemed likely to be solved. Every system which human ingenuity could devise had been devised by the early thinkers ; and not one had beei* able to stand examination. In the early annals of speculation, a new and decisive advance is made whenever a new question is asked ; to suggest a doubt, is to exercise ingenuity : to ask a question, is to awaken men to a new view of the subject. But now all questions had been asked ; old questions had been revived under new forms ; nothing remained to stimulate in- quiry, or to give speculators a hope of success. Unable to ask new questions, or to offer new answers to those already asked, the Philosophers readily seized on the only occasion which enabled them to gain renown : they travelled. They carried their doctrines into Egypt and into Rome ; and in those places they were listened to with wonder and delight. Their old doctrines were novelties to a people who had none of its own ; and, from the excessive cost of books in those days, almost all instruction being oral, the strangers were welcomed warmly, and the doctrines imported were as novel as if they had been just invented. Philosophy, exiled from Greece, was a favoured guest in Alexandria and Rome ; but in both cases it was a stranger, and 288 ALEXANDRIA. could not be naturalized. In Alexandria, however, it made a brilliant display ; and the men it produced gave it an originality and an influence which it never possessed in Rome. Roman Philosophy was but a weak paraphrase of the Grecian ; and we, therefore, give it no place in this history. To speak Greek, to write Greek, became the fashionable ambi- tion of Rome. The child was instructed by a Greek slave Greek Professors taught Philosophy and Rhetoric to aspiring youths. Athens had become the necessary " tour " which was to complete a man's education. It was there that Cicero learned those ideas which he delighted in setting forth in charming dialogues. It was there Horace learned that light and careless philosophy, which he has enshrined in the spark- ling crystal of his verse. Wandering from the Academy to the Porch, and from the Porch to the Garden, he became embued with that scepticism which checks his poetical enthusiasm ; and learned to make a system of that pensive epicureanism which gives so peculiar a character to his poems ; a character which, with a sort of after-dinner freedom and bonhomie, especially recommends him to men of the world. Not that this consti- tutes his sole merit ; his poems are the delight of every class ; how could they be otherwise ? They are not only wise, they are luxurious : it is rare old Falemian wine that sparkles in their veins, and their numbers are musical with kisses. In Rome, Philosophy might tinge the poetry, give weight to oratory, and supply some topics of conversation ; but it was no Belief filling the minds of serious men : it took no root in the national existence ; it produced no great Thinkers. In Alexandria the case was different. There several schools were formed, and some new elements introduced into the doctrines -then existent. Great thinkers — Plotinus, Proclus, Porphyry — made it illustrious; and it had a rival, whose antagonism alone would confer immortal renown upon it : that rival was Christianity. In no species of grandeur was the Alexandrian school de- ficient, as M. Saisset justly observes :* genius, power, and duration, have consecrated it. Reanimating, during an epoch of decline, the fecundity of an aged civilization, it created a whole family of illustrious names. Plotinus, its real founder resuscitated Plato ; Proclus gave the world another Aristotle ; * • Revue des Deux Aiondes,' 1844, tome iii. p. 783 ; an admirable article on this subject. RISE OF NEO-PLATON1SM : PHILO. 289 and, in the person of Julian the Apostate, it became master of the world. For three centuries it was a formidable rival to the greatest power that ever appeared on earth — the power of Christianity ; and, if it succumbed in the struggle, it only fell with the civilization of which it had been the last rampart. Alexandria, the centre of gigantic commerce, soon became a new metropolis of science rivalling Athens. The Alexandrian Library is too celebrated to need more than a passing allusion : to it, and to the men assembled there, we owe the vast labours of erudition in philosophy and literature which were of such service to the world. We cannot here enumerate all the men of science who made it illustrious ; enough, if we mention Euclid, for Mathematics ; Conon and Hipparchus, for Astro- nomy; Eratosthenes, for Geography; and Aristarchus, for literary criticism. Besides these, there were the Philosophers ; and Lucian, the witty Sceptic; and the Poets, Apollonius Rhodius, Callimachus, Lycophron, Tryphiodorus, and, above all, the sweet idyllic Theocritus. It is a curious spectacle. Beside the Museum of Alexandria there rises into formidable importance the Didascalia of the Christians. In the same city, Philo the Jew, and CEnesidemus the Pyrrhonist, founded their respective schools. Ammonius Sacca appears there. Lucian passes through at the same time that Clemens Alexandrinus is teaching. After Plotinus has taught, Arius and Athanasiuswill also teach. Greek Scepticism, Judaism, Platonism, Christianity — all have their interpreters within so small a distance from the temple of Serapis I CHAPTER II. RISE OF NEO-PLATONISM : PHILO. Alexandria, as we have seen, was the theatre of various struggles : of these we are to select one, and that one the struggle of the Neo-Platonists with the Christian fathers. Under the name of the Alexandrian School are designated, though loosely enough, all those thinkers who endeavoured to find a refuge from Scepticism in a new Philosophy, based on altogether new principles. Now, although these various T 2 9 o RISE OF NEO-PLATONISM : PHILO. Thinkers by no means constitute a School, they constitute a Movement, and they form an Epoch in the history of Philo- sophy. We may merely observe that the " Alexandrian School " and the " Neo-Platonists " are not convertible terms; the former designates a whole movement, the latter designates the most illustrious section of that movement. As we are writing the History of Philosophy only, we select only this section for our purpose. Philo the Jew is the first of these Neo-Platonists. He was born at Alexandria a few years before Christ. The influence of Greek ideas was already being felt in Alexandria, and Philo, commenting on the writings of the Jews, did so in the spirit ot one deeply imbued with Greek thought. His genius was Oriental, his education Greek ; the result was a strange mixture of mysticism and dialectics.* To Plato he owed much ; but to the New Academy, perhaps, more. From Carneades he learned to distrust the truth of all sensuous knowledge, and to deny that Reason had any criterium of truth. Thus far he was willing to travel with the Greeks ; thus far had dialectics conducted him. But there was another element in his mind beside the Greek : there was the Oriental, there was mysticism. If human knowledge is a delusion, we must seek for Truth in some higher sphere. The senses may de- ceive ; Reason may be powerless ; but there is still a faculty in man — there is Faith. Real Science is the gift of God : its dame is Faith ; its origin is the goodness of God : its cause is Piety. Now this conception is not Plato's, and is nevertheless Platonic. Plato would never have thus condemned Reason for the sake of Faith ; and yet he, too, thought that the nature of God could not be known, although his existence could be proved. In this respect he would have agreed with Philo. But, although Plato does not speak of Science as the gift of God, he does in one place so speak of Virtue ; and he devotes the whole dialogue of the ' Meno ' to show that Virtue cannot be taught, because it is not a thing of the understanding, but a gift of God. The reasons he there employs mayeasily have suggested to Philo their application to Science. From this point Philo's Philosophy of course becomes a * St. Paul thus comprehensively expresses the national characteristic of the Jews and Greeks: " The Jews require a sign {i.e. a miracle), and the Greeks seek after wisdom (*.r. philosophy)." — I. Corinth., i. v. 22. RISE OF NEO-PLATONISM : PHILO. 291 theology. God is ineffable, incomprehensible: his existence may be known ; his nature can never be known. oS* apa ov&X rw vw tcaraXriirrb^, otl fiyj Kara to eivcu yjovov. But to know that he exists is in itself the knowledge of his being one, perfect, simple, immutable, and without attribute. This is knowledge implied in the simple knowledge of his existence : he cannot be otherwise, if he exist at all. But to know this is not to know in what consists his perfection. We cannot penetrate with our glance the mystery of his essence. We can only believe. If, however, we cannot know God in his essence, we can obtain some knowledge of his Divinity : we know it in The Word. This Xoyos — this Word (using the expression in its scriptural sense) — fills a curious place in all the mystical systems. God being incomprehensible, inaccessible, an inter- mediate existence was necessary as an interpreter between God and Man, and this intermediate existence the 'Mystics called The Word. The- Word, according to Philo, is God V Thought * This Thought is two-fold ; it is Aoyos cvSta^eroc, the Thought as embracing all Ideas (in the Platonic sense of the term Idea), i.e. Thought as Thought; and it is Xoyos irpo0opuco5, the Thought realized: Thought became the World. In these three hypostases of the Deity we see the Trinity of Plotinus foreshadowed. There is first, God the Father; secondly, the Son of God, i.e. the Aoyos ; thirdly, the Son oi Aoyos, i.e. the World. This brief outline of Philo's Theology will sufficiently exemplify the two great facts which we are anxious to have understood : — 1st, the union of Platonism with oriental mysti- cism ; 2ndly, the entirely new direction given to Philosophy, by uniting it once more with Religion. It is this direction which characterizes the Movement of the Alexandrian School. Reason had been shown to be utterly powerless to solve the great questions of Philosophy then agitated. Various Schools had pursued various Methods, but all with one result. Scepticism was the conclusion of every struggle. And yet, said the Mystics, " we have an idea of God and of his goodness ; we have an ineradicable belief in his existence, and in the perfection of his nature, consequently, in the bene- ficence of his aims. Yet these ideas are not innate ; were they innate, they would be uniformly entertained by all men, and 292 RISE OF NEO-PLATONISM : PHILO. amongst all nations. If they are not innate, whence are they derived? Not from Reason; not from experience; then from Faith." Now, Philosophy, conceive it how you will, is entirely the offspring of Reason : it is the endeavour to explain by Reason the mysteries »amidst which we " move, live, and have our being/' Although legitimate to say, " Reason is incapable of solving the problems proposed to it," it is not legitimate to add : " therefore we must call in the aid of Faith." In Philo- sophy, Reason must either reign alone, or abdicate. No com- promise is permissible. If there are things between heaven and earth which are not dreamt of in our Philosophy — which do not come within the possible sphere of our Philosophy — we may believe in them, indeed; but we cannot christen that belief philosophical. One of two things — either Reason is capable of solving the problems, or it is incapable : in the one case its attempt is Philosophy; in the second case its attempt is futile. Any attempt to mix up Faith with Reason, in a matter exclusively addressed to the Reason, must be abortive. We do not say that what Faith implicitly accepts, Reason may not explicitly justify ; but we say that to bring Faith to the aid of Reason, is altogether to destroy the philosophical character of any in- quiry. Reason may justify Faith ; but Faith must not furnish conclusions for Philosophy. Directly Reason is abandoned, Philosophy ceases ; and every explanation then offered is a theological explanation, and must be put to altogether different tests, from what a philosophical explanation would require. All speculation must originally have been theological ; but in process of time Reason timidly ventured upon what are called " natural explanations " ; and from the moment that it felt itself strong enough to be independent, Philosophy was established. In the early speculations of the Ionian s we saw the pure efforts of Reason to explain mysteries. As Philo- sophy progressed, it became more and more evident that the problems so readily attacked by the early thinkers were, in truth, so far from being a solution, that their extreme difficulty was only just becoming appreciated. The difficulty became more and more apparent, till at last it was pronounced in- superable : Reason was declared incompetent. Then the Faith which had so long been set aside was again called to assist the CHRISTIANITY AND NEO-PLATONISM. 193 inquirer. In other words, Philosophy discovering itself to be powerless, resigned in favour of Theology. What is a Theology? It is a doctrine in which Reason undertakes to deduce conclusions from the premisses of Faith. When, therefore, we say that the direction given to the human mind by the Alexandrian School, in conjunction with Chris- tianity — the only two spiritual movements which materially influenced the epoch we are speaking of— was a theological direction, the reader will at once see its immense importance, and will be prepared to follow us in our exposition of the mystical doctrines of Plotinus. CHAPTER III. ANTAGONISM OF CHRISTIANITY AND NEO-PLATONISM. While Christianity was making rapid and enduring progress in *pite of every obstacle ; while the Apostles wandered from city to city, sometimes honoured as demi-gods, at other times in- sulted and stoned as enemies, the Neo-Platonists were develop- ing the germ deposited by Philo, and not only constructing a theology, but endeavouring on that theology to found a Church. Whilst a new religion, Christianity, was daily usurping the souls of men, these philosophers fondly imagined that an old Religion could effectually oppose it. Christianity triumphed without much difficulty. Looking at it with a purely moral view, its immense superiority is at once apparent. The Alexandrians exaggerated the vicious tendency of which we have already seen the fruits in the Cynics and Stoics, the tendency to despise Humanity. Plotinus blushed because he had a body : contempt of human personality could go no farther. What was offered in exchange ? The ecstatic perception ; the absorption of your personality in that of the Deity — a Deity inaccessible to knowledge as to love — a Deity which the soul can only attain by a complete annihilation of its personality. How different from Christianity; in which, so far from human nature being degraded and despised, it is elevated and sanctified by the Messiah who adopted it, and by «H CHRISTIANITY AND NEO-PLATONISM. the doctrine of immortality in which the body is to rise again and live the life to come ! The attempt of the Neo-Platonists failed, as it deserved to fail ; but it had great talents in its service, and it made great noise in the world. It had, as M. Saisset remarks, three periods. The first of these, the least brilliant but the most fruitful, is that of Ammonius Saccas and Plotinus. A porter of Alexandria becomes the chief of a school, and men of genius listen to him ; amongst his disciples are Plotinus, Origen, and Longinus. This School is perfected in obscurity, and receives at last a solid basis by the development of a metaphysical system. Plotinus, the author of this system, shortly after lectures at Rome with amazing success. It is then that the Alexandrian School enters upon its second period. With Porphyry and Iamblicus it becomes a sort of Church, and dis- putes with Christianity the empire of the world. Christianity had ascended the throne in the person of Constantine ; Neo- Platonism dethrones it, and usurps its place in the person of Julian the Apostate. But, now, mark the difference. In losing Constantine Chris tianity lost nothing of its real power; for its power lay in the might of convictions, and not in the support of potentates ; its power was a spiritual power, ever active, ever fruitful. In losing Julian, Neo-Platonism lost its power, political and religious. The third period commences with that loss : and the genius of Proclus bestows on it one last gleam of splendour. In vain did he strive to revive the scientific spirit of Platonism, as Plotinus had endeavoured to revive the religious spirit of Paganism ; his efforts were vigorous but sterile. Under Justi- nian the School of Alexandria became extinct. Such is the outward history of the School : let us now cast a glance at the doctrines which were there elaborated. In the writings of thinkers professedly eclectic, such as were the Alexandrians, it is obvious that the greater portion will be repetitions and reproductions of former thinkers ; and the historian will therefore neglect that portion to confine himself to that which constitutes the originality of the School. The originality of the Alexandrians consists in having employed the Platonic Dialectics as a guide to Mysticism and Pantheism ; in having connected the doctrine of the East with the dialectics of the Greeks ; in having made Reason the justification of Faith. THE ALEXANDRIAN DIALECTICS. 295 There are three essential points to be here examined. Their Dialectics, their theory of the Trinity, and their principle of Emanation. By their Dialectics they were Platonists ; by their theory of the Trinity they were Mystics ; by their principle of Emanation they were Pantheists. CHAPTER IV THE ALEXANDRIAN DIALECTICS. The nature of the Platonic Dialectics we hope to have already rendered intelligible; so that in saying Plotinus employed them we are saved from much needless repetition. But, although Dialectics formed the basis of Alexandrian science, they did not, as with Plato, furnish the grounds of belief. As far as human science went, Dialectics were efficient ; but there were problems which did not come within the sphere of human science, and for these another Method was requisite. Plotinus agreed with Plato that there could only be a science of Universals. Every individual thing was but a phenomenon, passing quickly away, and having no real existence ; it could not therefore be the object of science. But these universals — these Ideas which are the only real existences — are they not also subordinate to some higher Existence ? Phenomena were subordinate to Noumena ; but Noumena themselves were sub- ordinate to the One Noumenon. In other words, the Sensible world was but the Appearance of the Ideal World, and the Ideal World in its turn was but the mode of God's existence. The question then arises : How do we know anything of God ? The sensible world we perceive through our senses ; the Ideal World we gain glimpses of, through the reminiscence which the sensible world awakens in us ; but how are we to take the last step — how are we to know the Deity ? I am a finite being : how can I comprehend the Infinite ? As soon as I comprehend the Infinite, I am Infinite myself : that is to say, I am no longer myself, no longer that finite being, having a consciousness of his own separate existence.* * rig av ovv rrjv dvvaptv uvtov i\ot opov vaaav ; h yap optov Tcarray, H qv rt avrov Sia&ipoi. — Plotinns> Enn. V. I. v. c. *. 290 THE ALEXANDRIAN DIALECTICS. If, therefore, I attain to a knowledge of the Infinite, it is not by my Reason, which is finite and embraces only finite objects, but by some higher faculty, a faculty altogether impersonal, which identifies itself with its object. The identity of Subject and Object — of the thought with the thing thought of — is the only possible ground of knowledge. This position, which some of our readers will recognise as the fundamental position of modern German speculation, is so removed from all ordinary conceptions that we must digress awhile, in order to explain it. Neo-Platonism is a blank without it. Knowledge and Being are identical ; to know more is to be more. We do not of course maintain the absurd proposition that to know a horse is to be that horse ; but we maintain that all we know of that horse is only what we know of the changes in ourselves occasioned by some external cause, and, identi- fying our internal change with that external cause, we call it a horse. Here knowledge and being are identical : we really know nothing of the external cause (horse) we only know our own state of being ; and to say, therefore, that " in our know- ledge of the horse we are the horse " is only saying, in unusual language, that our knowledge is a state of our being, and nothing more. The discussion in the fourth chapter of the foregoing book respecting perception, was an attempt to prove that knowledge is only a state of our own consciousness, excited by some unknown cause. The cause must remain unknown because knowledge is effect, not cause. An apple is presented to you : you see it, feel it, taste it, smell it, and are said to know it. What is this knowledge ? Simply a consciousness of the various wave m which the apple affects you. You are blind and cannot see it : there is one quality less which it possesses, *.*. one mode less in which it is possible for you to be affected. You are without the nerves of smell and taste : there are two other deficiencies in your know- ledge of the apple. So that, by taking away your senses, we take away from the apple each of its qualities : in other words, we take away the means of your being affected. Your know- ledge of the apple is reduced to nothing. In a similar way, by endowing you with more senses we increase the qualities of the apple, we increase your knowledge, by enlarging your being. Thus are Knowledge and Being identical ; knowledge is a state of Being knowing. THE ALEXANDRIAN DIALECTICS. 397 ** If," said Plotinus, u knowledge is the same as the thing known, the Finite, as Finite, never can know the Infinite, be- cause it cannot be the Infinite. To attempt, therefore, to know the Infinite by Reason is futile, it can only be known in imme- diate presence, irapovo-t*. The faculty by which the mind divests itself of its personality is Ecstacy. In this Ecstacy the soul becomes loosened from its material prison, separated from individual consciousness, and becomes absorbed in the Infinite Intelligence from which it emanated. In this Ecstacy it con- templates real existence : it identifies itself with that which it contemplates." The enthusiasm upon which this Ecstacy is founded is not a faculty which we constantly possess, such as Reason or Percep- tion ; it is only a transitory state, at least so long as our per- sonal existence in this world continues. It is a flash o rapturous light, in which reminiscence is changed into i n tu i ti o n , because in that moment the captive soul is given back to its parent, its God. The bonds which attach the soul to the body are mortal; and God, our father, pitying us, has made those bonds, from which we suffer, fragile and delicate, and in his goodness he gives us certain intervals of respite : Zevs 8k irarr/p *X.€Ti to lv, — a conception which will at once be understood by recurring to our illustration of the identity of Knowledge and Being, given above. One would fancy that this was a degree of abstraction to satisfy the most ardent dialectician; to have analyzed thus far, and to have arrived at pure Thought and pure Existence — the Thought apart from Thinking and the Existence apart from its modes — would seem the very limit of human ingenuity, the last abstraction possible. But no : the dialectician is not yet con- tented : he seeks another degree of abstraction still higher, * " The flowers unsown in fields and meadows reigned ; And western winds immortal spring maintained. In following years the bearded corn ensued From earth unasked, nor was that earth renewed. From veins of valleys milk and nectar broke, And hone) sweating from the pores of oak." Dryden's Ovtd. 302 THE ALEXANDRIAN TRINITY. still simpler : he calls it unity. God, as Existence and Thought, is God as conceived by human intelligence ; but, although human intelligence is unable to embrace any higher notion of God, yet is there in human intelligence a hint of its own weakness and an assurance of God's being something ineffable, incomprehensible. God is not, e?i derniere analyse, Existence and Thought. What is Thought ? What is its type ? The type is evidently human reason. What does an examina- tion of human reason reveal ? This : To think is to be aware of some object from which the thinker distinguishes himself. To think is to have a self-consciousness, to distinguish one's personality from that of all other objects, to determine the relation of self to not-self. But nothing is external to God: in him there can be no distinction, no determination, no relation. Therefore God, in his highest hypostasis, cannot think, cannot be Thought, but something superior to Thought. Hence the necessity for a third hypostasis, which third in the order of discovery is first in the order of being: it is Unity, — rb tv carXovv. The Unity is not Existence, neither is it Intelligence — it is superior to both : it is superior to all action, to all determina- tion, to all knowledge ; for, in the same way as the multiple is contained in the simple^ the many in the one, in the same way is the simple contained in the unity ; and it is impossible to discover the truth of things until we have arrived at this abso- lute unity ; for, how can we conceive any existing thing except by unity ? What is an individual, an animal, a plant, but that unity which presides over multiplicity ? What even is multi- plicity — an army, an assembly, a flock — when not brought under unity ? Unity is omnipresent : it is the bond which unites even the most complex things. The Unity which is absolute, immutable, infinite, and self- sufficing is not the numerical unit, not the indivisible point. It is the absolute universal One in its perfect simplicity. It is the highest degree of perfection — the ideal Beauty, the supreme God, irpdrov ayaObv. God therefore in his absolute state — in his first and highest Hypostasis — is neither Existence nor Thought — neither moved nor mutable — he is the simple Unity — or, as Hegel would say, the Absolute Nothing, the Immanent Negative. Our readers will perhaps scarcely be patient under this infliction of dialec- tical subtlety, and absurdity; but we would beg them to THE ALEXANDRIAN TRINITY. 303 remember that the absurdities of genius are often more in- structive than the discoveries of common men, and that the subtleties and extravagances of the Alexandrians seem to us fraught with lessons. If rigorous logic conducted eminent minds to conceptions which appear extravagant and sterile, they may induce in us a wholesome suspicion of the efficacy of that logic to solve the problems it is occupied with. Nor is the lesson inapplicable to our age. The present enthusiasm for German Literature and German Philosophy will of course turn the attention of many young minds to the speculations in which Germany is so rife; we are consequently more interested in Plotinus, because he agitates similar questions and affords very similar answers. The German Metaphysicians resemble Plotinus more than Plato or Aristotle : nor is the reason diffi- cult of discovery. Plotinus, coming after all the great thinkers, had asked almost every metaphysical question, and given almost every possible answer, was condemned either to scepti- cism or to accept any consequences of his dialectics, however extreme. Philosophy was in this dilemma : either to abdicate or to be magnificently tyrannical : it chose to be the latter. Plotinus, therefore, shrank from no extravagances : where Reason failed, there he called upon Faith. The Germans, coming after the secure establishment of Positive Science, found Philosophy in a similar dilemma : either to declare itself incapable, or to proclaim its despotism and infallibility : what Logic demonstrated must be absolutely true. This faith in Logic is remarkable, and may be contrasted with the Alexandrian faith in Ecstacy. Of the possibility of human Logic not being the standard of truth the Germans have no suspicion ; they are without Greek scepticism as to the Criterium. They proceed with peaceful dogmatism to tell you that God is this, or that ; to explain how the Nothing becomes the Existing world, to explain many other inexplicable things, and, if you stop them with the simple inquiry, How do you know this? What is your ground of certitude? they smile, allude gently to Reason, and continue their exposition. Plotinus was wiser, though less consequent. He said, that although Dialectics raise us to some conviction of the existence of God, we cannot speak of his nature otherwise than nega- tively : kv d<£cu'p€?. The ancients began their speculations in the same way, but with less knowledge of the conditions of inquiry. Hence Water, Air, Soul, Number, Force, were severally accepted as THE ALEXANDRIAN TRINITY. 305 Priticipia. In the time of the Alexandrians something more subtle was required. They asked the same question, but they asked it with a full consciousness of the failure of their prede- cessors. Even Mind would not satisfy them as a Principium; nor would abstract Existence. They said there is something beyond Thought, something beyond Existence : there is that which thinks, that which exists. This " that " — id quod — this Indeterminate Ineffable is the Principium. It is self-sufficing, self-existent ; nothing can be conceived beyond it. In the old Indian hypothesis of the world being supported by an elephant, who stood on the back of a tortoise, and the tortoise standing on nothing, we see a rude solution of the same problem : the mind is forced to arrest itself somewhere, and wherever it arrests itself it is forced to declare, explicitly or implicitly, that it stops at Nothing ; because, as soon as it predicates anything of that at which it stops, it is forced to admit something be- yond : if the tortoise stands on the back of some other animal, upon what does that other animal stand ? is the question imme- diately presenting itself. Human Logic, when employed upon this subject, necessarily abuts upon Nothing, upon absolute Negation ; the terms in which this is clothed may differ, but the conception remains the same : Plotinus and Spinoza shake hands. In reviewing the history of Greek speculation, from the " Water " of Thales to the " Absolute Negation " of Plotinus, what a reflection is forced upon us of the vanity of meta- physics ! So many years of laborious inquiry, so many splendid minds engaged, and, after the lapse of ages, the inquiry re- mains the same, the answer only more ingeniously absurd ! Ah ! truly was it said, that Metaphysics was fart dc s'egarcr avec methodc! Was, then, all this labour vain ? Were those long laborious years all wasted ? Were those splendid minds all useless ? No : human endeavour is seldom without fruit. Those cen- turies of speculation were not useless, they were the education of the human race. They taught mankind this truth at least : the Infinite cannot be known by the finite ; man can only know phenomena. In those labours, so fruitless in their immediate object, there are indirect lessons. The speculations of the Greeks preserve the same privilege as the glorious pro- ducts of their art and literature ; they are the models from which the speculations of posterity are reproductions. The n yfi> THE DOCTRINE OF EAfANAT/ON. history of modern metaphysical philosophy is but the narrative of the same struggle which agitated Greece. The same pro- blems are revived and the same answers offered. How different the history of Positive Science, in which there is nothing but progression, slow but certain ! CHAPTER VI. THE DOCTRINE OF EMANATION. The science of Metaphysics consists in the answers to three questions: Has human knowledge any absolute certainty? What is the nature of God ? What is the origin of the world ? Our review of the various attempts to answer these questions has ended in the Alexandrian School, which answered them as follows: i st. Human knowledge is necessarily uncertain ; but this difficulty is got over by the hypothesis of an Ecstacy in which the soul becomes identified with the Infinite. 2nd. The Nature of God is a triple Unity — three hypostases of the One Being. 3rd. The origin of the world is the law of Emanation. This third answer is of course implied in the second. God, as Unity, is not Existence; but he becomes Existence by the Emanation from his Unity (Intelligence), and by the second emanation from his Intelligence (Soul), and this Soul in its manifestations is the World. Hitherto dualism had been the universal creed of those who admitted any distinction between the world and its creator. Jupiter organizing Chaos, the God of Anaxagoras whose force is wasted in creation ; the %«ov/oy69 of Plato, who conquers and regulates Matter and Motion ; the immovable Thought of Aristotle : all these creeds were dualistic ; and, indeed, to escape dualism was no easy task. If God is distinct from the World, dualism is at once assumed. If he is distinct, he must be distinct in Essence. If distinct in essence, the question of Whence came the world? is not answered; for the world must have existed contem- poraneously with him. Here lies the difficulty : either God made the world, or he did not. If he made it, whence did he make it ? He could THE DOCTRINE OF EMANATION. 307 not, said Logic, make it out of Nothing : for Nothing can come of Nothing ; he must, therefore, have made it out of his own substance. If it is made out of his own substance, then it is identical with him : it must then have existed already in him, or he could not have produced it But this identification of God with the world is Pantheism ; and begs the question it should answer. If he did not make it out of his own substance, he must have made it out of some substance already existing ; and the question still remains unanswered. This problem was solved by the Christians and Alexandrians in a similar, though apparently different, manner. The Chris- tians said that God created the world out of Nothing by the mere exercise of his omnipotent will ; for to omnipotence everything is possible ; one thing is as easy as another. The Alexandrians said that the world was distinct from God in act rather than in essence; it was the manifestation of his will or of his intelligence. Thus the world is God ; but God is not the world. With- out the necessity of two principles, the distinction is preserved between the Creator and the Created. God is not confounded with Matter ; and yet philosophy is no longer oppressed with the difficulty of accounting for two eternally existing and eternally distinct principles. Plotinus had by his Dialectics discovered the necessity of Unity as the apex of existence: he had also by the same means discovered that the Unity could not possibly remain alone : otherwise, there would never have been the Many. If the Many implies the One, the One also implies the Many. It is the property of each principle to engender that which follows it : to engender it in virtue of an ineffable power which loses nothing of itself. This power, ineffable, inexhaustible, exercises itself without stopping, from generation to generation, till it attains the limits of possibility. By this law, which governs the world, and from which God himself cannot escape, the totality of existences, which Dialec- tics teach us to arrange in a proper hierarchy from God to sensible Matter, appear to us thus united in one indissoluble chain, since each being is the necessary product of that which precedes it, and the necessary producer of that which suc- ceeds it. If asked why Unity should ever become Multiplicity — why 308 THE DOCTRINE OF EMANATION. God should ever manifest himself in the world ? the answer is ready, The One, as conceived by the Eleats, had long been found incomplete ; for a God that had no intelligence could not be perfect : as Aristotle says, a God that does not think is unworthy of respect. If, therefore, God is Intelligent, he is necessarily active : a force that engenders nothing, can that be a real force ? It was, therefore, in the very nature of God a necessity for him to create the world : kv rrj vo-€L rjv to rroLciv. God, therefore, is in his very essence a Creator, iroirjTijs. He is like a Sun pouring forth his rays, without losing any of its substance : oiov ck 0