/7 P" LANGUAGE AN INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF SPEECH EDWARD SAPIR NEW YORK HARCOURT, BRACE AND COMPANY COPYBIGHT, 1921, BY Kabcoubt, brace aad company, ma Minted in the u s. k p / OS PREFACE This little book aims to give a certain perspective on the subject of language rather than to assemble facts about it. It has little to say of the ultimate psychologi- cal basis of speech and gives only enough of the actual descriptive or historical facts of particular languages to illustrate principles. Its main purpose is to show what I conceive language to be, what is its variability in place and time, and what are its relations to other fundamen- tal human interests — the problem of thought, the nature of the historical process, race, culture, art. The perspective thus gained will be useful, I hope, both to linguistic students and to the outside public that is half inclined to dismiss linguistic notions as the pri- vate pedantries of essentially idle minds. Knowledge of the wider relations of their science is essential to professional students of language if they are to be saved from a sterile and purely technical attitude. Among contemporary writers of influence on liberal thought Croce is one of the very few who have gained an under- standing of the fundamental significance of language. He has pointed out its close relation to the problem of art. I am deeply indebted to him for this insight. Quite aside from their intrinsic interest, linguistic forms and historical processes have the greatest possible diag- nostic value for the understanding of some of the more difficult and elusive problems in the psychology of thought and in the strange, cumulative drift in the life of the human spirit that we call history or progress or iv PREFACE evolution. This value depends chiefly on the uncon- scious and unrationalized nature of linguistic structure. I have avoided most of the technical terms and all of the technical symbols of the linguistic academy. There is not a single diacritical mark in the book. Where possible, the discussion is based on English ma- terial. It was necessary, however, for the scheme of the book, which includes a consideration of the protean forms in which human thought has found expression, to quote some exotic instances. For these no apology seems necessary. Owing to limitations of space I have had to leave out many ideas or principles that I should have liked to touch upon. Other points have had to be barely hinted at in a sentence or flying phrase. Never- theless, I trust that enough has here been brought to- gether to serve as a stimulus for the more fundamental study of a neglected field. I desire to express my cordial appreciation of the friendly advice and helpful suggestions of a number of friends who have read the work in manuscript, notably Profs. A. L. Kroeber and R. H. Lowie of the University of California, Prof. W. D. Wallis of Reed College, and Prof. J. Zeitlin of the University of Illinois. Edward Sapir. Ottawa, Ont., April 8, 1921. CONTENTS FAGB Pbefack iii CHAPTER I. Inteoductoey : Language Defined .... 1 Language a cultural, not a biologically inherited, function. Futility of interjectional and sound- imitative theories of the origin of speech. Defini- tion of language. The psycho-physical basis of speech. Concepts and language. Is thought possi- ble without language? Abbreviations and transfers of the speech process. The universality of lan- guage. II. The Elements of Speech 24 Sounds not properly elements of speech. Words and significant parts of words (radical elements, grammatical elements ) . Types of words. The word a formal, not a functional unit. The word has a real psychological existence. The sentence. The cognitive, volitional, and emotional aspects of speech. Feeling-tones of words. V III. The Sounds of Language 43 The vast number of possible sounds. The articu- lating organs and their share in the production of speech sounds: lungs, glottal cords, nose, mouth and its parts. Vowel articulations. How and where consonants are articulated. The phonetic habits of a language. The "values" of sounds. Phonetic patterns. IV. FoEM IN Language: Geajisiatical Peocesses . . 59 Formal processes as distinct from grammatical functions. Intercrossing of the two points of view. Six main types of grammatical process. Word sequence as a method. Compounding of radical elements. Affixing: prefixes and suffixes; infixes. Internal vocalic change; consonantal change. Re- duplication. Functional variations of stress; of pitch. vi CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE V. FoBM IN Language: Geammaticax Concepts . . S6 Analysis of a typical English sentence. Types of concepts illustrated by it. Inconsistent expression of analogous concepts. How the same sentence may be expressed in other languages with striking dif- ferences in the selection and grouping of concepts. Essential and non-essential concepts. The mixing of essential relational concejJts wiih secondary ones of more concrete order. Form for form's sake. Classiiication of linguistic concepts: basic or con- crete, derivational, concrete relational, pure rela- tional. Tendency for these types of concepts to flow into each other. Categories expressed in various grammatical systems. Order and stress as relating principles in the sentence. Concord. Parts of speech: no absolute classification possible; noun and verb. VI. Types of Linguistic Stbuctuee 127 Tlie possibility of classifying languages. Difficul- ties. Classification into form-languages and form- less languages not valid. Classification according to formal processes used not practicable. Classifi- cation according to degree of synthesis. "Inflec- tive" and "agglutinative." Fusion and symbolism as linguistic techniques. Agglutination. "Inflec- tive" a confused term. Threefold classification sug- gested: what types of concepts are expressed? what is the prevailing technique? what is the de- gree of synthesis? Four fundamental conceptual tj-pes. Examples tabulated. Historical test of the validity of the suggested conceptual classification. VII. Language as a Historical Product: Drift . . 157 Variability of language. Individual and dialectic variations. Time variation or "drift." How dia- lects arise. Linguistic stocks. Direction or "slope" of linguistic drift. Tendencies illustrated in an English sentence. Hesitations of usage as symptomatic of the direction of drift. Leveling tendencies in English. Weakening of case elements. Tendency to fixed position in tlie sentence. Drift toward the invariable word. VTTT. Language as a Historicai. PnonrcT: Phonetic Law 183 Parallels in drift in related lansniajrcs. Plionetic -^ law as illustrated in the history of certain English and German vowels and consonants. Regularity of CONTENTS vii CHAPTER PAGE phonetic law. Shifting of sounds without destruc- tion of phonetic pattern. Difficulty of explaining the nature of phonetic drifts. Vowel mutation in English and German. Morphological influence on phonetic change. Analogical levelings to offset irregularities produced by phonetic laws. New morplioiogical features due to phonetic change. IX. How Languages I.nfluexce Each Other . . . 205 Linguistic influences due to cultural contact. Bor- rowing of words. Resistances to borrowing. Plio- netic modification of borrowed words. Phonetic interinfluencings of neighboring languages. Mor- phological borrowings. iMorpliological resemblances as vestiges of genetic relationship. ^ X. Lajsguage, Race, and Culture 221 Naive tendency to consider linguistic, racial, and cultural groupings as congruent. Race and lan- guage need not correspond. Cultural and linguistic boiuidaries not identical. Coincidences between lin- guistic cleavages and those of language and culture due to historical, not intrinsic psycliological, causes. Language does not in any deep sense "re- flect" culture. XI. Language and Literature 236 Language as the material or medium of literature. Literature may move on tlie generalized linguistic plane or may be inseparable from specific linguistic conditions. Langiiago as a collective art. Neces- sary estlietic advantages or limitations in any lan- guage. Style as conditioned by inherent features of the language. Prosody as conditioned by the phonetic dynamics of a language. Index 249 LANGUAGE, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF SPEECH I INTRODUCTORY: LANGUAGE DEFINED Speech is so familiar a feature of daily life that we rarely pause to define it. It seems as natural to man as walking, and only less so than breathing. Yet it needs but a moment's reflection to convince us that this naturalness of speech is but an illusory feeling. The process of acquiring speech is, in sober fact, an utterly different sort of thing from the process of learning to walk. In the case of the latter function, culture, in other words, the traditional body of social usage, is not seriously brought into play. The child is individually equipped, by the complex set of factors that we term biological heredity, to make all the needed muscular and nervous adjustments that result in walking. Indeed, the very conformation of these muscles and of the ap- propriate parts of the nervous system may be said to be primarily adapted to the movements made in walking and in similar activities. In a very real sense the nor- mal human being is predestined to walk, not because his elders will assist him to learn the art, but because his organism is prepared from birth, or even from the moment of conception, to take on all those expendi- 1 2 LANGUAGE tures of nervous energy and all those muscular adap- tations that result in walking. To put it concisely, walking is an inherent, biological function of man. Not so language. It is of course true that in u cer- tain sense the individual is predestined to talk, but that is due entirely to the circumstance that he is born not merely in nature, but in the lap of a society that is certain, reasonably certain, to lead him to its tradi- tions. Eliminate society and there is every reason to believe that he will learn to walk, if, indeed, he survives at all. But it is just as certain that he will never learn to talk, that is, to communicate ideas according to the traditional system of a particular society. Or, again, remove the new-born individual from the social envi- ronment into which he has come and transplant him to an utterly alien one. He will develop the art of walking in his new environment very much as he would have developed it in the old. But his speech will be completely at variance with the speech of his native environment. Walking, then, is a general human ac- tivity that varies only within circumscribed limits as we pass from individual to individual. Its variability is involuntary and purposeless. Speech is a human activity that varies without assignable limit as we pass from social group to social group, because it is a purely historical heritage of the group, the product of long- continued social usage. It varies as all creative effort varies — not as consciously, perhaps, but none the less as truly as do the religions, the beliefs, the customs, and the arts of different peoples. Walking is an or- ganic, an instinctive, function (not, of course, itself an instinct) ; speech is a non-instinctive, acquired, "cul- tural" function. There is one fact that has frequently tended to pre- INTRODUCTORY 3 vent the recognition of language as a merely conven- tional system of sound symbols, that has seduced the popular mind into attributing to it an instinctive basis that it' does not really possess. This is the well-known observation that under the stress of emotion, say of a sudden twinge of pain or of unbridled joy, we do in- voluntarily give utterance to sounds that the hearer in- terprets as indicative of the emotion itself. But there is all the difference in the world between such invol- untary expression of feeling and the normal type of communication of ideas that is speech. The former kind of utterance is indeed instinctive, but it is non- symbolic; in other words, the sound of pain or the sound of joy does not, as such, indicate the emotion, it does not stand aloof, as it were, and announce that such and such an emotion is being felt. What it does is to serve as a more or less automatic overflow of the emotional energy ; in a sense, it is part and parcel of the emotion itself. Moreover, such instinctive cries hardly constitute communication in any strict sense. They are not addressed to any one, they are merely overheard, if heard at all, as the bark of a dog, the sound of approaching footsteps, or the rustling of the wind is heard. If they convey certain ideas to the hearer, it is only in the very general sense in which any and every sound or even any phenomenon in our environment may be said to convey an idea to the per- ceiving mind. If the involuntary cry of pain which is conventionally represented by "Oh!" be looked upon as a true speech symbol equivalent to some such idea as "I am in great pain," it is just as allowable to in- terpret the appearance of clouds as an equivalent sym- bol that carries the definite message "It is likely to rain." A definition of language, however, that is sp 4 LANGUAGE extended as to cover every type of inference becomes ut- terly meaningless. The mistake must not be made of identifying our conventional interjections (our oh! and ah! and sh!) with the instinctive cries themselves. These interjec- tions are merely conventional fixations of the natural sounds. They therefore diifer widely in various lan- guages in accordance with the specific phonetic genius of each of these. As such they may be considered an integral portion of speech, in the properly cultural sense of the term, being no more identical with the instinctive cries themselves than such words as ' ' cuckoo ' ' and ' ' kill- deer" are identical with the cries of the birds they denote or than Rossini's treatment of a storm in the overture to "William Tell" is in fact a storm. In other words, the interjections and sound-imitative words of normal speech are related to their natural prototypes as is art, a purely social or cultural thing, to nature. It may be objected that, though the interjections differ somewhat as we pass from language to language, they do nevertheless offer striking family resemblances and may therefore be looked upon as having grown up out of a common instinctive base. But their case is nowise different from that, say, of the varying national modes of pictorial representation. A Japanese picture of a hill both differs from and resembles a typical mod- ern European painting of the same kind of hill. Both are suggested by and both "imitate" the same natural feature. Neither the one nor the other is the same thing as, or, in any intelligible sense, a direct outgrowth of, this natural feature. The two modes of representa- tion are not identical because they proceed from differ- ing historical traditions, are executed with differing pictorial techniques. The interjections of Japanese and INTRODUCTORY 5 English are, just so, suggested by a common natural prototype, the instinctive cries, and are thus unavoid- ably suggestive of each other. They differ, now greatly, now but little, because they are builded out of histori- cally diverse materials or techniques, the respective linguistic traditions, phonetic systems, speech habits of the two peoples. Yet the instinctive cries as such are practically identical for all humanity, just as the hu- man skeleton or nervous system is to all intents and purposes a "fixed," that is, an only slightly and "acci- dentally" variable, feature of man's organism. Interjections are among the least important of speech elements. Their discussion is valuable mainly because it can be shown that even they, avowedly the nearest of all language sounds to instinctive utterance, are only superficially of an instinctive nature. Were it there- fore possible to demonstrate that the whole of lan- guage is traceable, in its ultimate historical and psycho- logical foundations, to the interjections, it would still not follow that language is an instinctive activity. But, as a matter of fact, all attempts so to explain the origin of speech have been fruitless. There is no tangible evi- dence, historical or otherwise, tending to show that the mass of speech elements and speech processes has evolved out of the interjections. These are a very small and functionally insignificant proportion of the vocabu- lary of language ; at no time and in no linguistic prov- ince that we have record of do we see a noticeable tend- ency towards their elaboration into the primary warp and woof of language. They are never more, at best, than a decorative edging to the ample, complex fabric. What applies to the interjections applies with even greater force to the sound-imitative words. Such words as "whippoorwill," "to mew," "to caw" are in no sense 6 LANGUAGE natural sound;; that man has instinctively or automati- cally reproduced. They are just as truly creations of the human mind, flights of the human fancy, as any- thing else in language. They do not directly grow out of nature, they are suggested by it and play with it. Hence the onomatopoetic theory of the origin of speech, the theory that would explain all speech as a gradual evolution from sounds of an imitative character, really brings us no nearer to the instinctive level than is language as we know it to-day. As to the theory itself, it is scarcely more credible than its interjectional coun- terpart. It is true that a number of words which we do not now feel to have a sound-imitative value can be shown to have once had a phonetic form that strongly suggests their origin as imitations of natural sounds. Such is the English word "to laugh." For all that, it is quite impossible to show, nor does it seem intrinsi- cally reasonable to suppose, that more than a negligible proportion of the elements of speech or anything at all of its formal apparatus is derivable from an onomato- poetic source. However much we may be disposed on general principles to assign a fundamental impor- tance in the languages of primitive peoples to the imi- tation of natural sounds, the actual fact of the matter is that these languages show no particular preference for imitative words. Among the most primitive peoples of aboriginal America, the Athabaskan tribes of the Mac- kenzie River speak languages in which such words seem to be nearly or entirely absent, while they are used freely enough in languages as sophisticated as English and German. Such an instance shows how little the essential nature of speech is concerned with the mere imitation of things. The way is now cleared for a servieeal)le deflnition INTRODUCTORY 7 of language. Language is a purely human and non- instinctive method of communicating ideas, emotions, and desires by means of a system of voluntarily produced symbols. These symbols are, in the first instance, audi- tory and they are produced by the so-called "organs of speech." There is no discernible instinctive basis in human speech as such, however much instinctive ex- pressions and the natural environment may serve as a stimulus for the development of certain elements of speech, however much instinctive tendencies, motor and other, may give a predetermined range or mold to lin- guistic expression. Such human or animal communica- tion, if ''communication" it may be called, as is brought about by involuntary, instinctive cries is not, in our sense, language at all. I have just referred to the "organs of speech," and it would seem at first blush that this is tantamount to an admission that speech itself is an instinctive, bio- logically predetermiiied activity. We must not be mis- led by the mere term. There are, properly speaking, no organs of speech; there are only organs that are incidentally useful in the production of speech sounds. The lungs, the larynx, the palate, the nose, the tongue, the teeth, and the lips, are all so utilized, but they are no more to be thought of as primary organs of speech than are the fingers to be considered as essentially or- gans of piano-playing or the knees as organs of prayer. Speech is not a simple activity that is carried on by one or more organs biologically adapted to the purpose. It is an extremely complex and ever-shifting network of adjustments — in the brain, in the nervous system, and in the articulating and auditory organs — tending towards the desired end of communication. The lungs developed, roughly speaking, in connection with the 8 LANGUAGE necessary biological function known as breathing; the nose, as an organ of smell; the teeth, as organs useful in breaking up food before it was ready for digestion. If, then, these and other organs are being constantly utilized in speech, it is only because any organ, once existent and in so far as it is subject to voluntary con- trol, can be utilized by man for secondary purposes. Physiologically, speech is an overlaid function, or, to be more precise, a group of overlaid functions. It gets what service it can out of organs and functions, nerv- ous and muscular, that have come into being and are maintained for very different ends than its own. It is true that physiological psychologists speak of the localization of speech in the brain. This can only mean that the sounds of speech are localized in the audi- tory tract of the brain, or in some circumscribed por- tion of it, precisely as other classes of sounds are lo- calized; and that the motor processes involved in speech (such as the movements of the glottal cords in the larynx, the movements of the tongue required to pro- nounce the vowels, lip movements required to articulate certain consonants, and numerous others) are localized in the motor tract precisely as are all other impulses to special motor activities. In the same way control is lodged in the visual tract of the brain over all those processes of visual recognition involved in reading. Nat- urally the particular points or clusters of points of localization in the several tracts that refer to any ele- ment of language are connected in the brain by paths of association, so that the outward, or psycho-physical, aspect of language, is of a vast network of associated localizations in the brain and lower nervous tracts, the auditory localizations being without doubt the most fundamental of all for speech. However, a speech- INTRODUCTORY 9 sound localized in the brain, even when associated with the particular movements of the "speech organs" that are required to produce it, is very far from being an element of language. It must be further associated with some element or group of elements of experience, say a visual image or a class of visual images or a feel- ing of relation, before it has even rudimentary linguistic significance. This "element" of experience is the con- tent or "meaning" of the linguistic unit; the associated auditory, motor, and other cerebral processes that lie immediately back of the act of speaking and the act of hearing speech are merely a complicated symbol of or signal for these ' ' meanings, ' ' of which more anon. We see therefore at once that language as such is not and cannot be definitely localized, for it consists of a peculiar symbolic relation — physiologically an arbitrary one — between all possible elements of consciousness on the one hand and certain selected elements local- ized in the auditory, motor, and other cerebral and nervous tracts on the other. If language can be said to be definitely "localized" in the brain, it is only in that general and rather useless sense in which all as- pects of consciousness, all human interest and activity, may be said to be "in the brain." Hence, we have no recourse but to accept language as a fully formed func- tional system within man's psychic or "spiritual" con- stitution. We cannot define it as an entity in psycho- physical terms alone, however much the psycho-physical basis is essential to its functioning in the individual. From the physiologist's or psychologist's point of view we may seem to be making an unwarrantable abstrac- tion in desiring to handle the subject of speech without constant and explicit reference to that basis. However, such an abstraction is justifiable. We can profitably dis- 10 LANGUAGE cuss the intention, the form, and the history of speech, precisely as we discuss the nature of any other phase of human culture — say art or religion — as an institutional or cultural entity, leaving the organic and psychologi- cal mechanisms back of it as something to be taken for granted. Accordingly, it must be clearly understood that this introduction to the study of speech is not con- cerned with those aspects of physiology and of physio- logical psychology that underlie speech. Our study of language is not to be one of the genesis and opera- tion of a concrete mechanism ; it is, rather, to be an in- quiry into the function and form of the arbitrary sys- tems of symbolism that we term languages. I have already pointed out that the essence of lan- guage consists in the assigning of conventional, volun- tarily articulated, sounds, or of their equivalents, to the diverse elements of experience. The word "house" is not a linguistic fact if by it is meant merely the acoustic effect produced on the ear by its constituent consonants and vowels, pronounced in a certain order; nor the motor processes and tactile feelings which make up the articulation of the word ; nor the visual perception on the part of the hearer of this articulation ; nor the visual perception of the word "house" on the written or printed page; nor the motor processes and tactile feel- ings which enter into the writing of the word ; nor the memory of any or all of these experiences. It is only when these, and possibly still other, associated experi- ences are automatically associated with the image of a house that they begin to take on the nature of a symbol, a word, an element of language. But the mere fact of such an association is not eiiougli. One might have heard a particular word spoken in an individual house under such impressive circumstances that neither the word INTRODUCTORY 11 nor the image of the house ever recur in consciousness without the other becoming present at the same time. This tj'pe of association does not constitute speech. The association must be a purely symbolic one; in other words, the word must denote, tag off, the image, must have no other significance than to serve as a counter to refer to it whenever it is necessary or convenient to do so. Such an association, voluntary and, in a sense, arbi- trary as it is, demands a considerable exercise of self- conscious attention. At least to begin with, for habit soon makes the association nearly as automatic as any and more rapid than most. But we have traveled a little too fast. Were the sym- bol "house" — whether an auditory, motor, or visual ex- perience or image — attached but to the single image of a particular house once seen, it might perhaps, by an indulgent criticism, be termed an element of speech, yet it is obvious at the outset that speech so constituted would have little or no value for purposes of commu- nication. The world of our experiences must be enor- mously simplified and generalized before it is possible to make a symbolic inventory of all our experiences of things and relations; and this inventory is imperative before we can convey ideas. The elements of language, the symbols that ticket off experience, must therefore be associated with whole groups, delimited classes, of experience rather than with the single experiences them- selves. Only so is communication possible, for the single experience lodges in an individual consciousness and is, strictly speaking, incommunicable. To be communicated it needs to be referred to a class which is tacitly accepted by the community as an identity. Thus, the single im- pression which I have had of a particular house must be identified with all my other impressions of it. Fur- 12 LANGUAGE ther, my generalized memory or my "notion" of this house must be merged with the notions that all other individuals who have seen the house have formed of it. The particular experience that we started with has now been widened so as to embrace all possible impres- sions or images that sentient beings have formed or may form of the house in question. This first simplification of experience is at the bottom of a large number of ele- ments of speech, the so-called proper nouns or names of single individuals or objects. It is, essentially, the type of simplification which underlies, or forms the crude subject of, history and art. But we cannot be con- tent with this measure of reduction of the infinity of experience. We must cut to the bone of things, we must more or less arbitrarily throw whole masses of ex- perience together as similar enough to warrant their being looked upon — mistakenly, but conveniently — as identical. This house and that house and thousands of other phenomena of like character are thought of as having enough in common, in spite of great and obvious differences of detail, to be classed under the same head- ing. In other words, the speech element "house" is the symbol, first and foremost, not of a single perception, nor even of the notion of a particiilar object, but of a "concept," in other words, of a convenient capsule of thought that embraces thousands of distinct experiences .and that is ready to take in thousands more. If the single significant elements of speech are the symbols of concepts, the actual flow of speech may be interpreted as a record of the setting of these concepts into mutual relations. The question has often been raised whether thought is possible without speech ; further, if speech and thought be not but two facets of the same psychic process. The INTRODUCTORY 13 question is all the more difficult because it has been hedged about by misunderstandings. In the first place, it is well to observe that whether or not thought neces- sitates symbolism, that is speech, the flow of language itself is not always indicative of thought. We have seen that the typical linguistic element labels a concept. It does not follow from this that the use to which lan- guage is put is always or even mainly conceptual. We are not in ordinary life so much concerned with con- cepts as such as with concrete particularities and spe- cific relations. When I say, for instance, * ' I had a good breakfast this morning," it is clear that I am not in the throes of laborious thought, ti^at what I have to transmit is hardly more than a pleasurable memory symbolically rendered in the grooves of habitual expres- sion. Each element in the sentence defines a sepa- rate concept or conceptual relation or both combined, but the sentence as a whole has no conceptual significance whatever. It is somewhat as though a dynamo capable of generating enough power to run an elevator were operated almost exclusively to feed an electric door- bell. The parallel is more suggestive than at first sight appears. Language may be looked upon as an instru- ment capable of running a gamut of psychic uses. Its flow not only parallels that of the inner content of con- sciousness, but parallels it on different levels, ranging from the state of mind that is dominated by particular images to that in which abstract concepts and their relations are alone at the focus of attention and which is ordinarily termed reasoning. Thus the outward form only of language is constant; its inner meaning, its psychic value or intensity, varies freely with attention or the selective interest of the mind, also, needless to say, with the mind's general development. From the point 14 LANGUAGE of view of language, thought may be defined as the high- est latent or potential content of speech, the content that is obtained by interpreting each of the elements in the flow of language as possessed of its very fullest concep- tual value. From this it follows at once that language and thought are not strictly coterminous. At best lan- guage can but be the outward facet of thought on the highest, most generalized, level of symbolic expression. To put our viewpoint somewhat differently, language is primarily a pre-rational function. It humbly works up to the thought that is latent in, that may eventually be read into, its classifications and its forms; it is not, as is generally but naively assumed, the final label put upon the finished thought. Most people, asked if they can think without speech, would probably answer, ''Yes, but it is not easy for me to do so. Still I know it can be done." Language is but a garment! But what if language is not so much a garment as a prepared road or groove ? It is, indeed, in the highest degree likely that language is an instru- ment originally put to uses lower than the conceptual plane and that thought arises as a refined interpretation of its content. The product grows, in other words, with the instrument, and thought may be no more conceivable, in its genesis and daily practice, without speech than is mathematical reasoning practicable without the lever of an appropriate mathematical symbolism. No one be- lieves that even the most difficult mathematical proposi- tion is inherently dependent on an arbitrary set of sym- bols, but it is impossible to suppose that the human mind is capable of arriving at or holding such a proposition without the symbolism. The writer, for one, is strongly of the opinion that the feeling entertained by so many that they can think, or even reason, without language INTRODUCTORY 15 is an illusion. The illusion seems to be due to a number of factors. The simplest of these is the failure to dis- tinguish between imagery and thought. As a matter of fact, no sooner do we try to put an image into con- scious relation with another than we find ourselves slip- ping into a silent flow of words. Thought may be a natural domain apart from the artificial one of speech, but speech would seem to be the only road we know of that leads to it. A still more fruitful source of the illusive feeling that language may be dispensed with in thought is the common failure to realize that lan- guage is not identical with its auditory symbolism. The auditory symbolism may be replaced, point for point, by a motor or by a visual symbolism (many people can read, for instance, in a purely visual sense, that is, with- out the intermediating link of an inner flow of the audi- tory images that correspond to the printed or written words) or by still other, more subtle and elusive, types of transfer that are not so easy to define. Hence the contention that one thinks without language merely be- cause he is not aware of a coexisting auditory imageiy is very far indeed from being a valid one. One may go so far as to suspect that the symbolic expression of thought may in some cases run along outside the fringe of the conscious mind, so that the feeling of a free, non- linguistic stream of thought is for minds of a certain type a relatively, but only a relatively, justified one. Psycho-physically, this would mean that the auditory or equivalent visual or motor centers in the brain, to- gether with the appropriate paths of association, that are the cerebral equivalent of speech, are touched off so lightly during the process of thought as not to rise into consciousness at all. This would be a limiting case — thought riding lightly on the submerged crests of speech, 16 LANGUAGE instead of jogging along with it, hand in hand. The modern psychology has shown us how powerfully sym- bolism is at work in the unconscious mind. It is there- fore easier to understand at the present time than it would have been twenty years ago that the most rarefied thought may be but the conscious counterpart of an unconscious linguistic symbolism. One word more as to the relation between language and thought. The point of view that we have developed does not by any means preclude the possibility of the growth of speech being in a high degree dependent on the development of thought. We may assume that lan- guage arose pre-rationally — just how and on what pre- cise level of mental activity we do not know — but we must not imagine that a highly developed system of speech symbols worked itself out before the genesis of distinct concepts and of thinking, the handling of con- cepts. We must rather imagine that thought processes set in, as a kind of psychic overflow, almost at the be- ginning of linguistic expression; further, that the con- cept, once defined, necessarily reacted on the .life of its linguistic symbol, encouraging further linguistic growth. We see this complex process of the interaction of language and thought actually taking place under our eyes. The instrument makes possible the product, the product refines the instrument. The birth of a new concept is invariably foreshadowed by a more or less strained or extended use of old linguistic material; the concept does not attain to individual and independent life until it has found a distinctive linguistic embodi- ment. In most cases the new symbol is but a thing wrought from linguistic material already in existence in ways mapped out by crushingly despotic precedents. As soon as the word is at hand, we instinctively feel, INTRODUCTORY 17 with something of a sigh of relief, that the concept is ours for the handling. Not until we own the symbol do we feel that we hold a key to the immediate knowl- edge or understanding of the concept. Would we be so ready to die for "liberty," to struggle for "ideals," if the words themselves were not ringing within us? And the word, as we know, is not only a key ; it may also be a fetter. Language is primarily an auditory system of sym- bols. In so far as it is articulated it is also a motor system, but the motor aspect of speech is clearly sec- ondary to the auditory. In normal individuals the im- pulse to speech first takes effect in the sphere of auditory imagery and is then transmitted to the motor nerves that control the organs of speech. The motor processes and the accompanying motor feelings are not, however, the end, the final resting point. They are merely a means and a control leading to auditory perception in both speaker and hearer. Communication, which is the very object of speech, is successfully effected only when the hearer's auditory perceptions are translated into the appropriate and intended flow of imagery or thought or both combined. Hence the cycle of speech, in so far as we may look upon it as a purely external instrument, begins and ends in the realm of sounds. The concordance between the initial auditory imagery and the final audi- tory perceptions is the social seal or warrant of the successful issue of the process. As we have already seen, the typical course of this process may undergo endless modifications or transfers into equivalent systems with- out thereby losing its essential formal characteristics. The most important of these modifications is the ab- breviation of the speech process involved in thinking. This has doubtless many forms, according to the struc- 18 LANGUAGE tural or functional peculiarities of the individual mind. The least modified form is that known as "talking to one's self" or "thinking aloud." Here the speaker and the hearer are identified in a single person, who may be said to communicate with himself. More signifi- cant is the still further abbreviated form in which the sounds of speech are not articulated at all. To this belong all the varieties of silent speech and of normal thinking. The auditory centers alone may be excited; or the impulse to linguistic expression may be communi- cated as well to the motor nerves that communicate with the organs of speech but be inhibited either in the mus- cles of these organs or at some point in the motor nerves themselves; or, possibly, the auditory centers may be only slightly, if at all, affected, the speech process mani- festing itself directly in the motor sphere. There must be still other types of abbreviation. How common is the excitation of the motor nerves in silent speech, in which no audible or visible articulations result, is shown by the frequent experience of fatigue in the speech or- gans, particularly in the larynx, after unusually stimu- lating reading or intensive thinking. All the modifications so far considered are directly patterned on the typical process of normal speech. Of very great interest and importance is the possibility of transferring the whole system of speech symbolism into other terms than those that are involved in the typical process. This process, as we have seen, is a matter of sounds and of movements intended to produce these sounds. The sense of vision is not brought into play. But let us suppose that one not only hears the articu- lated sounds but sees the ar'ticulations themselves as they are being executed by the speaker. Clearly, if one can only gain a sufficiently high degree of adroitness in INTRODUCTORY 19 perceiving these movements of the speech organs, the way is opened for a new type of speech symbolism — that in which the sound is replaced hy the visual image of the articulations that correspond to the sound. This sort of system has no great value for most of us be- cause we are already possessed of the auditory-motor sys- tem of which it is at best but an imperfect translation, not all the articulations being visible to the eye. How- ever, it is well known what excellent use deaf-mutes can make of "reading from the lips" as a subsidiary method of apprehending speech. The most important of all visual speech symbolisms is, of course, that of the writ- ten or printed word, to which, on the motor side, corre- sponds the system of delicately adjusted movements which result in the writing or typewriting or other graphic method of recording speech. The significant feature for our recognition in these new types of sym- bolism, apart from the fact that they are no longer a by-product of normal speech itself, is that each ele- ment (letter or written word) in the system corresponds to a specific element (sound or sound-group or spoken word) in the primary system. Written language is thus a point-to-point equivalence, to borrow a mathematical phrase, to its spoken counterpart. The written forms are secondary symbols of the spaken ones — symbols of sjonbols — yet so close is the correspondence that they may, not only in theory but in the actual practice of cer- tain eye-readers and, possibly, in certain types of think- ing, be entirely substituted for the spoken ones. Yet the auditory-motor associations are probably always latent at the least, that is, they are unconsciously brought into play. Even those who read and think without the slight- est use of sound imagery are, at last analysis, dependent on it. They are merely handling the circulating medium, 20 LANGUAGE the money, of visual symbols as a convenient substitute for the economic goods and services of the fundamental auditory symbols. The possibilities of linguistic transfer are practically unlimited. A familiar example is the Morse telegraph code, in which the letters of written speech are repre- sented by a conventionally fixed sequence of longer or shorter ticks. Here the transfer takes place from the written word rather than directly from the sounds of spoken speech. The letter of the telegraph code is thus a symbol of a symbol of a symbol. It does not, of course, in the least follow that the skilled operator, in order to arrive at an understanding of a telegraphic message, needs to transpose the individual sequence of ticks into a visual image of the word before he experiences its normal auditory image. The precise method of reading off speech from the telegraphic communication undoubt- edly varies widely with the individual. It is even con- ceivable, if not exactly likely, that certain operators may have learned to think directly, so far as the purely con- scious part of the process of thought is concerned, in terms of the tick-auditory symbolism or, if they happen to have a strong natural bent toward motor symbolism, in terms of the correlated tactile-motor symbolism de- veloped in the sending of telegraphic messages. Still another interesting group of transfers are the different gesture languages, developed for the use of deaf-mutes, of Trappist monks vowed to perpetual si- lence, or of communicating parties that are within see- ing distance of each other but are out of earshot. Some of these systems are one-to-one equivalences of the normal system of speech ; others, like military gesture-symbolism or the gesture language of the Plains Indians of North America (understood by tribes of mutually unintelligible INTRODUCTORY 21 forms of speech) are imperfect transfers, limiting them- selves to the rendering of such grosser speech elements as are an imperative minimum under difficult circum- stances. In these latter systems, as in such still more im- perfect symbolisms as those used at sea or in the woods, it may be contended that language no longer properly plays a part but that the ideas are directly conveyed by an utterly unrelated symbolic process or by a quasi- instinctive imitativeness. Such an interpretation would be erroneous. The intelligibility of these vaguer sym- bolisms can hardly be due to anything but their auto- matic and silent translation into the terms of a fuller flow of speech. We shall no doubt conclude that all voluntary com- munication of ideas, aside from normal speech, is either a transfer, direct or indirect, from the typical sym- bolism of language as spoken and heard or, at the least, involves the intermediary of truly linguistic symbolism. This is a fact of the highest importance. Auditory image- ry and the correlated motor imagery leading to articu- lation are, by whatever devious ways we follow the pro- cess, the historic fountain-head of all speech and of all thinking. One other point is of still greater importance. The ease with which speech symbolism can be transferred from one sense to another, from technique to technique, itself indicates that the mere sounds of speech are not the essential fact of language, which lies rather in the classification, in the formal patterning, and in the relat- ing of concepts. Once more, language, as a structure, is on its inner face the mold of thought. It is this ab- stracted language, rather more than the physical facts of speech, that is to concern us in our inquiry. There is no more striking general fact about language than its universality. One may argue as to whether a 22 LANGUAGE particular tribe engages in activities that are worthy of the name of religion or of art, but we know of no people that is not possessed of a fully developed lan- guage. The lowliest South African Bushman speaks in the forms of a rich symbolic system that is in essence perfectly comparable to the speech of the cultivated Frenchman. It goes without saying that the more ab- stract concepts are not nearly so plentifully represented in the language of the savage, nor is there the rich ter- minology and the finer definition of nuances that reflect the higher culture. Yet the sort of linguistic development that parallels the historic growth of culture and which, in its later stages, we associate with literature is, at best, but a superficial thing. The fundamental groundwork of language — the development of a clear-cut phonetic system, the specific association of speech elements with concepts, and the delicate provision for the formal ex- pression of all manner of relations — all this meets us rigidly perfected and systematized in every language known to us. Many primitive languages have a formal richness, a latent luxuriance of expression, that eclipses anything known to the languages of modern civilization. Even in the mere matter of the inventory of speech the layman must be prepared for strange surprises. Popular statements as to the extreme poverty of expression to which primitive languages are doomed are simply myths. Scarcely less impressive than the universality of speech is its almost incredible diversity. Those of us that have studied French or German, or, better yet, Latin or Greek, know in what varied forms a thought may run. The formal divergences between the English plan and the Latin plan, however, are comparatively slight in the per- spective of what we know of more exotic linguistic patterns. The universality and the diversity of speech INTRODUCTORY 23 lead to a significant inference. We are forced to be- lieve that language is an immensely ancient heritage of the human race, whether or not all forms of speech are the historical outgrowth of a single pristine form. It is doubtful if any other cultural asset of man, be it the art of drilling for fire or of chipping stone, may lay claim to a greater age. I am inclined to believe that it antedated even the lowliest developments of mate- rial culture, that these developments, in fact, were not strictly possible until language, the tool of significant expression, had itself taken shape. II THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH "We have more than once referred to the ' ' elements of speech," by which we understood, roughly speaking, what are ordinarily called "words." We must now look more closely at these elements and acquaint our- selves with the stuff of language. The very simplest element of speech — and by "speech" we shall hence- forth mean the auditory system of speech symbolism, the flow of spoken words — is the individual sound, though, as we shall see later on, the sound is not itself a simple structure but the resultant of a series of independent, yet closely correlated, adjustments in the organs of speech. And yet the individual sound is not, properly consid- ered, an element of speech at all, for speech is a signifi- cant function and the sound as such has no significance. It happens occasionally that the single sound is an inde- pendently significant element (such as French a "has" and a "to" or Latin i "go!"), but such cases are for- tuitous coincidences between individual sound and sig- nificant word. The coincidence is apt to be foi'tuitous not only in theory but in point of actual historic fact; thus, the instances cited are merely reduced forms of originally fuller phonetic groups — Latin liahct and ad and Indo-European ei respectively. If language is a structure and if the significant elements of language are the bricks of the structure, then the sounds of speech can only be compared to the unformed and unburnt clay of 24 THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 25 which the bricks are fashioned. In this chapter we shall have nothing further to do with sounds as sounds. The true, significant elements of language are gener- ally sequences of sounds that are either words, significant parts of words, or word groupings. What distinguishes each of these elements is that it is the outward sign of a specific idea, whether of a single concept or image or of a number of such concepts or images definitely con- nected into a whole. The single word may or may not be the simplest significant element we have to deal with. The English words sing, sings, singing, singer each con- veys a perfectly definite and intelligible idea, though the idea is disconnected and is therefore functionally of no practical value. We recognize immediately that these words are of two sorts. The first word, sing, is an indivisible phonetic entity conveying the notion of a certain specific activity. The other words all involve the same fundamental notion but, owing to the addition of other phonetic elements, this notion is given a par- ticular twist that modifies or more closely defines it. They represent, in a sense, compounded concepts that have flowered from the fundamental one. We may, therefore, analyze the words sings, singing, and singer as binary expressions involving a fundamental concept, a concept of subject matter (sing), and a further con- cept of more abstract order — one of person, number, time, condition, function, or of several of these com- bined. If we symbolize such a term as sing by the algebraic formula A, we shall have to symbolize such terms as sings and singer by the formula A -\-b.^ The element A may be either a complete and independent word (sing) or the fundamental substance, the so-called root or 1 We shall reserve capitals for radical elements. 2G LANGUAGE stem - or "radical element" (sing-) of a word. The ele- ment b (-S, -ing, -er) is the indicator of a subsidiary and, as a rule, a more abstract concept ; in the widest sense of the word ' ' form, ' ' it puts upon the fundamental con- cept a formal limitation. We may term it a " grammati- cal element" or affix. As we shall see later on, the gram- matical element or the grammatical increment, as we had better put it, need not be suffixed to the radical ele- ment. It may be a prefixed element (like the un- of unsingahle) , it may be inserted into the very body of the stem (like the n of the Latin vinco "I conquer" as contrasted with its absence in vici "I have conquered"), it may be the complete or partial repetition of the stem, or it may consist of some modification of the inner form of the stem (change of vowel, as in sung and song; change of consonant as in dead and death; change of accent; actual abbreviation). Each and every one of these types of grammatical element or modification has this peculiarity, that it may not, in the vast majority of cases, be used independently but needs to be somehow attached to or welded with a radical element in order to convey an intelligible notion. We had better, there- fore, modify our formula, A -\-h, to A -{-' (h), the round brackets symbolizing the incapacity of an element to stand alone. The grammatical element, moreover, is not only non-existent except as associated with a radical one, it does not even, as a rule, obtain its measure of signifi- cance unless it is associated with a particular class of radical elements. Thus, the -s of English he hits sym- bolizes an utterly different notion from the -s of hooks, merely because hit and book are differently classified as to function. We must hasten to observe, however, that while the radical element may, on occasion, be identical 2 These words are not here used in a narrowly technical sense. THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 27 with the word, it does not follow that it may always, or even customarily, be used as a word. Thus, the horU "garden" of such Latin forms as liortus, horti, and liorto is as much of an abstraction, though one yielding a more easily apprehended significance, than the -ing of singing. Neither exists as an independently intelligible and sat- isfying element of speech. Both the radical element, as such, and the grammatical element, therefore, are reached only by a process of abstraction. It seemed proper to symbolize sing-er as A -|- (&) ; hort-us must be symbolized as (A) + (6). So far, the first speech element that we have found which we can say actually ' ' exists ' ' is the word. Before defining the word, however, we must look a little more closely at the type of word that is illustrated by sing. Are we, after all, justified in identifying it with a radical element ? Does it represent a simple correspond- ence between concept and linguistic expression? Is the element sing-, that we have abstracted from sings, sing- ing, and singer and to which we may justly ascribe a general unmodified conceptual value, actually the same linguistic fact as the word singf It would almost seem absurd to doubt it, yet a little reflection only is needed to convince us that the doubt is entirely legitimate. The word sing cannot, as a matter of fact, be freely used to refer to its own conceptual content. The existence of such evidently related forms as sang and sung at once shows that it cannot refer to past time, but that, for at least an important part of its range of usage, it is lim- ited to the present. On the other hand, the use of sing as an "infinitive" (in such locutions as to sing and he will sing) does indicate that there is a fairly strong tendency for the word sing to represent the full, untram- meled amplitude of a specific concept. Yet if sing were. 23 LANGUAGE in any adequate sense, the fixed expression of the un- modified concept, there should be no room for such vo- calic aberrations as we find in sa7ig and simg and song, nor should we find sing specifically used to indicate preS' ent time for all persons but one (third person singular sings). The truth of the matter is that sing is a kind of twi- light word, trembling between the status of a true radical element and that of a modified word of the type of sing- ing. Though it has no outward sign to indicate that it conveys more than a generalized idea, we do feel that there hangs about it a variable mist of added value. The formula A does not seem to represent it so well as A. -j- (0). We might suspect sing of belonging to the A +(6) type, with the reservation that the (&) had vanished. This report of the ''feel" of the word is far from fanciful, for historical evidence does, in all earnest, show that sing is in origin a number of quite distinct words, of type A -\- (h), that have pooled their separate values. The (&) of each of these has gone as a tangible phonetic element ; its force, however, lingers on in weak- ened measure. The sing of / sing is the correspondent of the Anglo-Saxon singe; the infinitive sing, of singan; the imperative sing of sing. Ever since the breakdown of English forms that set in about the time of the Norman Conquest, our language has been straining towards the creation of simple concept-words, unalloyed by formal connotations, but it has not yet succeeded in this, apart, possibly, from isolated adverbs and other elements of that sort. Were the typical unanalyzable word of the language truly a pure concept-word (typ^ A) instead of being of a strangely transitional type (type A -\- [0] ), our sing and work and hoiise and thou sands of others would compare with the genuine radical- THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 29 words of numerous other languages.^ Such a radical- word, to take a random example, is the Nootka* word Jianiot "bone." Our English correspondent is only su- perficially comparable. Hamot means ' ' bone " in a quite indefinite sense ; to our English word clings the notion of singularity. The Nootka Indian can convey the idea of plurality, in one of several ways, if he so desires, but he does not need to ; Jiamot may do for either singular or plural, should no interest happen to attach to the dis- tinction. As soon as we say "bone" (aside from its secondary usage to indicate material), we not merely specify the nature of the object but we imply, whether we will or no, that there is but one of these objects to be considered. And this increment of value makes all the difference. We now know of four distinct formal types of word: A (Nootka liamot) ; A -\- (0) {sing,hone) ; A -\- (h) (singing) ; (A) + (&) (Latin hortus). There is but one other type that is fundamentally possible : A -{- B, the union of two (or more) independently occurring radical elements into a single term. Such a word is the compound fire-engine or a Sioux form equivalent to eat-stand (i.e., "to eat while standing"). It frequently happens, however, that one of the radical elements be- comes functionally so subordinated to the other that it takes on the character of a grammatical element. We may symbolize this by A -|- &, a type that may gradually, by loss of external connection between the subordinated element b and its independent counterpart B merge with the commoner type A -j- (&)• A word like heauti- 3 It is not a question of the general isolating character of such languages as Chinese ( see Chapter VI ) . Radical-words may and do occur in languages of all varieties, many of them of a high degree of complexity. 4 Spoken by a group of Indian tribes in Vancouver Island. 30 LANGUAGE fill is an example of A -]-b, the -fid barely preserving the impress of its lineage. A word like Jiomely, on the other hand, is clearly of the type A -{-' (h), for no one but a linguistic student is aware of the connection be- tween the -ly and the independent word like. In actual use, of course, these five (or six) funda- mental types may be indefinitely complicated in a num- ber of ways. The (0) may have a multiple value; in other words, the inherent formal modification of the basic notion of the word may affect more than one cate- gory. In such a Latin word as cor "heart," for in- stance, not only is a concrete concept conveyed, but there cling to the form, which is actually shorter than its own radical element (cord-), the three distinct, yet inter- twined, formal concepts of singularity, gender classifica- tion (neuter), and case (subjective-objective). The complete grammatical formula for cor is, then, A -\- (0) + (0) + W, though the merely external, phonetic formula would be (A)—, (A) indicating the abstracted "stem" cord; the minus sign a loss of material. The significant thing about such a word as cor is that the three conceptual limitations are not merely expressed by implication as the word sinks into place in a sentence; they are tied up, for good and all, within the very vitals of the word and cannot be eliminated by any possibility of usage. Other complications result from a manifolding of parts. In a given word there may be several elements of the order A (we have already symbolized this by the type A-\-' B), of the order (A), of the order h, and of the order (&). Finally, the various types may be com- bined among themselves in endless ways. A compara- tively simple language like English, or even Latin, illus- trates but a modest proportion of these theoretical possi* THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 31 bilities. But if we take our examples freely from the vast storehouse of language, from languages exotic as well as from those that we are more familiar with, we shall find that there is hardly a possibility that is not realized in actual usage. One example will do for thousands, one complex type for hundreds of possible types. I select it from Paiute, the language of the In- dians of the arid plateaus of southwestern Utah. The W'ord wii-to-kuclium-punku-ruga7ii-yiigwi-va-ntu-in{u) ^ is of unusual length even for its own language, but it is no psychological monster for all that. It means "they who are going to sit and cut up with a knife a black cow {or bull)," or, in the order of the Indian elements, "knife-black-buffalo-pet-cut up-sit(plur.) -future -parti- ciple-animate plur." The formula for this word, in ac- cordance with our symbolism, would be {F )-\- (E) -{- C + cZ-|-A-f B+(^) 4-(70 +(0 + (0). It is the plural of the future participle of a compound verb "to sit and cut up" — A -\- B. The elements (g) — which denotes futurity — , (7i) — a participial suffix — , and (i) — indicating the animate plural — are grammatical ele- ments which convey nothing when detached. The formula (0) is intended to imply that the finished word conveys, in addition to what is definitely expressed, a further relational idea, that of subjectivity; in other words, the form can only be used as the subject of a sentence, not in an objective or other syntactic relation. The radical element A ("to cut up"), before entering into combination with the coordinate element B ("to sit"), is itself compounded with two nominal elements or element-groups — an instrumentally used stem {F) 5 In this and other examples taken from exotic languages 1 am forced by practical considerations to simplify the actual phonetic forms. This should not matter perceptibly, as we are concerned with form as such, not with phonetic content. 32 LANGUAGE C knife"), which may be freely used as the radical element of noun forms but cannot be employed as an absolute noun in its given form, and an objectively used group— (^) -h C + (Z ("black cow or bull"). This group in turn consists of an adjectival radical element (E) ("black"), which cannot be independently em- ployed (the absolute notion of "black" can be rendered only as the participle of a verb: "black-be-ing"), and the compound noun C -{- d ("buffalo-pet"). The radi- cal element C properly means "buffalo," but the ele- ment d, properly an independently occurring noun mean- ing "horse" (originally "dog" or "domesticated ani- mal" in general), is regularly used as a quasi-subordi- nate element indicating that the animal denoted by the stem to which it is ai^xed is owned by a human being. It will be observed that the whole complex (F) -\- (E) -\-' C -\- d -\- A -\- B is functionally no more than a verba] base, corresponding to the sing- of an English form like singing; that this complex remains verbal in force on the addition of the temporal element (g) — this (g), by the way, must not be understood as appended to B alone, but to the whole basic complex as a unit — ; and that the elements (li) -|- (*) + (0) transform the verbal expression into a formally well-defined noun. It is high time that we decided just what is meant by a word. Our first impulse, no doubt, would have been to define the word as the symbolic, linguistic counterpart of a single concept. We now know that such a defini- tion is impossible. In truth it is impossible to define the word from a functional standpoint at all, for the word may be anything from the expression of a single concept — concrete or abstract or purely relational (as in of or by or and) — to the expression of a complete THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 33 thought (as in Latin dico "I say" or, with greater elabo- rateness of form, in a Nootka verb form denoting "I have been accustomed to eat twenty round objects [e.g., apples] while engaged in [doing so and so]"). In the latter case the word becomes identical with the sentence. The word is merely a form, a definitely molded entity that takes in as much or as little of the conceptual mate- rial of the whole thought as the genius of the language cares to allow. Thus it is that while the single radical elements and grammatical elements, the carriers of iso- lated concepts, are comparable as we pass from language to language, the finished words are not. Radical (or grammatical) element and sentence — these are the pri- mary functional units of speech, the former as an ab- stracted minimum, the latter as the esthetically satisfy- ing embodiment of a unified thought. The actual formal units of speech, the words, may on occasion identify themselves with either of the two functional units ; more often they mediate between the two extremes, embody- ing one or more radical notions and also one or more subsidiary ones. We may put the whole matter in a nutshell by saying that the radical and grammatical elements of language, abstracted as they are from the realities of speech, respond to the conceptual world of science, abstracted as it is from the realities of experi- ence, and that the word, the existent unit of living speech, responds to the unit of actually apprehended ex- perience, of history, of art. The sentence is the logical counterpart of the complete thought only if it be felt as made up of the radical and grammatical elements that lurk in the recesses of its words. It is the psychological counterpart of experience, of art, when it is felt, as in- deed it normally is, as the finished play of word with 34 LANGUAGE word. As the necessity of defining thought solely and exclusively for its own sake becomes more urgent, the word becomes increasingly irrelevant as a means. We can therefore easily understand why the mathematician and the symbolic logician are driven to discard the word and to build up their thought with the help of sym- bols which have, each of them, a rigidly unitary value. But is not the word, one may object, as much of an abstraction as the radical element? Is it not as arbi- trarily lifted out of the living sentence as is the mini- mum conceptual element out of the word? Some stu- dents of language have, indeed, looked upon the word as such an abstraction, though with very doubtful war- rant, it seems to me. It is true that in particular cases, especially in some of the highly synthetic languages of aboriginal America, it is not always easy to say whether a particular element of language is to be interpreted as an independent word or as part of a larger word. These transitional cases, puzzling as they may be on occasion, do not, however, materially weaken the case for the psy- chological validity of the word. Linguistic experience, both as expressed in standardized, written form and as tested in daily usage, indicates overwhelmingly that there is not, as a rule, the slightest difficulty in bringing the word to consciousness as a psychological reality. No more convincing test could be desired than this, that the naive Indian, quite unaccustomed to the concept of the written word, has nevertheless no serious difficulty in dictating a text to a linguistic student word by word ; he tends, of course, to run his words together as in actual speech, but if he is called to a halt and is made to under- stand what is desired, he can readily isolate the words as such, repeating them as units. He regularly refuses, on the other hand, to isolate the radical or grammatical THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 35 element, on the ground that it ' ' makes no sense. ' ' ^ What, then, is the objective criterion of the word? The speaker and hearer feel the word, let us grant, but how shall we justify their feeling? If function is not the ulti- mate criterion of the word, what is? It is easier to ask the question than to answer it. The best that we can do is to say that the word is one of the smallest, completely satisfying bits of isolated "mean- ing" into which the sentence resolves itself. It cannot be cut into without a disturbance of meaning, one or the other or both of the severed parts remaining as a help- less waif on our hands. In practice this unpretentious criterion does better service than might be supposed. In such a sentence as It is untJiinkahle, it is simply im- possible to group the elements into any other and smaller "words" than the three indicated. Tliink or thinkable might be isolated, but as neither un- nor -able nor is-un yields a measurable satisfaction, we are compelled to leave unthinkable as an integral whole, a miniature bit of art. Added to the "feel" of the word are frequently, but by no means invariably, certain external phonetic 6 These oral experiences, whch I have had time and again as a field student of American Indian languages, are very neatly confirmed by personal experiences of another sort. Twice I have taught intelligent young Indians to write their own languages according to the phonetic system which I employ. They were taught merely how to render accurately the sounds as such. Both had some difficulty in learning to break up a word into its con- stituent sounds, but none whatever in determining the words. This they both did with spontaneous and complete accuracy. In the hundreds of pages of manuscript NootKa text that I have ob- tained from one of these young Indians the words, whether ab- stract relational entities like English that and but or complex sentence-words like the Nootka example quoted above, are, prac- tically without exception, isolated precisely as I or any other student would have isolated them. Such experiences with naive speakers and recorders do more to convince one of the definitely plastic unity of the word than any amount of purely theoretical argument. 36 LANGUAGE characteristics. Chief of these is accent. In many, per- haps in most, languages the single word is marked by a unifying accent, an emphasis on one of the syllables, to which the rest are subordinated. The particular sylla- ble that is to be so distinguished is dependent, needless to say, on the special genius of the language. The im- portance of accent as a unifying feature of the word is obvious in such English examples as untJiinkahle, char- acterizing. The long Paiute word that we have analyzed is marked as a rigid phonetic unit by several features, chief of which are the accent on its second syllable {wii'- " knife") and the slurring ("unvoicing," to use the technical phonetic term) of its final vowel (-mii, animate plural) . Such features as accent, cadence, and the treat- ment of consonants and vowels within the body of a word are often useful as aids in the external demarcation of the word, but they must by no means be interpreted, as is sometimes done, as themselves responsible for its psy- chological existence. They at best but strengthen a feel- ing of unity that is already present on other grounds. We have already seen that the major functional unit of speech, the sentence, has, like the word, a psychologi- cal as well as a merely logical or abstracted existence. Its definition is not difficult. It is the linguistic ex- pression of a proposition. It combines a subject of dis- course with a statement in regard to this subject. Sub- ject and "predicate" may be combined in a single word, as in Latin dico; each may be expressed independently, as in the English equivalent, / say; each or either may be so qualified as to lead to complex propositions of many sorts. No matter how many of these qualifying elements (words or functional parts of words) are introduced, the sentence does not lose its feeling of unity so long as each and every one of them falls in place as contributory THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 37 to the definition of either the subject of discourse or the core of the predicate.^ Such a sentence as Tlie mayor of New York is goitig to deliver a speech of welcome i>* FrencJi is readily felt as a unified statement, incapable of reduction by the transfer of certain of its elements, in their given form, to the preceding or following sen- tences. The contributory ideas of of New York, of wel- come, and in French may be eliminated without hurting the idiomatic flow of the sentence. The mayor is going to deliver a speech is a perfectly intelligible proposition. But further than this we cannot go in the process of re- duction. We cannot say, for instance, Mayor is going to deliver.^ The reduced sentence resolves itself into the subject of discourse — the mayor — and the predicate — is going to deliver a speech. It is customary to say that the true subject of such a sentence is mayor, the true predicate is going or even is, the other elements being strictly subordinate. Such an analysis, however, is purely schematic and is without psychological value. It is much better frankly to recognize the fact that either or both of the two terms of the sentence-proposition may be incapable of expression in the form of single words. There are languages that can convey all that is conveyed by Tlie-mayor is-going-to-deliver-a-speech in two w^ords, a subject word and a predicate word, but English is not so highly synthetic. The point that we are really making here is that underlying the finished 7 "Cooidinate sentences" like / shall remain but you may go may only doubtfully be consi ered as truly unified predications, as true sentences. They are sentences in a stylistic sense rather than from the strictly formal linguistic standpoint. The orthography / shall remain. But you may go is as intrinsically justified as / shall remain. Noio you may go. The closer connection in senti- ment between the first two propositions has led to a conventional visual representation that must not deceive the analytic spirit. 8 Except, possibly, in a newspaper headline. Such headlines, however, are language only in a derived sense. 38 LANGUAGE sentence is a living sentence type, of fixed formal char- acteristics. These fixed types or actual sentence-ground- works may be freely overlaid by such additional matter as the speaker or writer cares to put on, but they are themselves as rigidly "given" by tradition as are the radical and grammatical elements abstracted from the finished word. New words may be consciously created from these fundamental elements on the analogy of old ones, but hardly new types of words. In the same way new sentences are being constantly created, but always on strictly traditional lines. The enlarged sentence, how- ever, allows as a rule of considerable freedom in the handling of what may be called "unessential" parts. It is this margin of freedom which gives us the opportunity of individual style. The habitual association of radical elements, gram- matical elements, words, and sentences with concepts or groups of concepts related into wholes is the fact itself of language. It is important to note that there is in all languages a certain randomness of association. Thus, the idea of "hide" may be also expressed by the word "conceal," the notion of "three times" also by "thrice." The multiple expression of a single concept is universally felt as a source of linguistic strength and variety, not as a needless extravagance. More irksome is a random correspondence between idea and linguistic expression in the field of abstract and relational con- cepts, particularly when the concept is embodied in a grammatical element. Thus, the randomness of the expression of plurality in such words as hooks, oxen, sheep, and geese is felt to be rather more, I fancy, an unavoidable and traditional predicament than a welcome luxuriance. It is obvious that a language cannot go beyond a certain point in this randomness. Many Ian- THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 39 guages go incredibly far in this respect, it is true, but linguistic history shows conclusively that sooner or later the less frequently occurring associations are ironed out at the expense of the more vital ones. In other words, all languages have an inherent tendency to economy of expression. Were this tendency entirely inoperative, there would be no grammar. The fact of grammar, a universal trait of language, is simply a generalized ex- pression of the feeling that analogous concepts and rela- tions are most conveniently symbolized in analogous forms. Were a language ever completely "grammati- cal," it would be a perfect engine of conceptual expres- sion. Unfortunately, or luckily, no language is tyranni- cally consistent. All grammars leak. ^ Up to the present we have been assuming that the material of language reflects merely the world of con- cepts and, on what I have ventured to call the "pre- rational" plane, of images, which are the raw mate- rial of concepts. We have, in other words, been assum- ing that language moves entirely in the ideational or cognitive sphere. It is time that we amplified the pic- ture. The volitional aspect of consciousness also is to some extent explicitly provided for in language. Nearly all languages have special means for the expres- sion of commands (in the imperative forms of the verb, for example) and of desires, unattained or unattainable (Would he might come! or Would he were here!) The emotions, on the whole, seem to be given a less adequate outlet. Emotion, indeed, is proverbially inclined to speechlessness. Most, if not all, the interjections are to be put to the credit of emotional expression, also, it may be, a number of linguistic elements expressing cer- tain modalities, such as dubitative or potential forms, which may be interpreted as reflecting the emotional 40 LANGUAGE states of hesitation or doubt — attenuated fear. On the whole, it must be admitted that ideation reigns supreme in language, that volition and emotion come in as dis- tinctly secondary factors. This, after all, is perfectly intelligible. The world of image and concept, the end- less and ever-shifting picture of objective reality, is the unavoidable subject-matter of human communication, for it is only, or mainly, in terms of this world that effective action is possible. Desire, purpose, emotion are the personal color of the objective world; they are ap- plied privately by the individual soul and are of rela- tively little importance to the neighboring one. All this does not mean that volition and emotion are not expressed. They are, strictly speaking, never absent from normal speech, but their expression is not of a truly linguistic nature. The nuances of emphasis, tone, and phrasing, the varying speed and continuity of utter- ance, the accompanying bodily movements, all these express something of the inner life of impulse and feeling, but as these means of expression are, at last analysis, but modified forms of the instinctive utterance that man shares with the lower animals, they cannot be considered as forming part of the essential cultural conception of language, however much they may be in- separable from its actual life. And this instinctive ex- pression of volition and emotion is, for the most part, sufficient, often more than sufficient, for the purposes of communication. There are, it is true, certain writers on the psychology of language ^ who deny its prevailingly cognitive char- acter but attempt, on the contrary, to demonstrate the origin of most linguistic elements within the domain of feeling. I confess that I am utterly unable to follow » E.g., the brilliant Dutch writer, Jac van Ginneken. THE ELEMENTS OF SPEECH 41 them. What there is of truth in their contentions may be summed up, it seems to me, by saying that most words, like practically all elements of consciousness, have an associated feeling-tone, a mild, yet none the less real and at times insidiously powerful, derivative of pleas- ure or pain. This feeling-tone, however, is not as a rule an inherent value in the word itself ; it is rather a senti- mental growth on the word's true body, on its conceptual kernel. Not only may the feeling-tone change from one age to another (this, of course, is true of the conceptual content as well), but it varies remarkably from indi- vidual to individual according to the personal associa- tions of each, varies, indeed, from time to time in a single individual's consciousness as his experiences mold him and his moods change. To be sure, there are so- cially accepted feeling-tones, or ranges of feeling-tone, for many words over and above the force of individual association, but they are exceedingly variable and elusive things at best. They rarely have the rigidity of the central, primary fact. "We all grant, for instance, that storm, teTTipest, and liurricane, quite aside from their slight differences of actual meaning, have distinct feel- ing-tones, tones that are felt by all sensitive speakers and readers of English in a roughly equivalent fashion. Storm, we feel, is a more general and a decidedly less "magnificent" word than the other two; tempest is not only associated with the sea but is likely, in the minds of many, to have obtained a softened glamour from a specific association with Shakespeare's great play; Jiur- ricane has a greater forthrightness, a directer ruthless- ness than its synonyms. Yet the individual's feeling- tones for these words are likely to vary enormously. To some tempest and hurricane may seem "soft," literary words, the simpler storm having a fresh, rugged value 42 LANGUAGE which the others do not possess (think of storm and stress). If we have browsed much in our childhood days in books of the Spanish Main, liurricane is likely to have a pleasurably bracing tone ; if we have had the misfortune to be caught in one, we are not unlikely to feel the word as cold, cheerless, sinister. The feeling-tones of words are of no use, strictly speaking, to science ; the philosopher, if he desires to arrive at truth rather than merely to persuade, finds them his most insidious enemies. But man is rarely en- gaged in pure science, in solid thinking. Generally his mental activities are bathed in a warm current of feel- ing and he seizes upon the feeling-tones of words as gentle aids to the desired excitation. They are natu- rally of great value to the literary artist. It is inter- esting to note, however, that even to the artist they are a danger. A word whose customary feeling-tone is too unquestioningly accepted becomes a plushy bit of fur- niture, a cliche. Every now and then the artist has to fight the feeling-tone, to get the word to mean what it nakedly and conceptually should mean, depending for the effect of feeling on the creative power of an indi- vidual juxtaposition of concepts or images. Ill THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE "We have seen that the mere phonetic framework of speech does not constitute the inner fact of language and that the single sound of articulated speech is not, as such, a linguistic element at all. For all that, speech is so inevitably bound up with sounds and their articu- lation that we can hardly avoid giving the subject of phonetics some general consideration. Experience has shown that neither the purely formal aspects of a language nor the course of its history can be fully understood without reference to the sounds in which this form and this history are embodied. A detailed survey of phonetics would be both too technical for the general reader and too loosely related to our main theme to warrant the needed space, but we can well afford to consider a few outstanding facts and ideas con- nected with the sounds of language. The feeling that the average speaker has of his lan- guage is that it is built up, acoustically speaking, of a comparatively small number of distinct sounds, each of which is rather accurately provided for in the current alphabet by one letter or, in a few cases, by two or more alternative letters. As for the languages of foreigners, he generally feels that, aside from a few striking dif- ferences that cannot escape even the uncritical ear, the sounds they use are the same as those he is familiar with but that there is a mysterious "accent" to these foreign languages, a certain unanalyzed phonetic character, apart 43 44 LANGUAGE from the sounds as such, that gives them their air of strangeness. This naive feeling is largely illusory on both scores. Phonetic analysis convinces one that the number of clearly distinguishable sounds and nuances of sounds that are habitually employed by the speakers of a language is far greater than they themselves recog- nize. Probably not one English speaker out of a hun- dred has the remotest idea that the ^ of a word like sting is not at all the same sound as the t of teem, the latter t having a fullness of "breath release" that is inhibited in the former ease by the preceding s; that the ea of meat is of perceptibly shorter duration than the ea of mead; or that the final s of a word like heads is not the full, buzzing z sound of the s in such a word as please. It is the frequent failure of foreigners, who have ac- quired a practical mastery of English and who have eliminated all the cruder phonetic shortcomings of their less careful brethren, to observe such minor distinctions that helps to give their English pronunciation the curi- ously elusive ''accent" that we all vaguely feel. We do not diagnose the "accent" as the total acoustic effect produced by a series of slight but specific phonetic er- rors for the very good reason that we have never made clear to ourselves our own phonetic stock in trade. If two languages taken at random, say Eng- lish and Russian, are compared as to their phonetic systems, we are more apt than not to find that very few of the phonetic elements of the one find an exact analogue in the other. Thus, the # of a Russian word like tarn "there" is neither the English t of sting nor the English t of tee7n. It differs from both in its ' ' den- tal" articulation, in other words, in being produced by contact of the tip of the tongue with the upper teeth, not, as in English, by contact of the tongue back of the THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 45 tip with the gum ridge above the teeth; moreover, it differs from the t of teem also in the absence of a marked "breath release" before the following vowel is attached, so that its acoustic effect is of a more precise, "metallic" nature than in English. Again, the English I is un- known in Russian, which possesses, on the other hand, two distinct ^sounds that the normal English speaker would find it difficult exactly to reproduce — a * ' hollow, ' ' guttural-like I and a "soft," palatalized Z-sound that is only very approximately rendered, in English terms, as ly. Even so simple and, one would imagine, so invaria- ble a sound as m differs in the two languages. In a Rus- sian word like rthost "bridge" the m is not the same as the m of the English word most; the lips are more fully roiuided during its articulation, so that it makes a heav- ier, more resonant impression on the ear. The vowels, needless to say, differ completely in English and Rus- sian, hardly any two of them being quite the same. I have gone into these illustrative details, which are of little or no specific interest for us, merely in order to provide something of an experimental basis to con- vince ourselves of the tremendous variability of speech sounds. Yet a complete inventory of the acoustic re- sources of all the European languages, the languages nearer home, while unexpectedly large, would still fall far short of conveying a just idea of the true range of human articulation. In many of the languages of Asia, Africa, and aboriginal America there are whole classes of sounds that most of us have no knowledge of. They are not necessarily more difficult of enuncia- tion than sounds more familiar to our ears ; they merely involve such muscular adjustments of the organs of speech as we have never habituated ourselves to. It may be safely said that the total number of possible 46 LANGUAGE sounds is greatly in excess of those actually in use. In- deed, an experienced phonetician should have no diffi- culty in inventing sounds that are unknown to objective investigation. One reason why we find it difficult to believe that the range of possible speech sounds is indefi- nitely large is our habit of conceiving the sound as a simple, unanalyzable impression instead of as the re- sultant of a number of distinct muscular adjustments that take place simultaneously. A slight change in any one of these adjustments gives us a new sound which is akin to the old one, because of the continuance of the other adjustments, but which is acoustically distinct from it, so sensitive has the human ear become to the nuanced play of the vocal mechanism. Another reason for our lack of phonetic imagination is the fact that, while our ear is delicately responsive to the sounds of speech, the muscles of our speech organs have early in life become exclusively accustomed to the particular ad- justments and systems of adjustment that are required to produce the traditional sounds of the language. All or nearly all other adjustments have become perma- nently inhibited, whether through inexperience or through gradual elimination. Of course the power to produce these inhibited adjustments is not entirely lost, but the extreme difficulty we experience in learning the new sounds of foreign languages is sufficient evidence of the strange rigidity that has set in for most people in the voluntary control of the speech organs. The point may be brought home by contrasting the comparative lack of freedom of voluntary speech movements with the all but perfect freedom of voluntary gesture.^ Our rigidity in 1 Obsprve the "voluntary." When we shout or grunt or other- wise allow our voices to take care of themselves, as we are likely to do when alone in the country on a fine spring day, we are no longer THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 47 articulation is the price we have had to pay for easy- mastery of a highly necessary symbolism. One cannot be both splendidly free in the random choice of move- ments and selective with deadly certainty.^ There are, then, an indefinitely large number of ar- ticulated sounds available for the mechanics of speech; any given language makes use of an explicit, rigidly economical selection of these rich resources; and each of the many possible sounds of speech is conditioned by a number of independent muscular adjustments that work together simultaneously towards its production. A full account of the activity of each of the organs of speech — in so far as its activity has a bearing on lan- guage — is impossible here, nor can we concern ourselves in a systematic way with the classification of sounds on the basis of their mechanics.^ A few bold outlines are all that we can attempt. The organs of speech are the fixing vocal adjustmonts by voluntary control. Under these cir- cumstances we are almost certain to hit on speech sounds that we could never learn to control in actvial speech. 2 If speech, in its acoustic and articulatory aspect, is indeed a rigid system, how comes it, one may plausibly object, that no two people speak alike? The answer is simple. All that part of speech which falls out of the rigid articulatory framework is not speech in idea, l)ut is merely a superadded, more or less instinc- tively determined vocal complication inseparable from speech in practice. All the individual color of speech — personal emphasis, speed, personal cadence, personal pitch — is a non-linguistic fact, just as the incidental expression of desire and emotion are, for the most part, alien to linguistic expression. Speech, like all elements of culture, demands conceptual selection, inhibition of the randomness of instinctive behavior. That its "idea" is never realized as such in practice, its carriers being instinctively ani- mated organisms, is of course true of each and every aspect of culture. 3 Purely acoustic classifications, such as more easily suggest themselves to a first attempt at analysis, are now in less favor among students of phonetics than organic classifications. The latter have the advantage of being more olijective. Moreover, the acoustic quality of a sound is dependent on the articulation, even though in linguistic consciousness this quality is the primary, not the secondary, fact. 48 LANGUAGE lungs and bronchial tubes; the throat, particularly that part of it which is known as the larynx or, in popular parlance, the "Adam's apple"; the nose; the uvula, which is the soft, pointed, and easily movable organ that depends from the rear of the palate; the palate, which is divided into a posterior, movable "soft palate" or velum and a "hard palate"; the tongue; the teeth; and the lips. The palate, lower palate, tongue, teeth, and lips may be looked upon as a combined resonance cham- ber, whose constantly varying shape, chiefly due to the extreme mobility of the tongue, is the main factor in giving the outgoing breath its precise quality * of sound. The lungs and bronchial tubes are organs of speech only in so far as they supply and conduct the current of outgoing air without which audible articulation is impossible. They are not responsible for any specific sound or acoustic feature of sounds except, possibly, accent or stress. It may be that differences of stress are due to slight differences in the contracting force of the lung muscles, but even this influence of the lungs is denied by some students, who explain the fluctuations of stress that do so much to color speech by reference to the more delicate activity of the glottal cords. These glottal cords are two small, nearly horizontal, and highly sensitive membranes within the larynx, which consists, for the most part, of two large and several smaller car- tilages and of a number of small muscles that control the action of the cords. The cords, which are attached to the cartilages, are to the human speech organs what the two vibrating reeds 4 By "quality" is here meant tlie inherent nature and resonance of the sound as such. The general "quality" of the individual's voice is another matter altogether. Tliis is chiefly determined by the individual anatomical characteristics of the larynx and is of no linguistic interest whatever. THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 49 are to a clarinet or the strings to a violin. They are ca- pable of at least three distinct types of movement, each of which is of the greatest importance for speech. They may be drawn towards or away from each other, they may vibrate like reeds or strings, and they may be- come lax or tense in the direction of their length. The last class of these movements allows the cords to vibrate at different "lengths" or degrees of tenseness and is responsible for the variations in pitch which are present not only in song but in the more elusive modulations of ordinary speech. The two other types of glottal action determine the nature of the voice, "voice" being a con- venient term for breath as utilized in speech. If the cords are well apart, allowing the breath to escape in un- modified form, we have the condition technically known as "voicelessness." All sounds produced under these circumstances are ' ' voiceless ' ' sounds. Such are the sim- ple, unmodified breath as it passes into the mouth, which is, at least approximately, the same as the sound that we v/rite Ji, also a large number of special articulations in the mouth chamber, like p and s. On the other hand, the glottal cords may be brought tight together, without vibrating. When this happens, the current of breath is checked for the time being. The slight choke or "arrested cough" that is thus made audible is not rec- ognized in English as a definite sound but occurs never- theless not infrequently.^ This momentary check, tech- nically known as a " glottal stop, " is an integral element of speech in many languages, as Danish, Lettish, certain Chinese dialects, and nearly all American Indian lan- guages. Between the two extremes of voicelessness, that 5 As at the end of the snappily pronounced no ! ( sometimes written nope!) or in the over-carefuUy pronounced at all, where one may hear a slight check between the t and the a. 50 LANGUAGE of completely open breath and that of checked breath, lies the position of true voice. In this position the cords are close together, but not so tightly as to prevent the air from streaming through ; the cords are set vibrating and a musical tone of varying pitch results. A tone so produced is known as a "voiced sound." It may have an indefinite number of qualities according to the precise position of the upper organs of speech. Our vowels, nasals (such as m and n), and such sounds as h, z, and I are all voiced sounds. The most convenient test of a voiced sound is the possibility of pronouncing it on any given pitch, in other words, of singing on it.^ The voiced sounds are the most clearly audible elements of speech. As such they are the carriers of practically all significant differences in stress, pitch, and syllabification. The voiceless sounds are articulated noises that break up the stream of voice with fleeting moments of silence. Acoustically intermediate between the freely unvoiced and the voiced sounds are a number of other character- istic types of voicing, such as murmuring and whisper.'^ These and still other types of voice are relatively unim- portant in English and most other European languages, but there are languages in which they rise to some prominence in the normal flow of speech. The nose is not an active organ of speech, but it is highly important as a resonance chamber. It may be 6 "Singitia;" is licre used in a wide sense. One cannot sing continuously on sncli a sound as h or d, but one may easily outline a tune on a series of &'s or d's in the manner of the plucked "pizzicato" on stringed instruments. A series of tones executed on continuant consonants, like m, z, or /, gives the effect of humming, droning, or buzzing. The sound of "liumming," in- deed, is nothing but a continuous voiced nasal, held on one pitch or varying in pitch, as desired. 7 The whisper of ordinary speech is a combination of unvoiced sounds and "whispered" sounds, as the term is understood in phonetics. THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 51 disconnected from the mouth, which is the other great resonance chamber, by the lifting of the movable part of the soft palate so as to shut off the passage of the breath into the nasal cavity ; or, if the soft palate is allowed to hang down freely and unobstructively, so that the breath passes into both the nose and the mouth, these make a combined resonance chamber. Such sounds as h and a (as in father) are voiced "oral" sounds, that is, the voiced breath does not receive a nasal resonance. As soon as the soft palate is lowered, however, and the nose added as a participating resonance chamber, the sounds h and a take on a peculiar "nasal" quality and become, respectively, m and the nasalized vowel written an in French (e.g., sang, tant). The only English sounds® that normally receive a nasal resonance are m, n, and the ng sound of sing. Practically all sounds, however, may be nasalized, not only the vowels — nasalized vowels are common in all parts of the world — but such sounds as I or z. Voiceless nasals are perfectly possible. They oc- cur, for instance, in Welsh and in quite a number of American Indian languages. The organs that make up the oral resonance chamber may articulate in two ways. The breath, voiced or un- voiced, nasalized or unnasalized, may be allowed to pass through the mouth without being checked or impeded at any point; or it may be either momentarily checked or allowed to stream through a greatly narrowed pas- sage with resulting air friction. There are also tran- sitions between the two latter types of articulation. The unimpeded breath takes on a particular color or quality in accordance with the varying shape of the oral reso- nance chamber. This shape is chiefly determined by the 8 Aside from the involuntary nasalizing of all voiced sounds in the speech of those that talk with a "nasal twang." 52 LANGUAGE position of the movable parts — the tongue and the lips. As the tongue is raised or lowered, retracted or brought forward, held tense or lax, and as the lips are pursed ("rounded") in varying degree or allowed to keep their position of rest, a large number of distinct qualities result. These oral qualities are the vowels. In theory their number is infinite, in practice the ear can dif- ferentiate only a limited, yet a surprisingly large, num- ber of resonance positions. Vowels, whether nasalized or not, are normally voiced sounds; in not a few lan- guages, however, ' ' voiceless vowels ' ' ^ also occur. The remaining oral sounds are generally grouped to- gether as "consonants." In them the stream of breath is interfered with in some way, so that a lesser reso- nance results, and a sharper, more incisive quality of tone. There are four main types of articulation generally recognized within the consonantal group of sounds. The breath may be completely stopped for a moment at some definite point in the oral cavity. Sounds so produced, like t or d or p, are known as "stops" or "explosives." ^° Or the breath may be con- tinuously obstructed through a narrow passage, not en- tirely checked. Examples of such "spirants" or "frica- tives," as they are called, are s and z and y. The third class of consonants, the "laterals," are semi-stopped. There is a true stoppage at the central point of articu- lation, but the breath is allowed to escape through the two side passages or through one of them. Our English d, for instance, may be readily transformed into I, 9 These may be also defined as free unvoiced breath with vary- ing vocalic timbres. In the ioiifj Paiiite word quoted on page 31 the first 11 and the final ii are pronounced without voice. 10 Nasalized stops, say m or n, can iiaturally not be truly "stopped," as there is no way of checking the stream of breath in the nose by a definite articulation. THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 53 which has the voicing and the position of d, merely by depressing the sides of the tongue on either side of the point of contact sufficiently to allow the breath to come through. Laterals are possible in many distinct posi- tions. They may be unvoiced (the Welsh II is an ex- ample) as well as voiced. Finally, the stoppage of the breath may be rapidly intermittent ; in other words, the active organ of contact — generally the point of the tongue, less often the uvula " — may be made to vibrate against or near the point of contact. These sounds are the ''trills" or "rolled consonants," of which the normal English r is a none too typical example. They are well developed in many languages, however, generally in voiced form, sometimes, as in Welsh and Paiute, in unvoiced form as well. The oral manner of articulation Ls naturally not suf- ficient to define a consonant. The place of articulation must also be considered. Contacts may be formed at a large number of points, from the root of the tongue to the lips. It is not necessary here to go at length into this somewhat complicated matter. The contact is either between the root of the tongue and the throat,^- some part of the tongue and a point on the palate (as in A; or ch or I), some part of the tongue and the teeth (as in the English th of thick and then), the teeth and one of the lips (practically always the upper teeth and lower lip, as in /), or the two lips (as in p or English w). The tongue articulations are the most complicated of all, as the mobility of the tongue allows various points on its surface, say the tip, to articulate against a number of opposed points of contact. Hence arise many positions 11 The lips also may theoretically so articulate. "Labial trills.* however, are certainly rare in natural speech. 12 This position, known as "faucal," is not common. 54 LANGUAGE of articulation that we are not familiar with, such as the typical "dental" position of Russian or Italian t and d; or the "cerebral" position of Sanskrit and other languages of India, in which the tip of the tongue articu- lates against the hard palate. As there is no break at any point between the rims of the teeth back to the uvula nor from the tip of the tongue back to its root, it is evident that all the articulations that involve the tongue form a continuous organic (and acoustic) series. The positions grade into each other, but each language selects a limited number of clearly defined positions as characteristic of its consonantal system, ignoring transi- tional or extreme positions. Frequently a language al- lows a certain latitude in the fixing of the required posi- tion. This is true, for instance, of the English A;-sound, which is articulated much further to the front in a word like Jdn than in cool. We ignore this difference, psycho- logically, as a non-essential, mechanical one. Another language might well recognize the difference, or only a slightly greater one, as significant, as paralleling the distinction in position between the k of kin and the t of tin. The organic classification of speech sounds is a simple matter after what we have learned of their production. Any such sound may be put into its proper place by the appropriate answer to four main questions : — What is the position of the glottal cords during its articula- tion? Does the breath pass into the mouth alone or is it also allowed to stream into the nose ? Does the breath pass freely through the mouth or is it impeded at some point and, if so, in what manner? What are the pre- cise points of articulation in the mouth ? " This f our- i"? "Points of articulation" must be understood to include tongue and lip positions of the vowels. THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 55 fold classification of sounds, worked out in all its de- tailed ramifications/* is sufficient to account for all, or practically all, the sounds of language.^^ The phonetic habits of a given language are not ex- haustively defined by stating that it makes use of such and such particular sounds out of the all but endless gamut that we have briefly surveyed. There remains the important question of the dynamics of these phonetic elements. Two languages may, theoretically, be built up of precisely the same series of consonants and vowels and yet produce utterly different acoustic effects. One of them may not recognize striking variations in the lengths or "quantities" of the phonetic elements, the other may note such variations most punctiliously (in probably the majority of languages long and short vow- els are distinguished ; in many, as in Italian or Swedish or Ojibwa, long consonants are recognized as distinct from short ones). Or the one, say English, may be very sensitive to relative stresses, while in the other, say French, stress is a very minor consideration. Or, again, the pitch differences which are inseparable from the actual practice of language may not affect the word as such, but, as in English, may be a more or less ran- dom or, at best, but a rhetorical phenomenon, while in other languages, as in Swedish, Lithuanian, Chinese, Siamese, and the majority of African languages, they may be more finely graduated and felt as integral characteristics of the words themselves. Varying meth- 14 Including, under the fourth category, a number of special resonance adjustments that we have not been able to take up specifically. 15 In so far, it should be added, as these sounds are expiratory, i.e., pronounced with the outgoing breath. Certain languages, like the South African Hottentot and Bushman, have also a num- ber of inspiratory sounds, pronounced by sucking in the breath at various points of oral contact. These are the so-called "clicks." 56 LANGUAGE ods of syllabifying are also responsible for noteworthy acoustic differences. Most important of all, perhaps, are the very different possibilities of combining the phonetic elements. Each language has its peculiarities. The ts combination, for instance, is found in both Eng- lish and Grerman, but in English it can only occur at the end of a word (as in hats), while it occurs freely in German as the psychological equivalent of a single sound (as in Zeit, Katze). Some languages allow of great heapings of consonants or of vocalic groups (diph- thongs), in others no two consonants or no two vowels may ever come together. Frequently a sound occurs only in a special position or under special phonetic cir- cumstances. In English, for instance, the s-sound of azure cannot occur initially, while the peculiar quality of the t of sting is dependent on its being preceded by the s. These dynamic factors, in their totality, are as im- portant for the proper understanding of the phonetic genius of a language as the sound system itself, often far more so. We have already seen, in an incidental way, that phonetic elements or such dynamic features as quantity and stress have varying psychological "values." The English ts of hats is merely a t followed by a func- tionally independent s, the ts of the German word Zeit has an integral value equivalent, say, to the t of the English word tide. Again, the t of time is indeed no- ticeably distinct from that of sting, but the difference, to the consciousness of an English-speaking person, is quite irrelevant. It has no ''value." If we compare the ^sounds of Haida, the Indian language spoken in the Queen Charlotte Islands, we find that precisely the same difference of articulation has a real value. In such a word as sting "two," the t is pronounced precisely THE SOUNDS OF LANGUAGE 57 as in English, but in sta "from" the t is clearly ''aspi- rated," like that of time. In other words, an objective dilTerenee that is irrelevant in English is of functional value in Haida; from its own psychological standpoint the t of sting is as different from that of sta as, from our standpoint, is the t of time from the d of divine. Further investigation would yield the interesting result that the Haida ear finds the difference between the Eng- lish t of sting and the d of divine as irrelevant as the naive English ear finds that of the ^sounds of sting and time. The objective comparison of sounds in two or more languages is, then, of no psychological or historical significance unless these sounds are first "weighted," un- less their phonetic ' ' values ' ' are determined. These val- ues, in turn, flow from the general behavior and func- tioning of the sounds in actual speech. These considerations as to phonetic value lead to an important conception. Back of the purely objective sys- tem of sounds that is peculiar to a language and which can be arrived at only by a painstaking phonetic analy- sis, there is a more restricted "inner" or "ideal" system which, while perhaps equally unconscious as a system to the naive speaker, can far more readily than the other be brought to his consciousness as a finished pattern, a psychological mechanism. The inner sound-system, over- laid though it may be by the mechanical or the irrelevant, is a real and an immensely important principle in the life of a language. It may persist as a pattern, in- volving number, relation, and functioning of phonetic elements, long after its phonetic content is changed. Two historically related languages or dialects may not have a sound in common, but their ideal sound-systems may be identical patterns. I would not for a moment wish to imply that this pattern may not change. It may 58 LANGUAGE shrink or expand or change its functional complexion, but its rate of change is infinitely less rapid than that of the sounds as such. Every language, then, is character- ized as much by its ideal system of sounds and by the underlying phonetic pattern (system, one might term it, of symbolic atoms) as by a definite grammatical struc- ture. Both the phonetic and conceptual structures show the instinctive feeling of language for form.^^ 16 The conception of the ideal phonetic system, the phonetic pattern, of a language is not as well understood by linguistic students as it should be. In this respect the unschooled recorder of language, provided he has a good ear and a genuine instinct for language, is often at a great advantage as compared with the minute phonetician, who is apt to be swamped by his mass of observations. I have already employed my experience in teach- ing Indians to write their own language for its testing value in another connection. It yields equally valuable evidence here. I found that it was difficult or impossible to teach an Indian to make phonetic distinctions that did not correspond to "points in the pattern of his language," however these differences might strike our objective ear, but that subtle, barely audible, phonetic differences, if only they hit the "points in the pattern," were easily and voluntarily expressed in writing. In watching my Nootka interpreter write his language, I often had the curious feeling that he was transcribing an ideal flow of phonetic ele- ments which he heard, inadequately from a purely objective standpoint, as the intention of the actual rumble of speech. IV FORM IN LANGUAGE: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES The question of form in language presents itself under two aspects. We may either consider the formal meth- ods employed by a language, its ** grammatical proc- esses," or we may ascertain the distribution of concepts with reference to formal expression. What are the for- mal patterns of the language? And what types of con- cepts make up the content of these formal patterns ? The two points of view are quite distinct. The English word untMnkingly is, broadly speaking, formally parallel to the word reformers, each being built up on a radical ele- ment which may occur as an independent verb {think, form), this radical element being preceded by an ele- ment {un-, re-) that conveys a definite and fairly con- crete significance but that cannot be used independently, and followed by two elements {-ing, -ly ; -er, -s) that limit the application of the radical concept in a relational sense. This formal pattern — (&) -\- A -{- {c) -\- (d) ^ — is a characteristic feature of the language. A countless number of functions may be expressed by it; in other words, all the possible ideas conveyed by such prefixed and suffixed elements, while tending to fall into minor groups, do not necessarily form natural, functional sys- tems. There is no logical reason, for instance, why the numeral function of -s should be formally expressed in 1 For the symbolism, see chapter II. 59 60 LANGUAGE a manner that is analogous to the expression of the idea conveyed by -ly. It is perfectly conceivable that in an- other language the concept of manner {-ly) may be treated according to an entirely different pattern from that of plurality. The former might have to be ex- pressed by an independent word (say, tlius unthinking), the latter by a prefixed element (say, plural ^-refonn-er). There are, of course, an unlimited number of other pos- sibilities. Even within the confines of English alone the relative independence of form and function can be made obvious. Thus, the negative idea conveyed by un- can be just as adequately expressed by a suffixed element {-less) in such a word as tlioughtlessly. Such a twofold formal expression of the negative function would be in- conceivable in certain languages, say Eskimo, where a suffixed element would alone be possible. Again, the plural notion conveyed by the -s of reformers is just as definitely expressed in the word geese, where an utterly distinct method is employed. Furthermore, the prin- ciple of vocalic change {goose — geese) is by no means confined to the expression of the idea of plurality; it may also function as an indicator of difference of time (e.g., sing — sang, throw — threw). But the expression in English of past time is not by any means always bound up with a change of vowel. In the great ma- jority of cases the same idea is expressed by means of a distinct suffix {die-d, work-ed). Functionally, died and sang are analogous; so are reformers and geese. Formally, we must arrange these words quite otherwise. Both die-d and re-fornh-er-s employ the method of suffix- ing grammatical elements; both sang and geese have grammatical form by virtue of the fact that their vowels differ from the vowels of other words with which they 2 "Plural" is here a symbol for any prefix indicating plurality. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 61 are closely related in form and meaning {goose; sing, sung). Every language possesses one or more formal methods for indicating the relation of a secondary concept to the main concept of the radical element. Some of these grammatical processes, like suffixing, are exceedingly wide-spread; others, like vocalic change, are less com- mon but far from rare ; still others, like accent and con- sonantal change, are somewhat exceptional as functional processes. Not all languages are as irregular as Eng- lish in the assignment of functions to its stock of gram- matical processes. As a rule, such basic concepts as those of plurality and time are rendered by means of one or other method alone, but the rule has so many exceptions that we cannot safely lay it down as a prin- ciple. Wherever we go we are impressed by the fact that pattern is one thing, the utilization of pattern quite another. A few further examples of the multiple ex- pression of identical functions in other languages than English may help to make still more vivid this idea of the relative independence of form and function. In Hebrew, as in other Semitic languages, the verbal idea as such is expressed by three, less often by two or four, characteristic consonants. Thus, the group sh-m-r expresses the idea of "guarding," the group g-n-h that of "stealing," n^t-n that of "giving." Naturally these consonantal sequences are merely abstracted from the actual forms. The consonants are held together in different forms by characteristic vowels that vary ac- cording to the idea that it is desired to express. Pre- fixed and suffixed elements are also frequently used. The method of internal vocalic change is exemplified in slianiar "he has guarded," shomer "guarding," sliamur "being guarded," shmor "(to) guard." Analogously, 62 LANGUAGE ganah "he has stolen," goneh "stealing," ganuh "being stolen," giwb "(to) steal." But not all infinitives are formed according to the type of slimor and gnob or of other types of internal vowel change. Certain verbs suffix a ^-element for the infinitive, e.g., ten-etJi "to give," lieyo-tli "to be." Again, the pronominal ideas may be expressed by independent words (e.g., anoki "I"), by prefixed elements (e.g., e-shmor "I shall guard"), or by suffixed elements (e.g., sliamar-ti "I have guarded"). In Nass, an Indian language of Brit- ish Columbia, plurals are formed by four distinct meth- ods. Most nouns (and verbs) are reduplicated in the plural, that is, part of the radical element is repeated, e.g., gyat "person," gyigyat "people." A second method is the use of certain characteristic prefixes, e.g., an'on "hand," ka-an'on "hands"; ivai "one paddles," lu-ivai "several paddle." Still other plurals are formed by means of internal vowel change, e.g., gwula "cloak," givila "cloaks." Finally, a fourth class of plurals is constituted by such nouiLs as suffix a grammatical ele- ment, e.g., ivahy "brother," wakykiv "brothers." From such groups of examples as these — and they might be multiplied ad 7iauseam — we cannot but con- elude that linguistic form may and should be studied as types of patterning, apart from the associated functions. We are the more justified in this procedure as all lan- guages evince a curious instinct for the development of one or more particular grammatical processes at the ex- pense of others, tending always to lose sight of any ex- plicit functional value that the process may have had in the first instance, delighting, it would seem, in the sheer play of its means of expression. It does not matter that in such a case as the English goose — geese, foul — defile, sing — sang — sung we can pro-«^e that we are dealing with FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 63 historically distinct processes, that the vocalic alternation of sing and sang, for instance, is centuries older as a specific type of grammatical process than the outwardly parallel one of goose and geese. It remains true that there is (or was) an inherent tendency in English, at the time such forms as geese came into being, for the utilization of vocalic change as a significant linguistic method. Failing the precedent set by such already ex- isting types of vocalic alternation as sing — sang — sung, it is highly doubtful if the detailed conditions that brought about the evolution of forms like teeth and geese from tooth and goose would have been potent enough to allow the native linguistic feeling to win through to an acceptance of these new types of plural formation as psychologically possible. This feeling for form as such, freely expanding along predetermined lines and greatly inhibited in certain directions by the lack of controlling types of patterning, should be more clearly understood than it seems to be. A general survej^ of many diverse types of languages is needed to give us the proper per- spective on this point. We saw in the preceding chap- ter that every language has an inner phonetic system of definite pattern. We now learn that it has also a definite feeling for patterning on the level of gram- matical formation. Both of these submerged and pow- erfully controlling impulses to definite form operate as such, regardless of the need for expressing particular concepts or of giving consistent external shape to par- ticular groups of concepts. It goes without saying that these impulses can find realization only in concrete func- tional expression. We must say something to be able to say it in a certain manner. Let us now take up a little more systematically, how- ever briefly, the various grammatical processes that lin- 64 LANGUAGE guistic research has established. They may be grouped into six main types : word order ; composition ; affixation, including the use of prefixes, suffixes, and infixes ; inter- nal modification of the radical or grammatical element, whether this affects a vowel or a consonant; reduplica- tion; and accentual differences, whether dynamic (stress) or tonal (pitch). There are also special quantitative processes, like vocalic lengthening or shortening and con- sonantal doubling, but these may be looked upon as par- ticular sub-types of the process of internal modification. Possibly still other formal types exist, but they are not likely to be of importance in a general survey. It is important to bear in mind that a linguistic phenomenon cannot be looked upon as illustrating a definite ''proc- ess" unless it has an inherent functional value. The consonantal change in English, for instance, of hooks and hags {s in the former, z in the latter) is of no func- tional significance. It is a purely external, mechanical change induced by the presence of a preceding voiceless consonant, k, in the former case, of a voiced consonant, g, in the latter. This mechanical alternation is objec- tively the same as that between the noun house and the verb to house. In the latter case, however, it has an im- portant grammatical function, that of transforming a noun into a verb. The two alternations belong, then, to entirely different psychological categories. Only the latter is a true illustration of consonantal modification as a grammatical process. The simplest, at least the most economical, method of conveying some sort of grammatical notion is to juxta- pose two or more words in a definite sequence without making any attempt by inherent modification of these words to establish a connection between them. Let us put down two simple English words at random, say FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 65 sing praise. This conveys no finished thought in Eng- lish, nor does it clearly establish a relation between the idea of singing and that of praising. Nevertheless, it is psychologically impossible to hear or see the two words juxtaposed without straining to give them some measure of coherent significance. The attempt is not likely to yield an entirely satisfactory result, but what is signifi- cant is that as soon as two or more radical concepts are put before the human mind in immediate sequence it strives to bind them together with connecting values of some sort. In the ease of sing praise different individ- uals are likely to arrive at different provisional results. Some of the latent possibilities of the juxtaposition, expressed in currently satisfying form, are : sing praise {to liiin) ! or singing praise, praise expressed in a song or to sing and praise or one who sings a song of praise (compare such English compounds as killjoy, i.e., one wJio kills joy) or Jie sings a song of praise (to him). The theoretical possibilities in the way of rounding out these two concepts into a significant group of concepts or even into a finished thought are indefinitely numerous. None of them will quite work in English, but there are numerous languages where one or other of these amplify- ing processes is habitual. It depends entirely on the genius of the particular language what function is in- herently involved in a given sequence of words. Some languages, like Latin, express practically all relations by means of modifications within the body of the word itself. In these, sequence is apt to be a rheto- rical rather than a strictly grammatical principle. Whether I say in Latin hominem feynina videt or fernina hominem videt or Jiominem videt femina or videt femina Jiominem makes little or no difference beyond, possibly, a rhetorical or •stylistic one. The woman sees the man 66 LANGUAGE is the identical significance of each of these sentences. In Chinook, an Indian language of the Columbia River, one can be equally free, for the relation between the verb and the two nouns is as inherently fixed as in Latin. The difference between the two languages is that, while Latin allows the nouns to establish their relation to each other and to the verb, Chinook lays the formal burden entirely on the verb, the full content of which is more or less adequately rendered by sJie-him-sees. Eliminate the Latin case suffixes {-a and -em) and the Chinook pronominal prefixes {she-him-) and we cannot afford to be so indifferent to our word order. We need to husband our resources. In other words, word order takes on a real functional value. Latin and Chinook are at one extreme. Such languages as Chinese, Siam- ese, and Annamite, in which each and every word, if it is to function properly, falls into its assigned place, are at the other extreme. But the majority of languages fall between these two extremes. In English, for in- stance, it may make little grammatical difference whether I say yesterday the man saw the dog or the man saw the dog yesterday, but it is not a matter of indifference whether I say yesterday the man saw the dog or yester- day the dog saw the m.an or whether I say he is here or is he here? In the one case, of the latter group of ex- amples, the vital distinction of subject and object de- pends entirely on the placing of certain words of the sentence, in the latter a slight difference of sequence makes all the difference between statement and ques- tion. It goes without saying that in these cases the Eng- lish principle of word order is as potent a means of expression as is the Lntin use of case suffixes or of an in- terrogative particle. There is here no question of func* tional poverty, but of formal economy. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 67 We have already seen something of the process of composition, the uniting into a single word of two or more radical elements. Psychologically this process is closely allied to that of word order in so far as the relation between the elements is implied, not explicitly stated. It differs from the mere juxtaposition of words in the sentence in that the compounded elements are felt as constituting but parts of a single word-organism. Such languages as Chinese and English, in which the principle of rigid sequence is well developed, tend not infrequently also to the development of compound words. It is but a step from such a Chinese word sequence as jin tak "man virtue," i.e., "the virtue of men," to such more conventionalized and psychologically unified juxtaposi- tions as t'ien tsz "heaven son," i.e., "emperor," or shut fu "water man," i.e., "water carrier." In the latter case we may as well frankly write shui-fu as a single word, the meaning of the compound as a whole being as divergent from the precise etymological val- ues of its component elements as is that of our English word typewriter from the merely combined values of type and writer. In English the unity of the word typewriter is further safeguarded by a predominant ac- cent on the first syllable and by the possibility of adding such a suffixed element as the plural -s to the whole word. Chinese also unifies its compounds by means of stress. However, then, in its ultimate origins the pro- cess of composition may go back to typical sequences of words in the sentence, it is now, for the most part, a specialized method of expressing relations. French has as rigid a word order as English but does not possess anything like its power of compounding words into more complex units. On the other hand, classical Greek, in spite of its relative freedom in the placing of word^ 68 LANGUAGE has a very considerable bent for the formation of com- pound terms. It is curious to observe how greatly languages differ in their ability to make use of the process of composi- tion. One would have thought on general principles that so simple a device as gives us our typewriter and blackhird and hosts of other words would be an all but universal grammatical process. Such is not the case. There are a great many languages, like Eskimo and Nootka and, aside from paltry exceptions, the Semitic languages, that cannot compound radical elements. "What is even stranger is the fact that many of these languages are not in the least averse to complex word- formations, but may on the contrary effect a synthesis that far surpasses the utmost that Greek and Sanskrit are capable of. Such a Nootka word, for instance, as "when, as they say, he had been absent for four days" might be expected to embody at least three radical ele- ments corresponding to the concepts of "absent," "four," and "day." As a matter of fact the Nootka word is utterly incapable of composition in our sense. It is invariably built up out of a single radical element and a greater or less number of suffixed elements, some of which may have as concrete a significance as the radical element itself. In the particular case we have cited the radical element conveys the idea of "four," the notions of "day" and "absent" being expressed by suffixes that are as inseparable from the radical nucleus of the word as is an English element like -er from the sing or Jumt of such words as siiiger and hunter. The tendency to word synthesis is, then, by no means the same thing as the tendency to compounding radical ele- ments, though the latter is not infrequently a ready means for the synthetic tendency to work with. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 69 There is a bewildering variety of types of composi- tion. These types vary according to function, the nature of the compounded elements, and order. In a great many languages composition is confined to what we may call the delimiting function, that is, of the two or more compounded elements one is given a more precisely qualified significance by the others, which con- tribute nothing to the formal build of the sentence. In English, for instance, such compounded elements as red in redcoat or over in overlook merely modify the signifi- cance of the dominant coat or look without in any way sharing, as such, in the predication that is expressed by the sentence. Some languages, however, such as Iro- quois and Nahuatl,^ employ the method of composition for much heavier work than this. In Iroquois, for in- stance, the composition of a noun, in its radical form, with a following verb is a typical method of expressing case relations, particularly of the subject or object. I- meat-eat, for instance, is the regular Iroquois method of expressing the sentence I am eating meat. In other languages similar forms may express local or instru- mental or still other relations. Such English forms as killjoy and marplot also illustrate the compounding of a verb and a noun, but the resulting word has a strictly nominal, not a verbal, function. We cannot say lie marplots. Some languages allow the composition of all or nearly all types of elements. Paiute, for instance, may compound noun with noun, adjective with noun, verb with noun to make a noun, noun with verb to make a verb, adverb with verb, verb with verb. Yana, an Indian language of California, can freely compound noun with noun and verb with noun, but not verb with verb. 3 The language of the Aztecs, still spoken in large parts of Mexico. 70 LANGUAGE On the other hand, Iroquois can compound only noun with verb, never noun and noun as in English or verb and verb as in so many other languages. Finally, each language has its characteristic types of order of com- position. In English the qualifying element regularly precedes ; in certain other languages it follows. Some- times both types are used in the same language, as in Yana, where "beef" is "bitter-venison" but "deer- liver" is expressed by "liver-deer." The compounded object of a verb precedes the verbal element in Paiute, Nahuatl, and Iroquois, follows it in Yana, Tsimshian,* and the Algonkin languages. Of all grammatical processes affixing is incomparably the most frequently employed. There are languages, like Chinese and Siamese, that make no grammatical use of elements that do not at the same time possess an independent value as radical elements, but such lan- guages are uncommon. Of the three types of affixing — the use of prefixes, suffixes, and infixes — suffixing is much the commonest. Indeed, it is a fair guess that suffixes do more of the formative work of language than all other methods combined. It is worth noting that there are not a few affixing languages that make absolutely no use of prefixed elements but possess a complex apparatus of suffixes. Such are Turkish, Hot- tentot, Eskimo, Nootka, and Yana. Some of these, like the three last mentioned, have hundreds of suffixed ele- ments, many of them of a concreteness of significance that would demand expression in the vast majority of languages by means of radical elements. The reverse case, the use of prefixed elements to the complete exclu- sion of suffixes, is far less common. A good example is 4 An Tndin?! lini'niasjc! of British Columbia closely related to the Nass already cited. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 71 Khmer (or Cambodgian), spoken in French Coehin- China, though even here there are obscure traces of old suffixes that have ceased to function as such and are now felt to form part of the radical element. A considerable majority of known languages are prefixing and suffixing at one and the same time, but the relative importance of the two groups of affixed elements naturally varies enormously. In some lan- guages, such as Latin and Russian, the suffixes alone re- late the word to the rest of the sentence, the prefixes be- ing confined to the expression of such ideas as delimit the concrete significance of the radical element without influencing its bearing in the proposition. A Latin form like remittehantur "they were being sent back" may serve as an illustration of this type of distribution of elements. The prefixed element re- "back" merely qual- ifies to a certain extent the inherent significance of the radical element mitt- "send," while the suffixes -eha-, -nt-, and -ur convey the less concrete, more strictly for- mal, notions of time, person, plurality, and passivity. On the other hand, there are languages, like the Bantu group of Africa or the Athabaskan languages ^ of North America, in which the grammatically'^ signifi- cant elements precede, those that follow the radical ele- ment forming a relatively dispensable class. The Hupa word te-s-e-ya-te "I will go," for example, consists of a radical element -ya- "to go," three essential prefixes and a formally subsidiary suffix. The element te- indicates that the act takes place here and there in space or con- tinuously over space ; practically, it has no clear-cut sig- nificance apart from such verb stems as it is customary to connect it with. The second prefixed element, -s-, is s TnoliKlincr siifh languages as Navaho, Apache, Hupa, Carrier Chipewyan, Loucheux. 72 LANGUAGE even less easy to define. All we can say is that it is used in verb forms of ' ' definite ' ' time and that it marks action as in progress rather than as beginning or coming to an end. The third prefix, -e-, is a pronominal ele- ment, "I," which can be used only in "definite" tenses. It is highly important to understand that the use of -e- is conditional on that of -s- or of certain alternative pre- fixes and that te- also is in practice linked with -s-. The group te-s-e-ya is a firmly knit grammatical unit. The suffix -te, which indicates the future, is no more necessary to its formal balance than is the prefixed re- of the Latin word; it is not an element that is capable of standing alone but its function is materially delimiting rather than strictly formal.* It is not always, however, that we can clearly set off the suffixes of a language as a group against its pre- fixes. In probably the majority of languages that use both types of affixes each group has both delimiting and formal or relational functions. The most that we can say is that a language tends to express similar functions in either the one or the other manner. If a certain verb expresses a certain tense by suffixing, the probability is strong that it expresses its other tenses in an analogous fashion and that, indeed, all verbs have suffixed tense ele- ments. Similarly, we normally expect to find the pro- nominal elements, so far as they are included in the verb at all, either consistently prefixed or suffixed. But 6 This may seem surprising to an Enfjlish reader. We generally think of time as a function that is appropriately expressed in a purely formal manner. This notion is due to the bias that Latin grammar has given us. As a matter of fact the English future (/ shall go) is not expressed by affixing at all; moreover, it may be expressed by the present, as in to-morrow I leave this place, where the temporal function is inherent in the independent adverb. Though in lesser degree, the Hupa -te is as irrevelant to the vital word as is to-morrow to the grammatical "feel" of / leave. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 73 these rules are far from absolute. We have already seen that Hebrew prefixes its pronominal elements in certain cases, suffixes them in others. In Chimariko, an Indian language of California, the position of the pro- nominal affixes depends on the verb; they are prefixed for certain verbs, suffixed for others. It will not be necessary to give many further examples of prefixing and suffixing. One of each category will suffice to illustrate their formative possibilities. The idea expressed in English by the sentence / ca7ne to give it to her is rendered in Chinook ^ by i-n-i-a-l-u-d-am. This word — and it is a thoroughly unified word with a clear-cut accent on the first a — consists of a radical ele- ment, -d- ''to give," six functionally distinct, if phoneti- cally frail, prefixed elements, and a suffix. Of the pre- fixes, i- indicates recently past time; n-, the pronominal subject "I"; -i-, the pronominal object "it";^ -a-, the second pronominal object "her"; -1-, a prepositional ele- ment indicating that the preceding pronominal prefix is to be understood as an indirect object {-Jier-to-, i.e., "to her") ; and -u-, an element that it is not easy to define satisfactorily but which, on the whole, indicates movement away from the speaker. The suffixed -am modifies the verbal content in a local sense ; it adds to the notion conveyed by the radical element that of "ar- riving" or "going (or coming) for that particular pur- pose." It is obvious that in Chinook, as in Hupa, the greater part of the grammatical machinery resides in the prefixes rather than in the suffixes. A reverse case, one in which the grammatically signifi- cant elements cluster, as in Latin, at the end of the word 7 Wishram dialect. 8 Really "him," but Chinook, like Latin or French, possesses grammatical gender. An object may be referred to as "he," "she," or "it," according to the characteristic form of its noun. 74 LANGUAGE is yielded by Fox, one of the better known Algonkin lan- guages of the Mississippi Valley. We may take the form eh-kiwi-n-a-m-olit-ati-wa-cli{i) "then they together kept (him) in flight from them." The radical element here is kiwi-, a verb stem indicating the general notion of "indefinite movement round about, here and there." The prefixed element eh- is hardly more than an ad- verbial particle indicating temporal subordination; it may be conveniently rendered as "then." Of the seven suffixes included in this highly-wrought word, -n- seems to be merely a phonetic element serving to connect the verb stem with the following -a-;^ -a- is a "secondary stem"^" denoting the idea of "flight, to flee"; -m- de- notes causality with reference to an animate object ;^^ -o{Jit)- indicates activity done for the subject (the so- called "middle" or "medio-passive" voice of Greek) ; -{a)ti- is a reciprocal element, "one another"; -iva-ch{i) is the third person animate plural (-^vn-, plural; -cJii, more properly personal) of so-called "conjunctive" forms. The word may be translated more literally (and yet only approximately as to grammatical feeling) as "then they (animate) caused some animate being to wander about in flight from one another of themselves." Eskimo, Nootka, Yana, and other languages have simi- larly complex arrays of sufflxed elements, though the This analysis is doubtful. Tt is likely that -n- possesses a function that still remains to be ascertained. The Alf!;onkin lan- guages are unusually complex and present ] any unsolved prob- lems of detail. in "Secondary stems" are elements which are suffixes from a formal point of view, never appearing without the support of a true radical element, but whose function is as concrete, to all intents and purposes, as that of the radical element itself. Sec- ondary verb stems of this type are characteristic of the Algonkin languages and of Yana. 11 In the Algonkin languages all persons and things are con- ceived of as either animate or inanimate, just as in Latin or German they are conceived of as masculine, feminine, or neuter. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 75 functions performed by them and their principles of combination differ widely. We have reserved the very curious type of af- fixation known as "infixing" for separate illustra- tion. It is utterly unknown in English, unless we consider the -n- of stand (contrast stood) as an in- fixed element. The earlier Indo-European languages, such as Latin, Greek and Sanskrit, made a fairly considerable use of infixed nasals to differentiate the present tense of a certain class of verbs from other forms (contrast Latin vinc-o "I conquer" with vic-i "I con- quered"; Greek lamh-an-o "I take" with e-lah-on "I took"). There are, however, more striking examples of the process, examples in which it has assumed a more clearly defined function than in these Latin and Greek cases. It is particularly prevalent in many languages of southeastern Asia and of the Malay archipelago. Good examples from Khmer (Cambodgian) are tmeu "one who walks" and daneu "walking" (verbal noun), both derived from deu "to walk." Further examples may be quoted from Bontoc Igorot, a Filipino language. Thus, an infixed -in- conveys the idea of the product of an accomplished action, e.g., kayu "wood," kinayu "gath- ered wood." Infixes are also freely used in the Bontoc Igorot verb. Thus, an infixed -uni- is characteristic of many intransitive verbs with personal pronominal suf- fixes, e.g., sad- **to wait," sumid-ak "I wait"; kineg "silent," kuminek-ak "I am silent." In other verbs it indicates futurity, e.g., tengao- "to celebrate a holi- day," tumengao-ak "I shall have a holiday." The past tense is frequently indicated by an infixed -in-; if there is already an infixed -um-, the two elements combine to -in-m-, e.g., kinminek-ak "I am silent." Obviously the infixing process has in this (and related) languages the 76 LANGUAGE same vitality that is possessed by the commoner prefixes and suffixes of other languages. The process is also found in a number of aboriginal American languages. The Yana plural is sometimes formed by an infixed ele- ment, e.g., k'uruwi "medicine-men," k'uwi ''medicine- man"; in Chinook an infixed -I- is used in certain verbs to indicate repeated activity, e.g., ksik'ludelk "she keeps looking at him," iksik'lutk "she looked at him" (radical element -tk) . A peculiarly interesting type of infixation is found in the Siouan languages, in which certain verbs insert the pronominal elements into the very body of the radical element, e.g., Sioux cheti "to build a fire," chewati "I build a fire"; shuta "to miss," sJiuunta-pi *'we miss." A subsidiary but by no means unimportant grammati- cal process is that of internal vocalic or consonantal change. In some languages, as in English {sing, sang, sung, song; goose, geese), the former of these has be- come one of the major methods of indicating fundamental changes of grammatical function. At any rate, the proc- ess is alive enough to lead our children into untrodden ways. We all know of the growing youngster who speaks of having hrung something, on the analogy of such forms as sung and filing. In Hebrew, as we have seen, vocalic change is of even greater significance than in English. What is true of Hebrew is of course true of all other Semitic languages. A few examples of so-called "broken" plurals from Arabic ^^ will sup- plement the Hebrew verb forms that I have given in another connection. The noun halad "place" has the plural form hilad; " gild "hide" forms the plural gulud; 12 Egyptian dialect. 13 There are changes of accent and vocalic quantity in these forms as well, but the requirements of simplicity force us to neglect them. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 77 ragil "man," the plural rigal; shihbak "window," the plural shahabik. Very similar phenomena are illus- trated by the Hamitic languages of Northern Africa, e.g., Shilh " izhil "hair," plural izhel; a-sleni "fish," plural i-slim-en; sn "to know," sen "to be knowing"; rmi "to become tired," riimni "to be tired"; ttss ^^ "to fall asleep," ttoss "to sleep." Strikingly similar to English and Greek alternations of the type sing — sang and leip-o "I leave," leloip-a "I have left," are such Somali ^'^ cases as al "I am," il "I was"; i-dah-a "I say," i-di "I said," f^e/i "say!" Vocalic change is of great significance also in a num- ber of American Indian languages. In the Athabaskan group many verbs change the quality or quantity of the vowel of the radical element as it changes its tense or mode. The Navaho verb for "I put (grain) into a receptacle" is hi-Jii-sh-ju, in which -ja is the radical element; the past tense, hi-M-ja', has a long a- vowel, fol- lowed by the "glottal stop" ; ^' the future is bi-li-de-sh-ji with complete change of vowel. In other types of Navaho verbs the vocalic changes follow different lines, e.g., yali-a-ni-ye "you carry (a pack) into (a stable)"; past, yah'i-ni-yin (with long i in -yin; -n is here used to indicate nasalization) ; future, yah-a-di-yeJil (with long e). In another Indian language, Yokuts,^** vocalic modi- fications affect both noun and verb forms. Thus, huchong "son" forms the plural bocliang-i (contrast the objective huchong-a) ; enasli "grandfather," the plural inash-a; the verb engtyim "to sleep" forms the continu- 14 A Berber language of Morocco. 15 Some of the Berber languages allow consonantal combina- tions that seem unpronounceable to us. 16 One of the Hamitic languages of eastern Africa. 17 See page 49. 18 Spoken in the south-central part of California. 78 LANGUAGE ative ingetym-ad "to be sleeping" and the past ingetym- ash. Consonantal change as a functional process is prob- ably far less common than vocalic modifications, but it is not exactly rare. There is an interesting group of cases in English, certain nouns and corresponding verbs differing solely in that the final consonant is voiceless or voiced. Examples are wreath (with tJi as in tliink), but to wreatlie (with th as in then); house, but to house (with s pronounced like z). That we have a distinct feeling for the interchange as a means of dis- tinguishing the noun from the verb is indicated by the extension of the principle by many Americans to such a noun as rise (e.g., the rise of democracy) — pronounced like rice — in contrast to the verb to rise {s like z). In the Celtic languages the initial consonants undergo several types of change according to the grammatical relation that subsists between the word itself and the preceding word. Thus, in modern Irish, a word like ho "ox" may under the appropriate circumstances, take the forms hho (pronounce wo) or mo (e.g., an ho "the ox," as a subject, but tir Tia mo "land of the oxen," as a possessive plural). In the verb the principle has as one of its most striking consequences the "aspiration" of initial consonants in the past tenre. If a verb be- gins with t, say, it changes the t to th (now pronounced h) in forms of the past; if it begins with g, the conso- nant changes, in analogous forms, to gh (pronounced like a voiced spirant ^^ g or like y, according to the nature of the following vowel). In modern Irish the principle of consonantal change, which began in the oldest period of the language as a secondary conse- quence of certain phonetic conditions, has become one !!• See page 50. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 79 of the primary grammatical processes of the language. Perhaps as remarkable as these Irish phenomena are the consonantal interchanges of Ful, an African lan- guage of the Soudan. Here we find that all nouns be- longing to the personal class form the plural by chang- ing their initial g, j, d, h, k, cli, and p to y (or iv), y, r, w, h, s and / respectively; e.g., jim-o ''companion," yim- 'be " companions ' ' ; pio-o ' ' beater, " fio-'he " beat- ers." Curiously enough, nouns that belong to the class of things form their singular and plural in exactly re- verse fashion, e.g., yola-re "grass-grown place," jola-je ** grass-grown places"; fitan-du "soul," pital-i "souls." In Nootka, to refer to but one other language in which the process is found, the t or tl -° of many verbal suf- fixes becomes Id in forms denoting repetition, e.g., liita^'ato "to fall out," Jiita-'ald "to keep falling out"; mat-achislit-utl "to fly on to the water, ' ' mat-achisJit-ohl "to keep flying on to the water." Further, the hi of certain elements changes to a peculiar 7i-sound in plural forms, e.g., yak-old " sore-f aeed, " yak-oJi "sore-faced (people)." Nothing is more natural than the prevalence of re- duplication, in other words, the repetition of all or part of the radical element. The process is generally em- ployed, with self-evident symbolism, to indicate such concepts as distribution, plurality, repetition, customary activity, increase of size, added intensity, continuance. Even in English it is not unknown, though it is not gen- erally accounted one of the typical formative devices of our language. Such words as goody-goody and to pooh- pooh have become accepted as part of our normal vocabu- lary, but the method of duplication may on occasion be used more freely than is indicated by such stereotyped 20 These orthographies are but makeshifts for simple sounds. 80 LANGUAGE examples. Such locutions as a hig hig man or Let it cool till it's thick thick are far more common, especially in the speech of women and children, than our linguistic text-books would lead one to suppose. In a class by themselves are the really enormous number of words, many of them sound-imitative or contemptuous in psy- chological tone, that consist of duplications with either change of the vowel or change of the initial consonant — words of the type sing-song, riff-raff, wishy-washy, harum-skarum, roly-poly. Words of this type are all but universal. Such examples as the Eussian Chuda- Yudo (a dragon), the Chinese ping-pang "rattling of rain on the roof,"^^ the Tibetan kyang-kyong "lazy," and the Manchu porpon parpan "blear-eyed" are curi- ously reminiscent, both in form and in psychology, of words nearer home. But it can hardly be said that the duplicative process is of a distinctively grammatical significance in English. We must turn to other lan- guages for illustration. Such cases as Hottentot go-go "to look at carefully" (from go "to see"), Somali fen- fen "to gnaw at on all sides" (from fen "to gnaw at"), Chinook iwi iwi "to look about carefully, to examine" (from iwi "to appear"), or Tsimshian am' am "several (are) good" (from am "good") do not depart from the natural and fundamental range of significance of the process. A more abstract function is illustrated in Ewe,^^ in which both infinitives and verbal adjectives are formed from verbs by duplication; e.g., yi "to go," yiyi "to go, act of going"; ivo "to do," ivowo~^ "done"; mawomawo "not to do" (with both duplicated verb stem and duplicated negative particle). Causative du- 21 Whence our ping-pong. 22 An African language of the Guinea Coast. 23 In the verbal adjective the tone of the second syllable differs from that of the first. FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 81 plications are characteristic of Hottentot, e.g., gam- gam-^ "to cause to tell" (from gam "to tell"). Or the process may be used to derive verbs from nouns, as in Hottentot klioe-khoe "to talk Hottentot" (from khoe-b "man, Hottentot"), or as in Kwakiutl metmat "to eat clams" (radical element 7net- "clam"). The most characteristic examples of reduplication are such as repeat only part of the radical element. It would be possible to demonstrate the existence of a vast num- ber of formal types of such partial duplication, accord- ing to whether the process makes use of one or more of the radical consonants, preserves or weakens or alters the radical vowel, or affects the beginning, the middle, or the end of the radical element. The functions are even more exuberantly developed than with simple du- plication, though the basic notion, at least in origin, is nearly always one of repetition or continuance. Ex- amples illustrating this fundamental function can be quoted from all parts of the globe. Initially redupli- cating are, for instance, Shilh ggen "to be sleeping" (from gen "to sleep") ; Ful pepeu-'do "liar" (i.e., "one who always lies"), plural fefeu-'he (from fewa "to lie") ; Bontoc Igorot anak "child," ananak "children"; kamu-ek "I hasten," kakamu-ek "I hasten more"; Tsimshian gyad "person," gyigyad "people"; Nass gyibayuk "to fly," gyigyihayuk "one who is flying." Psychologically comparable, but with the reduplication at the end, are Somali ur "body," plural urar; Hausa suna "name," plural sunana-ki; Washo ^^ gusu "buf- falo," gususu "buffaloes"; Takelma -® himi-d- "to talk to," Jiimim-d- "to be accustomed to talk to." Even 24 Initial "click" (see page 55, note 15) omitted. 25 An Indian language of Nevada. 26 An Indian language of Oregon. 82 LANGUAGE more commonly than simple duplication, this partial duplication of the radical element has taken on in many languages functions that seem in no way related to the idea of increase. The best known examples are probably the initial reduplication of our older Indo- European languages, which helps to form the perfect tense of many verbs (e.g., Sanskrit dadarslia "I have seen," Greek leloipa "I have left," Latin tetigi "I have touched," Gothic lelot "I have let"). In Nootka re- duplication of the radical element is often employed in association with certain suffixes; e.g., hlucli- "woman" forms liluliluch-'ituhl "to dream of a woman," Jiliihluch- k'ok "resembling a woman." Psychologically similar to the Greek and Latin examples are many Takelma cases of verbs that exhibit two forms of the stem, one employed in the present or past, the other in the future and in certain modes and verbal derivatives. The for- mer has final reduplication, which is absent in the lat- ter; e.g., nl-i/eheh-i'n "I show (or showed) to him," al- yeh-in "I shall show him." We come now to the subtlest of all grammatical proc- esses, variations in accent, whether of stress or pitch. The chief difficulty in isolating accent as a functional process is that it is so often combined with alternations in vocalic quantity or quality or complicated by the presence of affixed elements that its grammatical value appears as a secondary rather than as a primary fea- ture. In Greek, for instance, it is characteristic of true verbal forms that they throw the accent back as far as the general accentual rules Avill permit, while nouns may be more freely accented. There is thus a striking ac- centual difference between a verbal form like elutJiemen "we were released," accented on the second syllable of the word, and its participial derivative lutJieis "re- FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 83 leased, ' ' accented on the last. The presence of the char- acteristic verbal elements e- and -me7i in the first case and of the nominal -s in the second tends to obscure the inherent value of the accentual alternation. This value comes out very neatly in such English doublets as to refund and a refund, to extract and an extract, to come down and a come down, to lack luster and lack-luster eyes, in which the difference between the verb and the noun is entirely a matter of changing stress. In the Athabaskan languages there are not infrequently sig- nificant alternations of accent, as in Navaho ta-di-gis "you wash yourself" (accented on the second syllable), ta-di-gis "he washes himself" (accented on the first ).-^ Pitch accent may be as functional as stress and is perhaps more often so. The mere fact, however, that pitch variations are phonetically essential to the lan- guage, as in Chinese (e.g., fe7ii{ "wind" with a level tone, feng "to serve" with a falling tone) or as in classi- cal Greek (e.g., lab-on "having taken" with a simple or high tone on the suffixed participial -on, gunaik-on "of women" with a compound or falling tone on the case suffix -on) does not necessarily constitute a functional, or perhaps we had better say grammatical, use of pitch. In such eases the pitch is merely inherent in the radi- cal element or affix, as any vowel or consonant might be. It is different with such Chinese alternations as chung (level) ''middle" and cluing (falling) "to hit the middle"; WAai (rising) "to buy" and mai (falling) "to sell"; pei (falling) "back" and pei (level) "to carry on the back." Examples of this type are not exactly common in Chinese and the language cannot be said to possess at present a definite feeling for tonal dif- ^7 It is not unlikely, however, that these Athabaskan alterna- tions are primarily tonal in character. 84 LANGUAGE ferences as symbolic of the distinction between noun and verb. There are languages, however, in which such differ- ences are of the most fundamental grammatical impor- tance. They are particularly common in the Soudan. In Ewe, for instance, there are formed from suho "to serve" two reduplicated forms, an infinitive suhosubo "to serve," with a low tone on the first two syllables and a high one on the last two, and an abjectival suho- suho "serving," in which all the syllables have a high tone. Even more striking are cases furnished by Shil- luk, one of the languages of the headwaters of the Nile. The plural of the noun often differs in tone from the singular, e.g., yit (high) "ear" but yit (low) "ears." In the pronoun three forms may be distinguished by tone alone ; e " he " has a high tone and is sub j eeti ve, -e " him ' ' (e.g., a chwol-e "he called him") has a low tone and is objective, -e "his" (e.g., wod-e "his house") has a middle tone and is possessive. Prom the verbal ele- ment gwed- "to write" are formed gwcd-o "(he) writes" with a low tone, the passive gwet "(it was) written" with a falling tone, the imperative gwet "write!" with a rising tone, and the verbal noun gwet "writing" with a middle tone. In aboriginal America also pitch accent is known to occur as a grammatical process. A good example of such a pitch language is Tlingit, spoken by the Indians of the southern coast of Alaska. In this language many verbs vary the tone of the radical element according to tense ; Jiun ' ' to sell, ' ' siyi "to hide," tin "to see," and numerous other radi- cal elements, if low-toned, refer to past time, if high- toned, to the future. Another type of function is illus- trated by the Takelma forms liel "song," with falling pitch, but hel "sing!" with a rising inflection; parallel FORM: GRAMMATICAL PROCESSES 85 to these forms are sel (falling) "black paint," sel (ris- ing) "paint it!" All in all it is clear that pitch ac- cent, like stress and vocalic or consonantal modifications, is far less infrequently employed as a grammatical proc- ess than our own habits of speech would prepare us tc believe probable. FORM IN LANGUAGE: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS We have seen that the single word expresses either a simple concept or a combination of concepts so inter- related as to form a psychological unity. We have, fur- thermore, briefly reviewed from a strictly formal stand- point the main processes that are used by all known languages to affect the fundamental concepts — those em- bodied in unanalyzable words or in the radical elements of words — by the modifying or formative influence of subsidiary concepts. In this chapter we shall look a little more closely into the nature of the world of con- cepts, in so far as that world is reflected and Systematized in linguistic structure. Let us begin with a simple sentence that involves va- rious kinds of concepts — the fanner kills the duckling. A rough and ready analysis discloses here the presence of three distinct and fundamental concepts that are brought into connection with each other in a number of ways. These three concepts are "farmer" (the subject 3f discourse), "kill" (defining the nature of the activity which the sentence informs us al)out), and "duckling" (another subject ^ of discourse that takes an important though somewhat passive part in this activity). We can visualize the farmer and the duckling and we have also no difficulty in constructing an image of the killing. In iNot in its technical sense. 86 FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 87 other words, the elements farmer, kill, and duckling de- fine concepts of a concrete order. But a more careful linguistic analysis soon brings us to see that the two subjects of discourse, however simply we may visualize them, are not expressed quite as di- rectly, as immediately, as we feel them. A "farmer" is in one sense a perfectly unified concept, in another he is * ' one who farms. ' ' The concept conveyed by the radi- cal element (faron-) is not one of personality at all but of an industrial activity {to farm), itself based on the concept of a particular type of object (a farm). Simi- larly, the concept of duckliyig is at one remove from that which is expressed by the radical element of the word, duck. This element, which may occur as an independ- ent word, refers to a whole class of animals, big and little, while duckling is limited in its application to the young of that class. The word farm er has an ' ' agentive ' * suffix -er that performs the function of indicating the one that carries out a given activity, in this case that of farming. It transforms the verb to farm into an agentive noun precisely as it transforms the verbs to sing, to paint, to teach into the corresponding agentive nouns singer, painter, teaclier. The element -ling is not so freely used, but its significance is obvious. It adds to the basic concept the notion of smallness (as also in gosling, fledgeling) or the somewhat related notion of "contemptible" (as in weakling, princeling, liircling). The agentive -er and the diminutive -ling both convey fairly concrete ideas (roughly those of "doer" and "lit- tle"), but the concreteness is not stressed. They do not so much define distinct concepts as mediate between concepts. The -er of farmer does not quite say * * one who (farms) " it merely indicates that the sort of person we call a "farmer" is closely enough associated with ac- 8S LANGUAGE t,ivity on a farm to be conventionally thought of as al- ways so occupied. He may, as a matter of fact, go to town and engage in any pursuit but farming, yet his linguistic label remains "farmer." Language here be- trays a certain helplessness or, if one prefers, a stub- born tendency to look away from the immediately sug- gested function, trusting to the imagination and to usage to fill in the transitions of thought and the details of application that distinguish one concrete concept (to farm) from another "derived" one {farmer). It would be impossible for any language to express every con- crete idea by an independent word or radical element. The concreteness of experience is infinite, the resources of the richest language are strictly limited. It must per- force throw countless concepts under the rubric of cer- tain basic ones, using other concrete or semi-concrete ideas as functional mediators. The ideas expressed by these mediating elements — they may be independent words, affixes, or modifications of the radical element — may be called "derivational" or "qualifying." Some concrete concepts, such as kill, are expressed radically; others, such as farmer and duckling, are expressed derivatively. Corresponding to these two modes of ex- pression we have two types of concepts and of linguistic elements, radical {f as a wliole. In the same way the -linff of duckling defines a specific relation of attribution that concerns only the radical element, not the sentence. FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 107 III. Concrete Relational Concepts (still more abstract, yet not entirely devoid of a measure of concreteness) : normally expressed by affixing non-radical elements to radical elements, but generally at a greater remove from these than is the case with elements of type II, or by inner moditlcation of radical elements; differ fundamentally from type II in indicating or implying relations that transcend the particular word to which they are immediately attached, thus leading over to IV. Pure Relational Concepts (purely abstract) : normally expressed by affixing non-radical elements to radical elements (in which case these concepts are frequently intertwmed with those of type III) or by their inner modification, by independent words, or by position ; serve to relate the concrete elements of the proposition to each other, thus giving it definite syntactic form. The nature of these four classes of concepts as regards their concreteness or their power to express syntactic relations may be thus symbolized: Material ( I. Basic Concepts Content 1 H- Derivational Concepts Relation i ^^^' Concrete Relational Concepts IV. Pure Relational Concepts These schemes must not be worshipped as fetiches. In the actual work of analysis difficult problems fre- quently arise and we may well be in doubt as to how to group a given set of concepts. This is particularly apt to be the case in exotic languages, where we may be quite sure of the analysis of the words in a sentence and yet not succeed in acquiring that inner ''feel" of its structure that enables us to tell infallibly what is "material content" and what is "relation." Concepts 108 LANGUAGE of class I are essential to all speech, also concepts of class IV. Concepts II and III are both common, but not essential; particularly group III, which represents, in effect, a psychological and formal confusion of types II and IV or of types I and IV, is an avoidable class of concepts. Logically there is an impassable gulf between I and IV, but the illogical, metaphorical genius of speech has wilfully spanned the gulf and set up a con- tinuous gamut of concepts and forms that leads imper- ceptibly from the crudest of materialities ("house" or "John Smith") to the most subtle of relations. It is particularly significant that the unanalyzable inde- pendent word belongs in most cases to either group I or group IV, rather less commonly to II or III. It is possible for a concrete concept, represented by a simple word, to lose its material significance entirely and pass over directly into the relational sphere without at the same time losing its independence as a word. This happens, for instance, in Chinese and Cam- bodgian when the verb "give" is used in an abstract sense as a mere symbol of the "indirect objective" rela- tion (e.g., Cambodgian "We make story this give all that person who have child," i.e., "We have made this story for all those that have children"). There are, of course, also not a few instances of transi- tions between groups I and II and I and III, as well as of the less radical one between II and III. To the first of these transitions belongs that whole class of ex- amples in which the independent word, after passing through the preliminary stage of functioning as the sec- ondary or qualifying element in a compound, ends up by being a derivational affix pure and simple, yet with- out losing the memory of its former independence. Such an element and concept is the full of teaspoonfull, which FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 109 hovers psychologically between the status of an inde- pendent, radical concept (compare full) or of a sub- sidiary element in a compound (cf. hrim-full) and that of a simple suffix (cf. dutiful) in which the primary con- creteness is no longer felt. In general, the more highly synthetic our linguistic type, the more difficult and even arbitrary it becomes to distinguish groups I and II. Not only is there a gradual loss of the concrete as we pass through from group I to group IV, there is also a constant fading away of the feeling of sensible re- ality within the main groups of linguistic concepts them- selves. In many languages it becomes almost imperative, therefore, to make various sub-classifications, to segre- gate, for instance, the more concrete from the more ab- stract concepts of group II. Yet we must always beware of reading into such abstracter groups that purely for- mal, relational feeling that we can hardly help associat- ing with certain of the abstracter concepts which, with us, fall in group III, unless, indeed, there is clear evi- dence to warrant such a reading in. An example or two should make clear these all-important distinctions.^* In Nootka we have an unusually large number of deriva- tional affixes (expressing concepts of group II). Some of these are quite material in content (e.g., "in the house," "to dream of"), others, like an element denot- ing plurality and a diminutive affix, are far more ab- stract in content. The former type are more closely welded v/ith the radical element than the latter, which can only be suffixed to formations that have the value of 1* It is precisely the failure to feel the "value" or "tone," as distinct from the outer significance, of the concept expressed by a given grammatical element that has so often led students to misunderstand the nature of languages profoundly alien to their own. Not everything that calls itself "tense" or "mode" or "number" or "gender" or "person" is genuinely comparable to what we mean by these terms in Latin or French. 110 LANGUAGE complete words. If, therefore, I wish to say * ' the small fires in the house" — and I can do this in one word — I must form the word "fire-in-the-house," to which ele- ments corresponding to "small," our plural, and "the" are appended. The element indicating the definiteness of reference that is implied in our "the" comes at the very end of the word. So far, so good. " Fire-in-the- house-the" is an intelligible correlate of our "the house- fire."^^ But is the Nootka correlate of "the small fires in the house" the true equivalent of an English "the Jiouse-firelets"? ^'^ By no means. First of all, the plural element precedes the diminutive in Nootka : ' ' fire-in-the- house-plural-small-the, ' ' in other words ' ' the house-fires- let," which at once reveals the important fact that the plural concept is not as abstractly, as relationally, felt as in English. A more adequate rendering would be "the house-fire-several-let," in which, however, "sev- eral" is too gross a word, "-let" too choice an element ("small" again is too gross). In truth we cannot carry over into English the inherent feeling of the Nootka word, which seems to hover somewhere between "the house-firelets " and "the house-fire-several-small." But what more than anything else cuts off all possibility of comparison between the English -s of "house-firelets" and the "-several-small" of the Nootka word is this, that in Nootka neither the plural nor the diminutive affix corresponds or refers to anything else in the sen- tence. In English "the house-firelets burn" (not "burns"), in Nootka neither verb, nor adjective, nor 15 Suffixed articles occur also in Danish and Rwedisli and in numermis other lanpnaj?es. The Nootka element for "in the house" differs from our "house-" in that it is suffixed and cannot occur as an independent word ; nor is it related to the Nootka word for "house." 16 Assuming the existence of a word "firelet." FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 111 anything else in the proposition is in the least concerned with the plurality or the diminutiveness of the fire. Hence, while Nootka recognizes a cleavage between con- crete and less concrete concepts within group II, the less concrete do not transcend the group and lead us into that abstracter air into which our plural -s carries us. But at any rate, the reader may object, it is something that the Nootka plural affix is set apart from the con- ereter group of affixes ; and may not the Nootka diminu- tive have a slenderer, a more elusive content than our -let or -ling or the German -chen or -leinf ^'^ Can such a concept as that of plurality ever be clas- sified with the more material concepts of group II? Indeed it can be. In Yana the third person of the verb makes no formal distinction between singular and plural. Nevertheless the plural concept can be, and nearly always is, expressed by the suffixing of an ele- ment (-ha-) to the radical element of the verb. ''It burns in the east" is rendered by the verb ya-liau-si "burn-east-s." ^^ ''They burn in the east" is ya-ha- Jiau-si. Note that the plural affile immediately follows the radical element (ya-), disconnecting it from the local element {-Tiau-). It needs no labored argument to prove that the concept of plurality is here hardly less concrete than that of location "in the east," and that the Yana form corresponds in feeling not so much to our "They burn in the east" (ardunt oriente) as to a "Burn-several- east-s, it plurally burns in the east, ' ' an expression which 17 The Nootka diminutive is doubtless more of a feeling-element, an element of nuance, than our -ling. This is shown by the fact that it may be used with verbs as well as with nouns. In speak- ing to a child, one is likely to add the diminutive to any word in the sentence, regardless of whether there is an inherent diminutive meaning in the word or not. 18 -si is the third person of the present tense, -hau- "east" is an affix, not a compounded radical element. U2 LANGUAGE we cannot adequately assimilate for lack of the necessary form-grooves into which to run it. But can we go a step farther and dispose of the cate- gory of plurality as an utterly material idea, one that would make of "books" a "plural book," in which the "plural," like the "white" of "white book," falls con- tentedly into group I? Our "many books" and "sev- eral books" are obviously not cases in point. Even if we could say "many book" and "several book" (as we can say "many a book" and "each book"), the plural concept would still not emerge as clearly as it should for our argument; "many" and "several" are contaminated by certain notions of quantity or scale that are not essen- tial to the idea of plurality itself. We must turn to central and eastern Asia for the type of expression we are seeking. In Tibetan, for instance, nga-s mi mtJiong ^^ "I-by man see, by me a man is seen, I see a man" may just as well be understood to mean "I see men," if there happens to be no reason to emphasize the fact of plu- rality.'" If the fact is worth expressing, however, I can say nga-s mi mams mthong "by me man plural see," where mams is the perfect conceptual analogue of -s in books, divested of all relational strings. Rnams follows its noun as would any other attributive word — "man plural" (whether two or a million) like "man white." No need to bother about his plurality any more than about his whiteness unless we insist on the point. What is true of the idea of plurality is naturally just as true of a great many other concepts. They do not necessarily belong where we who speak English are in the habit of putting them. They may be shifted to- 19 These are classical, not modern colloquial, forms. 20 Just as in English "He lias written books" makes no com- mitment on the score of quantity ("a few, several, many"). FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 113 wards I or towards IV, the two poles of linguistic ex- pression. Nor dare we look down on the Nootka In- dian and the Tibetan for their material attitude towards a concept which to us is abstract and relational, lest we invite the reproaches of the Frenchman who feels a subtlety of relation in femme blanche and liomme hlanc that he misses in the coarser-grained white woman and white man. But the Bantu Negro, were he a philoso- pher, might go further and find it strange that we put in group II a category, the diminutive, which he strongly feels to belong to group III and which he uses, along with a number of other classificatory concepts,^^ to relate his subjects and objects, attributes and predicates, as a Russian or a German handles his genders and, if pos- sible, with an even greater finesse. It is because our conceptual scheme is a sliding scale rather than a philosophical analysis of experience that we cannot say in advance just where to put a given concept. "We must dispense, in other words, with a well-ordered classification of categories. "What boots it to put tense and mode here or number there when the next language one handles puts tense a peg "lower down" (towards I), mode and number a peg ''higher up" (towards I"V) f Nor is there much to be gained in a summary work of this kind from a general inventory of the types of concepts generally found in groups II, III, and I"V. There are too many possibilities. It would be interesting to show what are the most typical noun-forming and verb-forming ele- ments of group II ; how variously nouns may be classi- fied (by gender ; personal and non-personal ; animate and inanimate ; by form ; common and proper) ; how the con- 21 Such as person class, animal class, instrument class, augmen- tative class. 114 LANGUAGE cept of number is elaborated (singular and plural; sin- gular, dual, and plural ; singular, dual, trial, and plural ; single, distributive, and collective) ; what tense distinc- tions may be made in verb or noun (the "past," for in- stance, may be an indefinite past, immediate, remote, mythical, completed, prior) ; how delicately certain lan- guages have developed the idea of "aspect"-- (momen- taneous, durative, continuative, inceptive, cessative, durative-inceptive, iterative, momentaneous-iterative, du- rative-iterative, resultative, and still others) ; what mo- dalities may be recognized (indicative, imperative, po- tential, dubitative, optative, negative, and a host of others-^); what distinctions of person are possible (is "we," for instance, conceived of as a plurality of "I" or is it as distinct from "I" as either is from "you" or "he"? — both attitudes are illustrated in language; moreover, does "we" include you to whom I speak or not? — "inclusive" and "exclusive" forms) ; what may be the general scheme of orientation, the so-called demon- strative categories ("this" and "that" in an endless procession of nuances) ; -* how frequently the form ex- 22 A term borrowed from Slavic grammar. It indicates the lapse of action, its nature from the standpoint of continuity. Our "cry" is indefinite as to aspect, "be crying" is durative, "cry out" is momentaneous, "burst into tears" is inceptive, "keep cry- ing" is continuative, "start in crying" is durative-inceptive, "cry now and again" is iterative, "cry out every now and then" or "cry in fits and starts" is momentaneous-iterative. "To put on a coat" is momentaneous. "to wear a coat" is resultative. As our examples show, aspect is expressed in English by all kinds of idiomatic turns rather than i)y Cf. Latin ire "to go"; also our English idiom "I have to go," i.e., "must go." FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 119 tion. Stress is the most natural means at our disposal to emphasize a linguistic contrast, to indicate the major element in a sequence. Hence we need not be sur- prised to find that accent too, no less than sequence, may serve as the unaided symbol of certain relations. Such a contrast as that of go between ("one who goes be- tween") and to go between may be of quite secondary origin in English, but there is every reason to believe that analogous distinctions have prevailed at all times in linguistic history. A sequence like see man might imply some type of relation in which see qualifies the following w^ord, hence "a seeing man" or "a seen (or visible) man," or is its predication, hence "the man sees" or "the man is seen," while a sequence like see man might indicate that the accented word in some way limits the application of the first, say as direct object, hence "to see a man" or "(he) sees the man." Such alternations of relation, as symbolized by varying stresses, are important and frequent in a number of languages.^" It is a somewhat venturesome and yet not an altogether unreasonable speculation that sees in word order and stress the primary methods for the expression of all syn- tactic relations and looks upon the present relational value of specific words and elements as but a secondary condition due to a transfer of values. Thus, we may surmise that the Latin -m of words like feminam, dominum, and civem did not originally ^^ denote that "woman," "master," and "citizen" were objectively related to the verb of the proposition but indicated some- 30 In Chinese no less than in English. 31 By "originally" 1 mean, of course, some time antedating the earliest period of the Indo-European languages that we can get at by comparative evidence. 120 LANGUAGE thing far more concrete,^- that the objective relation was merely implied by the position or accent of the word (radical element) immediately precediaig the -m, and that gradually, as its more concrete significance faded away, it took over a syntactic function that did not originally be'ong to it. This sort of evolution by trans- fer is traceable in many instances. Thus, the of in an English phrase like "the law of the land" is now as colorless in content, as purely a relational indicator as the ''genitive" suffix -is in the Latin lex urhis "the law of the city. ' ' We know, however, that it was originally an adverb of considerable concreteness of meaning,^^ "away, moving from," and that the syntactic relation was originally expressed by the case form ^* of the sec- ond noun. As the case form lost its vitality, the adverb took over its function. If we are actually justified in assuming that the expression of all syntactic relations is ultimately traceable to these two unavoidable, dynamic features of speech — sequence and stress ^^ — an interest- ing thesis results: — All of the actual content of speech, its clusters of vocalic and consonantal sounds, is in origin limited to the concrete; relations were originally not expressed in outward form but were merely implied and articulated with the help of order and rhj'-thm. In other words, relations were intuitively felt and could only "leak out" with the help of dynamic factors that themselves move on an intuitional plane. There is a special method for the expression of rela- tions that has been so often evolved in the history of language that we must glance at it for a moment. This is the method of "concord" or of like signaling. It is 32 Perhaps it was a noun-classifying element of some sort. 33 Compare its close historical parallel off. 34 "At)lative" at last analysis. 35 Very likely jjitch should be understood along with stress. FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 121 based on the same principle as the password or label. All persons or objects that answer to the same counter- sign or that bear the same imprint are thereby stamped as somehow related. It makes little difference, once they are so stamped, where they are to be found or how they behave themselves. They are known to belong to- gether. We are familiar with the principle of concord in Latin and Greek. Many of us have been struck by such relentless rhymes as vidi ilium honum dominum "I saw that good master" or quarum dearum saevarum "of which stern goddesses." Not that sound-echo, whether in the form of rhyme or of alliteration ^'^ is nec- essary to concord, though in its most typical and orig- inal forms concord is nearly always accompanied by sound repetition. The essence of the principle is sim- ply this, that words (elements) that belong together, particularly if they are syntactic equivalents or are re- lated in like fashion to another word or element, are outwardly marked by the same or functionally equiva- lent affixes. The application of the principle varies considerably according to the genius of the particular language. In Latin and Greek, for instance, there is concord between noun and qualifying word (adjective or demonstrative) as regards gender, number, and case, between verb and subject only as regards number, and no concord between verb and object. In Chinook there is a more far-reaching concord be- tween noun, whether subject or object, and verb. Every noun is classified according to five categories — masculine, feminine, neuter,^^ dual, and plural. ' ' Woman ' ' is f em- 36 As in Bantu or Chinook. 37 Perhaps better "general." The Chinook "neuter" may refer to persons as well as things and may also be used as a plural. "Masculine" and "feminine," as in German and French, include a great number of inanimate nouns. 122 LANGUAGE inine, "sand" is neuter, "table" is masculine. If, therefore, I wish to say "The woman put the sand on the table," I must place in the verb certain class or gender prefixes that accord with corresponding noun pre- fixes. The sentence reads then, "The (fern.) -woman she (fern.) -it (neut.)-it (masc.) -on-put the (neut.)-sand the (masc.) -table." If "sand" is qualified as "much" and "table" as "large," these new ideas are expressed as abstract nouns, each with its inherent class-prefix ("much" is neuter or feminine, "large" is masculine) and with a possessive prefix referring to the qualified noun. Adjective thus calls to noun, noun to verb. "The woman put much sand on the large table," there- fore, takes the form: "The (fem.) -woman she (fem.)-it (neut.)-it (masc.) -on-put the (fem.) -thereof (neut.)- quantity the (neut.)-sand the (masc.) -thereof (masc.)- largeness the (masc.) -table." The classification of "ta- ble" as masculine is thus three times insisted on — in the noun, in the adjective, and in the verb. In the Bantu languages,^^ the principle of concord works very much as in Chinook. In them also nouns are classified into a number of categories and are brought into relation with adjectives, demonstratives, relative pronouns, and verbs by means of prefixed elements that call off the class and make up a complex system of concordances. In such a sentence as "That fierce lion who came here is dead," the class of "lion," which we may call the animal class, would be referred to by concording prefixes no less than six times, — with the demonstrative ("that"), the quali- fying adjective, the noun itself, the relative pronoun, 38 Spoken in the greater part of the southern half of Africa. Chinook is spoken in a number of diah^cts in the lower Columbia River valley. It is impressive to observe how the human mind has arrived at the same form of expression in two such histori- cally unconnected regions. FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 123 the subjective prefix to the verb of the relative clause, and the subjective prefix to the verb of the main clause ("is dead"). We recognize in this insistence on exter- nal clarity of reference the same spirit as moves in the more familiar ilium bonum dominum. Psychologically the methods of sequence and accent lie at the opposite pole to that of concord. Where they are all for implication, for subtlety of feeling, concord is impatient of the least ambiguity but must have its well-certificated tags at every turn. Concord tends to dispense with order. In Latin and Chinook the inde- pendent words are free in position, less so in Bantu. In both Chinook and Bantu, however, the methods of concord and order are equallj^ important for the differ- entiation of subject and object, as the classifying verb prefixes refer to subject, object, or indirect object ac- cording to the relative position they occupy. These ex- amples again bring home to us the significant fact that at some point or other order asserts itself in every lan- guage as the most fundamental of relating principles. The observant reader has probably been surprised that all this time we have had so little to say of the time- honored ''parts of speech." The reason for this is not far to seek. Our conventional classification of words into parts of speech is only a vague, wavering approxi- mation to a consistently worked out inventory of experi- ence. We imagine, to begin Avith, that all "verbs" are inherently concerned with action as such, that a "noun" is the name of some definite object or personality that can be pictured by the mind, that all qualities are neces- sarily expressed by a definite group of words to which we may appropriately apply the term "adjective." As soon as we test our vocabulary, we discover that the parts of speech are far from corresponding to so sim- 124 ' LANGUAGE pie an analysis of reality. We say *'it is red" and define "red" as a quality- word or adjective. We should consider it strange to think of an equivalent of ''is red" in which the whole predication (adjective and verb of being) is conceived of as a verb in precisely the same way in which we think of "extends" or "lies" or "sleeps" as a verb. Yet as soon as we give the "dura- tive" notion of being red an inceptive or transitional turn, we can avoid the parallel form "it becomes red, it turns red ' ' and say ' ' it reddens. ' ' No one denies that "reddens" is as good a verb as "sleeps" or even "walks." Yet "it is red" is related to "it reddens" very much as is " he stands " to "he stands up " or "he rises." It is merely a matter of English or of general Indo-European idiom that we cannot say "it reds" in the sense of "it is red." There are hundreds of lan- guages that can. Indeed there are many that can ex- press what we should call an adjective only by making a participle out of a verb. "Red" in such languages is merely a derivative "being red," as our "sleeping" or "walking" are derivatives of primary verbs. Just as we can verbify the idea of a quality in such eases as "reddens," so we can represent a quality or an action to ourselves as a thing. We speak of "the height of a building" or "the fall of an apple" quite as though these ideas were parallel to "the roof of a building" or "the skin of an apple," forgetting that the nouns (lieigJity fall) have not ceased to indicate a quality and an act when we have made them speak with the accent of mere objects. And just as there are languages that make verbs of the great mass of adjectives, so there are others that make nouns of them. In Chinook, as we have seen, "the big table" is "the-table its-bigness"; in Tibetan the same idea may be expressed by "the table FORM: GRAMMATICAL CONCEPTS 125 of bigness," very much as we may say "a man of wealth" instead of "a rich man." But are there not certain ideas that it is impossible to render except by way of such and such parts of speech ? What can be done with the " to " of "he came to the house"! Well, we can say "he reached the house" and dodge the preposition altogether, giving the verb a nuance that absorbs the idea of local relation carried by the "to." But let us insist on giving independence to this idea of local relation. Must we not then hold to the preposition? No, we can make a noun of it. We can say something like "he reached the proximity of the house" or "he reached the house-locality." Instead of saying "he looked into the glass" we may say "he scrutinized the glass-interior." Such expressions are stilted in English because they do not easily fit into our formal grooves, but in language after language we find that local relations are expressed in just this way. The local relation is nominalized. And so wx might go on examining the various parts of speech and showing how they not merely grade into each other but are to an astonishing degree actually con- vertible into each other. The upshot of such an exami- nation would be to feel convinced that the "part of speech" reflects not so much our intuitive analysis of reality as our ability to compose that reality into a variety of formal patterns. A part of speech outside of the limitations of syntactic form is but a will o' the wisp. For this reason no logical scheme of the parts of speech — their number, nature, and necessary confines — is of the slightest interest to the linguist. Each language has its own scheme. Everything depends on the formal de- marcations which it recognizes. Yet we must not be too destructive. It is well to re- 126 LANGUAGE member that speech consists of a series of propositions. There must be something to talk about and something must be said about this subject of discourse once it is selected. This distinction is of such fundamental im- portance that the vast majority of languages have em- phasized it by creating some sort of formal barrier between the two terms of the proposition. The subject of discourse is a noun. As the most common subject of diseour.se is either a person or a thing, the noun clusters about concrete concepts of that order. As the thing predicated of a subject is generally an activity in the widest sense of the word, a passage from one moment of existence to another, the form which has been set aside for the business of predicating, in other words, the verb, clusters about concepts of activit}^ No language wholly fails to distinguish noun and verb, though in particular cases the nature of the distinction may be an elusive one. It is different with the other parts of speech. Not one of them is imperatively required for the life of language.^^ 39 In Yana the noun and the verb are well distinct, though there are certain features that they hold in common which tend to draw them nearer to each other than we feel to be possible. But there are, strictly speaking, no other parts of speech. The adjective is a verb. So are the numeral, the interrogative pronoun (e.g., "to be what?"), and certain "conjunctions" and adverbs (e.g., "to be and" and "to be not"; one says "and-past-I go," i.e., "and I went"). Adverbs and prepositions are either nouns or merely derivative affixes in the verb. VI TYPES OP LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE So far, in dealing with linguistic form, we have been concerned only with single words and with the relations of words in sentences. We have not envisaged whole languages as conforming to this or that general type. Incidentally we have observed that one language runs to tight-knit synthesis where another contents itself with a more analytic, piece-meal handling of its elements, or that in one language syntactic relations appear pure which in another are combined with certain other no- tions that have something concrete about them, however abstract they may be felt to be in practice. In this way we may have obtained some inkling of what is meant when we speak of the general form of a language. For it must be obvious to any one v/ho has thought about the question at all or who has felt something of the spirit of a foreign language that there is such a thing as a basic plan, a certain cut, to each language. This type or plan or structural "genius" of the lan- guage is something much more fundamental, much more pervasive, than any single feature of it that we can mention, nor can we gain an adequate idea of its na- ture by a mere recital of the sundry facts that make up the grammar of the language. When we pass from Latin to Russian, we feel that it is approximately the same horizon that bounds our view, even though the near, familiar landmarks have changed. When we come to English, we seem to notice that the hills have dipped 127 128 LANGUAGE down a little, yet we recognize the general lay of the land. And when we have arrived at Chinese, it is an utterly different sky that is looking down upon us. We can translate these metaphors and say that all languages differ from one another but that certain ones differ far more than others. This is tantamount to saying that it is possible to group them into morphological types. Strictly speaking, we know in advance that it is impossible to set up a limited number of types that would do full justice to the peculiarities of the thou- sands of languages and dialects spoken on the surface of the earth. Like all human institutions, speech is too variable and too elusive to be quite safely ticketed. Even if we operate with a minutely subdivided scale of types, we may be quite certain that many of our languages will need trimming before they fit. To get them into the scheme at all it will be necessary to over- estimate the significance of this or that feature or to ignore, for the time being, certain contradictions in their mechanism. Does the difficulty of classification prove the uselessness of the task? I do not think so. It would be too easy to relieve ourselves of the burden of constructive thinking and to take the standpoint that each language has its unique history, therefore its unique structure. Such a standpoint expresses only a half truth. Just as similar social, economic, and religious institutions have grown up in different parts of the world from distinct historical antecedents, so also lan- guages, traveling along different roads, have tended to converge toward similar forms. Moreover, the historical study of language has proven to us beyond all doubt that a language changes not only gradually but consistently, that it moves unconsciously from one type towards another, and that analogous trends are observ- TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 129 able in remote quarters of the globe. From this it fol- lows that broadly similar morphologies must have been reached by unrelated languages, independently and fre- quently. In assuming the existence of comparable types, therefore, we are not gainsaying the individuality of all historical processes; we are merely affirming that back of the face of history are powerful drifts that move language, like other social products, to balanced pat- terns, in other words, to types. As linguists we shall be content to realize that there are these types and that certain processes in the life of language tend to modify them. Why similar types should be formed, just what is the nature of the forces that make them and dissolve them — these questions are more easily asked than an- swered. Perhaps the psychologists of the future will be able to give us the ultimate reasons for the formation of linguistic types. When it comes to the actual task of classification, we find that we have no easy road to travel. Various classi- fications have been suggested, and they all contain ele- ments of value. Yet none proves satisfactory. They do not so much enfold the known languages in their embrace as force them down into narrow, straight-backed seats. The difficulties have been of various kinds. First and foremost, it has been difficult to choose a point of view. On what basis shall we classify? A language shows us so many facets that we may well be puzzled. And is one point of view sufficient? Secondly, it is dangerous to generalize from a small number of se- lected languages. To take, as the sum total of our ma- terial, Latin, Arabic, Turkish, Chinese, and perhaps Es- kimo or Sioux as an afterthought, is to court disaster. We have no right to assume that a sprinkling of exotic types will do to supplement the few languages nearer 130 LANGUAGE home that we are more immediately interested in, Thirdly, the strong craving for a simple formula^ has been the undoing of linguists. There is something irre- sistible about a method of classification that starts with two poles, exemplified, say, by Cliinese and Latin, clus- ters what it conveniently can about these poles, and throws everything else into a "transitional type." Hence has arisen the still popular classification of lan- guages into an "isolating" group, an "agglutinative" group, and an "inflective" group. Sometimes the lan- guages of the American Indians are made to straggle along as an uncomfortable "polysynthetic" rear-guard to the agglutinative languages. There is justification for the use of all of these terms, though not perhaps in quite the spirit in which they are commonly employed. In any case it is very difficult to assign all known languages to one or other of these groups, the more so as they are not mutually exclusive. A language may be both agglutinative and inflective, or inflective and poly- synthetic, or even polysynthetic and isolating, as we shall see a little later on. There is a fourth reason why the classification of lan- guages has generally proved a fruitless undertaking. It is probably the most powerful deterrent of all to clear thinking. This is the evolutionary prejudice which instilled itself into the social sciences towards the middle of the last century and which is only now beginning to abate its tyrannical hold on our mind. In- termingled with this scientific prejudice and largely an- ticipating it was another, a more human one. The vast majority of linguistic theorists themselves spoke lan- guages of a certain type, of which the most fully de- veloped varieties were the Latin and Greek that they 1 If possible, a triune formula. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 131 had learned in their childhood. It was not difficult for them to be persuaded that these familiar languages represented the "highest" development that speech had yet attained and that all other types were but steps on the way to this beloved "inflective" type. Whatever conformed to the pattern of Sanskrit and Greek and Latin and German was accepted as expressive of the "highest," whatever departed from it was frowned upon as a shortcoming or was at best an inter- esting aberration.- Now any classification that starts with preconceived values or that works up to senti- mental satisfactions is self-condemned as unscientific. A linguist that insists on talking about the Latin type of morphology as though it were necessarily the high- water mark of linguistic development is like the zoolo- gist that sees in the organic world a huge conspiracy to evolve the race-horse or the Jersey cow. Language in its fundamental forms is the symbolic expression of human intuitions. These may shape themselves in a hundred ways, regardless of the material advancement or backwardness of the people that handle the forms, of which, it need hardly be said, they are in the main un- conscious. If, therefore, we wish to understand lan- guage in its true inwardness we must disabuse our minds of preferred "values"^ and accustom ourselves 2 One celebrated American writer on culture and language de- livered himself of the dictum that, estimable as the speakers of agglutinative languages might be, it was nevertheless a crime for an inflecting woman to marry an agglutinating man. Tremendous spiritual values were evidently at stake. Champions of the "inflec- tive" languages are wont to glory in the very irrationalities of Latin and Greek, except when it suits them to emphasize thoir pro- foundly "logical" character. Yet the sober logic of Turkish or Chinese leaves them cold. The glorious irrationalities and formal complexities of many "savaee" languages they have no stomach for. Sentimentalists are difficult people. 3 1 have in mind valuations of form as such. Whether or not 132 LANGUAGE to look upon English and Hottentot with the same cool, yet interested, detachment. We come back to our first difficulty. What point of view shall we adopt for our classification? After all that we have said about grammatical form in the pre- ceding chapter, it is clear that we cannot now make the distinction between form languages and formless languages that used to appeal to some of the older writers. Every language can and must express the fun- damental syntactic relations even though there is not a single affix to be found in its vocabulary. We con- clude that every language is a form language. Aside from the expression of pure relation a language may, of course, be ' ' formless ' ' — formless, that is, in the mechani- cal and rather superficial sense that it is not encumbered by the use of non-radical elements. The attempt has sometimes been made to formulate a distinction on the basis of ''inner form." Chinese, for instance, has no formal elements pure and simple, no "outer form," but it evidences a keen sense of relations, of the difference between subject and object, attribute and predicate, and so on. In other words, it has an "inner form" in the same sense in which Latin possesses it, though it is out- wardly "formless" where Latin is outwardly "formal." On the other hand, there are supposed to be languages * which have no true grasp of the fundamental relations but content themselves with the more or less minute a language has a large and useful vocabulary is another matter. The actual size of a vocabulary at a given time is not a thing of real interest to the linguist, as all languages have the resources at their disposal for the creation of new words, should need for them arise. Furthermore, we are not in the least concerned with whether or not a language is of great practical value or is the medium of a great culture. All these considerations, important from other standpoints, have nothing to do with form value. 4 E.g., Malay, Polynesian. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 133 expression of material ideas, sometimes with an exu- berant display of "outer form," leaving the pure rela- tions to be merely inferred from the context. I am strongly inclined to believe that this supposed "inner formlessness" of certain languages is an illusion. It may well be that in these languages the relations are not expressed in as immaterial a way as in Chinese or even as in Latin,^ or that the principle of order is sub- ject to greater fluctuations than in Chinese, or that a tendency to complex derivations relieves the language of the necessity of expressing certain relations as ex- plicitly as a more analytic language would have them expressed. ** All this does not mean that the languages in question have not a true feeling for the fundamental relations. We shall therefore not be able to use the no- tion of ' ' inner formlessness, ' ' except in the greatly modi- fied sense that syntactic relations may be fused with notions of another order. To this criterion of classi- fication we shall have to return a little later. More justifiable would be a classification according to the formal processes "^ most typically developed in the language. Those languages that always identify the word with the radical element would be set off as an "isolating" group against such as either affix modifying elements (affixing languages) or possess the power to change the significance of the radical element by in- ternal changes (reduplication; vocalic and consonantal change; changes in quantity, stress, and pitch). The latter type might be not inaptly termed "symbolic" 5 Where, as we have seen, the syntactic relations are by no means free from an alloy of the concrete. 6 Very much as an English cod-liver oil dodges to some extent the task of explicitly defining the relations of the three nouns. Contrast French huile do foie de morue "oil of liver of cod." 7 See Chapter IV. 134 LANGUAGE languages.^ The affixing languages would naturally sub- divide themselves into such as are prevailingly prefix- ing, like Bantu or Tlingit, and such as are mainly or entirely suffixing, like Eskimo or Algonkin or Latin. There are two serious difficulties with this fourfold clas- sification (isolating, prefixing, suffixing, symbolic). In the first place, most languages fall into more than one of these groups. The Semitic languages, for instance, are prefixing, suffixing, and symbolic at one and the same time. In the second place, the classification in its bare form is superficial. It would throw together lan- guages that differ utterly in spirit merely because of a certain external formal resemblance. There is clearly a world of difference between a prefixing language like Cambodgian, which limits itself, so far as its prefixes (and infixes) are concerned, to the expression of deriva- tional concepts, and the Bantu languages, in which the prefixed elements have a far-reaching significance as symbols of syntactic relations. The classification has much greater value if it is taken to refer to the expres- sion of relational concepts ^ alone. In this modified form we shall return to it as a subsidiary criterion. We shall find that the terms "isolating," "affixing," and "sym- bolic" have a real value. But instead of distinguishing between prefixing and suffixing languages, we shall find that it is of superior interest to make another distinc- tion, one that is based on the relative firmness with 8 Tliere is probably a real psychological connection between sym- bolism and such significant alternations as drink, drank, drunk or Chinese mai (with rising tone) "to buy" and mai (with fall- ing tone) "to sell." The unconscious tendency toward symbolism is justly emphasized by recent psychological literature. Personally T feel that the passage from sinrj to sang has very much the same feeling as the alternation of symbolic colors — e.g., green for safe, red for danger. But we probably diiTer greatly as to the intensity with which we feel symbolism in linguistic changes of this ty.oe. 8 Pure or "concrete relational." See Chapter V. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 135 which the affixed elements are united with the core of the word." There is another very useful set of distinctions that can be made, but these too must not be applied exclu- sively, or our classification will again be superficial. I refer to the notions of "analytic," "synthetic," and "polysynthetic." The terms explain themselves. An analytic language is one that either does not combine concepts into single words at all (Chinese) or does so economically (English, French). In an analytic lan- guage the sentence is always of prime importance, the word is of minor interest. In a synthetic language (Latin, Arabic, Finnish) the concepts cluster more thickly, the words are more richly chambered, but there is a tendency, on the whole, to keep the range of con- crete significance in the single word down to a mod- erate compass. A polysynthetic language, as its name implies, is more than ordinarily synthetic. The elabora- tion of the word is extreme. Concepts which we should never dream of treating in a subordinate fashion are 10 In spite of my reluctance to emphasize the difference between a prefixing and a suffixing language, I feel that there is more involved in this difference tlian linguists have generally recog- nized. It seems to me that there is a rather important psycho- logical distinction between a language that settles the formal status of a radical clement before announcing it — and this, in effect, is what such languages as Tlingit and Chinook and Bantu are in the habit of doing — and one that begins with the concrete nucleus of a word and defines the status of this nucleus by suc- cessive limitations, each curtailing in some degree the generality of all that precedes. The spirit of the former method has some- thing diagrammatic or architectural about it, the latter is a method of pruning afterthoughts. In the more highly wrought prefixing languages the word is apt to affect us as a crystalliza- tion of floating elements, the words of the typical suffixing lan- guages (Turkish, Eskimo, Nootka) are "determinative" forma- tions, each added element determining the form of the whole anew. It is so difficult in practice to apply these elusive, yet impor- tant, distinctions that an elementary study has no recourse but to ignore them. 136 LANGUAGE symbolized by derivational affixes or ' ' symbolic ' ' changes in the radical element, while the more abstract notions, including the syntactic relations, may also be conveyed by the word. A polysynthetic language illustrates no principles that are not already exemplified in the more familiar synthetic languages. It is related to them very much as a synthetic language is related to our own analytic English.^^ The three terms are purely quantitative — and relative, that is, a language may be "analytic" from one standpoint, "synthetic" from an- other. I believe the terms are more useful in defining certain drifts than as absolute counters. It is often illuminating to point out that a language has been becoming more and more analytic in the course of its history or that it shows signs of having crystallized from a simple analytic base into a highly synthetic form.^^ "We now come to the difference between an "inflec- tive" and an "agglutinative" language. As I have al- ready remarked, the distinction is a useful, even a neces- sary, one, but it has been generally obscured by a number of irrelevancies and by the unavailing effort to make the terms cover all languages that are not, like Chinese, of a definitely isolating cast. The meaning that we had best assign to the term ' ' inflective ' ' can be gained by considering very briefly what are some of the basic features of Latin and Greek that have been looked upon 11 English, however, is only analytic in tendency. Relatively to French, it is still fairly synthetic, at least in certain aspects. 12 The former process is demonstrable for English, French, Dan- ish, Tibetan, Chinese, and a host of other languages. The latter tendency may be proven, I believe, for a number of American Indian languages, e.g., Chinook, Navaho. Underneath tlieir pres- ent moderately polysynthetic form is discernible an analytic base that in the one case may be roughly described as English-like, in the other, Tibetan-like. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 137 as peculiar to the inflective languages. First of all, they are synthetic rather than analytic. This does not help us much. Relatively to many another language that resembles them in broad structural respects, Latin and Greek are not notably synthetic ; on the other hand, their modern descendants, Italian and Modern G-reek, while far more analytic ^^ than they, have not departed so widely in structural outlines as to warrant their being put in a distinct major group. An inflective language, we must insist, may be analytic, synthetic, or polysyn- thetic. Latin and Greek are mainly affixmg in their method, with the emphasis heavily on suffixing. The agglutina- tive languages are just as typically affixing as they, some among them favoring prefixes, others running to the use of suffixes. Affixing alone does not define inflection. Possibly everything depends on just what kind of affix- ing we have to deal with. If we compare our English words farmer and goodness with such words as height and depth, we cannot fail to be struck by a notable dif- ference in the affixing technique of the two sets. The -er and -ness are affixed quite mechanically to radical elements which are at the same time independent words (farm, good). They are in no sense independently sig- nificant elements, but they convey their meaning (agen- tive, abstract quality) with unfailing directness. Their use is simple and regular and we should have no diffi- culty in appending them to any verb or to any adjec- tive, however recent in origin. From a verb to camou- flage we may form the noun camo^iflager "one who camouflages," from an adjective jazzy proceeds with 13 This applies more particularly to the Romance group: Italian, Spanish, Portuguese, French, Roumanian. Modern Greek is not so clearly analytic. 138 LANGUAGE perfect ease the noun jazziness. It is different with JieigJit and deptli. Functionally they are related to JiigJi and deep precisely as is goodness to good, but the degree of coalescence between radical element and affix is greater. Radical element and affix, while measurably distinct, cannot be torn apart quite so readily as could the good and -ness of goodness. The 4 of height is not the typical form of the affix (compare strength, length, filth, breadth, youth), while dep- is not identical with deep. We may designate the two types of affixing as ''fusing" and "juxtaposing." The juxtaposing tech- nique we may call an "agglutinative" one, if w^e like. Is the fusing technique thereby set off as the essence of inflection? I am afraid that we have not yet reached our goal. If our language were crammed full of coalescences of the type of depth, but if, on the other hand, it used the plural independently of verb concord (e.g., the hooks falls like the hook falls, or the hook fall like the hooks fall), the personal endings independently of tense (e.g., the hook fells like the hook falls, or the hook fall like the hook fell), and the pronouns inde- pendently of case (e.g., I see he like he sees me, or him see the man like the man sees him), we should hesitate to describe it as inflective. The mere fact of fusion does not seem to satisfy us as a clear indication of the inflective process. There are, indeed, a large number of languages that fuse radical element and affix in as complete and intricate a fashion as one could hope to find anywhere without thereby giving signs of that par- ticular kind of formalism that marks off' sucli languages as Latin and Greek as inflective. What is true of fusion is equally true of the "sym- bolic" processes.^* There are linguists that speak of 14 See pages 133, 134. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 139 alternations like drink and drank as though they repre- sented the high-water mark of inflection, a kind of spir- itualized essence of pure inflective form. In such Greek forms, nevertheless, as pcpom.pJi-a "1 have sent," as con- trasted with penip-o ''I send," with its trebly symbolic change of the radical element (reduplicating pe-, change of e to 0, change of p to ph), it is rather the peculiar alternation of the first person singular -a of the perfect with the -0 of the present that gives them their inflective cast. Nothing could be more erroneous than to imagine that symbolic changes of the radical element, even for the expression of such abstract concepts as those of num- ber and tense, is always associated with the syntactic peculiarities of an inflective language. If by an "ag- glutinative" language we mean one that affixes accord- ing to the juxtaposing technique, then we can only say that there are hundreds of fusing and symbolic lan- guages — non-agglutinative by definition — that are, for all that, quite alien in spirit to the inflective type of Latin and Greek. "We can call such languages inflective, if we like, but we must then be prepared to revise radi- cally our notion of inflective form. It is necessary to understand that fusion of the radi- cal element and the affix may be taken in a broader psy- chological sense than I have yet indicated. If every noun plural in English were of the type of hook: hooks, if there were not such conflicting patterns as deer: deer, ox: oxen, goose: geese to complicate the general form picture of plurality, there is little doubt that the fusion of the elements hook and -s into the unified word hooks would be felt as a little less complete than it actually is. One reasons, or feels, unconsciously about the matter somewhat as follows: — If the form pattern represented by the word hooks is identical, as far as use is concerned, 140 LANGUAGE with that of the word oxen, the pluralizing elements -s and -en cannot have quite so definite, quite so autono- mous, a value as we might at first be inclined to sup- pose. They are plural elements only in so far as plural- ity is predicated of certain selected concepts. The words hooks and oxen are therefore a little other than mechani- cal combinations of the symbol of a thing {hook, ox) and a clear symbol of plurality. There is a slight psycho- logical uncertainty or haze about the juncture in hooks and ox-en. A little of the force of -s and -en is anticipated by, or appropriated by, the words hook and ox them- selves, just as the conceptual force of -tli in dep-tli is appreciably weaker than that of -ness in good-ness in spite of the functional parallelism between depth and goodness. Where there is uncertainty about the junc- ture, where the affixed element cannot rightly claim to possess its full share of significance, the unity of the complete word is more strongly emphasized. The mind must rest on something. If it cannot linger on the constituent elements, it hastens all the more eagerly to the acceptance of the word as a whole. A word like goodness illustrates ''agglutination," hooks "regular fusion," depth "irregular fusion," geese "symbolic fu- sion" or "symbolism." ^^ The psychological distinctness of the affixed elements in an agglutinative term may be even more marked than in the -ness of goodness. To be strictly accurate, the significance of the -ness is not quite as inherently deter- 15 The following formulie may prove useful to those that are mathcmatipally inclined. Agglutination: c = a-j-t); regular fu- sion: c:=a-|-(b — x)-f-x; irregular fusion: cr=(a — x)-}- (b — y) -)- (x-j-y); symbolism :c=:(a — x)-{-x. I do not wish to imply that there is any mystic value in the process of fusion. It is quite likely to have dev(>loped as a pxirely mechanical prod- uct of phonetic forces that brought about irregularities of various aorts. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 141 mined, as autonomous, as it might be. It is at the mercy of the preceding radical element to this extent, that it requires to be preceded by a particular type of such element, an adjective. Its own power is thus, in a man- ner, checked in advance. The fusion here, however, is so vague and elementary, so much a matter of course in the great majority of all cases of affixing, that it is natural to overlook its reality and to emphasize rather the juxtaposing or agglutinative nature of the affixing process. If the -ness could be affixed as an abstractive element to each and every type of radical element, if we could say figJitness ("the act or quality of fighting") or waterness ("the quality or state of water") or away- ness ("the state of being away") as we can say goodness ("the state of being good"), we should have moved ap- preciably nearer the agglutinative pole, A language that runs to synthesis of this loose-jointed sort may be looked upon as an example of the ideal agglutinative type, particularly if the concepts expressed by the agglu- tinated elements are relational or, at the least, belong to the abstracter class of derivational ideas. Instructive forms may be cited from Nootka. We shall return to our ' ' fire in the house. ' ' ^® The Nootka word inikiv-iJil "fire in the house" is not as definitely formalized a word as its translation suggests. The radical element inikw- "fire" is really as much of a verbal as of a nominal term ; it may be rendered now by "fire," now by "burn," according to the syntactic exigencies of the sentence. The derivational element -ihl "in the house" does not mitigate this vagueness or gen- erality; inikiv-ihl is still "fire in the house" or "burn in the house." It may be definitely nominalized or ver- balized by the affixing of elements that are exclusively 16 See page 110. 142 LANGUAGE nominal or verbal in force. For example, inikw-ihl-'i, with its suffixed article, is a clear-cut nominal form: "the burning in the house, the fire in the house"; inikw-ihl-nm, with its indicative suffix, is just as clearly verbal : " it burns in the house. ' ' How weak must be the degree of fusion between "fire in the house" and the nominalizing or verbalizing suffix is apparent from the fact that the formally indifferent inikwilil is not an ab- straction gained by analysis but a full-fledged word, ready for use in the sentence. The nominalizing -'i and the indicative -ma are not fused form-affijxes, they are simply additions of formal import. But we can con- tinue to hold the verbal or nominal nature of inikwihl in abeyance long before we reach the - 'i or -m 5 < 1 a> O (V a a 3 s: H a o a a ,2 .5 "3) "=^ _. '= o j2 =^ a "3 — 2. u a s ti S O H H O M a; !» o t> _o 0) "9 .a a> a s Xi o g o >» o >ia o « o o o ^ a .^ a ~ o B ^ B 0) >> tSa £a^ 0) -*-» Si i? ^ Oi ■a XJ >> "5 ^ rt >. S5 "3 "5 dj a aw a--D. a S a a a a o >3 o >i >i >> a < < <^ < 04 < M 04 SQ &Q cc ■< i i ? a> i: i a^~. 13 u'-" bJO u'^ >o . ^ O OS c3 .^ ^ •^ C3 rt S 03 S , a rt rt o s to tt^ a H^ — 3^ t: a — .2 93? « a -o-o2 M "^ bij a - a *-5 r a -■:5t;-='-aa o.2Ss;-fl5§ *^ a "^ *^ ib^ "3 -^ a o o ^ m a a t*4 ^1^ a;>. be w to -!3 <1 --( es d 03^ cd •o ■^1 I 1 1 1 1 I 1 _ t 1 _ ►^ 1 XI 1 s ■-s 1 1 1 1 1 1 ^ I 1 ■a >« -^3 ^ 1 -^ X! v^^ -o XJ to , 5 0) c^ 3cr '^^ Qj ea a "a u C,aj ftrt 5 a-3 a«3 ■s s'' 5 t^ 1 TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 151 ■5^ to a .^ O S-r a b MS a 03 Scs -S aa 4) -M—J-l M <1 ,ja a-o a to ca CO t»-.n fc% >-.j3 «C1 a >> (In Ch Km 1 tljO "•C.2 3 CS tC o — .— . '^ ;^ fa pa a?, to to^S T ti g O 1 I TC^ 'OT3 ag "O ^ a oj D 0) ^ H oj u «p 4) i> Ul ca 3 d ft — M ts ft ~ 0) • -I- 152 LANGUAGE I need hardly point out that these examples are far from exhausting the possibilities of linguistic structure. Nor that the fact that two languages are similarly classi- fied does not necessarily mean that they present a great similarity on the surface. We are here concerned with the most fundamental and generalized features of the spirit, the technique, and the degree of elaboration of a given language. Nevertheless, in numerous instances we may observe this highly suggestive and remarkable fact, that languages that fall into the same class have a way of paralleling each other in many details or in structural features not envisaged by the scheme of clas- sification. Thus, a most interesting parallel could be drawn on structural lines between Takelma and Greek,^^ languages that are as geographically remote from each other and as unconnected in a historical sense as two languages selected at random can well be. Their simi- larity goes beyond the generalized facts registered in the table. It would almost seem that linguistic features that are easily thinkable apart from each other, that seem to have no necessary connection in theory, have nevertheless a tendency to cluster or to follow together in the wake of some deep, controlling impulse to form all; spinster and Webster have been completely disconnected from the etymological group of spin and of weave ( web ) . Simi- larly, there are hosts of related words in Chinese which differ in the initial consonant, the vowel, the tone, or in the presence or absence of a final consonant. Even where the Chinaman feels the etymological relationship, as in certain cases he can hardly help doing, he can assign no particular function to the phonetic variation as such. Hence it forms no live feature of the language- mechanism and must be ignored in defining the general form of the language. The caution is all the more necessary, as it is precisely the foreigner, who approaches a new language with a certain prying inquisitiveness, that is most apt to see life in vestigial features which the native is either completely unaware of or feels merely as dead form. 23 Not Greek specifically, of course, but aa a typical representa- tive of Indo-European. TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 153 that dominates their drift. If, therefore, we can only be sure of the intuitive similarity of two given lan- guages, of their possession of the same submerged form- feeling, we need not be too much surprised to find that they seek and avoid certain linguistic developments in common. We are at present very far from able to de- fine just what these fundamental form intuitions are. We can only feel them rather vaguely at best and must content ourselves for the most part with noting their symptoms. These symptoms are being garnered in our descriptive and historical grammars of diverse lan- guages. Some day, it may be, we shall be able to read from them the great underlying ground-plans. Such a purely technical classification of languages as the current one into ''isolating," ''agglutinative," and "inflective" (read "fusional") cannot claim to have great value as an entering wedge into the discovery of the intuitional forms of language. I do not know whether the suggested classification into four conceptual groups is likely to drive deeper or not. My own feel- ing is that it does, but classifications, neat constructions of the speculative mind, are slippery things. They have to be tested at every possible opportunity before they have the right to cry for acceptance. Meanwhile we may take some encouragement from the application of a rather curious, yet simple, historical test. Languages are in constant process of change, but it is only reason- able to suppose that they tend to preserve longest what is most fundamental in their structure. Now if we take great groups of genetically related languages,-* we find that as we pass from one to another or trace the course 24 Such, in other words, as can be shown by documentary or comparative evidence to have been derived from a common source. See Chapter VII. 154 LANGUAGE of their development we frequently encounter a gradual change of morphological type. This is not surprising, for there is no reason why a language should remain per- manently true to its original form. It is interesting, however, to note that of the three intercrossing classifi- cations represented in our table (conceptual type, tech- nique, and degree of synthesis), it is the degree of syn- thesis that seems to change most readily, that the tech- nique is modifiable but far less readily so, and that the conceptual type tends to persist the longest of all. The illustrative material gathered in the table is far too scanty to serve as a real basis of proof, but it is highly suggestive as far as it goes. The only changes of conceptual type within groups of related languages that are to be gleaned from the table are of B to A (Shilluk as contrasted with Ewe; -^ Classical Tibetan as contrasted with Modern Tibetan and Chinese) and of D to C (French as contrasted with Latin -*'). But types A : B and C : D are respectively related to each other as a simple and a complex form of a still more fundamental type (pure-relational, mixed-relational). Of a passage from a pure-relational to a mixed-relational type or vice versa I can give no convincing examples. The table shows clearly enough how little relative per- manence there is in the technical features of language. That highly synthetic languages (Latin; Sanskrit) have frequently broken down into analytic forms (French; 25 These are far-eastorn and far-western representatives of the "Soudan" group recently proposed by D. Westermann. The genetic relationship between Ewe and Shilluk is exceedingly re- mote at best. 26 This case is doubtful at that. I have put French in C rather than in D with considerable misgivings. Everything depends on how one evaluates elements like -al in national, -U in bont4, or re- in retourner. They are common enough, but are they as alive, as little petrified or bookish, as our English -ness and -ful and un-? TYPES OF LINGUISTIC STRUCTURE 155 Bengali) or that agglutinative languages (Finnish) have in many instances gradually taken on "inflective" fea- tures are well-known facts, but the natural inference does not seem to have been often drawn that possibly the contrast between synthetic and analytic or agglutinative and "inflective" (fusional) is not so fundamental after all. Turning to the Indo-Chinese languages, we find that Chinese is as near to being a perfectly isolating language as any example we are likely to find, while Classical Ti- betan has not only fusional but strong symbolic features (e.g., g-tong-ba "to give," past h-tang, future g-tang, imperative tliong) ; but both are pure-relational lan- guages. Ewe is either isolating or only barely agglutina- tive, while Shilluk, though soberly analytic, is one of the most definitely symbolic languages I know ; both of these Soudanese languages are pure-relational. The relation- ship between Polynesian and Cambodgian is remote, though practically certain; while the latter has more markedly fusional features than the former,-^ both con- form to the complex pure-relational type. Yana and Salinan are superficially very dissimilar languages. Yana is highly polysynthetic and quite typically agglu- tinative, Salinan is no more synthetic than and as irreg- ularly and compactly fusional ("inflective") as Latin; both are pure-relational. Chinook and Takelma, re- motely related languages of Oregon, have diverged very far from each other, not only as regards technique and synthesis in general but in almost all the details of their structure ; both are complex mixed-relational lan- guages, though in very different ways. Facts such as these seem to lend color to the suspicion that in the contrast of pure-relational and mixed-relational (or con- crete-relational) we are confronted by something deeper, 27 In spite of its more isolating cast. 156 LANGUAGE more far-reaching, than the contrast of isolating, agglu- tinative, and fusional.^* 28 In a book of this sort it is naturally impossible to give an adequate idea of linguistic structure in ii,s varying forms. Only a few schematic indications are possible. A separate volume would be needed to breathe life into the sclieme. Such a volume would point out the salient structural characteristics of a num- ber of languages, so selected as to give the reader an insight into the formal economy of strikingly divergent types. VII LANGUAGE AS A HISTORICAL PEODUCT: DRIFT Every one knows that language is variable. Two in- dividuals of the same generation and locality, speaking precisely the same dialect and moving in the same social circles, are never absolutely at one in their speech habits. A minute investigation of the speech of each individual would reveal countless differences of detail — in choice of words, in sentence structure, in the relative frequency with which particular forms or combinations of words are used, in the pronunciation of particular vowels and consonants and of combinations of vowels and consonants, in all those features, such as speed, stress, and tone, that give life to spoken language. In a sense they speak slightly divergent dialects of the same language rather than identically the same language. There is an important difference, however, between individual and dialectic variations. If we take two closely related dialects, say English as spoken by the "middle classes" of London and English as spoken by the average New Yorker, we observe that, however much the individual speakers in each city differ from each other, the body of Londoners forms a compact, rela- tively unified group in contrast to the body of New Yorkers. The individual variations are swamped in or absorbed by certain major agreements — say of pronun- ciation and vocabulary — which stand out very strongly 157 158 LANGUAGE when the language of the group as a whole is contrasted with that of the other group. This means that there is something like an ideal linguistic entity dominating the speech habits of the members of each group, that the sense of almost unlimited freedom which each individual feels in the use of his language is held in leash by a tacitly directing norm. One individual plays on the norm in a way peculiar to himself, the next individual is nearer the dead average in that particular respect in which the first speaker most characteristically departs from it but in turn diverges from the average in a way peculiar to himself, and so on. What keeps the indi- vidual's variations from rising to dialectic importance is not merely the fact that they are in any event of small moment — there are well-marked dialectic variations that are of no greater magnitude than individual varia- tions within a dialect — it is chiefly that they are silently "corrected" or canceled by the consensus of usage. If all the speakers of a given dialect were arranged in order in accordance with the degree of their conformity to average usage, there is little doubt that they would constitute a very finely intergrading series clustered about a well-defined center or norm. The differences between any two neighboring speakers of the series ^ would be negligible for any but the most microscopic linguistic research. The differences between the outer- most members of the series are sure to be considerable, in all likelihood considerable enough to measure up to a true dialectic variation. What prevents us from say- ing that these untypical individuals speak distinct dia- lects is that their peculiarities, as a unified whole, are 1 In so far as tlioy do not fall out of the normal speech pjroup by reason of a marked speech defect or because they are isolated foreigners that have acQuired the language late in life. DRIFT 159 not referable to another norm than the norm of their own series. If the speech of any member of the series could actu- ally be made to fit into another dialect series,^ we should have no true barriers between dialects (and languages) at all. We should merely have a continuous series of individual variations extending over the whole range of a historically unified linguistic area, and the cutting up of this large area (in some cases embracing parts of several continents) into distinct dialects and languages would be an essentially arbitrary proceeding with no warrant save that of practical convenience. But such a conception of the nature of dialectic variation does not correspond to the facts as we know them. Isolated in- dividuals may be found who speak a compromise be- tween two dialects of a language, and if their number and importance increases they may even end by creat- ing a new dialectic norm of their own, a dialect in which the extreme peculiarities of the parent dialects are ironed out. In course of time the compromise dialect may ab- sorb the parents, though more frequently these will tend to linger indefinitely as marginal forms of the enlarged dialect area. But such phenemena — and they are com- mon enough in the history of language — are evidently quite secondary. They are closely linked with such so- cial developments as the rise of nationality, the forma- tion of literatures that aim to have more than a local appeal, the movement of rural populations into the cities, and all those other tendencies that break up the intense localism that unsophisticated man has always found natural. 2 Observe that we are speaking of an individual's speech as a whole. It is not a question of isolating some particular pecu- liarity of pronunciation or usage and noting its resemblance to or identity with a feature in another dialect. 160 LANGUAGE The explanation of primary dialectic differences is still to seek. It is evidently not enough to say that if a dialect or language is spoken in two distinct localities or by two distinct social strata it naturally takes on distinctive forms, which in time come to be divergent enough to deserve the name of dialects. This is cer- tainly true as far as it goes. Dialects do belong, in the first instance, to very definitely circumscribed social groups, homogeneous enough to secure the common feel- ing and purpose needed to create a norm. But the em- barrassing question immediately arises, If all the indi- vidual variations within a dialect are being constantly leveled out to the dialectic norm, if there is no appre- ciable tendency for the individual's peculiarities to initiate a dialectic schism, why should we have dialectic variations at all? Ought not the norm, wherever and whenever threatened, automatically to reassert itself? Ought not the individual variations of each locality, even in the absence of intercourse between them, to cancel out to the same accepted speech average? If individual variations ''on a flat" were the only kind of variability in language, I believe we should be at a loss to explain why and how dialects arise, why it is that a linguistic prototype gradually breaks up into a number of mutually unintelligible languages. But language is not merely something that is spread out in space, as it were — a series of reflections in indi- vidual minds of one and the same timeless picture. Lan- guage moves down time in a current of its own making. It has a drift. If there were no breaking up of a lan- guage into dialects, if each language continued as a firm, self-contained unity, it would still be constantly moving away from any assignable norm, developing new fea- tures unceasingly and gradually transforming itself into DRIFT 161 a lan^age so different from its starting point as to be in effect a new language. Now dialects arise not be- cause of the mere fact of individual variation but be- cause two or more groups of individuals have become sufficiently disconnected to drift apart, or independently, instead of together. So long as they keep strictly to- gether, no amount of individual variation would lead to the formation of dialects. In practice, of course, no language can be spread over a vast territory or even over a considerable area without showing dialectic va- riations, for it is impossible to keep a large population from segregating itself into local groups, the language of each of which tends to drift independently. Under cultural conditions such as apparently prevail to-day, conditions that fight localism at every turn, the tend- ency to dialectic cleavage is being constantly counter- acted and in part "corrected" by the uniformizing fac- tors already referred to. Yet even in so young a coun- try as America the dialectic differences are not incon- siderable. Under primitive conditions the political groups are small, the tendency to localism exceedingly strong. It is natural, therefore, that the languages of primitive folk or of non-urban populations in general are differ- entiated into a great number of dialects. There are parts of the globe where almost every village has its own dialect. The life of the geographically limited community is narrow and intense ; its speech is corre- spondingly peculiar to itself. It is exceedingly doubtful if a language will ever be spoken over a wide area with- out multiplying itself dialectically. No sooner are the old dialects ironed out by compromises or ousted by the spread and influence of the one dialect which is cul- turally predominant when a new crop of dialects arises 162 LANGUAGE to "undo the leveling work of the past. This is pre- cisely what happened in Greece, for instance. In classical antiquity there were spoken a large number of local dialects, several of which are represented in the literature. As the cultural supremacy of Athens grew, its dialect, the Attic, spread at the expense of the rest, until, in the so-called Hellenistic period following the Macedonian conquest, the Attic dia- lect, in the vulgarized form known as the ' ' Koine, ' ' be- came the standard speech of all Greece. But this lin- guistic uniformity ^ did not long continue. During the two millennia that separate the Greek of to-day from its classical prototype the Koine gradually split up into a number of dialects. Now Greece is as richly diversi- fied in speech as in the time of Homer, though the pres- ent local dialects, aside from those of Attica itself, are not the lineal descendants of the old dialects of pre- Alexandrian days.* The experience of Greece is not exceptional. Old dialects are being continually wiped out only to make room for new ones. Languages can change at so many points of phonetics, morphology, and vocabulary that it is not surprising that once the lin- guistic community is broken it should slip off in differ- ent directions. It would be too much to expect a locally diversified language to develop along strictly parallel lines. If once the speech of a locality has begun to drift on its own account, it is practically certain to move fur- ther and further away from its linguistic fellows. Fail- 3 It is doubtful if we have the right to speak of linguistic uni- formity even during the predominance of the Koine. It is liardly conceivable that when the various groups of non-Attic Greeks took on the Koine they did not at once tinge it with dialectic peculiarities induced by tlieir previous speech habits. 4 The Zaconic dialect of Lacedaemon is tlie sole exception. It is not derived from the Koine, but stems directly from the Doric dialect of Sparta. DRIFT 163 ing the retarding effect of dialectic interinfluences, which I have already touched upon, a group of dialects is bound to diverge on the whole, each from all of the others. In course of time each dialect itself splits up into sub- dialects, which gradually take on the dignity of dialects proper while the primary dialects develop into mutu- ally unintelligible languages. And so the budding proc- ess continues, until the divergences become so great that none but a linguistic student, armed with his docu- mentary evidence and with his comparative or recon- structive method, would infer that the languages in question were genealogically related, represented inde- pendent lines of development, in other words, from a remote and common starting point. Yet it is as certain as any historical fact can be that languages so little resembling each other as Modern Irish, English, Italian, Greek, Russian, Armenian, Persian, and Ben- gali are but end-points in the present of drifts that converge to a meeting-point in the dim past. There is naturally no reason to believe that this earliest "Indo- European" (or "Aryan") prototype which we can in part reconstruct, in part but dimly guess at, is itself other than a single "dialect" of a group that has either become largely extinct or is now further represented by languages too divergent for us, with our limited means, to recognize as clear kin.^ All languages that are known to be genetically re- lated, i.e., to be divergent forms of a single prototype, may be considered as constituting a "linguistic stock." There is nothing final about a linguistic stock. When 5 Though indications are not lacking of what these remoter kin of the Indo-European languages may be. This is disputed ground, however, and hardly fit subject for a purely general study of speech. 164 LANGUAGE we set it up, we merely say, in effect, that thus far we can go and no farther. At any point in the progress of our researches an unexpected ray of light may reveal the "stock" as but a "dialect" of a larger group. The terms dialect, language, branch, stock — it goes without saying — are purely relative terms. They are convertible as our perspective widens or contracts.^ It would be vain to speculate as to whether or not we shall ever be able to demonstrate that all languages stem from a com- mon source. Of late years linguists have been able to make larger historical syntheses than were at one time deemed feasible, just as students of culture have been able to show historical connections between culture areas or institutions that were at one time believed to be totally isolated from each other. The human world is con- tracting not only prospectively but to the backward- probing eye of culture-history. Nevertheless we are as yet far from able to reduce the riot of spoken languages to a small number of ' ' stocks. ' ' "We must still operate with a quite considerable number of these stocks. Some of them, like Indo-European or Indo-Chinese, are spoken over tremendous reaches; others, like Basque,'^ have a curiously restricted range and are in all likeli- hood but dwindling remnants of groups that were at one time more widely distributed. As for the single or multiple origin of speech, it is likely enough that lan- guage as a human institution (or, if one prefers, as a human "faculty") developed but once in the history of the race, that all the complex history of language is a unique cultural event. Such a theory constructed "on general principles" is of no real interest, however, 6 "Dialect" in contrast to an accepted literary norm is a use of the term that we are not considering. 7 Spoken in France and Spain in the region of the Pyrenees. DRIFT 165 to linguistic science. What lies beyond the demonstrable must be left to the philosopher or the romancer. We must return to the conception of "drift" in lan- guage. If the historical changes that take place in a language, if the vast accumulation of minute modifica- tions which in time results in the complete remodeling of the language, are not in essence identical with the indi- vidual variations that we note on every hand about us, if these variations are born only to die without a trace, while the equally minute, or even minuter, changes that make up the drift are forever imprinted on the history of the language, are we not imputing to this history a certain mystical quality? Are we not giving language a power to change of its own accord over and above the involuntary tendency of individuals to vary the norm? And if this drift of language is not merely the familiar set of individual variations seen in vertical perspective, that is historically, instead of horizontally, that is in daily experience, what is it? Language exists only in so far as it is actually used — spoken and heard, writ- ten and read. What significant changes take place in it must exist, to begin with, as individual variations. This is perfectly true, and yet it by no means follows that the general drift of language can be understood * from an exhaustive descriptive study of these variations alone. They themselves are random phenomena,^ like the waves of the sea, moving backward and forward in purposeless flux. The linguistic drift has direction. In other words, only those individual variations embody it or carry it which move in a certain direction, just as only certain wave movements in the bay outline the tide. The drift 8 Or rather apprehended, for we do not, in sober fact, entirely understand it as yet. S'Not ultimately random, of course, only relatively so. 166 LANGUAGE of a language is constituted by the unconscious selection on the part of its speakers of those individual variations that are cumulative in some special direction. This di- rection may be inferred, in the main, from the past history of the language. In the long run any new fea- ture of the drift becomes part and parcel of the com- mon, accepted speech, but for a long time it may exist as a mere tendency in the speech of a few, perhaps of a despised few. As we look about us and observe cur- rent usage, it is not likely to occur to us that our lan- guage has a "slope," that the changes of the next few centuries are in a sense prefigured in certain obscure tendencies of the present and that these changes, when consummated, will be seen to be but continuations of changes that have been already effected. We feel rather that our language is practically a fixed system and that what slight changes are destined to take place in it are as likely to move in one direction as another. The feeling is fallacious. Our very uncertainty as to the impending details of change makes the eventual con- sistency of their direction all the more impressive. Sometimes we can feel where the drift is taking us even while we struggle against it. Probably the ma- jority of those who read these words feel that it is quite "incorrect" to say "Who did you see?" We readers of many books are still very careful to say "Whom did you see?" but we feel a little uncomfort- able (uncomfortably proud, it may be) in the process. We are likely to avoid the locution altogether and to say "Who was it you saw?" conserving literary tradi- tion (the "whom") with the dignity of silence.^" The 10 In relative clauses too we tend to avoid tlie objective form of who." Instead of "The man whom I saw" we are likely to say The man that I saw" or "The man I saw." DRIFT 167 folk makes no apology. ''Whom did you see?" might do for an epitaph, but "Who did you see?" is the natu- ral form for an eager inquiry. It is of course the un- controlled speech of the folk to which we must look for advance information as to the general linguistic movement. It is safe to prophesy that within a couple of hundred years from to-day not even the most learned jurist will be saying "Whom did you see?" By that time the "whom" will be as delightfully archaic as the Elizabethan "his" for "its."" No logical or histori- cal argument will avail to save this hapless "whom." The demonstration " I : me = he : him = who : whom ' ' will be convincing in theory and will go unheeded in practice. Even now we may go so far as to say that the majority of us are secretly wishing they could say "Who did you see?" It would be a weight off their uncon- scious minds if some divine authority, overruling the lifted finger of the pedagogue, gave them carte hlanche. But we cannot too frankly anticipate the drift and maintain caste. We must affect ignorance of whither we are going and rest content with our mental conflict — uncomfortable conscious acceptance of the "whom," unconscious desire for the "who."^- Mean- 11 "Its" was at one time as impertinent a departure as the "who" of "Wlio did you see?" It forced itself into English be- cause the old cleavage between masculine, feminine, and neuter was being slowly and powerfully supplemented by a new one between thing-class and animate-class. The latter classification proved too vital to allow usage to couple males and things ( "his" ) as against females ('Hier"). The form "its" had to be created on the analogy of words like "man's," to satisfy the growing form feeling. The drift was strong enough to sanction a grammatical blunder. 12 Psychoanalysts will recognize the mechanism. The mechan- isms of "repression of impulse" and of its symptomatic sym- bolization can be illustrated in the most unexpected corners of individual and group psychology. A more general psychology 168 LANGUAGE while we indulge our sneaking desire for the forbidden locution by the use of the "who" in certain twilight cases in which we can cover up our fault by a bit of unconscious special pleading. Imagine that some one drops the remark when you are not listening attentively, "John Smith is coming to-night." You have not caught the name and ask, not "Wliom did you say?" but "Who did you say?" There is likely to be a little hesitation in the choice of the form, but the precedent of usages like ' ' Whom did you see ? " will probably not seem quite strong enough to induce a "Whom did you say?" Not quite relevant enough, the grammarian may remark, for a sentence like "Who did you say?" is not strictly analogous to "Whom did you see?" or "Whom did you mean?" It is rather an abbreviated form of some such sentence as "Who, did you say, is coming to-night*?" This is the special pleading that I have referred to, and it has a certain logic on its side. Yet the case is more hollow than the grammarian thinks it to be, for in reply to such a query as "You're a good hand at bridge, John, aren't you?" John, a little taken aback, might mutter "Did you say me?" hardly "Did you say I?" Yet the logic for the latter ("Did you say I was a good hand at bridge?") is evident. The real point is that there is not enough vitality in the "whom" to carry it over such little difficulties as a "me" can compass with- out a thought. The proportion " I : me = he : him =: who: whom" is logically and historically sound, but psychologically shaky. "Whom did you see?" is cor- rect, but there is something false about its correctness. It is worth looking into the reason for our curious than Freud'a will eventually prove them to be as applicable to the groping for abstract form, the logical or estlictic ordering of experience, aa to the life of the fundamental instincts. DRIFT 169 reluctance to use locutions involving the word "whom,** particularly in its interrogative sense. The only distinc- tively objective forms which we still possess in English are me, liini, Tier (a little blurred because of its identity with the possessive Jier), us, tliem, and whom. In all other cases the objective has come to be identical with the subjective — that is, in outer form, for we are not now taking account of position in the sentence. We ob- serve immediately in looking through the list of objec- tive forms that whom, is psychologically isolated. Me, Mm, her, us, and them form a solid, well-integrated group of objective personal pronouns parallel to the subjective series I, he, she, we, they. The forms who and whom are technically ''pronouns" but they are not felt to be in the same box as the personal pronouns. Whom has clearly a weak position, an exposed flank, for words of a feather tend to flock together, and if one strays behind, it is likely to incur danger of life. Now the other interrogative and relative pronouns (which, what, that), with which whom should properly flock, do not distinguish the subjective and objective forms. It is psychologically unsound to draw the line of form cleavage between whom and the personal pronouns on the one side, the remaining interrogative and relative pronouns on the other. The form groups should be sym- metrically related to, if not identical with, the function groups. Had which, what, and that objective forms parallel to whom, the position of this last would be more secure. As it is, there is something unesthetic about the word. It suggests a form pattern which is not filled out by its fellows. The only way to remedy the irregu- larity of form distribution is to abandon the whom alto- gether, for we have lost the power to create new objec- tive forms and cannot remodel our which-what-that group 170 LANGUAGE so as to make it parallel with the smaller group wJio- wTiom. Once this is done, who joins its flock and our unconscious desire for form symmetry is satisfied. "We do not secretly chafe at ' * Whom did you see ? ' ' without reason." But the drift away from wlwm has still other deter- minants. The words wlio and wliovi in their interroga- tive sense are psychologically related not merely to the pronouns which and what, but to a group of interroga- tive adverbs — where, when, how — al\ of which are in- variable and generally emphatic. I believe it is safe to infer that there is a rather strong feeling in English that the interrogative pronoun or adverb, typically an emphatic element in the sentence, should be invariable. The inflective -m of whom is felt as a drag upon the rhetorical effectiveness of the word. It needs to be eliminated if the interrogative pronoun is to receive all its latent power. There is still a third, and a very powerful, reason for the avoidance of whom. The con- trast between the subjective and objective series of per- sonal pronouns (/, he, she, we, tlicy:me, him, her, us, them) is in English associated with a difference of posi- tion. We say / see the man but the man sees me; he told him-, never him he told or him told he. Such usages as the last two are distinctly poetic and archaic ; they are opposed to the present drift of the language. Even in the interrogative one does not say Him did you see? It is only in sentences of the type Whom did you see? that an inflected objective before the verb is now used 13 Note that it is different witli irhose. Tliis has not the support of analogous possessive forma in its own functional group, but the analogical power of tlie great body of possessives of nouns {man's, boi/'s) as well as of certain personal pronouns {his, its; as predicated possessive also hers, yours, theirs) is sufticient to give it vitality. DRIFT 171 at all. On the other hand, the order in Whom did you see? is imperative because of its interrogative form; the interrogative pronoun or adverb normally comes first in the sentence {What are yon doing? When did he go? Where are you from?). In the "whom" of Whom did you see? there is concealed, therefore, a conflict between the order proper to a sentence containing an inflected ob- jective and the order natural to a sentence with an inter- rogative pronoun or adverb. The solution Did you see whom? or You saw whom? ^* is too contrary to the idio- matic drift of our language to receive acceptance. The more radical solution Who did you see? is the one the language is gradually making for. These three conflicts — on the score of form grouping, of rhetorical emphasis, and of order — are supplemented by a fourth difficulty. The emphatic whom, with its heavy build (half -long vowel followed by labial con- sonant), should contrast with a lightly tripping syllable immediately following. In whom did, however, we have an involuntary retardation that makes the locution sound "clumsy." This clumsiness is a phonetic verdict, quite apart from the dissatisfaction due to the grammatical factors which we have analyzed. The same prosodic ob- jection does not apply to such parallel locutions as what did and ivhen did. The vowels of what and when are shorter and their final consonants melt easily into the following d, which is pronounced in the same tongue position as t and n. Our instinct for appropriate rhythms makes it as difficult for us to feel content with whom did as for a poet to use words like dreamed and 1* Aside from certain idiomatic usages, as when You saw tvhomf is equivalent to You saw so and so and that so and so is ichof In such sentences whom is pronounced high and lingeringly to emphasize the fact that the person just referred to by the listener is not known or recognized. 172 LANGUAGE hummtd in a rapid line. Neither common feeling nor the poet's choice need be at all conscious. It may be that not all are equally sensitive to the rhythmic flow of speech, but it is probable that rhythm is an uncon- scious linguistic determinant even with those who set little store by its artistic use. In any event the poet's rhythms can only be a more sensitive and stylicized ap- plication of rhythmic tendencies that are characteristic of the daily speech of his people. We have discovered no less than four factors which enter into our subtle disinclination to say "Whom did you see?" The uneducated folk that says "Who did you see?" with no twinge of conscience has a more acute flair for the genuine drift of the language than its students. Naturally the four restraining factors do not operate independently. Their separate energies, if we may make bold to use a mechanical concept, are "canalized" into a single force. This force or minute embodiment of the general drift of the language is psy- chologically registered as a slight hesitation in using the word whom. The hesitation is likely to be quite un- conscious, though it may be readily acknowledged when attention is called to it. The analysis is certain to be unconscious, or rather unknown, to the normal speaker.^^ How, then, can we be certain in such an analysis as we have undertaken that all of the assigned determinants are really operative and not merely some one of them? Certainly they are not equally powerful in all eases. Their values are variable, rising and falling according to the individual and the locution.^^ But that they really 15 students of language cannot be entirely normal in their atti- tude towards their own speech. Perhaps it would be better to say "naiVe" than "normal." 16 It is probably this variability of value in the sigriificant compounds of a general linguistic drift that is responsible for DRIFT 173 exist, each in its own right, may sometimes be tested by the method of elimination. If one or other of the factors is missing and we observe a slight diminution in the corresponding psychological reaction ("hesitation" in our case), we may conclude that the factor is in other uses genuinely positive. The second of our four factors applies only to the interrogative use of ivJiom, the fourth factor applies with more force to the interrogative than to the relative. We can therefore understand why a sen- tence like 7s he the man whom you referred tof though not as idiomatic as 7s he the man (that) you referred tof (remember that it sins against counts one and three), is still not as difficult to reconcile with our innate feel- ing for English expression as Whom did you see? If we eliminate the fourth factor from the interrogative usage,^^ say in Whom are you looking atf where the vowel following whom relieves this word of its phonetic weight, we can observe, if I am not mistaken, a lesser reluctance to use the whom. Who are you looking at? might even sound slightly offensive to ears that welcome Who did you see? We may set up a scale of ''hesitation values" some- what after this fashion: Value 1: factors 1, 3. "The man whom I referred to." Value 2 : factors 1, 3, 4. "The man whom they referred to." Value 3: factors 1, 2, 3. "Whom are you looking at?" Value 4: factors 1, 2, 3, 4. "Whom did you see?" the rise of dialectic variations. Each dialect continues the gen- eral drift of the common parent, but has not been able to hold fast to constant values for each component of the drift. Devia- tions as to the drift itself, at first slight, later cumulative, are therefore unavoidable. 17 Most sentences beginning with interrogative whom are likely to be followed by did or does, do. Yet not all. 174 LANGUAGE We may venture to surmise that while wJiom will ulti- mately disappear from English speech, locutions of the type WJiojn did you see? will be obsolete when phrases like The man whom I referred to are still in lingering use. It is impossible to be certain, however, for we can never tell if we have isolated all the determinants of a drift. In our particular case we have ignored what may well prove to be a controlling factor in the history of who and whom in the relative sense. This is the uncon- scious desire to leave these words to their interrogative function and to concentrate on that or mere word order as expressions of the relative (e.g., The man that- 1 re- ferred to or The man I referred to). This drift, which does not directly concern the use of whom as such (merely of whom as a form of who), may have made the relative who obsolete before the other factors af- fecting relative whom have run their course. A consid- eration like this is instructive because it indicates that knowledge of the general drift of a language is insuffi- cient to enable us to see clearly what the drift is head- ing for. We need to know something of the relative potencies and speeds of the components of the drift. It is hardly necessary to say that the particular drifts involved in the use of whom are of interest to us not for their own sake but as symptoms of larger tendencies at work in the language. At least three drifts of major importance are discernible. Each of these has oper- ated for centuries, each is at work in other parts of our linguistic mechanism, each is almost certain to continue for centuries, possibly millennia. The first is the fa- miliar tendency to level the distinction between the sub- jective and the objective, itself but a late chapter in the steady reduction of the old Indo-European system of syntactic cases. This system, which is at present best DRIFT 175 preserved in Lithuanian,^^ was already considerably re- duced in the old Germanic language of which English, Dutch, German, Danish, and Swedish are modern dia- lectic forms. The seven Indo-European cases (nomi- native, genitive, dative, accusative, ablative, locative, in- strumental) had been already reduced to four (nomi- native, genitive, dative, accusative). We know this from a careful comparison of and reconstruction based on the oldest Germanic dialects of which we still have rec- ords (Gothic, Old Icelandic, Old High German, Anglo- Saxon). In the group of West Germanic dialects, for the study of which Old High German, Anglo-Saxon, Old Frisian, and Old Saxon are our oldest and most valuable sources, we still have these four cases, but the phonetic form of the case syllables is already greatly reduced and in certain paradigms particular cases have coalesced. The case system is practically intact but it is evidently moving towards further disintegration. Within the Anglo-Saxon and early Middle English period there took place further changes in the same direction. The phonetic form of the case syllables be- came still further reduced and the distinction between the accusative and the dative finally disappeared. The new "objective" is really an amalgam of old accusative and dative forms; thus, Tim, the old dative (we still say 7 give him the hook, not ''abbreviated" from I give to him; compare Gothic imma, modern German ihm), took over the functions of the old accusative (Anglo- Saxon hine; compare Gothic ina, Modern German ihn) and dative. The distinction between the nominative and accusative was nibbled away by phonetic processes and 18 Better, indeed, than in our oldest Latin and Greek records. The old Indo-Iranian languages alone (Sanskrit, Avestan) show an equally or more archaic status of the Indo-European parent tongue as regards case forms. 176 LANGUAGE morphological levelings until only certain pronouns re- tained distinctive subjective and objective forms. In later medieval and in modern times there have been comparatively few apparent changes in our case system apart from the gradual replacement of thou — thee (sin- gular) and subjective ye — objective you (plural) by a single undifferentiated form you. All the while, how- ever, the case system, such as it is (subjective-objective, really absolutive, and possessive in nouns; subjective, objective, and possessive in certain pronouns) has been steadily weakening in psychological respects. At pres- ent it is more seriously undermined than most of us realize. The possessive has little vitality except in the pronoun and in animate nouns. Theoretically we can still say the moon's phases or a newspaper's vogue; prac- tically we limit ourselves pretty much to analytic locu- tions like the phases of the moon and the vogue of a newspaper. The drift is clearly toward the limitation, of possessive forms to animate nouns. All the possessive pronominal forms except its and, in part, their and theirs, are also animate. It is significant that theirs is hardly ever used in reference to inanimate nouns, that there is some reluctance to so use their, and that its also is beginning to give way to of it. The appearance of it or the looks of it is more in the current of the language than its appearance. It is curiously sig- nificant that its young (referring to an animal's cubs) is idiomatically preferable to the young of it. The form is only ostensibly neuter, in feeling it is animate; psy- chologically it belongs with his children, not with the pieces of it. Can it be that so common a word as its is actually beginning to be difficult? Is it too doomed to disappear? It would be rash to say that it shows signs of approaching obsolescence, but that it is steadily weak- DRIFT 177 ening is fairly clear.^'' lu any events it is not too much to say that there is a strong drift towards the restriction of the inflected possessive forms to animate nouns and pronouns. How is it with the alternation of subjective and ob- jective in the pronoun? Granted that wJiom is a weak sister, that the two cases have been leveled in you (in it, that, and wliat they were never distinct, so far as we can tell-®), and that her as an objective is a trifle weak be- cause of its formal identity with the possessive her, is there any reason to doubt the vitality of such alterna- tions as / see the man and the man sees mef Surely the distinction between subjective / and objective me, be- tween subjective he and objective him, and correspond- ingly for other personal pronouns, belongs to the very core of the language. We can throw whom to the dogs, somehow make shift to do without an its, but to level / and me to a single case — would that not be to un- English our language beyond recognition? There is no drift toward such horrors as Me see him or / see he. True, the phonetic disparity between / and me, he and Mm, ive and us, has been too great for any serious pos- sibility of form leveling. It does not follow that the case distinction as such is still vital. One of the most j insidious peculiarities of a linguistic drift is that where it cannot destroy what lies in its way it renders it innoc- uous by washing the old significance out of it. It turns its very enemies to its own uses. This brings us to the ' second of the major drifts, the tendency to fixed posi- 19 Should its eventually drop out, it will have had a curious history. It will have played the role of a stop-gap between his in its non-personal use (see footnote 11, page 167) and the later analytic of it. 20 Except in so far as that has absorbed other functions than such as originally belonged to it. It was only a nominative- accusative neuter to begin with. 178 LANGUAGE tion in the sentence, determined by the syntactic relation of the word. We need not go into the history of this all-important drift. It is enough to know that as the inflected forms of English became scantier, as the syntactic relations were more and more inadequately expressed by the forms of the words themselves, position in the sentence gradu- ally took over functions originally foreign to it. The man in the man sees the dog is subjective; in the dog sees the man, objective. Strictly parallel to these sen- tences are he sees the dog and the dog sees him. Are the subjective value of he and the objective value of him entirely, or even mainly, dependent on the difference of form? I doubt it. We could hold to such a view if it were possible to say the dog sees he or him sees the dog. It was once possible to say such things, but we have lost the power. In other words, at least part of the case feeling in he and him is to be credited to their position before or after the verb. May it not be, then, that he and hi^n, we and lis, are not so much subjective and objective forms as pre-verbal and post-verbal ^^ forms, very much as my and mijie are now pre-nominal and post-nominal forms of the possessive (my father but father mine; it is my hook but the hook is mine) ? That this interpretation corresponds to the actual drift of the English language is again indicated by the language of the folk. The folk says it is me, not it is I, which is "correct" but just as falsely so as the whom did you see? that we have analyzed. I'm the one, it's me; we're 21 Aside from the interrogative: am I? is he? Emphasis counts for something. There is a strong tendency for the old "objec- tive" forms to bear a stronger stress than the "subjective" forms. This is why the stress in locutions like He didn't go, did he? and isn't he? is thrown back on the verb; it is not a matter of logical emphasis. DRIFT 179 the ones, it's us that will win out — such are the live parallelisms in English to-day. There is little doubt that it is I will one day be as impossible in English as c'est je, for c'est moi, is now in French. How differently our /; me feels than in Chaucer's day is shown by the Chaucerian it am I. Here the dis- tinctively subjective aspect of the / was enough to influ- ence the form of the preceding verb in spite of the intro- ductory it; Chaucer's locution clearly felt more like a Latin sum ego than a modern it is I or colloquial it is me. We have a curious bit of further evidence to prove that the English personal pronouns have lost some share of their original syntactic force. Were he and she sub- jective forms pure and simple, were they not striving, so to speak, to become caseless absolutives, like man or any other noun, we should not have been able to coin such compounds as he-goat and she-goat, words that are psychologically analogous to hull-moose and mother-hear. Again, in inquiring about a new-born baby, we ask Is it a he or a she? quite as though he and she were the equiv- alents of male and female or hoy and girl. All in all, we may conclude that our English case system is weaker than it looks and that, in one way or another, it is des- tined to get itself reduced to an absolutive (caseless) form for all nouns and pronouns but those that are animate. Animate nouns and pronouns are sure to have distinctive possessive forms for an indefinitely long period. Meanwhile observe that the old alignment of case forms is being invaded by two new categories — a posi- tional category (pre-verbal, post- verbal) and a clas- sificatory category (animate, inanimate). The facts that in the possessive animate nouns and pronouns are destined to be more and more sharply distinguished 180 LANGUAGE from inanimate nouns and pronouns {the man's, but of the house; his, but of it) and that, on the whole, it is only animate pronouns that distinguish pre-verbal and post-verbal forms "^ are of the greatest theoretical interest. They show that, however the language strive for a more and more analytic form, it is by no means manifesting a drift toward the expression of "pure" relational concepts in the Indo-Chinese manner.^^ The insistence on the concreteness of the relational concepts is clearly stronger than the destructive power of the most sweeping and persistent drifts that we know of in the history and prehistory of our language. The drift toward the abolition of most case distinc- tions and the correlative drift toward position as an all-important grammatical method ave accompanied, in a sense dominated, by the last of the three major drifts that I have referred to. This is the drift toward the invariable word. In analyzing the "whom" sen- tence I pointed out that the rhetorical emphasis natural to an interrogative pronoun lost something by its form variability {who, whose, whom). This striving for a simple, unnuanced correspondence between idea and word, as invariable as may be, is very strong in Eng- lish. It accounts for a number of tendencies which at first sight seem unconnected. Certain well-established forms, like the present third person singular -s of works or the plural -s of hooks, have resisted the drift to invariable words, possibly because they sym- bolize certain stronger form cravings that we do not yet fully understand. It is interesting to note that derivations that get away sufficiently from the 22 They: them as an inanimate group may be looked upon as a kind of borrowing from the animate, to which, in feeling, it more properly belongs. 23 See page 155. DRIFT 181 concrete notion of the radical word to exist as inde- pendent conceptual centers are not affected by this elu- sive drift. As soon as the derivation runs danger of being felt as a mere nuancing of, a finicky play on, the primary concept, it tends to be absorbed by the radical word, to disappear as such. English words crave spaces between them, they do not like to huddle in clusters of slightly divergent centers of meaning, each edging a little away from the rest. Goodness, a noun of qual- ity, almost a noun of relation, that takes its cue from the concrete idea of "good" without necessarily predi- cating that quality (e.g., I do not think much of his goodness) is sufficiently spaced from good itself not to need fear absorption. Similarly, unable can hold its own against able because it destroys the latter 's sphere of influence ; unable is psychologically as distinct from able as is blundering or stupid. It is different with adverbs in -ly. These lean too heavily on their adjec- tives to have the kind of vitality that English demands of its words. Do it quickly! drags psychologically. The nuance expressed by quickly is too close to that of quick, their circles of concreteness are too nearly the same, for the two words to feel comfortable together. The adverbs in -ly are likely to go to the wall in the not too distant future for this very reason and in face of their obvious usefulness. Another instance of the sac- rifice of highly useful forms to this impatience of nuancing is the group whence, whither, hence, hither, thence, thither. They could not persist in live usage because they impinged too solidly upon the circles of meaning represented by the words where, here and there. In saying whither we feel too keenly that we repeat all of where. That we add to where an important nuance of direction irritates rather than satisfies. We prefer 182 LANGUAGE to merge the static and the directive {WJiere do you live? like Where are you going?) or, if need be, to overdo a little the concept of direction ( Where are you running to'i). Now it is highly symptomatic of the nature of the drift away from word clusters that we do not object to nuances as such, we object to having the nuances for- mally earmarked for us. As a matter of fact our vo- cabulary is rich in near-synonyms and in groups of words that are psychologically near relatives, but these near-synonyms and these groups do not hang together by reason of etymology. "We are satisfied with believe and credible just because they keep aloof from each other. Good and ivell go better together than quick and quickly. The English vocabulary is a rich medley be- cause each English word wants its own castle. Has English long been peculiarly receptive to foreign words because it craves the staking out of as many word areas as possible, or, conversely, has the mechanical imposi- tion of a flood of French and Latin loan-words, un- rooted in our earlier tradition, so dulled our feeling for the possibilities of our native resources that we are allowing these to shrink by default? I suspect that both propositions are true. Each feeds on the other. I do not think it likely, however, that the borrowings in English have been as mechanical and external a process as they are generally represented to have been. There was something about the English drift as early as the period following the Norman Conquest that wel- comed the new words. They were a compensation for something that was weakening within. VIII LANGUAGE AS A HISTORICAL PRODUCT: PHONETIC LAW I HAVE preferred to take up in some detail the analysis of our hesitation in using a locution like "Whom did you see?" and to point to some of the English drifts, particular and general, that are implied by this hesi- tation than to discuss linguistic change in the abstract. What is true of the particular idiom that we started with is true of everything else in language. Nothing is perfectly static. Every word, every grammatical ele- ment, every locution, every sound and accent is a slowly changing configuration, molded by the invisible and im- personal drift that is the life of language. The evidence is overwhelming that this drift has a certain consistent direction. Its speed varies enormously according to cir- cumstances that it is not always easy to define. We have already seen that Lithuanian is to-day nearer its Indo- European prototype than was the hypothetical Germanic mother-tongue five hundred or a thousand years before Christ. German has moved more slowly than English; in some respects it stands roughly midway between Eng- lish and Anglo-Saxon, in others it has of course diverged from the Anglo-Saxon line. When I pointed out in the preceding chapter that dialects formed because a lan- guage broken up into local segments could not move along the same drift in all of these segments, I meant of course that it could not move along identically the same drift. The general drift of a language has its depthSt 183 184 LANGUAGE At the surface the current is relatively fast. In certain features dialects drift apart rapidly. By that very fact these features betray themselves as less fundamental to the genius of the language than the more slowly modi- fiable features in which the dialects keep together long after they have grown to be mutually alien forms of speech. But this is not all. The momentum of the more fundamental, the pre-dialectic, drift is often such that languages long disconnected will pass through the same or strikingly similar phases. In many such cases it is perfectly clear that there could have been no dia- lectic interinfluencing. These parallelisms in drift may operate in the phonetic as well as in the morphological sphere, or they may affect both at the same time. Here is an interesting example. The English type of plural represented by foot: feet, mouse: mice is strictly parallel to the Ger- man Fuss : Filsse, Maus : Mliuse. One would be inclined to surmise that these dialectic forms go back to old Germanic or West-Germanic alternations of the same type. But the documentary evidence shows conclusively that there could have been no plurals of this type in primitive Germanic. There is no trace of such vocalic mutation ("umlaut") in Gothic, our most archaic Ger- manic language. More significant still is the fact that it does not appear in our oldest Old High German texts and begins to develop only at the very end of the Old High German period (circa 1000 a.d.). In the Middle High German period the mutation was carried through in all dialects. The typical Old High German forms are singular fuoss, plural fuossi; ^ singular mus, plural 1 1 have cliangcd the Old and Middle High German orthography slightly in order to bring it into accord with modern usage. These purely orthographical changes are immaterial. The u of mus is a long vowel, very nearly like the oo of English moose. PHONETIC LAW 185 musi. The corresponding Middle High German forms are fuoss, fiiesse; mus, miise. Modern German Fuss: Filsse, Maus: Mduse are the regular developments of these medieval forms. Turning to Anglo-Saxon, we find that our modern English forms correspond to fot, fet; mus, mysr These forms are already in use in the earliest English monuments that we possess, dating from the eighth century, and thus antedate the Middle High German forms by three hundred years or more. In other words, on this particular point it took German at least three hundred years to catch up with a phonetic- morphological drift ^ that had long been under way in English. The mere fact that the affected vowels of related words (Old High German uo, Anglo-Saxon o) are not always the same shows that the affection took place at different periods in German and English.* There was evidently some general tendency or group of tendencies at work in early Germanic, long before English and German had developed as such, that eventu- ally drove both of these dialects along closely parallel paths. How did such strikingly individual alternations as fot: fet, fuoss: fiiesse develop? We have now reached 2 The vowels of these four words are long ; o as in rode, e like o of fade, u like oo of brood, y like German il. 3 Or rather stage in a drift. 4 Anglo-Saxon fet is "unrounded" from an older fot, which is phonetically related to fot precisely as is mys (i.e., miis) to mus. Middle High German ue (Modern German it) did not develop from an "umlauted" prototype of Old High German uo and Anglo- Saxon 0, but was based directly on the dialectic uo. The unaf- fected prototype was long o. Had this been affected in the earliest Germanic or West-Germanic period, we should have had a pre-German alternation fot: foti; this older o could not well have resulted in He. Fortunately we do not need inferential evi- dence in this case, yet inferential comparative methods, if handled with care, may be exceedingly useful. They are indeed indis- pensable to the historian of language. 186 LANGUAGE what is probably the most central problem in linguistic history, gradual phonetic change. "Phonetic laws" make up a large and fundamental share of the subject- matter of linguistics. Their influence reaches far be- yond the proper sphere of phonetics and invades that of morphology, as we shall see. A drift that begins as a slight phonetic readjustment or unsettlement may in the course of millennia bring about the most profound structural changes. The mere fact, for instance, that there is a growing tendency to throw the stress auto- matically on the first syllable of a word may eventually change the fundamental type of the language, reducing its final syllables to zero and driving it to the use of more and more analytical or symbolic ^ methods. The English phonetic laws involved in the rise of the words foot, feet, mouse and mice from their early West-Ger- manic prototypes fot, foti, mus, musi^ may be briefly summarized as follows: 1. In foti "feet" the long o was colored by the fol- lowing * to long 0, that is, o kept its lip-rounded quality and its middle height of tongue position but anticipated the front tongue position of the i; o is the resulting com- promise. This assimilatory change was regular, i.e., every accented long o followed by an i in the following syllable automatically developed to long o; hence totlii *' teeth" became totJii, fodian "to feed" became fodian. At first there is no doubt the alternation between o and was not felt as intrinsically significant. It could only have been an unconscious mechanical adjustment such as may be observed in the speech of many to-day who mod- ify the "oo" sound of words like you and feiv in the 5 See page 13.3. 6 Primitive Germanic fot{s),fotiz, mus,m.vsiz; Indo-European pods,podes, mus,inuses. The vowels of the first syllables are all long. PHONETIC LAW 187 direction of German ii without, however, actually de- parting far enough from the "oo" vowel to prevent their acceptance of wlio and you as satisfactory rhyming words. Later on the quality of the o vowel must have departed widely enough from that of o to enable o to rise in consciousness ^ as a neatly distinct vowel. As soon as this happened, the expression of plurality in foti, tdtlii, and analogous words became symbolic and fusional, not merely fusional. 2. In 7nusi "mice" the long u was colored by the following i to long il. This change also was regular; liisi "lice" became lilsi, kui "cows" became kili (later simplified to kit; still preserved as ki- in kine), fulian "to make foul" became fulian (still preserved as -iile in defile). The psychology of this phonetic law is entirely analogous to that of 1. 3. The old drift toward reducing final syllables, a rhythmic consequence of the strong Germanic stress on the first syllable, now manifested itself. The final -*, originally an important functional element, had long lost a great share of its value, transferred as that was to the symbolic vowel change {o: o). It had little power of resistance, therefore, to the drift. It became dulled to a colorless -e; foti became fote. 4. The weak -e finally disappeared. Probably the forms fijie and fot long coexisted as prosodic variants according to the rhythmic requirements of the sentence, very much as Fiisse and Fiiss' now coexist in German. 5. The of fot became "unrounded" to long e (our present a of fade). The alternation of fot: foti, transi- tionally fot: foti, fote, fot, now appears as fot: fet. Analogously, toth appears as tetli, fodian as fedian, later 7 Or in that unconscious sound patterning which is ever on the point of becoming conscious. See page 57. 188 LANGUAGE fedan. The new long rdinate sentences, 37 Corean, 205 Croce, Benedetto, 237, 239 Culttire, 221 ; language and, 227-30, 231, 232. 233-5; lan- guage as aspect of, 2, 10; language, race and, 222. 223, 230, 231; reflection of his- tory of, in language, 206, 207 INDEX 251 Culture areas, 221, 222, 228 D Danish, 49, 110, 136, 175, 217 Demonstrative ideas, !)7, 98, 114 Dental articulations, 54, 192 Derivational concepts. See Concepts. Determinative structure, 135 Dialects, causes of, 160-3; com- promise between, 159; dis- tinctness of, 159; drifts in, diverging, 183, 184; drifts in, parallel, 184-93; splitting up of, 163, 164; unity of, 157-9. DifTusion, morphological, 217- 20 Diphthongs, 56 Drift, linguistic: 160-3, 183, 184; components of, 172-4; determinants of, in English, 168-82; direction of, 165, 166, 183; direction of, illus- trated in English, 166-8; examples of general, in Eng- lish, 174-82; parallelisms in, 184-93; speed of, 183, 184. See Phonetic Law; Phonetic processes. Duplication of words, 79-81 Dutch, 175, 188, 212, 224 E Elements of speech, 24-42 Emotion, expression of: invol- untary, 3; linguistic, 39- 41 English: agentive suffix, 87; analogical leveling, 202, 203; analytic tendency, 135, 136, 216, 217; animate and in- animate, 176. 177, 179, 180; aspect, 114; attribution, 101; case, history of, 169, 170, 175-7, 179;' compounds, 67, 68, 69, 70; concepts, gram- matical, in sentence, 86-94 ; concepts, passage of concrete into derivational, 108, 109 consonantal change, 64, 78 culture of speakers of, 229 230; desire, expression of 39; diminutive suffix, 87 drift, 166-82; duplication word, 79, 80; esthetic quali ties, 241, 243; feeling-tone 41, 42; form, word, 59, 60 61 ; French influence on, 206 207, 208, 210, 211, 215, 216 function and form, 93, 94 fusing and juxtaposing, 137 138, 139-41; gender, 100 Greek influence on, 215, 216 influence of, 207 ; influence on, morphological, lack of deep, 215-17; interrogative words, 170; invariable words, tendency to, 180-2, 208; in- fixing, 75; Latin influence on, 206, 207, 208, 215, 216; loan-words, 182; modality, 90, 91, 92, 93; number, 90, 91; order, word. 65. 66. 170, 171, 177-9, 191, 192; parts of speech, 123-5; patterning, formal, 62, 63; personal re- lations, 91, 92, 93; plionetic drifts, history of. 184-93, 194, 197-9; phonetic drifts, history of, 184-93, 194, 197-9; phonetic leveling, 193, 194; phonetic pattern, 200, 206; plurality, 38, 99, 100, 105, 106, 202; race of speakers of, 223-7 ; reference, definite- ness of, 89, 90, 92, 93; re- lational words, 32 ; relations, genetic, 163, 175, 183, 218; rhythm, 171, 172; sentence, analysis of, 37 ; sentence, de- pendence of word on, 116; sound-imitative words, 6, 80; sounds, 44, 45, 49. 51. 53. 54, 56, 57; stress and pitch, 36, 55, 83; structure, 151. 180; survivals, morphological, 149, 152; symbolism, 134; syn- tactic adhesions, 117. 118; syntactic values, transfer of, 252 INDEX 120; tense, 91, 93, 102, 103, 104; verb, syntactic rela- tions of, 115; verse, 245, 24G; vocalic change, 70; word and element, analysis of, 25, 26, 27, 28, 29, 30, 35 English, Middle, 175, 176, 188, 191, 201, 202, 203 Enj?lish people, 223, 224 Eshimo, 60, 68, 70, 74, 118, 134, 135, 230, 243 Eskimos, 230 Eice (Guinea coast, Africa), 80, 84, 150, 154, 155 Expiratory sounds, 55 "Explosives," 62 F Faucal position, 53 Feeling-tones of words, 41, 42 Fijians, 230 Finnish, 135, 155, 219 Finns, 226 Flemish, 212 "Foot, feet" (English), history of, 184-93, 197-9, 201, 202 Form, cultural, 233, 234; feel- ing of langiiage for, 58, 62, 63, 152, 153, 210, 220; "in- ner," 132, 133 Form, linguistic: conservatism of, 102-4; differences of, me- chanical origin of, 105, 100; elaboration of, reasons for, 102-6; function and, inde- pendence of, 59-63, 93, 94; grammatical concepts em- bodied in, 86-12G; gram- matical processes embodying, 59-85 ; permanence of differ- ent aspects of, relative, 153- 6; twofold consideration of, 59-61. See Structure, lin- guistic. Form-classes, 105, 113. See Gender. Formal units of speech, 33 "Formlessness, inner," 132, 133 Fox (N. Amer.), 74 French : analytical tendency, 135, 136, 137; esthetic quali- ties, 241; gender, 102, 104, 113; influence, 205, 206, 207, 208, 209, 210, 211, 212, 215, 216; order, word, 67; plu- rality, 99; sounds, 51, 212; sounds as words, single, 24; stress, 55, 118; structure, 151, 154; tense forms, 103; verse, 245, 246 French, Norman, 224 French people, 224, 225 Freud, 168 Fricatives, 52 Frisian, 175, 224 Fid (Soudan), 79, 81 Function, independence of form and, 59-63, 93, 94 Functional units of speech, 33 Fusion, 137, 138, 139, 140, 141, 149 Fusional languages, 147, 150, 151. See Fusion. Fusioiial-agglutinative, 148, 150, 151 Fusional-isolating, 148, 150 "Fuss, Fiisse" (German), his- tory of, 184, 185, 191-3, 197- 99 G Gaelic, 225 Gender, 100-2, 113 German: French influence on, 208, 209, 212; grammatical concepts in sentence, 95; Latin influence on, 206, 208; phonetic drifts, history of, 184, 18,5, 188, 191-3, 197-9; plurality, 100; relations, 175, 183; soimd-imitative words, 6; sounds, 56, 212; tense forms, 103; "umlaut," 202, 203, 204; unanalvzable words, resistance to, 208, 209 German, High, 224 German, Middle High, 184, 185, 192, 204 INDEX 253 German, Old High, 175, 184, 185, 192, 194 Germanic languages, 175, 183, 184, 185, 186, 206, 212, 226 Germanic, West, 175, 184, 185, 186, 187, 191, 192, 224 Germans, 224, 225, 226 Gesture languages, 20, 21 Ginneken, Jac van, 40 Glottal cords, 48; action of, 48-50 Glottal stop, 49 Gothic, 82, 175, 184 Grammar, 39 Grammatical element, 26-32 Grammatical concepts. See Co7i- cepts, grammatical. Grammatical processes, classi- fied by, languages, 133-5; particular, development by each langiiage of, 62, 63 ; types of, 63, 64; variety of, use in one language of, 61, 62 Greek, dialectic history of, 162 Greek, classical: affixing, 137; compounds, 67, 68 ; concord, 121; infixing, 75; influence, 207, 215, 216; pitch accent, 83; plurality, 100; redupli- cated perfects, 82, 216; stress, 82, 83; structure, 139, 151, 152; synthetic char- acter, 137; verse, 244, 246 Greek, modern, 137, 163, 194, 212 H Haida (British Columbia), 56, 57, 150, 219, 229 Hamitio languages (N". Africa), 77, 219, 221 Hausa (Soudan), 81 Hebrew, 61, 62, 73, 76, 151, 207 Heine, 240 Hesitation, 172, 173, 183 History, linguistic, 153-6, 7- 204 Eokan languages (N. Amer.), 220, 229 Hottentot (S. Africa), 55, 81, 70, 80, 81 Hudson, W. H., 242 Humming, 50 Hupa (N. California), 71, 72 Hupa Indians, 228 Icelandic, Old, 175 India, languages of, 54 Indians, American, languages of, 34, 35, 49, 51, 56, 57, 68, 84, 85, 105, 130, 212, 213. See also Algonkin; Atlia^ iaskan; Chimariko ; Chinook/ Eskimo; Fox; Haida; Hokan; Hitpa; Iroquois; Karok; Kivakiutl; Nahuatl; Nass; Navaho; Nootka; Ojibwa; Paitite; Sahaptin; Salinan; Shasta; Siouan; Sioxix ; Tak- elma; Tlingit ; Tsimshian; Washo; Yana; Yakuts; Yurok. Indo-Chinese languages, 155, 164 Indo-European, 24, 75, 82, 163, 164, 174, 175, 186, 200, 226 Indo-Iranian languages, 175, 212 Infixes, 26, 64, 75, 76 Inflection. See Inflective lan- guages. Inflective languages, 130, 136- 41, 143, 144, 14G, 155 Influence, cultural, reflected in language, 205-10; morpho- logical, of alien language, 215-17, 220; phonetic, of alien language, 210-15 Inspiratory sounds, 65 Interjections, 4, 5 Irish, 224 Irish, 78, 79, 163, 218 Iroquois (N. Amer.), 69, 70 Isolating languages, 130, 133, 147, 150 Italian, 54, 55, 137, 163 "Its," history of, 167, 176, 177 254 INDEX Japanese, 205, 207 Jutes, 224 Juxtaposing. See Agglutinate tion. Karok (N. California), 220, 229; K. Indians, 227 Khmer. See Camhodgian. Knowledge, source of : as gram- matical category, 115 Ko'me, 162 Kwakivtl (Britisli Columbia), 81, 07, 98 Labial trills, 53 _ Language : associations in, 38, 39; associations underlying elements of, 10, 11; auditory cycle in, 17; concepts ex- pressed in, 12; a cultural function, 2, 10; definition of, 7; diversity of, 21-3; ele- ments of, 24-38; emotion ex- pressed in, 39-41; feeling- tones in, 41, 42; grammatical concepts of, 86-126; gram- matical processes of, 59-85; historical aspects of, 157- 204; imitations of sounds, not evolved from, 5, 6; influ- ences on, exotic, 205-20; in- terjections, not evolved from, 5; ■ literature and, 236-47; modifications and transfers of typical form of, 17-21; an "overlaid" function, 8; psy- cho-physical basis of, 8, 9; race, culture and, 221-35; simplification of experience in, 11, 12; sounds of, 43-58; structure of, 127-56; thought and, 12-17, 232, 233; uni- versality of, 21-3; vnriability of, 157-65; volition expressed in, 39-41 Larynx, 48-50 Lateral sounds, 52, 53 Latin: attribution, 101; con- cord, 121; infixing, 26, 75; influence of, 206, 207, 215, 216; objective -m, 119, 120; order of words, 65, 66, 123; plurality. 100; prefixes and suffixes, 71 ; reduplicated per- fects, 82, 216; relational con- cepts expressed, 101, 102; sentence-word, 33, 36; sound as word in, single, 24 ; struc- ture, 151, 154; style, 243, 244; suffixing character, 134, 137; syntactic nature of sentence, 116, 118; synthetic character, 135, 137; verse, 244, 245, 246; word and ele- ment in, analysis of, 27, 29, 30 Lettish, 49 Leveling, phonetic, 193, 194, 195. See Analogical leveling. Lips, 48 ; action of, 62, 53 Literature, compensations in, formal, 246, 247; language and, 42, 236-47; levels in, linguistic, 237-41; medium of, language as, 236, 237 ; science and, 238-40 Literature, determinants of: linguistic, 240, 241 ; metrical, 244-6; morphological, 241-4; phonetic, 241 Lithuanian, 55, 175, 183 Localism, 161 Localization of speech, 8, 9 Lonchrvx (N". Amer.), 71; L. Indians, 228 Lun.TS, 48 Lutlier, German, of, 192 M Mnlaif, 132; M. race, 227 Malayan, 227 Malayo- Pnlynesian languages, 219. 221,' 227 Manrhu, 80 Mannr, 225 INDEX 255 '"Maus, Ma use" (German), his- tory of, 184, 185, l!)l-3 Mediterranean race, 223 Melanesian languages, 227, 230 Meter. See Terse. JMilton, 242 Mixed-relational languages, 146, 147, 154; complex, 146, 147, 151, 155; simple, 146, 147, 151 Modality, 90, 91, 92, 93, 114 Mon-Khmer (S. E. Asia), 210 Moore, George, 242 Morphological features, diffu- sion of, 217-20 Morphology. See Structure, linguistic. "Mouse, mice" (English), his- tory of, 184-93 Munda languages (E. India), 219 Murmuring, 50 Mutation, vocalic, 184, 185, 197-9, 20.3, 204 N Nahuatl (Mexico), 69, 70 Nasal sounds, 51 "Nasal twang," 51 Nasalized stops, 52 Nass (British Columbia), 62, 81 Nationality, 222, 227, 228 Navaho (Arizona, New Mex- ico), 71, 77, 83, 136; N. In- dians, 228 Nietzsche, 241 Nootka (Vancouver Id.), 29, 3.3, 35, 68, 70, 74, 79, 82, 95, 109-11, 135, 141-3, 151 Nose, 48; action of, 50, 51 Noun, 123, 124, 126 Nouns, classification of, 113 Number, 90, 91, 93, 114. See Plurality. O Object, 92, 08. See Personal relations. Ojibwa (N. Amer.), 55 Onomatopoetic theory of origin of speech, 5, 6 Oral sounds, 51-4 Order, word: 64-6, 91, 92; com- position as related to, 67, 68; fixed, English tendency to, 177-9; sentence molded by, 117, 118; significance of, fundamental, 119, 120, 123 Organs of speech, 7, 8, 47, 48 ; action of, 48-54 Paiute (N. Amer.), 31, 32, 36, .52, 53, 69, 70 Palate, 48; action of soft, 51; articulations of, 53 Pali (India), 207 Papuan languages, 227 Papuans, 227, 230 Parts of speech, 123-5, 126 Pattern, formal, 61, 63, 234, 242; phonetic, 57, 58, 187, 93-6, 99, 200, 206, 211, 214, 215, 220 Persian, 163, 207 Person, 114 Personal relations, 91, 92, 93, 115 Phonetic adaptation, 210, 211 Plionetic diffusion, 211-15 Phonetic law, basis of, 195, 196, 199, 200; direction of, 194, 195, 199; examples of, 186-93; influence of, on mor- phology, 203, 204; influence of morphology on, 196-9; regu- larity of, 193, 194; signifi- cance of, 186; spread of, slow, 190, 191. See Leveling, phonetic; Pattern, phonetic. Phonetic processes, form caused by, diff'erences of, 105, 106; parallel drifts in, 184-93, 197-9 Pitch, grammatical use of, 88- 5; metrical use of, 246; pro- duction of, 49 ; significant diflFerences in, 55, 64 256 INDEX Plains Indians, gesture lan- guage of, 20 "Plattdeutsch," 224, 225 Plurality: classification of con- cept of, variable, 110, 111, 112; a concrete relational category, 90, 100; a deriva- tional or radical concept, 99 ; expression of, multiple, 38, 62. See Number. Poles, 225 Poh/nesian, 132, 150, 155, 227, 230 Polynesians, 221, 222, 227, 230 Polysyntlictic languages, 130, 135, 146, 148, 150, 151 Portuguese, 137 Predicate, 37, 126 Prefixes, 26, 64, 70, 71-5 Prefixing languages, 134, 135 Preposition, 125 Psycho -pliysieal, aspect of speech, 8, 9 Pure-relational languages, 145, 147, 154, 155; complex, 145, 147, 150, 155; simple, 145, 147, 150 Q Qualifying concepts. See Con- cepts, derivational. Quality of speech sounds, 48; of individual's voice, 48 Quantity of speech sounds, 65, 04 R Race, 221, 222; language and, lack of correspondence be- tween, 227; language and, theoretical relation between, 231-3; language as correlated with, English, 223-7; lan- guage, culture and, corre- spondence between, 230, 231 ; language, culture and, inde- pendence of, 222, 223 Radical concepts. See Concepts. Radical element, 26-32 Radical word, 28, 29 "Reading from the lips," 19 Reduplication, 64, 79-82 Reference, definite and indefi- nite, 89, 90 Repetition of stem, 26. See Re- duplication. Repression of impulse, 167, 168 Rhyme, 245, 246 Rolled consonants, 53 Ixomance languages, 137 Root, 25 Roumanian, 137 Rounded vowels, 52 Russian, 44, 45, 54, 71, 80, 103, 212 S Saliaptin languages (N. Amer.), 220 Salinan (S. W. California), 150, 155 Sanskrit (India), 54, 75, 82. If)!, 154, 175, 200, 207, 209, 210 Sarcee Indians, 228 Saxon, Low, 224; Old, 175; Upper, 225 Saxons, 224, 225 Scandinavian, 224. See Danish ; Icelandic; Swedish. Scandinavians, 224 Scotch, 224, 226 Scotch, Lowland, 188 Semitic languages, 61, 68, 76, 134, 151, 219, 228 Sentence, 33, 36-8; binding words into, methods of, 115- 17; stress in, influence of, 118, 119; word-order in, 117, 118 Sequence. See Order of words. Shakespeare, art of, 238, 240; English of, 188, 189. 191 Sha.