-~7 LOGIC INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE AN INTRODUCTION TO SCIENTIFIC METHOD BY ADAM LEROY ADJUNCT PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY ,'*.* .COPYRIGHT, 1909, BY HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY UNIV To L. S. M. 574274 PREFACE THIS book is intended as a text-book and not at all as a contribution to logical theory. It aims to present {in outline of scientific method as briefly and as con- cretely as possible. It is not designed to serve as an introduction to general philosophy. Its chief claim to novelty is in the arrangement of the subject matter. The traditional arrangement in which the deductive processes are presented first usually leaves with the student the impression that method is chiefly deduction, and that there is no very close connection between this and the rest of subject. The arrangement, which is here adopted, was selected on pedagogical grounds and not in the interests of any epistemological theory. The justification for dogmatic statements on dis- puted points is also pedagogical. Argument on such points in a text-book usually fails to interest the stu- dent and often tends to make him think that the whole subject is in an uncertain state and mostly a matter of opinion. Some subjects are treated much more briefly than they deserve, but I wished to keep them in due proportion with the rest. Fallacies are first discussed along with the processes with which they are connected, but they are all brought together in a later chapter. Many of the exercises are new, but I have also drawn freely from other text- books. The longer exercises at the end of the book give the student an opportunity to bring to bear al- vi PREFACE most the whole of scientific method, and for this reason they seem to me to be very important. My indebtedness to Jevons, Hyslop, Mill, and Bow- ley will be obvious. I owe much to Aikins' Principles of Logic; his broader treatment of many topics and his chapters on Testimony, Averages, Statistics, etc., were very suggestive. Sidgwick's The Use of Words in Reasoning, Creighton's treatment of the Figures of the Syllogism in his Introduction to Logic, Hibben's use of the idea of system in his Logic and Cramer's The Method of Darwin, were also suggestive. I have tried to give credit in each case in which I am con- scious of having borrowed. I am much indebted to three of my former col- leagues in Princeton University: to Professor W. T. Marvin for going over the whole of the copy and giv- ing me much useful advice, and to Professors W. H. Sheldon and E. M. Rankin for assistance with the proof; and to my colleagues, Professors Woodbridge and Montague, for many valuable discussions of logical problems. A. L. J. NEW YORK, April, 1909. CONTENTS PART I AN OUTLINE OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY PAGE Science and Common Sense Induction and Deduction in- cluded in Scientific Method The Beginning of knowl- edge Natural Sciences and others The Sources of Knowledge, Direct and Indirect Organizing knowledge Classification as a preliminary step Language as a necessary instrument Further steps in organized knowl- edge What is presupposed? 1 CHAPTER II FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE Facts and "the ways in which they are known Perception and what it includes Indirect means to knowledge of facts* ......... 13 CHAPTER III CLASSIFICATION Types of Classification Division Requirements of Classi- fication . . . . . . . . o 32 CHAPTER IV THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS Discrimination, Conception, Abstraction Necessity for Lan- guageTerms Kinds of Terms Definition Defects of Definitions 45 vii viii CONTENTS PAGS CHAPTER V PROPOSITIONS Kinds of Propositions Propositions and Terms The Rela- tion of Subject and Predicate The Distribution of Terms in a proposition Euler's Method Ambiguous Propositions 66 CHAPTER VI INDUCTION Generalization and what it includes Causal Connection Testing Inductive inferences Complete Enumeration How Generalizations are verified Observation and An- alysis are pre-supposed Postponing inference till test conditions are present The Inductive Methods. . . 79 CHAPTER VII VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION Verification and Deduction Systematic Knowledge How propositions are related to each other Relations of Opposition among propositions which have not identical terms Conversion Obversion Contraposition . . . 110 CHAPTER VIII THE SYLLOGISM The Principles of Syllogistic Reasoning The First Figure and its Principles The Second Figure The Third Figure The Fourth Figure 126 CHAPTER IX TRADITIONAL TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM Traditional treatment Moods Figures Note on the Re- duction of the Moods and Figures 137 CHAPTER X ABBREVIATED AND COMPLEX FORMS OF REASON' ING HYPOTHETICAL AND DISJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS The Enthymeme Prosyllogism and Episyllogism The So- rites Hypothetical Reasoning Disjunctive Reasoning More Complex Forms Extra-syllogistic Reasoning . 15J CONTENTS ix CHAPTER XI PAGE I. PROOF AND DISPROOF II. FAILURE TO PROVE Various Kinds of Proof Failures to Prove Fallacies . , 166 GENERAL EXERCISES *.. 171 PART II SUPPLEMENTARY METHODS CHAPTER I STATISTICS Statistics, their uses and limits Correlation The Processes used in Statistical Investigations 189 CHAPTER II AVERAGES The Arithmetical Average The "Weighted" Average The Mode The Median The Geometrical Average Meas- uring Deviations from an average Measurement of phe- nomena The Comparison of quantities which cannot be measured 198 CHAPTER III PROBABILITY The Meaning of Probability Deducing the probability of a phenomenon Dangers to be avoided in interpreting probability 213 SUPPLEMENT TO PART II The Graphic Method of Representing Data and Their Re- lations 226 PART III THE CONSTRUCTION OF SYSTEMS CHAPTER I EXPLANATION What is Explanation? , , , 231 x CONTENTS PAGH CHAPTER II HYPOTHESIS What is an Hypothesis? The Value of Hypotheses How are Hypotheses suggested to us? Requisites of a good hypothesis 246 CHAPTER III TYPICAL SYSTEMS OF KNOWLEDGE The Geometric System Others closely related to this Sys- tems which are more concerned with concrete phenom- ena Systems of Historical Facts 257 EXERCISES IN THE EXAMINATION OF COMPLEX REASONING Professor James's Argument for his Theory of the Emotions A. H. Fison on "The Evolution of Double Stars" Huxley on " The Demonstrative Evidence of Evolution " 279 PART I AN OUTLINE OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY Science and Common Sense. The methods of sci- 1 ence are the methods of all correct thinking. In all thinking we are concerned with getting and organiz- ing knowledge, or with testing, applying, and devel- oping the knowledge we have already acquired. We are all aware that correct thinking differs from that which is incorrect in its conformity to certain laws. These laws are usually spoken of as the laws of thought. They are not simply laws of thought, how- ever ; they are laws of things as well ; they are the laws of the world as we know it. They are adhered to, consciously or unconsciously, in all correct think- ing, whether casual or systematic. Science differs from common sense " only as a veteran differs from a raw recruit; and its methods differ from those of common sense only so far as the guardsman's cut and thrust differ from the manner in which the savage wields his club. The primary power is the same in each case, and perhaps the untutored savage has the more brawny arm of the two. The real advantage lies in the point and polish of the guardsman's weapon ; in the trained eye, quick to spy out the weakness of the adversary; in the ready hand, prompt to follow it upon the in- stant. But, after all, the sword exercise is only the hewing and poking of the clubman developed and perfected. 2 INTRODUCTORY " So the vast results obtained by science are won . . . by no mental processes other than those which are practised in every one of the humblest and meanest affairs of life. A detective policeman discovers a bur- glar from the marks made by his shoe, by a mental process identical with that by which Cuvier restored the extinct animals of Montmartre from the fragments of their bones. Nor does the process of induction and deduction by which a lady, finding a stain of a peculiar color upon her dress, concludes that somebody has up- set the inkstand thereon, differ in any way, in kind, from that by which Adams and Leverrier discovered a new planet. The man of science, in fact, simply uses with scrupulous exactness the methods which we all habitually and at every moment use 'Carelessly ; and the man of business must as much avail himself of the scientific method must be as truly a man of science as the veriest bookworm of us all." 1 ^ It is of course true that the conclusions of science are often in disagreement with those of common sense, but the disagreement is due to the difference in the thoroughness and completeness with which the facts have been examined. In many cases the -common sense of to-day is simply the science of yesterday, for com- mon sense is usually very conservative, and often re- gards the novelty of a conclusion as an argument against it. Induction and Deduction included in Scientific Method. Scientific method being simply a more thor- ough application of principles universally employed in i Huxley, The Educational Value of the Natural History Sciences. ' INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 3 reasoning, a good means of getting a general view of those principles will be to examine the procedure of science. It includes both formal and inductive logic. Formal or deductive logic is simply one part of scien- tific method ; hence any exposition of scientific method will include an examination of deduction. Sometimes induction is identified with scientific method, but it is often used in a narrower sense ; and, in any case, it might seem to exclude deduction, which is an essen- tial part of complete scientific method : therefore it is less confusing to think of induction as simply a part of scientific method. Inductive and deductive reason- ing are constituent elements in a single system. For purposes of study, it will be advisable to break up the system into several parts. The first of these parts will include the processes and principles involved in acquir- ing a knowledge of facts ; the second, those employed in the classification of facts ; the third, includes the discovery and formulation of laws ; and the fourth, the testing of these laws and their further organiza- tion and application. Each of these processes will be found to involve a number of subsidiary processes. As they are parts of a system, they are, of course, mutu- ally dependent; each leads up to or implies the others. The Beginning of Knowledge. Nowadays there is almost universal agreement to the statement that all knowledge begins in the perception of concrete facts. It has sometimes been thought that the mind began its -career with a capital stock of knowledge in the form of " innate " ideas or principles. But no one now maintains tlmt there is any knowledge before ex- 4 INTRODUCTORY perience begins. That, however, is no warrant for the conclusion which John Locke drew. 2 He held that the mind, at the beginning of its history, is like a sheet of white paper or a waxen tablet or an empty cabinet, and that experience, like some external force, writes upon the tablet or fills the cabinet. To him the mind seemed to be passive in the acquisition of knowledge, able at most to combine and analyze its sensations and ideas. Immanuel Kant, on the other hand, contended 3 that, even in those mental operations in which the mind is seemingly least active, it is contributing essential (elements; that it makes knowledge, as it were, out of .the material which is furnished from without ; it cannot roperate without material, hence there is no knowledge [before sense-experience begins ; but this sense-experi- ence itself is, in his view, a product of the mind's activ- ity. We cannot pursue this question any further; our concern is not with the philosophical problem of the ultimate source of knowledge ; it is enough for our purposes to know that knowledge begins in concrete experience, in perception, in knowing sounds and colors, odors, moving objects, pains, pleasures, emo- tions, and so on. Natural Sciences and Others. Things and events and relations in the external world constitute the data of what are sometimes known as the " natural " sci- ences, such as biology, physics and chemistry. Mental facts' and their relations make up the data of psychol- ogy ; they are quite as concrete in their way as any physical facts, and the methods employed by psychol- 2 In his Essay on the Human Understanding. s In his Critique of the Pure Reason. THE SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE 5 ogists are the same as those used in the physical sciences. Such sciences illustrate almost all the processes env ployed in the acquisition of knowledge, whereas a sci- ence like mathematics makes most use of a few of them, which it applies and elaborates with great thorough- ness. We shall attempt to follow, as closely as may be, the stages in building up knowledge as they appear in the natural sciences. As in knowledge generally, these sciences begin with the perception of facts, external or internal. Then sooner or later they proceed to classify arid organize the knowledge thus gained. The Sources of Knowledge, Direct and Indirect. Perception of concrete facts comes first as a source of knowledge, or rather as the primitive form of knowledge. Its limitations are obvious ; it is often far from clear ; it is frequently mistaken ; it embraces com- paratively few facts at any one time, and it does not extend beyond the present, or, at most, the immediate past. If we had to depend upon it alone, we could never get together a body of knowledge. It is possi- ble dimly to picture a mind which could be aware only of what was immediately present in time and space; its knowledge would be rudimentary, and without knowledge of something besides the present, the pres- ent itself would be meaningless. In all but the lowest types of consciousness there is a constant use of indi~ red means to knowledge. Memory is the first of these. 4 Memory restores a larger or smaller part of the 4 It might perhaps be said that memory is direct knowledge of the past, and this is true in a sense ; but the dependence of memory jupon previous perception, the fact that we do not remember what' we have not previously perceived, shows that it is also indirect. 6 INTRODUCTORY knowledge previously gained in perception, and thus makes it possible to draw upon past as well as present experience. Another indirect means to knowledge is the testimony of others ; by this means we can come into possession of a knowledge of facts which have never come under our own observation. Oral reports and written rec- ords furnish incomparably more information than any man's unaided observation could afford. A further way of extending our knowledge is to be found in inference. From knowledge which we already possess we are able to arrive at conclusions which shall be true of things which may never have been observed by any one; we infer the cause of a distant sound, or the character of the other side of the moon, or the stature and habits of man's remote ancestors, or the climate of the Northern Hemisphere in the Carbonifer- ous Age, etc. As we shall see later, inference is in- volved in greater or less degree in all the other means to knowledge. An inference may, of course, be wrong; if it is to possess any degree of certainty, there must be a con- siderable body of information about the facts in ques- tion or about other facts closely related to them. The same is true, to a great extent, of memory, and even of perception, and to a very great extent in the case of testimony. Errors may arise at any point, and one of the most important problems in all thinking is the detection and elimination of errors. Organizing Knowledge. Classification as a Pre- liminary Step. So far, attention has been fixed upon the processes employed in acquiring knowledge of facts. LANGUAGE 7 In order to make this knowledge available, the data thus acquired must be arranged or classified. The ob- ject of science is to get organized knowledge, and before knowledge can be organized it must be so ar- ranged as to enable us to see what facts are similar and what are different. Classification is the grouping of phenomena according to their likenesses and differ- ences ; those possessing a given characteristic are put into a group or class ; those lacking it may be put into one or more other classes. Classes may be grouped together in a larger class or subdivided into smaller ones. Language as a Necessary Instrument. There is one very important instrument for the acquisition of knowledge which has not yet been mentioned ; and that is language. Without some means of describing or otherwise representing facts, only a very limited use could be made of our perceptions: testimony would be impossible without it; inference involves representing to ourselves the consequences of certain principles or facts or situations; imagination and memory are ways of representing what is absent by means of pictures of the facts themselves or by means of other symbols. A great variety of symbols might be employed, but lan- guage, spoken and written, supplies by far the most important and complete set of symbols. The descrip- tion and classification of facts would be practically impossible without language. Further Steps in Organized Knowledge. In some sciences: we find little more than classified knowledge; the so-called " classificatory sciences," such as botany and zoology, have, until recently, consisted almost 8 INTRODUCTORY wholly of classified data. Science aims not simply at classified knowledge, but at organized knowledge, at knowledge organized into a coherent system. 5 It aims at the discovery of the laws manifested by its data as well as at the discovery of the data themselves and their arrangement into groups. What is a scientific law? A law in the -field of sci- ence is a statement of the way in which things do invariably behave. Unlike a moral law, a scientific law has nothing to say about the way in which things ought to behave, and, unlike a civil law, it does not prescribe a mode of action whose violation involves a penalty. The law of gravitation, for example, simply states that bodies do attract each other in certain defi- nite ways ; if bodies should fail to do this, the law of gravitation would be no genuine law. A scientific law states an invariable, unconditional -connection between phenomena. How are laws of this character discovered? They are based originally upon observation of particular instances of the behavior of phenomena. From ob- served instances we draw an inference which covers all other cases of the sort, past and future. This, that and the other acid turns blue litmus paper red ; we conclude that all acids will have a like effect. This conclusion may, of course, be mistaken ; it is an infer- ence, and must be tested or verified. Verification is then the next step. It may be under- taken in several ways: our conclusion may be com- 5 There are of course fields of science where classified knowledge is the most that can be had, But the ideal of science goes beyond this. PRESUPPOSITIONS d pared with other things which we know about the facts under investigation ; it may be shown to be a conse- quence of some known law ; or it may be possible to find some further fact which would be consistent with our inference and with no alternative inference that can be suggested. Speaking generally, verification in- volves finding whether the inference in question fits in with the system of things to which it belongs. If such a test cannot be applied, if there is no such system of which it can be shown to be a member, it remains uncertain. What is Presupposed? One important question re- mains to be asked. Are there any laws or universal propositions which do not require verification? Are there any statements which are self-evident and not open to question or to proof? Axioms, such as those of mathematics, are sometimes said to be of this char- acter. For example, take the statement that two things equal to the same thing are equal to each other; can this statement be doubted or can a proof for it be conceived? Are there not propositions which are so fundamental that they cannot be based upon any which are more general, and so necessary to all thought that they cannot be based upon perception, but are presupposed in perception? This raises again the question at issue between Locke and Kant; without attempting to answer it, we may at least say that no proposition which does not justify itself in experi- ence can be accepted as true. Many propositions have seemed to be self-evident only to be proved false by later development in knowledge, and whatever else may be urged in favor of any proposition, it must at any 10 INTRODUCTORY rate fit in with the rest of the things we know if it is to be accepted as true. Certain of these axioms or postulates are to be found in every science. In logic they appear under the name of the Laws of Thought. They are: The Law of Identity, expressed by the formula: A is A. The Law of Contradiction, expressed by the formula : A is not non-A. The Law of Excluded Middle: Either A is B or A is not B. The Law of Sufficient Reason: Every thing which exists has a sufficient reason or cause for being what it is. There is some disagreement regarding the meaning of some of these laws. The Law of Identity, for ex- ample, seems to be a mere tautology: to state that A is A, or that a thing is what it is, does not seem to give us any information. It is true, of course, that in a world where the Law of Identity, in this sense, did not hold, reason could do nothing. But the Law of Identity is usually taken to mean also that there must be an element of identity in every act of thought and in every piece of reasoning. In the proposition " Man is rational," it is obvious that man and rational are not identical; still there is something common to the two; without this core of identity no single judg- ment would be possible. The Law of Contradiction complements the Law of Identity. A thing is not its opposite, and in so far as there is opposition between two things it is neces- sary to assert that one is not the other. THE LAWS OF THOUGHT 11 The Law of Excluded Middle asserts that of two contradictory statements one or the other must be true. The law does not hold if the two statements are not contradictory, i.e., if there is any third possibility. There is a middle ground between " A is brilliant " and " A is stupid " : he may be an average person. But " This figure is square " and " This figure is not square " are contradictories. All these laws are, of course, laws for thought, but they are equally laws of things, and they are laws for thought for that reason only. Certainly they must hold for any world in which reason can operate. The Law of Sufficient Reason asserts that the uni- verse is a rational universe; that for everything that exists there is a reason, and an adequate reason; that things are capable of explanation, implying that the world is a coherent system. In the words of Leibniz, who gave the principle its rank, ". . . nothing occurs for which one having sufficient knowledge might not be able to give a sufficient reason why it is as it is and not otherwise." 6 If the world were entirely chaotic, knowledge, except that of the most primitive sort, would be impossible ; there could be no general knowledge, no knowledge of laws or principles, for laws and principles would not exist. It is conceivable, how- ever, that the world is only partly rational, that there are things for which there is no sufficient reason ; if so, rational knowledge would be limited to the fields within which principles did hold. Summarizing, we may say that every science aims 6 Principes de la Nature et de la Grace. Quoted in Dictionary of Philosophy, Ed. J. Mark Baldwin, Art. "Sufficient Reason." 12 INTRODUCTORY at the discovery of the laws of the data with which it deals, and at the organization of all its content into a single systematic whole. A completely organized system of knowledge would be one in which every part would imply every other, and he who understood the system perfectly could reconstruct the whole from any part. Cuvier claimed that a naturalist could recon- struct an animal from a single bone, and he himself, as noted by Huxley in the passage quoted above, gave evidence of the validity of his claim. Perfection of organization is not to be found in any natural science; the mathematical sciences show something approxi- .mating completeness, but they do not deal directly with concrete facts. CHAPTER II FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE I. Facts and the Ways in Which They are Known. Knowledge begins with the perception of facts; and these facts are of many kinds. What is a fact? A fact is anything which exists ; it is that which is real, apart from any opinion we may have about it or any attitude which we may take toward it ; it is that which is as opposed to that which is merely imag- ined or conceived. When we ask for facts, we ask for something which shall be independent of any belief 1 or disbelief, approval or disapproval, on the part of any person. 2 Some or all of these characteristics belong to laws, but fact is distinguished from law in being con- crete and particular, instead of abstract and general. A. PERCEPTION AND WHAT IT INCLUDES. Facts are known primarily through perception and memory ; they are known directly only by means of perception, 1 Belief and disbelief, whether true or false, are themselves facts; they are psychological facts. Belief in the Ptolemaic as- tronomy was a fact; that is, the belief actually existed. A false belief is one in which the thing believed is not a fact; it asserts or assents to something which does not really exist. Belief or dis- belief may bring about changes in facts; in other words, give rise to new facts, as may any other existing thing. To say that a fact is independent of our attitude means that its existence and char- acter are what they are apart from our attitude and aside from any possible effects which may be produced upon them by our attitude. 2 This position is confessedly dogmatic. Further reflection uiight show that nothing is independent, but for our present pur- pose this position is justified. 13 14 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE though there are various ways in which they may be known indirectly. One of the most important of these indirect means, and one which is an important element in all the rest, is inference; a perceived fact may be evidence to our minds of the existence of something which we cannot perceive. Much that is often included under perception must be eliminated when we are trying to use the term with scientific accuracy. For example, we say that we per- ceive the inkstand upon the table, or a man on the other side of the street, or that lightning has set fire to a distant building, or that Mr. X is an able law- yer, or that history repeats itself, and so on. Are any of these pure perceptions? We may perceive certain events, but to " perceive " that history is therein re- peating itself involves, at the very least, these infer- ences : that the words of historians represent what has occurred in the past; that they are competent and truthful and that we understand them; and that the events we perceive are really like those which they have described. In the example of the lawyer, we base our belief on observation of certain acts of his which have brought about desired results in spite of difficulties ; and on the inferences that he understood the situation and intended to bring about the results which actually occurred. Again, though the flash and the distant light were perceived, the conclusions that the flash was lightning and that the light was that of a burning building in the distance, and that the first of these was the cause of the second, involve far more than percep- tion. In such instances as these the presence of infer- ence is evident and the importance of distinguishing PERCEPTION AND INFERENCE 15 what is perceived from what is inferred is obvious. The perception might be correct, while the inference was erroneous, or vice versa. By distinguishing the two, the problems of discovering error and of correct- ing it are much simplified. But it is by no means easy to know where to draw the line between perception and inference. We should say ordinarily that we perceive the ink-well or the man across the street, but even in these cases there is some- thing which is very like inference. A perception con- tains many different elements, and these get themselves before the mind in a variety of ways ; comparatively little in any perception can be said to come directly from the object. In the perception of the ink-well or the man all that we get directly is a spot of color with certain variations of light, shade, and so on. But we seem to see an object in three dimensions, of a cer- tain size, at a given distance from us, and possessing weight, resistance, a certain degree of hardness, a pe- culiar internal structure and an indefinite number of other qualities, which may be more or less definitely present to the mind. If we had not, in the past, found these qualities in combination with spots of color sim- ilar to those now present, we should not be aware of them now; but that does not mean that these qualities are simply remembered, for they are present to the mind as genuinely objective qualities, and we seem to be as directly aware of them as we are of the color, although reflection shows us that they could not be given by sight alone. They all seem to present them- selves together, while in remembering a number of events, first one appears before the mind and then an- 16 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE other; in perceiving an object, the qualities do not come forward one after another, but all seem to be present together in a single thing. A perception is a reaction of the mind to an object, quality, or event of some kind. !A mind which has had little experience in a given field will react to an object in that field with a perception of a comparatively simple sort; if one had seen and handled oranges but had not tasted them, his percep- tion would contain no suggestion of the flavor, as a blind man's perception contains no suggestion of color or other visual qualities. Every time an object is perceived under new condi- tions something is added which will modify future per- ceptions in greater or less degree. The child builds up his perceptions gradually ; from a first vague, indefi- nite perception he advances to one that is more coher- ent and complete. The way in which any person will perceive an object will depend largely upon his past experience: different persons will consequently perceive the same object dif- ferently; as no two persons have ever had precisely the same experience, they will never see a given object in precisely the same way. But in most instances the differences will be slight, because there is so much that is common in the experience of all, and in the percep- tion of ordinary objects the differences are usually small and comparatively unimportant. " Fallacies " of Perception, and Their Causes. We think of perception as a certain and infallible source of knowledge ; but if in all perceptions there is a large addition from past experience it is clear that many of them are likely to be wrong. The present object may CAUSES OF MISTAKEN PERCEPTIONS 17 not be similar in all respects to like objects which we have seen in the past. A spot of color of a certain shape and apparent size may have stood invariably for an orange ; in other words, it may have been found along with other sensations indicating a solid spherical object, of a certain flavor and odor, with a certain in- ternal structure, and so on. If the spot of color again appears we seem to be aware of the other qualities. But there may be only a spot of color, as on the painter's canvas. Again, when two persons are similar in appearance, one may easily be mistaken for the other. The visual appearance of A may seem to as- sure the presence of the other qualities which, as a matter of fact, belong to B. The possibility of erroneous perceptions was com- mented upon very early in the history of thought, and because errors of this sort occur so frequently, some thinkers concluded that the senses were altogether unre- liable as sources of knowledge. Others urged that the fault was not with the senses; they pointed out that the trouble lay in adding to what the senses gave. When we have a sensation of greenness, they said, greenness is actually present to the mind ; if we go on to say that there is present an apple, we are adding a . number of qualities to those which are given by sensa- tion, and the qualities we add may not really be there. : If we should refrain from adding those other qualities we should never be mistaken, but it is impossible en- . tirely to separate the sensational element from the others. The perception is a unit in spite of the com- plexity of the qualities which make it up, and these qualities are capable of modifying each other. The 18 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE green of a picture or of a landscape does not look the same if the scene is looked at upside down; of course we should be correct in saying that we seem to see a certain shade of green in the first case and a different one in the second. We may be perfectly certain with regard to what we seem to see ; but then we seem to see an object as having three dimensions, when it may have only two, as in a painting; what we usually want to know is whether we see the thing as it is, whether other people seem to see the same thing, whether we may expect to seem to see it in the future, whether handling the object would give confirmatory sensations, and so on. The attempt to limit our statements to what is unmistakably before the mind takes us a very little way toward -certainty in knowledge. Perceptions in- clude more than that. They should, of course, be made as carefully as possible. But although errors are cer- tain to occur, yet if we do not run this risk of error we make little progress toward knowledge. This first form then in which knowledge appears is open to mistake ; there are mistaken perceptions. It may be well to note the different types of error and their chief causes. The types are usually said to be two; and they have been called Mai-observation and Non-observation. The names are self-explanatory. Mai-observation is of two kinds : in the one, something which does not belong to the object is added in the perception ; in the other, the relations of the parts are wrongly perceived, as when we read there for three. Of course, both kinds of mal-observation may be pres- ent together, and non-observation also. Otherwise stated, there are really three kinds of error; omission, THREE KINDS OF ERROR 19 addition and wrong relation of the parts in a whole. They may occur at any stage in knowledge, and they are, in fact, the only kinds which can occur at any stage. What are their causes in the field of percep- tion? A passage from Bacon, quoted by Jevons, calls attention to a number of the causes which give rise to them: "Things escape the senses because the object is not sufficient in quantity to strike the sense: as all minute bodies; because the percussion of the object is too great to be endured by the senses: as the form of the sun when looking directly at it in mid-day ; be- cause the time is not proportionate to actuate the sense: as the motion of a bullet in the air, or the quick circular motion of a fire-brand, which are too fast, or the hour hand of a common clock, which is too slow; from the distance of the object as to place: as the size of celestial bodies, and the size and nature of all dis- tant bodies; from prepossession by another object: as one powerful smell renders other smells in the same room imperceptible; from the interruption of interpos- ing bodies : as the internal parts of animals ; and be- cause the object is unfit to make an impression upon the sense: as the air, or the invisible and untangible spirit which is included in every living body." The various kinds of causes may be classified as follows : 1. In the first place, the external or physical con- ditio-ns of the perception may be unfavorable ; in a red or green light, the color of objects is wrongly seen; in a fog, sounding objects seem nearer than they really are; if the light is dim, details are overlooked; if we look through an imperfect window-pane, objects ap- 20 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE pear distorted. In all these cases there is something in the medium through which the object is perceivec] which leads to error. Similar difficulties arise when instruments are employed to extend the range or in- crease the accuracy of our perceptions. Any imper- fection in the instrument is almost certain to be a fruit- ful source of error. Other things might be cited in this field, but these will suffice to illustrate the class. 2. Next in order we may mention the physiological causes of mistaken perceptions. Imperfections in the sense-organ, fatigue, illness, and the like are obvious examples. There is one sort of perception which is always inaccurate, that of the time at which an event occurs ; a flash of lightning is seen a fraction of a second after the light reaches our eyes ; a sound is not heard in the instant at which it reaches our ears. The reason is this : a thing cannot be perceived until the nerve current which it sets up in our sense-organ has passed along through the nerves to the brain ; this takes time, and in some -cases, as in astronomy, the errors which arise from this source may be very im- portant. Again, we often tend to perceive an event for a moment after it has ceased, since the nervous system continues to reverberate, as it were, after the original cause of its activity has ceased to act. Hence the flash or sound seems to be present after it has really passed. This is seen in our inability to distin- guish the spokes of a rapidly revolving wheel or the successive vibrations of a tone, or single views in mov- ing pictures ; in all these the succeeding event begins before we have ceased to perceive the one before it. 3. But if all physiological and physical conditions PSYCHOLOGICAL CAUSES OF ERROR 21 were favorable, if all organs and media and instru- ments were perfect, there would still remain the psycho- logical sources of error. These are often or even always present along with the others. One of the psy- chological causes has already been alluded to, namely, (1) the tendency to see what we have previously seen in similar circumstances. There is also (2) a tendency to perceive what we expect or wish or hope or fear, or what has been recently or habitually in the mind, or that which has been vividly perceived or imagined. What is known as the " proof-reader's " illusion illus- trates one of these; in reading, the context often sug- gests a certain word and we see that word and overlook mistakes in spelling. In the following passage (based on one in James's Psychology) few persons reading at the ordinary rate, and with ordinary care, would succeed in detecting all the mistakes in spelling : Any one wateing in a dark plase and expectng or faer- ing a certaon objectt will interpret an abrup seusation to mean that object's presense. The boy playing " I spy," the criminel skulhing from his persuers, the superstitions personn hureying throuh the churchvard at midnight, the man losst in the woods, the girl who tremulusly has made an eveniug apointmnt with her swain, all are subjec to ilusions of sight and sound wkich make there hearts beat til they ate dispelld. Another case illustrating some of these principles is that of the prisoner who had already been convicted of one crime and served his sentence, and who narrowly escaped conviction a second time, although entirely innocent in both cases. He bore a superficial resem- blance to the real criminal; the witnesses were predis- 22 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE posed to believe that he was the criminal, and they positively identified him as the one whom they had seen committing the crime. The effectiveness of all these tendencies is enhanced by (3) lack of attention or misplaced attention. The inattentive reader overlooks misprints, and so does the reader who is very intent upon the thought. Presti- digitators, fraudulent spiritualistic mediums, and the like, take advantage of these tendencies. They direct attention to unimportant things in order that they may do the important ones unobserved, and by leading the spectator to expect certain events they can often persuade him to believe that he actually witnesses them. Mistakes as to the order of events are very easy in some circumstances; if two events, one in the field of sight and the other in that of sound, occur very nearly at the same time, this often happens. (4) Lack of training in observing events of a given kind may make correct perception impossible; the use of the micro- scope, finding and following a trail in the woods^ seeing distant objects at sea or on the plains, distin- guishing flavors, colors, etc., are examples. (5) Abnormal psychological conditions, such aa, nervous excitement, those produced by drugs, etc., modify the keenness and accuracy of perceptions, sometimes for the better and sometimes for the worse. These various causes, physical, physiological and psy- chological, are so closely bound up together that it is often difficult to say which is chiefly operative in any given case. Careful and intelligent attention will prevent many errors. A careful perception made with a purpose is OBSERVATION 23 called an observation. This term is sometimes used to cover all perception whatsoever, but it will be used here in the narrower sense. Still, the most carefully made perception may prove to be mistaken. In some of the sciences there are various special and technical methods of eliminating error. 3 The discovery of error does not always lead to its elimination nor enable us to make the requisite correc- tion. In some cases it does ; we have already seen that the perception of an event takes time; this time is longer for some persons than for others, but for each it is approximately constant under given conditions. By means of a device which registers the exact time at which a certain event occurs and the time at which the observer indicates that he perceives it, it is possible to determine his " personal error " and to make the proper correction in cases in which the exact time of the occurrence cannot be otherwise determined. But in most cases it is riot possible to do this or even to guess at the presence or the amount of error. Some- times, as in the case of measurements, it may be pos- sible to repeat the observation, and if the results cannot be made to agree, we can sometimes get a result approximately correct by taking an average. Testing Perceptions. It can almost be said that every observation should be held in suspicion until tested. The test would consist in finding out whether it agreed with other observations of the same fact or of similar facts made by ourselves or others, whether it was in agreement with the laws of the field in which it was found, with the laws of Nature generally, and so s See Jevons, Principles of Science, chap. xv. 2.4 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE on. We always proceed upon the principle that ail knowledge should hang together, should be consistent and coherent ; that the world is a consistent and coherent world ; and that correct perceptions will agree with each other and with the rest of our expe- rience. When it is possible to repeat an observation, we have at once a starting-point for testing it ; and when new observations can be made under more exact conditions, we are in a very favorable position for extending our knowledge of the facts under observation. One of the chief reasons why modern astronomy, for example, is so far in advance of that of the Greeks is to be found in the fact that modern instruments make the observa- tions of astronomical phenomena so much more reli- able. Experiment. Sometimes it is possible to reproduce at will the phenomenon under observation. This is the case, to a great degree, in physics and chemistry: sounds, chemical changes, and so on, can be repeated indefinitely. Moreover, the circumstances in which the phenomenon occurs may often be controlled and varied more or less, and that is very often a matter of great importance, as will appear later. To bring about an event for the sake of observing it is to experiment. An experiment may be performed for various reasons ; it may be that we wish simply to get an additional ob- servation as a basis for inference or a means of testing the accuracy of one which we have made already; or we may wish to see the result of changing certain of the circumstances in which the phenomenon occurs ; or of finding the consequences of any condi^on whatso" EXPERIMENT 25 ever. " Whenever we can, by our own agency, influence the object we are investigating, we can remedy this want [insufficient observation] by experiment. We can institute at will a certain group of conditions C, and so compel the causes which are really at work to respond with an effect E, which would otherwise per- haps have never come within the domain of our senses. By varying at will the quantity and composition of that C we can bring about in E a series of changes in quantity and kind, which were still less likely to offer themselves unsolicited to our observation. Again, we can break up C into its component parts, and in each experiment allow but one of these, or a definitely as- signed group of several of them, to take effect, at the same time cutting off the rest from action. The con- stituent elements of the result E admit of being sepa- rated in the same way, so that we learn which of them depends upon which element of the compound C. Thus experiment is the practical means by which we furnish ourselves with observations in such number and involv- ing such mutual differences and affinities as is requisite in order to the elimination of what is unessential in them. . . . Defined in this way, it is clear that ex- periment only has an advantage over observation in so far as it is capable of supplementing the usual defi- ciencies of the latter ; its function is to furnish us with suitable and fruitful observations instead of the un- suitable and unfruitful ones which offer themselves. . . . It is merely a way of preparing and setting be- fore ourselves phenomena which it is of importance that we should observe." 4 But its function is exceedingly *Lotze, Logic, Bk. II, chap, vii, 260. 26 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE important, and without it many sciences could make lit- tle progress. The peculiar advantage of being able to control and vary the conditions of an event to be observed will be evident at a later point. B. INDIRECT MEANS TO KNOWLEDGE OF FACTS. I. Memory and its Defects. So far in the present chapter we have discussed only the direct means of knowing facts. It appeared, however, that even in per- ception there is much that is a revival of past experi- ence, reinstated by the memory. Knowledge of the past, reappearing in memory, bulks very large in the total of our knowledge. True memory is simply the recall of past experience accompanied by awareness of the fact that it was our experience. If one experience or one object of experience is similar to what is now before our minds, or if it has been related to the latter in any way, it tends to reappear. That tendency is often overcome, otherwise practically everything would be remembered. Not only do many things drop out of the memory, but many are also changed in their character or order, and some things may be added. Ordinary for- getfulness corresponds to non-observation. It is prac- tically always present in greater or less degree, and it obviously tends to increase with the lapse of time. Many things disappear altogether ; sometimes the main outlines are remembered and details forgotten; some- times only a few of the details remain. Remembering wrongly corresponds to mal-observa- tion: words which were correctly heard may be incor- rectly remembered; an object which was seen as red may be remembered as brown, and so on. Hardly ever DEFECTS OF MEMORY 27 do any two witnesses agree exactly in their memory of events which could easily have been observed with little danger of mistake. This is so generally recognized that too close a correspondence between the stories of two witnesses is regarded as an evidence of collusion and dishonesty. Besides the modification of details, the order of events may be changed in memory or their relations may be modified in other ways, and entirely new elements may be introduced. Among the causes of mistaken memory the following may be noted: 1. A tendency to remember what would usually have happened in the circumstances. 2. A tendency to remember things or elements which were particularly pleasant or unpleasant, desired or feared, etc., at the expense of those which were more neutral. Elements or events of this sort, which did not occur but were suggested or expected, may be remem- bered as if they had occurred. 3. A tendency to remember things in a way which would make them more complete or logical, or more in agreement with our own opinions or wishes, or more in harmony with what we expected, or feared, etc. 4. Events which have often been described in one's hearing may seem to be remembered. The tests of memory, like those of perception, are based upon the principle that genuine knowledge is always consistent and coherent, that the world of facts is throughout harmonious. Where accurate records are available the memory, as a source of knowledge of the past, becomes much less important. Accurate records made at the time 28 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE when the phenomena were perceived are an essential part of all the concrete sciences. The methods of re- cording are many, and they are too technical for pres- ent discussion. II. Testimony. Written records and oral reports make up a large part of what is known as evidence. Besides these, evidence includes historical remains of every sort, products of man's activity, natural phe- nomena of every kind, such as glacial scratches, geo- logical deposits, etc., etc. The evidence may be of something in the remote past, of something not ob- served in the present, or of future events. The use of evidence clearly involves making inferences; it also in- volves perception. Some phenomenon is perceived, such as an uttered sound or an inscription or a fossil, and on the basis of this perception the observer draws con- clusions concerning something which may never be per- ceived. Oral and written reports, or, in other words, testi- mony, furnish a frequent ground of inference. Testi- mony includes every statement of fact made by any one. The opportunities for error in using it are so numerous that it is surprising that correct information can ever be reached by means of it. 1. In the first place, the person making the state- ment was liable to error in many ways when he observed the fact which his statement purports to represent. 2. In the second place, his memory is almost cer- tainly inaccurate in one way or another. 3. Again, the words which he uses may not correctly represent to us what he has in mind ; he may not use words accurately, or he may use them in a sense unfa- miliar to his hearer. DEFECTS OF TESTIMONY 29 4. In the fourth place, he may not be truthful; he may never have witnessed what he pretends to report, or he may intentionally misrepresent what he has wit- nessed. These difficulties are present in both oral and written testimony ; in the latter there are additional difficulties. What seems to be the witness of one person may be a garbled account; or errors may have been intro- duced by a copyist or an editor. In oral testimony cross-examination gives a basis for testing statements of the witness. In written testimony the substitute for this is found in other statements by the same writers and by contemporaries ; when these are not to be found, little credence can be given to the testimony. III. Inference. Inferences from facts of every sort are also liable to error. In every -case the final test is that of consistency and coherency. The application of the tests. very often involves complicated reasoning and a large body of special information ; it will be discussed incidentally in later chapters; much of sci- entific method is for the purpose of making such tests. EXERCISES 1. How much is really observed in seeing a marksman shoot a clay pigeon? In hearing an automobile pass, a block away? In seeing a prestidigitator take an object from a pocket in which it was not? 2. What are the causes of mal-observation and non-ob- servation in the following cases? (1) A straight stick partly immersed in water seems to be bent. (2) Two objects looked at through a stereoscope seem to be one, and they seem to be solid in- stead of flat. (3) The sun seen through a fog sometimes appears red. 30 FIRST STAGES IN KNOWLEDGE (4) Mirrors increase the apparent size of a room. (5) Distant objects appear small. (6) Patients often seem to feel pain in amputated limbs. (7) A table seems to throb if the fingers are pressed against it. (8) A rearrangement of the furniture in a room is often unnoticed. (9) We sometimes seem to feel the motion of a boat after landing. (10) There are marked differences in what the ordi- nary good observer, the artist, and the botanist see in a flower. (11) Silas Marner mistook Effie's hair for the lost gold. (12) Looking at one's watch and not knowing the time a moment later. (13) Not seeing the people one meets. (14) In Poe's Sphinx, a small animal on the window pane is thought to be a large moth of a strange species. (15) Mistaking the order of numbers, as 546 for 564. (16) Finding a likeness between an infant and its parents. (17) Macbeth seeing Birnam Wood coming to Dunsi- nane. (18) The pain of amputation when, instead of am- putation, an icicle is drawn across a limb. (19) Shooting a man for a deer when hunting in the woods. (20) The child's " seeing " things at night. 3. Give five examples of mistaken observation arising from each kind of cause described in the text. 4. Suggest causes for errors of memory in the follow- ing cases: (1) Memory of "the good old days " as better than the present. (2) Remembering the childhood of men who later became famous. EXERCISES 31 (3) In Ivanhoe, Wamba tells the travelers to go in one direction*, but points in the other; one of them remembers the verbal directions, the other the direction pointed out. (4) Forgetting cases which do not support one's view. (5) Forgetting certain items in lists of things to be bought, etc. (6) Dropping out characters or events in remember- ing a story or play. (7) Ascribing to one person words or deeds of an- other. (8) " Remembering " events which occurred before one was born. (9) " Remembering " the apt replies which one might have made. (10) Remembering as an actual experience what was merely a fiction often related as an experi- ence. 5. In how many different ways could you account for the statement of a witness that he had seen a ghost? 6. Suppose three honest witnesses to have testified to seeing a man catch a bullet in his teeth: What would your conclusion be ? 7. How would you test the statement: General X was killed in the battle of Gettysburg? CHAPTER III CLASSIFICATION OBJECTS of experience make their appearance in an order which seems to be almost chaotic ; and in memory they are often reproduced very much in the order in which they originally occurred. But even in memory, and still more in reflection, there is a tendency to arrange things according to their likenesses and differ- ences. This is the beginning of classification. Classi- fication " is not identical with collection. It denotes the systematic association of kindred facts, the collec- tion, not of all, but of relevant and crucial facts." A -classification is necessarily based on a similarity of some sort: of quality or structure or origin, and so on. Any given collection of things may be classified in many different ways. Books, for example, may be grouped according to subject, size, style of binding, publisher, and so on ; minerals, according to composi- tion, value or chemical properties ; the people of a city, according to race, income, occupation or religion. Any quality or relation whatever may serve as a basis of classification. In the abstract, one may be as good as another, and the one to be employed in a given instance will be that which best serves the purpose we have in hand. There are several different types of classification, each serving a special purpose. Types of Classification. 1. INDEX CLASSIFICATION. 1 Karl Pearson, The Grammar of Science, chap. III., n. 1. CLASSIFICATION 33 We may notice briefly the " Index Classification." 2 The purpose of this mode of grouping is to enable us to get hold of a given fact quickly and easily. Cata- logues are usually constructed with this end in view, and they illustrate the principles involved. Certain obvious characteristics are selected, and very often a given item may appear under several different heads, as in cross-references. Alphabetical catalogues are the most familiar examples of the index classification. 2. DIAGNOSTIC CLASSIFICATION. A second type is the " Diagnostic Classification " ; its purpose is the identification of an object or the discovery of the group to which it belongs. " Nature Study " books abound in classifications of this sort. Here, too, certain obvi- ous characteristics are made the basis of classification. Flowers, for example, may be classified according to color or time of appearance or habitat; or the main divisions may be made upon one basis, as color, the first subdivision on another, as time of appearance, etc. The identification of ailments by the physician depends upon a classification of symptoms made upon this plan. 3. " NATURAL " AND " ARTIFICIAL " CLASSIFICATIONS. Both index and diagnostic classifications are useful, but they do not, by themselves, lead directly to any greater knowledge of the facts or of their essential re- lations. They are based, for the greater part, upon superficial and easily noticed characteristics, 3 and have little relation to the essential properties of th& things classified. It is often possible, however, so to group 2 See Jevons, Principles of Science, chap. xxx. 3 A diagnostic classification which is to be a sure means for the identification of any and all cases should be based on essential qualities. Those based on superficial and striking qualities serve 34 CLASSIFICATION phenomena as to display at once their most significant characteristics. Compare, for example, the popular classification of the whale as a fish with the scientific classification of the same animal as a mammal. To call a whale a fish is to imply that it lives in the water, but tells little more ; to call it a mammal tells us that it has warm blood, lungs instead of gills, a four-chambered heart, certain peculiarities of the skeleton, and so on. Grouping data in such a way as to make manifest at once their essential characteristics is the aim of classification in science. Since science aims at complete and systematic knowledge, it will obviously select as the basis of classification in any given case that quality which does correlate the greatest amount of knowledge about the facts under consideration. Scientists usually make a distinction between " arti- ficial " and " natural " classifications. " It would be possible to classify all living things according to color, as white, yellow, green organisms, etc. Such a classifi- cation would, however, be artificial and destitute of sci- entific value because based upon a purely artificial and highly inconstant character. An interesting example of an artificial classification formerly employed is the system of Linnaeus, who classified flowering plants into Monandria, Diandria, Triandria, Tetrandria, etc., ac- cording to the number of stamens. This was sufficiently convenient for a first rough arrangement, but was soon found to lead to the most incongruous association of plants agreeing in the number of stamens but differing in almost all characters. From such cases it is plain that plants and animals cannot be naturally classified for ready identification of many cases, but not for all. See Bosar- quet's Logic for a discussion of Diagnostic Classification as one based upon deeper and more essential qualities. NATURAL CLASSIFICATIONS 35 by likenesses or differences in a single character arti- ficially selected. The entire organisms must be taken into account, and the natural classification differs from the artificial one in representing real relationship and not merely superficial likeness. Modern biology teaches that this relationship is of precisely the same nature .as human relationship, i.e., that it is due to community of descent from ancestral plants or animals. . . , 'The labor of determining the natural classification is much lightened by the fact that certain structures are often found as a matter of experience to be constantly .associated or -correlated, so that the presence of one indicates the presence of the others. In such cases a single character may be taken as the basis of a classi- fication which is natural, because agreement in one character has been previously proved empirically to in- dicate agreement in the others. For example, it has been proved that the differences or resemblances of ani- mals are correlated with corresponding differences or resemblances in their teeth. Hence mammals, to a great extent, can be classified according to the structure and disposition of the teeth. And so in many groups it is usually possible to discover empirically some one or few characters on which, by reason of their constant association with other characters, a natural classifica- tion can be based." 4 Biology furnishes one of the best illustrations of a field in which a natural classification can be made, al- though even here in many cases there is no universal agreement as to which is the natural classification. For each of two characters or sets of characters might be -correlated with a number of others, and it might be 4 Sedgwick and Wilson, Biology, p. 175. 36 CLASSIFICATION difficult to decide which of the two correlated the greater number or the more important ones. Even if there were such agreement, it would not necessarily be permanent; new information might result in the selec- tion of a new basis of relationship. The difference be- tween natural and artificial classifications is, as Jevons points out, one of degree only : " It will be found al- most impossible to arrange objects according to any circumstance without finding that some correlation of other circumstances is thus made apparent." The principle employed in classification for scientific purposes is well stated in Huxley's definition, which was modified somewhat by Jevons and stated in the follow- ing form : " By the classification of any series of ob- jects is meant the actual or ideal arrangement together of those things which are like and the separation of those which are unlike, the purpose of the arrangement being, primarily, to disclose the correlations or laws of union of properties and circumstances, and, secondarily, to facilitate the operations of the mind in clearly con- ceiving and retaining in memory the characters of the objects in question." A scientific classification is ordinarily designed to serve the purposes here enumerated, but there may be cases, especially in everyday life, where our primary interest is not in getting a -complete knowledge of things, but in getting together things which have a re- lation to some common purpose or problem ; and in such cases the grouping together of things which are, in most respects, very dissimilar, may be justifiable. Custom-house regulations, for example, proverbially group together things which, apart from certain eco- nomic considerations, may be totally unlike. The so- DIVISION - 37 called artificial classification may be entirely satisfac- tory as an index or diagnostic classification, though in a diagnostic classification, as we have seen, the use of essential qualities would furnish a surer means for iden- tifying doubtful cases than the use of obvious qualities. Classification, of whatever sort, is not simply bring- ing together data into a single group ; it involves the further ordering of the data in sub-groups. Division. Breaking up the group into sub-groups is known in logic as " Division." The first thing to do in making a logical division is to select some charac- teristic which will serve to distinguish some members of the group from the rest. It may belong to some and not to others, or it may belong to all in different degrees, etc. The technical name of a character used for this purpose is fundamentum divisionis, or basis of division. The simplest sort of division is that in which the fundamentum divisionis is a character pres- ent in some members of the class and lacking in the rest. Material substances may be divided into those which are mineral and those which are not; or, to cite an ancient example, we may divide and subdivide sub- stances as follows : 5 Substance A " Corporeal Incorporeal" f \ Animate Inanimate A _ t "S Sensible Insensible f \ Rational Irrational, etc. 5 This is known as the Tree of Porphyry, so-named from the Greek logician who was the earliest writer to give a distinct ac- count of this type of division. 38 CLASSIFICATION Division of this kind is called dichotomous or bifur- cate, from the fact that each group or sub-group is always divided into two. A more complex classification results from selecting as the basis of division some character which is pos- sessed by all the members of the class but with differ- ences of degree or quality, etc. Books, for example, if classified according to subject matter, would fall into several groups, and each of these might again be sub- divided into several more. 6 A dichotomous division e As further examples of classification of this kind we may cite the following from Hy slop's Logic, pages 96, 97. Figures - Plane., Solid, Rectilinear . . Curvilinear. Rectilinear. Curvilinear. Mechanical . Science . Physical, Moral , [ Trilateral ] Quadrilateral I Multilateral Circular Elliptical Parabolic Hyperbolic Tetrahedrons Pentahedrons Cubes Parallelepipeds, etc. Spheres Cones Cylinders Paraboloids {Physics Chemistry I Organic { Biology \ Physiology f History [ Polltlcal {Sociology f Noetics Psychological. -! Aesthetics [ Ethics DICHOTOMOUS DIVISION 39 would, of course, be possible here ; we might have some- thing like the following: Books On history Not on history r \ On chemistry Not on chemistry, etc. But a dichotomous division would soon become un- wieldly ; moreover, it does not present the classes in such a way as to indicate which are coordinate. The ex- ample just given might seem to make history coordi- nate with all other subjects taken together, and chemistry might seem to be subordinate to history. It is desirable, usually, that the classification shall put coordinate classes on the same plane, and this the dichotomous division cannot do. Moreover, this sort of division embodies very little information ; it points out a class which has a certain character and another which lacks it; the latter is de- scribed in negative terms only. The other type of classification presents a number of classes, each de- scribed in terms of some positive quality. Still there are many cases in which interest centers in those mem- bers of a class which possess (or lack) some certain character. For some purposes the division of popula- tion into voters and non-voters, or into literate and illiterate, may be quite as satisfactory as any other. Sometimes our information regarding a class is so imperfect that a dichotomous division is the only one we can use, In a given shipload of immigrants we might know that some were Italians ? and know nothing 40 CLASSIFICATION about the nationality of the rest except that they were not Italians. Or it might be that those outside the class positively characterized had so little in common that no class or series of classes, coordinate with the first, could include them all: the chemist's division of elements into metals and non-metals illustrates this. It has often been said that a dichotomous division is the only one which insures against the omission of any individual. Every member of a class must either pos- sess a certain quality or be without it ; all that are ex- cluded from the first class are necessarily included in the second, while in the other sort of division it is easy to overlook something. But if many classes are to be included, the dichotomous division soon becomes almost unmanageable, and if it is not carried out to the end we will not discover every class, although all are for- mally included. If it is carried out exhaustively, every- thing will of course be identified ; but the same would be true of any other type of classification. Jevons holds that diagnostic classifications should usually be dichotomous. Requirements of Classification. In any scientific classification (1) the sub-classes must include all that is included in the main class; and (2) they must not overlap, i. e., no individual should belong to two classes at once. To classify people as large and small would violate the first of these rules, while to classify them as large, small, and blue-eyed, would violate both. Viola- tion of the first rule results in incomplete division ; violation of the second, in cross-division. Incomplete division is a consequence of failure to carry out a division to the end ; sometimes the principle FAULTY CLASSIFICATION 41 of division does not seem to permit this, or some of the data included may be of so peculiar a character that they do not seem to fall into any well-marked classes, An escape from difficulties is sometimes found in a miscellaneous class, which shall include all cases not otherwise provided for. When this is employed, the classification is certain to include all cases. The mis- cellaneous class corresponds to the negative class in dichotomous division. Cross-division is a consequence of employing more than one fundamentum divisionis. In the example above, both size and eye-color were employed as bases of division. Every classification should be complete or exhaustive ; it should provide a place for every item. But a sort of cross-division may sometimes be very useful, as in index or diagnostic classifications. Ordinary subject indexes, classification of books under author and subject, or of college courses under department and year, are cases in point, as is also the classification of a disease under ea-ch of its several symptoms. A class which is divided into sub-classes is technically called a genus; while each of the sub-classes is a species. " Caucasian " is a species of the genus " man." If a sub-class were to be divided it would be a genus in rela- tion to its sub-classes : Slavs are a species of the genus Caucasian. Any class, then, regarded as inclusive of other classes is a genus, whereas if it is regarded as subordinate to some higher class it is a species. A class which is so wide that no other can contain it is called a summum genus or highest genus ; it alone can never be a species. A class which includes so little that 42 CLASSIFICATION it can not be subdivided is an infima species or lowest species ; it can never become a genus. An individual which is so unique that it can be in- cluded in no class whatever is sui generis. Under ordinary conditions there is little use for these last three terms. It may be doubted whether there is such a thing as an individual thing sui generis, and whether there can be more than one summum genus, or any infima species which is not a class of one member only. In any given investigation they may be employed in a relative sense. For anthropology, mammal might be regarded as the summum genus; and an individual whose peculiarities defy all attempts at classification on usual lines might be spoken of as sui generis; a species which could not usefully be divided might be regarded as an infima species. But this use of the terms would not be entirely accurate. The use of genus and species as described above is the traditional logical usage ; but in the biological sci- ences they are used in a different sense. In those sci- ences the terms are not relative ; a class is not a species at one time and a genus at another. Homo is always a genus ; formerly it was thought to have two species,, man and the chimpanzee, but now man, homo sapiens, is regarded as the only species in the genus. The Cau- casian race is a variety under the species, homo sapiens. Homo is included in the order, primates, etc. EXERCISES 1. What is classification? 2. What is an Index-classification? What is its purpose EXERCISES 43 and on what sort of quality is it based? How would you construct ait Index-classification of the rulers of Europe during the Nineteenth Century? 3. What is a Diagnostic-classification? State its purpose and its principles. How would you construct a classifica- tion which would serve for the identification of birds? 4. What is the purpose of classification as used in scien- tific work? What is the difference between an artificial and a natural classification? 5. What is a Dichotomous Division, and what are its strong and weak points? Make a dichotomous division of educational institutions. What is a cross-division? How is it caused, and when may it be useful ? Give examples of a genus, a species, a summum genus, an infima species, a thing sui generis. Contrast the biologist's use of " genus " and " species " with the more general logical usage. 6. Criticise the following classifications and divisions: a Men may be classified as white and colored. b Trees, as fruit-trees, shade-trees and forest-trees. c The fine arts, as sculpture, painting, drawing, architecture, poetry and photography. (Fowler.) d Books, as those on history, science, poetry, religion and belles-lettres. e Political parties, as conservative and radical. / The states of New England, as Maine, New Hamp- shire, Vermont, and Connecticut. g Mind, into intellect, feeling and will. h Body, into extension, weight, resistance, etc. (Mel- lone.) i Religious, into monotheistic and polytheistic. j Americans, into white, black and foreign-born. Ic Politicians, into honest and dishonest. I Books, into dull and interesting. m Games, into those which are athletic and those which are intellectual. n Pictures, into paintings, engravings, posters and pen and ink sketches. o Domestic animals, into those which are useful and those which are pets. p Motion, into molecular and molar. ^ Bodies, into light, heavy, and dense. 44 CLASSIFICATION r Men, into those whose main pre-occupation is to get through time and those whose aim it is to find time for all that has to be got through. Can you state circumstances in which any of the above might be useful and satisfactory? 7. Divide and sub-divide: Propositions, Athletic sports, College publications, Government, Poetry, Furniture, Races, Schools. 8. Criticise the classing together of negroes, coal, and black chalk on the ground that they are similar in being black, solid, extended, divisible, heavy, etc. (MeHone.) CHAPTER IV THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS Discrimination, Conception, Abstraction. It will be remembered that a thing is put into a given class by virtue of its possession of some quality or relation, a class being simply a group of things which have in common one or more qualities or relations. Any given thing might, therefore, be classified in several different ways. Bucephalus, for example, might be classified as a horse, or as a colored object, or as a consumer of hay, or as a possession of Alexander the Great, and so on. Indeed, most concrete objects might be classified in hundreds of ways. For every characteristic which a thing possesses there may be a class, and the way in which we shall classify it in any given instance will depend upon the purpose we have in view. For his teacher the small boy is a pupil; for the cat, a source of danger, and so on. And each mode of classification is correct in its place. But before an object can be classified in a given way it is, of course, necessary to note what qualities it does possess. Ordinarily we note very few of these. Most of us see only the most obvious and striking qualities of things, and we often see those very imperfectly. We get a vague general impression and fail to analyse it into its elements. The child, in his earliest experiences, hardly discriminates the different qualities of a thing at all, for his first experiences are very much confused. 45 46 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS We know things only as we know their qualities and relations, and the better we can distinguish and relate these the better we know the object. Analysis of the concrete datum is presupposed in classification and in all the other higher manifestations of consciousness. When we analyse a thing we pick out its various ele- ments and think of them as more or less isolated from the complex in which they were perceived. We can think of greenness or roundness without thinking of size or hardness or of any of the other qualities with which greenness or hardness always occurs. We never perceive greenness or hardness by themselves, but we can think of them without taking into account the other qualities. The mental act whereby we think of them in that way cannot be perception ; nor can it be memory, for memory, like perception, is of concrete complex things, whereas these qualities are simple and abstract. The mental act in which we bring before ourselves a simple quality is conception; and the thought of the quality is a concept. We have concepts of abstract qualities, but we cannot have percepts of them. But we may also have concepts of concrete things. Our idea of some particular horse, say Bucephalus, is not a memory, nor is it a perception ; it is a concept. 1 We may also have concepts of things which we have per- ceived; indeed, every perception involves conception as well. We are immediately aware of certain qualities, but, more than that, we have an idea of a complex whole possessing more or less coherence, permanence, etc. Whenever we think of a class of objects, qualities, or i Both Concept and Conception are used for the idea of the thing or quality. CONCEPTS 47 what not, we do so by means of conception. The thought of anything is a concept. Some concepts are universal, some are particular ; some are concrete, some are abstract ; some are of real things, some of imaginary things, and so on. Everything that is thought of is thought of in a concept, or rather, the thought of any- thing is a concept of that thing. In conceiving anything two elements are present: the symbol, and its meaning. In the concept " horse " the symbol is the word " horse " ; the meaning is the sum-total of qualities which that word implies or the objects to which it may be applied. The symbol is not necessarily a word: we might think of horses without having in mind the word. The mental picture of a horse might be the symbol. If we were trying to con- vey the idea of a horse to a person who did not under- stand English, we might use a drawing or imitate the sound of galloping, and so on. In all these cases the meaning would be the same, though the symbol would not. The essential element in the concept is .the mean- ing; so long as that remains the same we have the same concept, no matter what the symbol. The same thoughts may be present in two minds, one of which thinks in English and the other in German, or one of which thinks in words and the other in mental pictures. The superiority of words as symbols will be discussed presently. It is customary to treat logic as if it dealt solely with concepts, judgments and inferences; but in treat- ing logic as a part of scientific method, as a part of the science of getting knowledge, it will be well to con- tinue to speak as if we were dealing directly with the 48 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS facts and not with mental counters. In other words, logic may be regarded as a science of things as well as a science of thoughts. It deals, it is true, only with the most general aspects of things ; not with their spe- cial qualities, as do the special sciences, such as physics, etc. It has to do with that which is common to all fields of facts. In certain cases it may be more convenient to speak of the concepts rather than of the things conceived, as, for example, in -geometry, where the things conceived are certain highly abstract rela- tions and the like ; but even in such cases the other way of speaking would be possible. Necessity for Language. Mention has already been made of the necessity for describing or in some way representing the things we know. The means most uni- versally employed and most completely developed is, of course, language. A language, from the point of view of logic and scientific method, is simply a highly com- plex system of symbols for the representation of all kinds of objects and experiences, of the conclusions and constructions based upon experience, of laws, and so on. Language, as already noted, is a -condition of all progress beyond the merest rudiments of knowl- edge. It might seem to be of no use in the field of observation, but an observation made for some special purpose or under experimental conditions implies a previous statement or representation of the thing to be observed. Memory includes a representation of past experience by means either of a mental picture or of some other sort of symbol, such as the name of the thing. All spoken and written evidence, of course, im- plies language; and inference involves the statement to LANGUAGE 49 ourselves of a conclusion from something observed or thought of. Classification obviously requires the use of symbols. 2 So important is language for the work of thinking that logic has sometimes been defined as a branch of the study of language. Whately said that " Logic is entirely conversant about language." Some have maintained that all growth in thought has fol- lowed the development of language and would have been impossible without it ; in other words, that lan- guage always precedes thought ; that man is intelligent because he has language and not vice versa. These may be extreme views, but it is certain that systematic knowledge cannot go far without a coherent system of symbols, and that language is infinitely superior to all other kinds of symbols. 3 Any examination of the processes by which knowledge is attained must give careful attention to the consideration of language. If language were perfect, it would not be necessary to discuss it at any length in this connection, but its imperfections are such as to lead very often to mistaken ideas and wrong conclusions. It will be necessary, therefore, to examine language in order to discover these imperfections and the means of avoiding them. Terms. A word or group of words stands as the representative of some thing, quality, relation, action, 2 Sometimes the mental picture of an individual may stand for the class; the image of a tree may stand for the class tree, but when we know the name of the class or kind, we usually represent the class to ourselves by means of the name. Mental pictures are liable to vagueness and to modification, and it has been shown that scientists, for example, tend to represent things to themselves almost exclusively by means of words, particularly as they advance in years. 3 For a discussion of this question see Stout, Manual of Psy- chology, chap. v. 50 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS idea, and so on, or some group or combination of them. Such a word or group of words is called a term. A term might consist of any number of words and con- tain various subordinate clauses, but if it stood as the symbol of some single object of thought it would still be one term. " Man " and " The torch in the hand of the Statue of Liberty in New York Harbor " are equally terms, for each stands for a single object of thought. The inevitable difficulties with regard to the use of terms arise from the fact that a word or a group of words may stand for more than one thing; it may have a variety of meanings and is therefore liable to misinterpretation. Most words are used in more senses than one, so the danger of confusion is always present. There are several causes for this multiplica- tion of meanings. One of the most important is (1) the tendency to use a word in a sense wider than the one in which it was formerly used, to use it more generally, to generalize it. Lens meant originally only a double con- vex piece of glass ; such words as curve, acid, metal, salt, etc., illustrate this tendency. There is also (2) a contrary tendency to limit the ap- plication of words, to use a term in a narrower sense than formerly, a tendency toward specialization. Minister meant originally a servant; now it means, among other things, the highest representative of a state, one of the most exalted " servants " of a govern- ment. " Deacon, bishop, clerk, queen, captain, general, are all words which have undergone a like process of specialization. In such words as telegraph, rail, signal, station, and many other words arising from new inven- tions, we mav trace the progress of change in a lif(v SPECIALIZATION OF TERMS 51 time." The use of Congressman to describe Repre- sentatives only, and of Protection as a name for an economic policy, are further illustrations of the process. These tendencies may affect a word and its deriva- tives in different degrees and different directions. Com- pare, for example, distinguish and distinguished; dissolve, dissolute and dissolution; matter and material- istic; respond and responsible; design, designer and de- signing, etc. The popular and the technical uses of a term are usually different, one being broader or nar- rower than the other; phenomenon, sensation, idea, are illustrations. Sometimes a special use of a word is only local, as in dialects, or for a short space of time, as in slang. In addition to these tendencies to generalize and to specialize the meaning of terms there is (3) another by which there is a transfer, of meaning to associated objects or to those which are analogous. The use of the word church to designate a religious society, or of chair to indicate a presiding officer, or of bench to stand for the judiciary, are illustrations of the trans- fer of meaning to associated objects, and such expres- sions as a dull student, a hard examination, a brilliant game, etc., illustrate the transfer to analogous objects. There are (4) some other cases of less importance: sometimes two words which were originally different and of different derivations are alike in sound and spelling and might possibly be mistaken for each other ; such as, mean in the sense of middle and mean in the sense of low; pound :n the sense of weight and pound meaning a pen, pen as an inclosurc and pen as an instrument of 52 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS writing, etc. Sometimes words are alike in sound but different in spelling, as right, wright and rite, or rain and reign; in other cases they are alike in spelling but different in sound, as lead, the metal, and lead, some- thing to be followed, etc. 4 These last three cases are of little importance since the confusions resulting are usually of only momentary duration. In the first three cases, those of generalization, specialization and trans- fer of meaning, the confusion results from the con- tinued use of a word in the older sense after its meaning has been extended to a new field. If the various meanings are clearly distinguished and widely separate, the context will usually make clear which is intended ; but the meanings are most frequently very similar or closely connected, otherwise the same word would never have been used for both. The serious consequences of these confusions are seen in the fact that so many disputes and differences of opinion result from a difference in the use of terms. Kinds of Terms. 1. SINGULAR AND GENERAL. We have discussed the causes of ambiguity in terms ; it will be well to examine some of the different kinds of terms in order to discover just what sorts of confusion are likely to be found. There are some words, such as proper names, which would not seem liable to ambi- guity since they usually have little or no meaning; but after all there may be uncertainty enough with regard to the application of the name, as every case of mis- taken identity shows. Proper names are simply one variety of INDIVIDUAL 4 Most of the illustrations used in the two pages above have been taken from Jevons, Lesson in Logic. SINGULAR AND GENERAL TERMS 53 or SINGULAR terms. " The first president of the United States " is quite as definite in its application as any proper name could be. A singular term is a term which can be applied, in a given sense, to one single, indi- vidual object only. On the other hand there are terms which may be applied in the same sense to an indefinite number of objects. Man, president, book, college, etc., are GENERAL terms. A term which was originally sin- gular may become general, as illustrated in the expres- sions, " A Daniel come to judgment," " A Homer," " A Hannibal," etc. On the other hand singular terms may be so combined as to apply to only one individual ; the first president, the wisest man in the world, the longest river, the highest mountain, etc., are such cases. The chief difficulty in the case of singular terms is the liability to error with regard to the individual to whom the name applies. The form or the context usu- ally shows clearly enough whether a term is singular or general. In the case of general terms there is much more diffi- culty: in the first place the meaning may be vague; the application of the term may not be definite; in the case of such words as rich and poor, wise and ignorant, and a great many others, there is no universal agree- ment and there is seldom a definite notion as to tho range of application in any particular case. Again, where the term has a plurality of applications, each of which may be sufficiently definite, the wrong one may be employed or understood in any given case. The word law, for example, means, in one field, a prescribed rule of action, something imposed from without and having 54 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS a binding force, as a civil law. In the natural sciences, on the other hand, a law is simply a statement of the way in which things do invariably behave. Obviously, one who carries over into the consideration of natural phenomena the conception of law employed in legal practice, is liable to have a very mistaken view of Nature. There is a multitude of terms in which such differences are to be found. The Latin lex meant origi- nally something fixed or set, so both these meanings might be regarded as specializations in different direc- tions of the original meanings. In other cases one meaning is obviously more or less general than the other. In the commandment, " Thou shalt not kill," the word kill is obviously less general than is the state- ment, " To kill is to deprive of life"; or again, the words rest, sleep, etc., are not intended to cover all possible cases in the statement, " Rest, food and sleep are necessary to life." Any mistake as to the exact sense in which a word is used will be certain to lead to mistaken opinions. 2. CONCRETE AND ABSTRACT TERMS. This brings us to the distinction between concrete and abstract terms, or between terms used in an abstract sense and the same terms as used in a concrete sense. An abstract term, as the name implies, stands for something which is the product of abstraction; it is something separated from its context and considered by itself. For example, qualities are known only as they occur in an object, in a complex something which in- cludes many other qualities. We have already seen that these qualities are not recognized as separate things in the child's earliest experience. ABSTRACT TERMS 55 If a quality always appeared in the same setting, it would never be discriminated and hence could never be abstracted. To quote Professor James's illustration, if all wet things were cold and all cold things were wet, we should never distinguish coldness from wet- ness. But most qualities do occur in a variety of set- tings and can therefore be discriminated and abstracted. When a quality is abstracted it can be treated, for cer- tain purposes, as a separate thing. In studying color, we disregard the other properties of colored objects and treat their -colors as something independent. There are many degrees of abstraction : blue is ab- stract as related to a blue object, but comparatively concrete as related to color. An abstract term mav be the name of a relation, as height, or an action, as walking, or of any characteristic whatever, abstracted from its setting and regarded as an independent thing. The word which stands for this characteristic will be an abstract term. A given term is often used in both senses : in the sentence, " Government is necessary to civilization," the term government is said to be used in an abstract sense ; in the sentence, " This government is a republic," it is concrete. To confuse the more general with the less general meaning of a term or the abstract with the concrete use of it, or to argue from a term taken without qualification to the same term qualified in some particular way, is to commit a fallacy, the Fallacy of Accident. To conclude that it would be meritorious to give a beggar a dollar because charity is a virtue would be to commit this fallacy. To con- clude that, because the only Filipinos you have seen are small, a Filipino is a small person, would be to commit 56 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS what is sometimes called the Converse Fallacy of Acci- dent; in this, we argue from the concrete or the less general or what is true in particular circumstances, to the abstract or the more general or to what is true apart from particular circumstances. The ancient example, "What is bought in the mar- ket is eaten ; raw meat is bought in the market ; there- fore raw meat is eaten," illustrates the simple fallacy of Accident. So also does the following: " The Greeks produced masterpieces of art, and as the Spartans were Greeks, they produced masterpieces of art." (Davis.) " Greeks," in the major premise, is used in the generic sense. In the minor, it has a more specific meaning. To argue that strychnine should be freely sold be- cause it is very useful (as a medicine) would be to com- mit the converse fallacy. 3. COLLECTIVE AND DISTRIBUTIVE TERMS. Another distinction which is of great importance in dealing with terms is that between collective and distributive terms. Army, for example, is a collective term; it stands for a number of individuals taken together in a group; it is a group term. A term like man, on the other hand, has no such significance. It applies equally to any and every individual in a class. In an expression like all men, for example, there is danger of confusion ; it might be taken to mean all taken together, as in " All Jiving men number about 1,500,000,000 " ; or it might be used distributively, as in " All men are mortal." Synonyms of the terms collective and distributive are jointly and severally. Obligations are sometimes laid upon individuals which they are bound joiptly or sev- erally to observe. COMPOSITION AND DIVISION 57 Confusion between the collective and the distributive uses of a term leads to the Fallacies of Composition and Division; arguing from the distributive to the collec- tive use results in the fallacy of Composition. " Each member of the committee is insufficiently informed, therefore the committee as a whole is not sufficiently informed," contains a fallacy of Composition. But to argue that because a navy as a whole was weak, the individual ships were therefore weak, would be to com- mit a fallacy of Division. These fallacies should be kept clearly distinct from the fallacy of Accident. Here we are dealing with a group ; the question is, are we dealing with it simply as a group, or are we thinking of the individuals of which it is made up? In the other case we were not concerned with a group at all. 4. OTHER KINDS OF TERMS. Various other distinc- tions might be made among terms ; there is, for ex- ample, a distinction between positive and negative terms ; the former being those which imply the presence, and the latter those which imply the absence, of a qual- ity. White, just, warm, etc., illustrate the former; blind, empty, unconscious, the latter. There is little danger of confusion in this and in most of the other cases which might be included, so we will pursue them no further. Definition. In any case in which misunderstanding is likely to occur, the first thing to do is, obviously, to make clear what it is that the term stands for. In the case of a proper name the application of the term could be shown by producing, or pointing out, or describing, the individual thing for which it stands, and so of other singular terms. But with general terms that is not 58 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS possible ; a general term stands for all possible cases of a given sort, past, present and to come, and any example or series of examples could at most illustrate the meaning of the term. Sometimes an example will show clearly enough, for ordinary purposes, what is meant. But any example might illustrate a variety of things ; if two persons, each of whom was entirely un- acquainted with the language of the other, should try to communicate by pointing to objects to indicate the meaning of the words they were using, they would illus- trate the uncertainty of this method in its extreme form. If one of them should point to a horse, he might mean any one of a dozen different things: horse, or simply animal, or useful animal, or large object, or gray, or beautiful, or dangerous, and so on. In a minor degree that sort of difficulty is always present when illustra- tions are employed to indicate the meaning of terms, and the method of illustrations is never entirely satis- factory. In Plato's Euthyphro Socrates asks Euthyphro, who claims to have a precise knowledge of the subject, " What is piety and what is impiety? " The reply is, " Piety is doing as I am doing ; that is to say, prose- cuting any one who is guilty of murder, sacrilege, or of any other crime whether he be your father or mother or some other person, that makes no difference ; and not prosecuting them is impiety." But Socrates is not satisfied with this. " Remember," he says, " that I did not ask you to give me two or three examples of piety, but to explain the general idea which makes all pious things to be pious." In other words, what quality must things possess in order to be called pious? When we THE MEANING OF TERMS 59 ask for a definition of a term we wish to know what qualities a thing must have in order to make the term applicable. It should be noted that nearly all terms have two aspects: they stand for objects and they imply the qualities which those objects possess. The term man stands_for any or all individual men, past, present and to_come. It also implies all the qualities which a being must possess in order to be included in the class. In the case of a general term it is obvious that all the in- dividuals for which it stands in technical language, its total extension could never be presented. The only way of indicating the full extent of its application is to show what qualities it implies, to tell what its inten- sion is. That might conceivably be done by enumerat- ing all the qualities which were regarded as essential. If things in a given group were so unique that they could not be included in a larger class, enumeration of their qualities would be the only way of showing what they were. But in all ordinary circumstances, this proc- ess can be abbreviated by stating (1) the class to which the things belong and () the quality which distin- guishes them from the other members of the class. 5 The class-name will obviously imply the presence of 5 " Definition " has been variously defined. " Given any set of notions, a term jyt definable by means of these notions when, and only when, it is the only term having to certain of these notions a certain relation which itself is one of the said notions." (Rus- sell, The Principles of Mathematics, Vol. I, chap, xi, sec. 108.) A term is defined by being given a place in a set of notions, which place can be occupied by it and by it alone. Instead of being assigned to a class it is given its place in a complex system of concepts. This last might be regarded as the more complete form of definition, whereas the former, the traditional form, is less complete, though adequate for ordinary purposes. 60 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS the qualities which these things have in common with the others in the class. The class which includes a thing is its genus: " plane figure " is the genus of " triangle." And the quality which distinguishes it from the other members of the class is its differentia or peculiar property; " three- sided " is the differentia of " triangle." A property is any essential quality: having an equal number of sides and angles would be a property of " triangle." An accident is a quality which may or may not be present in any or all members of a group : having a right angle is an accident of " triangle." 6 Defects of Definitions. There are several defects to which definitions are liable. 1. They may be too broad, i. e., they may include more than the term is intended to cover. To define a square as a rectilinear figure would be a case in point. In such definitions the differentia is not given or not properly given. #. Again, the definition may be too narrow, that is, it may exclude part of what the term is intended to cover. To define " American citizen " as one born in the United States would exclude naturalized citizens. In this case an accidental quality is taken as the dif- ferentia. 3. Definitions are sometimes given in obscure or figur- ative or ambiguous language. Dr. Johnson's defini- tion of a network as " anything decussated or reticu- lated with interstices between the intersections " is a These four terms, genus, differentia, property and accident, together with species, are what have been traditionally known in logic as the five Heads of Predicables or the five ways in which a predicate may be affirmed of a subject. DEFINITION 61 favorite illustration of the obscure definition, the defini- tion of ignotum per ignotius. Spencer's definition of evolution as " an integration of matter and a concom- mitant dissipation of motion ; during which the matter passes from an indefinite incoherent homogeneity to a definite coherent heterogeneity; and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation," is sometimes charged with this fault. It should be re- membered, however, that when a term is to be used with scientific exactness it may be necessary to couch its definition in very technical terms ; to one who had read the discussions which lead up to it, Spencer's definition would not seem obscure. Figurative and ambiguous language should always be avoided when exactness is the aim. Such language may give some suggestion of the meaning of a term, but does not really define it. 4. Sometimes unessential attributes are employed in defining a term : e. g., " Books are the things out of which libraries are made." Such definitions are obvi- ously faulty. They use an accident as the differentia and do not give the meaning of the term. 5. Whenever it is possible, a definition should "be stated in positive rather than negative terms ; to define " an under-classman " as " a student who is not an up- per-classman " is to tell what he is not instead of telling what he is. 6. Another sort of bad definition is one in which the definition contains the term to be defined or some syno- nym or exact correlative of it. " Life is that which distinguishes living from non-living things " would be a flagrant case ; " A cause is that which produces an effect " is little better. _A definition should state clearly 62 THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS the exact meaning of the term to be defined. There are cases, however, where a complete definition is not neces- sary. Where the hearer is in doubt which of two well- known meanings is intended, or where the term is al- ready familiar but is used with a slightly different shade of meaning, in other words, where the genus is already known, the briefest indication of the differentia may suffice; sometimes the mention of any accidental quality, or even the use of an illustration, may be sufficient. EXERCISES 1. Make a list of ten words which are sometimes misused through the fact that they have undergone generalization; a similar list of those which have undergone specialization; a list of five in which there has been a transfer of mean- ing to arralagous objects. 2. Bring ten examples of singular terms and ten of general terms; five of general terms which were originally singular or were derived from singular terms. 3. Give ten examples of collective terms and ten of dis- tributive. Show how error might arise in this connection. 4. What is a definition? Compare definition and de- scription. Define the following terms: Book, Party, Col- lege, Republican, Honesty, Foot-ball, Dormitory, College- spirit, Club, Money, Success, Trustee, Tariff, Saint, Geo- metrical figure. 5. Criticise the following definitions: (1) A phonograph is a mechanism xor recording and reproducing sounds. (2) A sea is a body of water, next in size to tho oceans, entirely, or almost entirely, surrounded by land. (3) A library is a collection of books generally for personal use and not meant for merchandise. (4) A wagon is a conveyance mounted on wheels and drawn by some animal, usually a horse. EXERCISES 63 (5) Oxygen is the most important gaseous element known, without which combustion and animal life would be impossible. (6) A sensation is a modification of consciousness produced by the excitation of a cortical cen- ter through the agency of an afferent nerve- current. (7) " Life is a continuous adjustment of internal to external relations." (8) Logic is the Baedeker of the world of thought. (9) A cause is that which produces an effect. (10) A book is a combination of leaves and cover. (11) A sun-dial is an affair for telling time by means of the sun. (12) Public opinion is the opinion of people gen- erally. (13) A student is one whose principal business is study. (14) A just judge is one who never shows partiality in his decisions. (15) Wood is the ligneous part of trees. (16) Football is a game which is usually played in America with a large ball in the shape of an oblate spheroid, whereas in England a spherical ball is used. (17) A liar is a man who wilfully misplaces his onto- logical predicates. (18) A philosophical work is one which treats of some metaphysical subject. (19) A philosophical work is one which deals with something abstract and difficult. (20) A false weight is an abomination. (21) The quality of a proposition is what tells us whether it is affirmative or negative. (22) Definition is telling what a word means. (23) A religion is that which satisfies the highest needs of man. (24) Matter is the stuff out of which things are made. 6. What fallacies are committed in the following cases? 64- THE USE AND MISUSE OF WORDS (1) The holder of some shares in a lottery is sure to gain a prize, and as I am the holder of some shares in a lottery I am sure to gain a prize. (Hyslop.) (2) A monopoly of the sugar-refining business is beneficial to the sugar-refiners j and of the corn trade to the corn growers; and of silk-manu- facture to the silk weavers; and of labor to the laborers. Now all these classes of men make up the whole community. Therefore a system of restrictions upon competition is beneficial to the community. (Hyslop.) (3) Who is most hungry eats most; who eats least is most hungry; therefore who eats least eats most. (4) All the trees in the field make a dense shade; therefore this elm tree, which is one of them, makes a thick shade. (5) Cities are governed by mayors; hence a mayoi was the highest official in ancient Rome. (6) The major received a D.S.O. for attacking the enemy and appropriating their supplies ; there- fore it is praiseworthy to steal. (7) The Irish are quick-witted; hence that Irish policeman must be quick-witted. (8) This ship is one of the best in the world, for it belongs to the British Navy, which is the best in the world. (9) Americans are liberal; hence this man may be counted on to give liberally, since he is an American. (10) We can now see the results of giving the negro all the rights and privileges of the white man. Two months after he was placed in office, this colored man absconded with all the funds un- der his control. (11) Every man has a right to teach his religious be- liefs; therefore it is not out of place for a college instructor to do so in the discharge of his duties. EXERCISES 65 (12) Any student in college would stand higher in his class if he received higher marks; hence if all marks were raised 10% every man would stand nearer the head of his class. (13) Pine wood is good for lumber; matches are pine wood; therefore matches are good for lumber. (Hyslop.) (14) To teach a child is to improve him; showing him how to pick pockets is teaching him; hence that improves him. (15) Poisons cause death; nux vomica is a poison; therefore it causes death. (16) This reformer was working for selfish ends all the time ; no more reformers for me. (17) Since attending that socialist meeting I have had no confidence in socialistic doctrines. (18) He cannot be innocent, for he was a member of the mob which committed the deed. (19) Those two horses would make an excellent team, for each is the best of its class. (20) Five is an odd number; three and two are five; and hence each is an odd number. CHAPTER V PROPOSITIONS DIFFICULTIES in the use of language are not all pro- vided against by the correct definition of terms. Many arise in the combination of words into sentences. A term, as we have seen, is the representative in lan- guage of some object of thought, real or imaginary, concrete or abstract. But the mind never rests in the contemplation of a single object; it always tends to make an assertion or judgment about this object. Most logicians are now of the opinion that, even in the simplest perception, a judgment is either present or im- plied. Introspection will show at once that when we hold an object before the mind, there is an inevitable tendency to think some assertion about it. The ex- pression of this mental assertion or judgment in lan- guage is a proposition. Kinds of Propositions. Propositions are usually distinguished according to quality and quantity. (1) The qualities are two, affirmative and negative. The difference between affirmative and negative propositions is sufficiently familiar. It should be remembered, how- ever, that the mere occurrence of not or some other negative particle in a proposition does not necessarily make the proposition negative. The proposition, " Those who do not study are in danger of failing," is not a negative proposition. It asserts positively something about a certain class, namely, " those who 66 QUALITY AND QUANTITY 67 do not study " ; these words constitute a negative term. An affirmative statement can be made about a negative subject as readily as about any other. In the proposi- tion, " Those who do not study are unwise," the term unwise is also negative, but the proposition is affirma- tive. To decide whether any proposition is affirma- tive or negative, determine whether something is affirmed or denied of a subject. What the subject is, and what the predicate is, makes no difference ; the only question is, do we affirm something or do we deny some- thing? (2) With regard to quantity, propositions may be either universal or particular. A universal proposition is one which expresses a judgment about the whole of the class to which the subject applies. " All the stars are suns " is a universal proposition ; so is " No planets are self-luminous." (The latter propo- sition is negative and denies something of all planets.) " Some stars are double " is called a particular propo- sition. It asserts something of some individuals of the class " stars." By " particular proposition " is not meant a statement about some particular individual. The proposition " Jupiter is the largest of the planets " is not a particular proposition. It is a sin- gular proposition, but, since it expresses a judgment about the whole of that for which the term " Jupiter " stands, it may be treated as a universal proposition. The so-called particular propositions are really indefi- nite; if the " some " in any proposition meant certain particular ones, as it does in certain cases, the propo- sition would really be universal ; it would say something about all those of whom the assertion was made: as " some persons " (meaning A, B, C) " are certain to be 68 PROPOSITIONS late." As used ordinarily, some means certain unspeci- fied individuals, it may or may not be all. The word indefinite would certainly be more appropriate here, but the word particular, with this special meaning, is the one which has been used traditionally. With this two-fold distinction of quality and quan- tity we get four different kinds of propositions: uni- versal affirmative, universal negative, particular affirm- ative and particular negative. For the affirmative propositions the letters A and I are used as symbols, A standing for the universal affirmative and I for the particular affirmative. E stands for the universal nega- tive and O for the particular negative. (These letters are from the Latin Affirmo and Nego.) Propositions Quality Universal Particular f Affirmative | Negative f Universal ( Particular f Affirmative A | Negative E f Affirmative I 1 Negative O Propositions and Terms. The Relation of Subject to Predicate. The question of the relation of propo- sitions and terms is one that naturally arises here. A proposition obviously contains terms. Ordinarily it is said that a proposition is made up of two terms and a copula. One of these terms is the subject and the other is the predicate. The copula is that which con- SUBJECT AND PREDICATE 69 nects subject and predicate; it is always some part of the verb to be. Some propositions do not fall natu- rally into this form : for example, " The earth moves." This can, however, be expressed in this form : " The earth is a body which moves." This form, subject-copula-predicate, is called the " logical form " of the proposition. It often seems artificial, but for certain purposes it is convenient to employ it, and the attempt to restate propositions in this form is an excellent way of finding out just what the proposition means. The subject of a proposition stands for that about which something is said. 1 The predicate is that which is asserted of the sub- ject. The copula is that which connects the two terms in a proposition; but the nature of that connection is not always the same. In the propositions, " Aristotle was the greatest pupil of Plato," " Aristotle was wise," " Aristotle was traveling in Asia Minor," and " Aris- totle was a philosopher," the copula has, in each case, a different meaning. In the first, the relation is that of 1 A distinction may be made between the grammatical and the logical subjects. The grammatical subject is the subject of the proposition; it is, as we have seen, a term. The logical subject has been variously defined. The definition of the logical subject as the subject of the thought seem, on the whole, to be the best. (See for discussion, Joseph, Introduction to Logic.) The logical subject is that about which the judgment is made. For example, in the proposition, " Acid turns blue litmus paper red," the grammatical subject is, of course, the word " acid." The grammatical predicate is that which stands for what is asserted about the subject; in this case, the words "turns blue litmus paper red." Changing the proposition into the form of subject-copula-predicate, it would read " acid is that which turns blue litmus paper red," and the complete predicate would be the words following the copula. Now the form of the propo- sition may not indicate the real logical subject. If the statement just given were the answer to the question, "What can you say 70 PROPOSITIONS identity; in the second, that of subject and attribute; in the third, that of agent and action; in the fourth, that of inclusion of an individual in a class. .Logicians have usually taken the last of these as the typical relation ; the others can be transformed with more or less success into it. The proposition, " Aristotle was wise," can be put in the form, " Aristotle was a wise man " ; and " Aristotle was traveling," etc., can be ex- pressed in the form, " Aristotle was a man who was traveling," etc. These forms are sometimes criticised as not expressing the exact shade of meaning contained in the other forms ; but the difference is usually not serious, and the performance of certain logical opera- tions is much facilitated by so expressing the judg- ment as t'o indicate the inclusion of an individual, or a class, in another class. In the negative proposition the relation will, of course, be that of exclusion. " Minors are not voters " indicates the exclusion of the first class from the second. about acid, the grammatical and logical subjects would cor- respond; but if the question were, "What is the effect of acid on litmus paper?" the logical subject (i. e., the thing about which the judgment is made) would be that which is expressed by the grammatical predicate of the proposition. The form of the sentence could be so changed as to make the grammatical or verbal subject correspond to the logical subject; in a great many cases they do not so correspond. Ordinarily the logical subject can be determined only by the context, though sometimes it can be indicated by emphasis on certain words. For example, "Acid turns blue litmus paper red " would imply, as the subject, what is expressed by the words, " the color to which blue litmus is turned by acid." Unless otherwise specified the term subject will be understood to mean grammatical subject; and predicate will mean the term that is joined to the subject by the copula. In the treatment of isolated propositions there is no occasion for the distinction. It is sometimes said that reality as a whole is the logical subject of every judgment. It might better be called the ultimate or metaphysical subject. DISTRIBUTION 71 The Distribution of Terms in a Proposition, There are degrees of inclusion and exclusion. In the illus- tration just given the whole of the class minors is ex- cluded from the whole of the class voters. In the proposition, " Some men are not good citizens," only some men or a part of the class men is excluded from the class good citizens, but the whole of the class good citizens is excluded from that part of the class men which is included in the subject. In the proposition, " Some men are healthy animals," a part of the class men is included in the class healthy animals, and conse- quently a part of the class healthy animals may be included in the class men. Again, in the propo- sition, " All men are bipeds," the whole of the class men is included in the class bipeds, but so far as this proposition informs us, only a part of the class bipeds can be included in the class men. When- ever, in a proposition, a term is used to indicate the whole of the class for which it stands, it is said to be distributed; when it covers only a part of the class, it is undistributed. The subject of a universal proposi- tion is always distributed, because, by definition, a uni- versal proposition is one which asserts something about the whole of its subject. It will be seen in the examples given above that both the negative propositions dis- tribute their predicates. That is always the case with negative propositions. They always indicate the en- tire exclusion of the predicate from the subject. The proposition A, being universal and affirmative, will dis- tribute its subject but not its predicate; /, being par- ticular (indefinite) and affirmative, will distribute neither; the particular negative, 0, will distribute the 72 PROPOSITIONS predicate, but not the subject, while the universal nega- tive, E, will distribute both subject and predicate. Euler's Method. Euler, a Swiss mathematician of the Eighteenth Century, devised the following method of representing the relation of subject and predicate and the distribution of each. Let each term be repre- sented by a circle ; then the E proposition will be rep- resented as follows, S standing for the subject and P for the predicate: ()(?) S and P are shown to be entirely excluded from each other; each is distributed. The A proposition would be represented in this way: , --- x S is seen to be entirely included in P, while, so ( P} ^ ar as we know, only a part of P falls within S ; s x __ S S is distributed, P is not. In the I proposition the circles would overlap. Each would be partially in- \ eluded within the other: that is, neither would 1 S ( )P \ y ./ be distributed. Whether cither extended fur- ther would be left undetermined ; there are four possi- bilities, in each of which at least some S is some P. In the O proposition, part of S would be excluded SOP ^ ^-xfrom P; the rest would be left undetermined; while all of P would be outside the specified part of S ; S is not distributed, P is. The distribution or non-distribution of terms in the various propositions may be represented by the follow- ing symbols : " - ' indicating an affirmative proposi- tion, " x " a negative one, and a circle about a term the fact that it is distributed. 2 A, -P; E, () x ; I, S-P; O, S x (5) 2 The last two of these symbols are adapted from Hyslop, ments of Log\\,* AMBIGUOUS PROPOSITIONS 73 Ambiguous Propositions. There are several kinds of ambiguous propositions. In the first place the ar- rangement of the words and phrases may be such as to admit of two interpretations. Familiar examples are the prophecy in Shakespeare's Henry VI, " The Duke yet lives that Henry shall depose," and the re- sponse of the oracle, " Pyrrhus, I say, the Romans shall subdue." The expression, " Twice two and three," is ambiguous for the same reason, and so is the state- ment, " He went away and returned yesterday." In the two last, punctuation would, of course, remove the ambiguity. Propositions, like " He jests at scars who never felt a wound," will sometimes, mislead a careless reader. Care in the construction of a proposition will /obviate such difficulties ; where such sentences are found, only the context can make clear what the mean- ing is. Wrong conclusions in such cases are said to result from committing the Fallacy of Amphiboly or Amphibology. Certain other cases of ambiguity might be brought under this heading. One of these is found in the use of " all ... not." In the statement, "All these men are not swift-footed," it might be thought that the meaning was, " None of these men is swift-footed " ; that is, that the subject, these men, was distributed, and that_ the proposition was an E proposition. It is usually interpreted as meaning " some are not swift- footed," not " all are." It is an E proposition in form, but an O proposition in meaning. Again, it might seem to imply that " some are swift- footed " ; but this last implication is not to be trusted, for we could make the original statement if we knew that some of these 74 PROPOSITIONS were not swift without knowing anything about the rest. The word some, as already noted, is indefinite ; in an affirmative proposition, such as " Some are going," it seems to imply the corresponding negative, " Some are not going," and vice versa ; but these implications count for nothing if not confirmed in some other way. In interpreting a proposition the only safe rule is to in- clude in its meaning only what it must mean, not what it may mean. In still other cases it is not so much the arrangement as it is the character of the terms that occasions diffi- culty. Propositions which are introduced by the word few are ambiguous. " Few are completely masters of themselves " really means that most are not masters of themselves, or that not many are. It is an O proposi- tion in meaning, though like an I proposition in form. It may also seem to suggest the corresponding I propo- sition, " Some are masters," etc. The importance of making clear the negative force of such a proposition may be illustrated thus : suppose we have also the state- ment, " All who are masters of themselves are mature individuals " ; it might seem that we could conclude that few are mature individuals. If the proposition " Few," etc., be put in the negative form given above there will be no temptation to draw the erroneous con- clusion. Thus in, " Most men are not masters, etc. ; those who are, are mature," etc. ; the conclusion, " Most men are not mature," does not even seem to follow. Professor Hyslop, in his Elements of Logic, calls propo- sitions of this sort partitive propositions, because they " express a part of a whole of which the implied propo- sition is a complementary part." PARTITIVE AND EXCLUSIVE 75 Another sort, similar in certain respects to these, is found in the exclusive propositions; they are such as have their application determined by such expressions as only, alone, none but, and the like. " None but native-born citizens are eligible to the presidency," " Only students will be admitted," etc., are exclusive propositions. These statements do not mean that all native-born citizens are eligible nor that all students will be admitted. They are not universal propositions ; they do not distribute their subjects. They are equiva- lent to the propositions, " Those who are not native- born are not eligible," " Those who are not students will not be admitted," which are the complementary opposites of the original propositions, and are in this case E propositions. As the original propositions stand they really limit the application of their predicates, i. e. 9 they include the whole of the predicate in the sub- ject. Thus they distribute the predicate, in spite of the fact that they are affirmative propositions. They are, therefore, exceptions to the rule for affirmative propositions (p. 71). Another way of restating ex- clusive propositions is to convert them, making the converse a universal proposition. Thus : " All persons eligible to the presidency are native-born citizens " ; " All who are to be admitted are college students." One other sort of proposition of this general class may' be mentioned, the exceptive proposition: it is in- troduced by such words as " All except," " all but," etc. For example : " All but the best will be excluded." In addition to the positive statement, a corresponding negative is suggested, namely, " The best will not be " ; though this last is not certainly true. It is well to re- 76 PROPOSITIONS state such propositions, eliminating the exceptive par- ticle. Thus : " All those who are not the best," etc. Figurative statements are peculiarly liable to mis- interpretation ; Hyperbole and metaphor, symbolical and allegorical statements, may all be mistaken for literal statements, or if recognized as figurative, they may be wrongly interpreted on account of the inherent vagueness of most figurative expressions. Fallacies arising from this cause are known as Fallacies of Figure of Speech. 3 Another source of ambiguity and misinterpretation in propositions is to be found in misplaced emphasis. Wrong emphasis gives rise to what is known as the Fallacy of Accent. To quote from Jevons : " It is cu- rious to observe how many and various may be the meanings attributable to the same sentence according as emphasis is thrown on one word or another. Thus the sentence, ' The study of Logic is not supposed to communicate the knowledge of many useful facts,' may be made to imply that the study of Logic does communicate such a knowledge although it is not sup- posed to do so ; or that it communicates a knowledge of a few useful facts ; or that it communicates a knowl- edge of many useless facts. . . . Jeremy Bentham was so much afraid of being misled by this fal- lacy of accent that he employed a person to read to him, as I have heard, who had a peculiarly monotonous manner of reading." To introduce italics into a quo- tation, with no mention of the fact that they did not 3 It has been said that some of Locke's erroneous conclusions, in his Essay on the Human Understanding, resulted from his own use of " the sheet of white paper " as a figure representing the mind before experience has begun. THE FALLACY OF ACCENT 77 occur in the original, is usually to misrepresent the meaning of the original. De Morgan and others have pointed out that taking words or passages out of their context may have the same consequences. Isolated texts from sacred writings are often misused in this way ; e. g., " Eat, drink and be merry, for to-morrow ye die," "Take no thought for the morrow," etc. Quoting an argument which an author has presented only in order to refute it, without mention of his pur- pose, is another case of the same sort. EXERCISES 1. In each of the following propositions give (a) the complete subject and (b) the complete predicate; (c) re- state each in its logical form; (d) give its quantity and quality and the letter which symbolizes it. And state whether (e) the subject and (f) the predicate are dis- tributed. , (1) He laughs best who laughs last. (2) Few are able to endure such hardships. (3) Not all who are called are chosen. (4) Nothing of worth is without honor. (5) Only genius could have accomplished it. (6) He little knows you, who can speak of you in such terms. (7) Every bit of success makes further success easier. (8) Like cures like. (9) There is nothing either good or bad but thinking makes it so. (10) It is the first step that costs. (11) Everything has its limit. (12) We demand non-partisan judges. (13) His lack of enterprise cost him his position. (14) The plowman homeward plods his weary way. (15) Contentment is better than riches. (16) Every deed returns upon the doer. (17) All's fair in war, 78 PROPOSITIONS (18) Many a morning on the moorland have we heard the copses ring. (19) Perfection is beyond the reach of man. (20) My mind to me a kingdom is. (21) No admission except to ticket holders. (22) Every one has the defects of his qualities. (23) Socrates taught that no man would knowingly do wrong. (24) And silence,, like a poultice, comes to heal the wounds of sound. (25) All the world admires heroism. (26) It rains. CHAPTER VI INDUCTION Generalization and What it Involves In the two last chapters we have been studying the use of lan- guage, the most important instrument of thought. We now return to the consideration of the further proc- esses mentioned in our preliminary survey of scientific method. (Chap. I.) Observation and classification have been discussed already ; it remains to examine the way in which laws * can be discovered after considerable body of facts has been observed and classified. We have seen that a law is a statement of the way in which facts of a certain kind behave, how they are related to other facts, what are the universal relations in which they stand. Our first question is : How are these laws suggested? What is the source of these general state- ments of relationship? And our second question is: How is a supposed law to be established or verified? In answer to the first question, it may be said that a general statement is usually arrived at by generalizing some observed relationship. If we have observed one or more instances in which a cold winter has been fol- lowed by a hot summer, we may generalize the connec- tion and assert that a cold winter is always followed by a hot summer, that there is an invariable and inevitable i The previous chapter has dealt, in part, with. universal propo- sitions; the present one is a discussion of the way in which such propositions are established. 79 80 INDUCTION connection between them. And similarly in any other case : A has been followed by B and we conclude that every A is followed by B 9 that every A has its B. A single instance may be enough to suggest a generaliza- tion. A generalization is a universal assertion, not a mjore^attitude of expectation. The lower animals ex- hibit a tendency to expect a given thing when another, which has occurred along with this, reappears ; when an animal hears a certain call he may expect food, be- cause in the past the two have been connected; when he sees a blow descending he may expect pain, and so on. But to expect a thing on the recurrence of another formerly connected with it, is not the same as to infer a universal connection. When I perceive A, I may re- member and expect B, without ever having thought of a universal relation between the two, without asserting that B always follows A. There is no proof that an animal can generalize, that he can think to himself: " A call of a certain sort is followed by food," " A blow causes pain," and so on. He hears the call and expects food, but he does not generalize the connection. To do the latter would be difficult if not impossible, without language. Tlais^power to generalize, to iise_ general and abstract ideas, is usually regarded as one of the most important differences between human and animal intelligence. "" Without generalization, our knowledge would be con- fined to individual facts or to groups of these. We have seen that knowledge is not completed by the mere accumulation of observations and the classification of what has been observed. The aim of science is usually said to be the discovery of laws. Now a law, as already LAWS 81 remarked, is the statement of the way in which phe- nomena behave, or the way in which they are inevitably related to other phenomena. This tendency to generalize is, then, a pre-condition of all but the most primitive kind of knowledge. But, of course, our generalization may not turn out to be a law. A law states a universal connection which ac- tually holds true, whereas our hasty generalization may be entirely unsound. A generalization arrived at in the way described above is an inductive inference. An inductive inference is a judgment about a whole class of facts based upon the observation of individual cases. It is a universal conclusion based upon one or more particular instances. Obviously, an inductive inference must be tested or verified; but before proceeding to the discussion of verification it will be well to mention cer- tain other terms which are frequently employed in this connection. Causal Connection. The terms, cause, causal con- nection^ causal law, occur constantly in this part of scientific method. What is a cause? The term implies a connection of some sort between phenomena; but of what sort? In ordinary usage it probably means most frequently something which produces or brings about something else. It has been objected that we can never observe one thing producing another; that we can at most observe that one thing is followed by another, and perhaps find reason for believing that it will always have such a connection; and that to say that A pro- duces B, is to raise a metaphysical question with which science and everyday thinking are not concerned. But if we give up this way of conceiving cause, what can we 82 INDUCTION put in its place ? Is it sufficient to say that cause means simply invariable succession? No, for the succession of day and night is an invariable succession. The notion of cause implies that the relation of cause and effect not only is invariable, but also that it must be so ; that there is an unconditional or necessary -connection be- tween the two; that if the first does not happen, the second cannot. In the field of physical phenomena, it is held also that the amount of energy in the cause is exactly equal to the amount of energy in the sum-total of its effects; in other words, that no energy is either lost or created. This is known as the Law of the Con- servation of Energy. Whether it applies where mental phenomena are concerned has been questioned. How- ever this may be, cause always means unconditional connection. 2 Two things stand in a relation of causal connection when they are so related that one is the un- conditional accompaniment of the other ; the cause usu- ally occurs or begins before the effect, but there are cases in which both seem to begin together. Heat is a cause of expansion, but a body does not first become hot and then expand; the two phenomena occur simul- taneously. A causal law is a statement, in general terms, of a causal connection. Thus : " Heat causes ex- pansion." The sort of generalization which is most frequently of interest and importance is one which asserts a -con- nection of this sort, although this is not the only sort which may be investigated. For instance, the universal 2 Of course, the fact that a connection is unconditional cannot be observed. The reasons for asserting that it is unconditional will appetrrpresently. CO-EXISTENCE AND CAUSATION 83 concurrence of two properties in a given substance may be a matter of importance, but their connection would not be called a causal connection. The specific gravity and the atomic weight of carbon would be a case in point. The co-existence of gravity and inertia is an- other example mentioned by Bain ; the sciences furnish innumerable instances of a like sort. Bain remarks that " there are very few general laws of pure co-existence ; causation is singular in providing a comprehensive uni- formity that may be appealed to deductively for all cases. The uniformities of co-existence (independent of causation) can be proved only piecemeal; each stands on its own evidence of observation in detail; no one assists us to prove another." The causal law is the one to which we shall give most attention. Testing Inductive Inferences. We return to the question, " How can we prove an inductive inference to be true? How can we show that it is a law? " There are several things which would show that it was not true; if we found that there were facts which were in- consistent with it, or if it were found to be inconsistent with itself, or if it proved to be in disagreement with any established law, it could be rejected at once. But suppose that none of these things were found ; should the inference be accepted as true? Not necessarily; it might be that our observation or our reflection on the case had been insufficient to show us exceptions or in- consistencies if such did exist. If we have inferred a universal connection we are very likely to overlook exceptions or to forget those which we have observed. A good many people still believe that Friday is an un- lucky day and that the number 13 brings misfortune. 84 INDUCTION But even if no exceptions have occurred and if the in- ference is not inconsistent with known laws, how can we be assured that exceptions may not occur in the future, or that further reflection might not discover fatal inconsistencies? A large number of favorable cases is not alone sufficient to give this assurance. The example of the succession of day and night illustrates that. Millions of cases do not prove inevitable con- nection. On the other hand, a single experiment made .by some scientist in his laboratory may be sufficient to establish some very important law. " Why," asks Mill, " is a single instance in some cases sufficient for a com- plete induction, while in others myriads of concurring instances, without a single exception known or pre- sumed, go such a very little way towards establishing an universal proposition? Whoever can answer this question knows more of the philosophy of logic than the wisest of the ancients, and has solved the problem of Induction." Mill himself aided very materially in the formulation of the conditions under which we do regard our inductive inference as established, and the inductive methods presently to be discussed are usually called " Mill's methods." Whether or not he has solved the whole problem of induction is another question and one with which we shall not at present concern ourselves. Complete Enumeration. There are -cases in which the establishment of universal conclusion might seem to be comparatively easy. It is sometimes possible that all the cases of a given sort may have been observed. For example, observation has shown that Mercury re- volves about the sun ; that Venus does also ; and like- wise of the Earth, Mars, Jupiter and each of the other COMPLETE ENUMERATION 85 planets. We can say then with perfect safety, that all the planets 3 revolve about the sun. The universal statement is warranted because each of the instances which it covers has been observed. We are saying no more in the conclusion than we had already said in the several statements on which the conclusion is based. The universal is, in fact, simply a summary way of expressing what had already been said. It is merely a " telescoping " of the other statements, as it were. This act of basing a general statement on a complete enum- eration of the particular cases which it covers has been called Perfect Induction. It was so called because the conclusion is one which possesses complete certainty, whereas most inductive inferences are more or less un- certain. It might seem then that this was the solution of the problem raised above ; you are sure of your uni- versal if you have seen all the particulars which it covers. But how can we be sure that we have counted all the particulars? The field of observation may be so small and so easily explored that every existing case may be observed. But even if all existing cases have been observed, how can we be sure that others may not arise, and that they may not differ from those we have observed? We may have such knowledge about a class of objects as will enable us to say that if any other members of the class should come into existence they would be like those already known. We may know that the sum of the angles of every plane triangle which may ever exist will be equal to two right angles, not because we have counted cases, but because we know that this necessarily follows from the properties essen- s Leaving the asteroids out of consideration. 86 INDUCTION tial to all triangles. However numerous the class which has been completely observed, the knowledge that each of the observed members stands in certain relations does not by itself assure us that other con- ceivable members of the class would be like them in this respect. Complete enumeration is useful as an abbre- viated way of stating certain kinds of information, but it throws no light on the methods of discovering uncon- ditional connections. 4 The judgments which result from the complete enum- eration of cases have been called, by some writers, Enumerative Judgments and by others, Collective Judg- ments. How Generalizations can be Verified It appears then that enumeration of all the existing members of a class does not enable us to establish laws. Anything short of that might seem to leave us still farther from that goal. And it is of course true, as appeared on page 84, that an incomplete enumeration of instances furnishes no verification. Then if verification is pos- sible at all it can not rest on mere enumeration, or counting of cases. Suppose that the observation of one 4 It may be well to note one case in which a statement in the universal form must be distinguished from a law. As an example, we may take, " Every three-sided figure is a triangle.'* This is not an inductive inference; it is not based upon the ob- servation of individual instances at all. It is true in all cases, but it is true because we have previously said, "If any figure has three sides we will call it a triangle." In other words, it is true by definition. It is like an inductive generalization in apply- ing to all possible cases, past, present and to come, real and imaginary, etc., but it is not based upon the observation of in- dividual facts. Other judgments and operations, which must be distinguished from those which are present in induction properly so called, will be discussed in a later chapter; and still others may be found by referring to Mill's Logic, Book III, chapter ii. VERIFICATION 87 or more instances in which B has followed A has sug- gested to us the inference that A and B are causally related. Let us ask ourselves what consequences would follow upon the truth of this inference. In the first place we could conclude that if B were present in any case A must have been present also ; and, again, if A were absent in any case, its supposed effect B must have been absent also ; or if either A or B varied in amount or degree the other should show a corresponding varia- tion. All these things should be true of phenomena which are causally related. Phenomena which failed to satisfy such conditions could not be unconditionally connected. Suppose we had inferred that absence of oxygen would cause death. If that is true, an animal immersed in nitrogen should die. If experiment showed that an animal could live under such conditions, our inference would, of course, be disproved ; but suppose the animal did die, would the inference be proved? Not necessarily. Perhaps the nitrogen acted as a poison or perhaps the death of the animal was due to rough handling, etc. Our inductive inference would be com- pletely verified only if we could show that death could not have been due to anything except the absence of oxygen. If we could be sure that all the circumstances which were present before the experiment remained pre- cisely the same with the one exception that oxygen was present in the first case and absent in the second, then we should have shown a necessary connection between the absence of oxygen and the occurrence of death. Nothing else could have been the cause because all were present when death did not occur. If a second circum- stance were present when the phenomenon occurred and 88 INDUCTION absent when it did not occur, it would dispute with the first the right to be called the cause and no final con- clusion would be possible. When all other possibilities can be excluded, the one which remains is the -cause. When no other inference is consistent with the facts, the one which is consistent must be accepted as true. We can say, then, that an inductive inference is com- pletely verified when we have found facts which are con- sistent with its truth and inconsistent with any possible rival inference; or more briefly, when it fits the facts and no alternative inference does. We establish one in- ference by eliminating all others. We reason that the phenomenon under investigation has some cause; this other phenomenon, A, may be the cause; it fulfills the requirements and no other does ; therefore, this one is and must be the cause in question. There are several ways of selecting or grouping instances so as to show that some one factor alone satisfies the requirements. These are known as the INDUCTIVE METHODS. Observation, and Analysis are Presupposed. One thing should not be forgotten. It is that the application of such principles as these presupposes very careful ob- servation ; if we are to be certain that no other circum- stance is present when a given phenomenon is present or absent when it is absent, we must have observed all the other circumstances. In ordinary observation we note only a few of the circumstances ; if we are un- trained observers it may be impossible for us to ob- serve more than a few. It is quite impossible for a child to observe in a flower all that a trained botanist can observe there. Accurate observation presupposes anal- ysis, i. e. t breaking up the total complex phenome- TEST CONDITIONS 89 non into its element. The beginner in any science is unable to handle the facts properly because he is un- able to analyse them; he sees only their most obvious characteristics. Postponing Inference till Test Conditions are Pres- ent Before we begin the more detailed examination of the methods of verifying an inductive inference, there is one more statement to be made, namely this : instead of making a generalization and then searching for means of verifying it, we may refrain from drawing any inference until we have before us a group of facts which will make it possible to draw a correct inference. In other words, we may make our inference under test conditions. Suppose, for example, that we are trying to discover the cause of eclipses. Before making any theories on the subject we might observe a number of cases. If we found that whenever an eclipse occurred there was an opaque body between us and the source of light and that at other times everything was the same except that there was no body in that position, we should infer at once that the presence of the opaque body in that position wa*s the cause of the eclipse. And so in any other case we might form no theory until we had facts which would make it possible to form a cor- rect one. " If a chemist discovers a new element, he will pro- ceed to try a variety of experiments in order to de- termine the proportions in which it will combine with other elements as well as to discover the various prop- erties of such combinations. Supposing such experi- ments to have been properly conducted, the inductions at which he arrives will be perfectly valid, though he 90 INDUCTION may have formed no previous theories as to the results of his researches. Occasionally, too, an induction will not be the result of any definite course of investigation, but will be obtruded on our notice." 5 But such cases are rare, and ordinarily we have some theory before we have the facts which will verify it. It is often better to draw an inference early in the investigation ; the reasons for this will be discussed in a later chapter. 6 In the meantime it should be remem- bered that the Inductive Methods which are now to be discussed may be used either to test an inference al- ready made or to furnish a basis for drawing a correct inference if none has previously been drawn. The Inductive Methods. I. AGREEMENT. Sup- pose we find that A was followed by B in a number of instances, but that the attendant circumstances varied greatly. Suppose, for example, that three or four in- dividuals, of different races, different habits of life, and otherwise as different as possible, were all bitten by a certain kind of mosquito and that each developed yellow fever: would not such a set of cases give some warrant to the inference that \he bite of the mosquito was causally connected with the development of the fever? The fact that these individuals were different in all other respects would seem to exclude the possi- bility that anything else could have been the cause. Or suppose again that we find dew deposited on two or more objects which differ in position, chemical com- position, character of surface, and, in short, all respects except that both are cooler than the surrounding atmo- B Fowler, Inductive Logic, p. 11. Part III, chapter ii, Hypothesis. THE METHOD OF AGREEMENT 91 sphere ; we should have good grounds for believing that this last characteristic was causally related to the dep- osition of dew. Or, once more, if a number of persons who recovered from a given disease were similar only in having used a certain drug, the inference would be that the drug was causally related to the cure. In each of these examples we have a set of instances in which a given phenomenon is present, an attack of fever, deposition of dew, recovery from illness ; nothing else is present in all cases except one other phenomenon, being bitten by the mosquito, being cooler than the surrounding air, having used a certain drug. Our infer- ence is that the phenomena which are constantly pres- ent together are causally related. If A is causally, i. e. 9 unconditionally, related to something else, that thing must be present when A is present. As only one other phenomenon is present in all cases, that alone among all those at any time present can be causally related to the first. This method of isolating the phenomena which are so related is known as the Method of Agree- ment. Mill's statement of the Canon of Agreement is as follows : " If two or more instances of the phenom- enon under investigation" [fever, deposition of dew, etc.], " have only one circumstance in common " [being bitten by a mosquito, being cooler than the surrounding air, etc. ] , " the circumstances in which alone all the in- stances agree is the cause (or effect) of the given phe- nomenon." His statement of the axiom of this method is : " Whatever circumstance can be excluded without prejudice to the phenomenon, or can be absent notwith- standing its presence, is not connected with it in the way 92 INDUCTION of causation." The only circumstance which is com- mon to a number of instances in which a given phe- nomenon is present, is causally related to it, because all the rest are excluded by the fact that they are separable from it. In this method, as in the others to be discussed, the point of first importance is that we are selecting instances of the occurrence of a phenomenon, and selecting them in such a way as to identify the cir- cumstance or circumstances causally related to the phenomenon. We might re-word the main points as follows: select instances in which the phenomenon under investigation is present, but which are as different as possible in all other respects ; if there is one circum- stance and one only which is always present when the phenomenon under investigation is present, that cir- cumstance is causally related to the phenomenon. Difficulties in Using this Method. An ideal case might be represented symbolically in this way: let the phenomenon under investigation be represented by x; and let the accompanying circumstances, in the severaJ. instances we have selected be represented by abcde* afghi, ajklm, respectively ; or the phenomenon and its accompanying circumstances by : abcdex a-fgliix ajklmx. The only circumstances common to all the instances is a. Therefore a is causally related to x. No actual DIFFICULTIES 93 case would be quite so simple ; any phenomenon has among its accompanying circumstances everything that is happening in the universe at the time of its occur- rence. Most of these circumstances can, of -course, be eliminated as irrelevant ; still it is easily possible to overlook something that is relevant. 1. Circumstances which might seem to have no con- nection with the phenomenon may be causally related to it. For example, it might be supposed that the number of sun-spots had no relation to financial con- ditions ; yet it has been shown that the periods when sun-spots are most numerous have the same frequency as the periods when panics occur ; and it has been sug- gested that sun-spots influence climatic conditions, that these in turn, by influencing crops, and so on, do affect financial conditions. Whether there is any truth in this or not, it will remind us that it is not easy to determine just what circumstances are relevant. 2. Another difficulty arises from the fact that analy- sis is never complete; not all the elements are singled out, and some of those which have been overlooked may be all-important. For example : it had been noticed that persons who had been much out of doors at night were more likely than others to be attacked by malaria; it was inferred that " night-air " was a cause of malaria, and consequently people tried to exclude it from their houses. Later it was shown that the attacks of mos- quitoes were the causes. Mosquitoes are more active at night, but instead of noting this, the more obvious fact that " night-air " is damp, and so on, was selected as the important one. When it was found that the bite 94 INDUCTION of the mosquito was the circumstance always present, while the time of the attack made no difference, the older theory was overthrown. In symbolizing an actual case we should need some- thing to represent the circumstances which were dis- regarded or overlooked. We might use the symbol X; the accompanying circumstances would then be rep- resented by abode. .X 9 afghi. .X, etc. This would in- dicate that there is a margin of uncertainty in such cases. 3. There is one other difficulty in the application of the method of Agreement. It may be illustrated in this way : suppose a man should drink coffee with his lunch- eon on one day and afterwards smoke a strong cigar; suppose on the following day, with a different bill of fare, he should drink tea and smoke a cigar; on both days he has a headache in the afternoon. The applica- tion of the method of Agreement would lead him to be- lieve that the cigar was the -cause of the headache,, whereas the cause may have been the coffee in one in- stance and the tea in the other. This illustrates what is known as the Plurality of Causes. A given phenome- non may have one cause in one instance and another cause in a second instance. It is sometimes said that if our analysis were complete we should find that a given phenomenon always had the same cause ; that in the in- stances just mentioned, the cause of the headache wag something common to tea and coffee ; or that the head- ache caused by coffee differs from that caused by tea and that two things which are different never can pro- duce the same effect. Perhaps that is true, but the fact still remains that, in practice, effects which are so simi- THE METHOD OF DIFFERENCE 95 lar as to be indistinguishable may be produced by causes that, for ordinary observation, are very different. This makes a very serious limitation to the application of the method of Agreement. The method is still valuable as suggesting causal relations, though imperfect as a means of proof. May it not be possible to select in- stances on some other principle in such a way as to obviate some of these difficulties? II. THE METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. Take another concrete case : suppose two individuals as similar as possible in all respects, race, family, occupation, man- ner of living, state of health and so on; one of these is bitten by mosquitos of a certain sort and the other protects himself against their attacks ; the first con- tracts the fever, the second escapes it. We should regard such a group of facts as warranting the conclu- sion that the bite of the mosquito and the contraction of yellow fever were causally related. Or, if two objects of similar chemical construction, character of surface, location, etc., differed only in that one was for some reason cooler than the surrounding air, while the other was not, and if dew were deposited on the first and not on the second, we should conclude that the cooler temperature of the one was causally related to the deposition of dew upon it. , Cases like these illustrate the Method of Difference." Mill's statment of the Canon of this method is : " If an instance in which the phenomenon under in- vestigation occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every circumstance in common save one, that one occurring only in the former; the circum- stance in which alone the two instances differ is the 96 INDUCTION effect or the cause, or an indispensable part of the cause, of the phenomenon." Its axioms, in the words of the same writer, are : " Whatever antecedent cannot be excluded without preventing the phenomenon, is the cause, or a condition of the phenomenon; whatever con- sequent can be excluded with no other difference in the antecedents than the exclusion of a particular one, is the effect of that one." Relation of this to the First Method. We quote from Mill again regarding the relation of this method to the other: " Instead of comparing different instances of a phe- nomenon to discover in what they agree, this method compares an instance of its occurrence with an instance of its non-occurrence, to discover in what they differ. . . . Both are methods of elimination. ... The Method of Agreement stands on the ground that what- ever can be eliminated is not connected with the phe- nomenon by any law. The Method of Difference has for its foundation, that whatever cannot be eliminated is connected with the phenomenon by a law." Incomplete analysis of the circumstances attending the phenomenon may vitiate the inference in both methods: in the method of Agreement as already stated; in the method of Difference, by leading us to overlook points of difference in cases supposed to be alike except in the particulars specified in the Canon of this method. Difficulties in Using the Method of Difference. 1. One danger in employing the method of Difference results from the possibility of the Composition of Causes. It often happens that a given phenomenon DIFFICULTIES 97 is the effect of the joint action of several causes. Heat, light, moisture, etc., are all causally related to the life of plants. If two plants were similarly situated as regards all but moisture, it would be incorrect to con- clude that moisture was the sole cause of the life of the one because its absence was followed by the death of the other. Application of the method of Difference does show that the antecedent is causally related to the consequent, but not that it is the sole or adequate cause. If we could supplement the method of Difference by the method of Agreement, if we could find a set of in- stances in which the supposed cause was alone common to the cases in which the phenomenon was present, then we could conclude that this supposed cause was ade- quate to produce the phenomenon. . Another source of difficulty closely connected with the one just discussed is to be found in the existence of Counteracting Causes. Even if a cause is adequate to the production of an effect under ordinary conditions, it may fail to produce it owing to the presence of some opposed tendency. The poison can be counteracted by an antidote ; the tendency of the moon to fall to the earth is in part overcome by centrifugal force, and so on. The presence of a counteracting cause might lead us to overlook the real cause of the phenomenon. The cause is present without the effect; that is, without the usual effect. In such a case its effect is to be found in its modification of the counteracting cause. The ten- dency of the moon to fall does modify the effect which would otherwise be produced by its tendency to fly off at a tangent. We may symbolize one sort of case in which error might arise, as follows : Let m be the phenomenon 98 INDUCTION whose cause we are seeking and suppose that we have abed X abcr X m We should probably conclude that r was the cause of m, whereas it might well be that a was the real cause, but that it was counteracted in the first instance by d. It is no doubt true that in an ideal application of the methods there would be little difficulty ; if we could get cases which differed in only one circumstance it would at any rate be easy to see that the absence of the effect m was connected with the presence of the circumstance d; we should still have to search for the cause of m's presence. But in actual cases the matter is not so sim- ple; we cannot find ideal cases and the instances we select for the application of the method of Difference may differ in more than one respect, as in the case just discussed. III. THE JOINT METHOD. Nature presents very few instances in which the method of Difference can be directly applied, and even experiment fails to present ideal conditions. It seldom happens that the conditions stated in the Canon of Difference are realized. The same is true to a great extent with regard to the method of Agreement. Usually two or more cases in which a given phenomenon occurs are similar in more than one circumstance. In such cases it is sometimes possible to use a combination of the two methods. The following instance illustrates the use of The Joint Method of Agreement and Difference: a large number of cases of typhoid fever occurred at about the same time in a college community. It happened that all those who de- THE JOINT METHOD 99 veloped the disease ate at a certain few fraternity and boarding-house tables. The water supply was first in- vestigated. It was found that all these places used water from the same source. But it was also true that the other houses were supplied from the same source, so this possible cause was eliminated. The fresh vege- tables were supplied from various sources; some of the places in which the disease was developed used one ; source, others a different one ; moreover, the places in which the disease was not developed were supplied from the same variety of sources. The other food supplies fcame from various places and the method of Agreement ncould not be applied so far as they were concerned, with cone exception ; it appeared that the milk supply was the same for all the places in which the fever was developed, whereas none of the places which escaped used milk from that source. The inference was that the milk contained the cause of the disease. Further, it was found that when milk from this source was no longer used, no new cases of the disease appeared. There were two sets of cases: in one the disease was developed, in the other it was not. Those in which it appeared were alike in several respects ; the ages, habits and previous general health were similar in all ; the water supply was the same and also the milk supply ; it might be any one of these; the method of Agreement could not be suc- cessfully applied. The other set of cases, those in which the disease did not appear, were like the first in many respects, but there was no one of these which differed from any one of the others, in one respect only. There was one and one only circumstance in which all the members of the first group differed from all the mem~ 100 INDUCTION bers of the second, namely in the milk supply. All of one group agreed in having a given milk supply and developing typhoid fever; all of the other group agreed in using milk from another source and escaping the disease. Comparing group with group the method of Difference could be used. There was only one cir- cumstance in which all the instances in which fever was developed differed from all of those in which it was not developed. Within each set of instances there is a partial application of the method of Agreement. One set agreed in having the disease and also in having an- other common circumstance ; but more than one circum- stance was common, so the application could not be complete; similarly the other set of instances agreed in the absence of the fever and in the absence of this circumstance; but they also agreed in lacking va- rious other circumstances. However, they agreed in lacking only one which was present in all those of the other set, and that is the important point. The two sets of instances might be symbolized thus ; p representing the phenomenon under investigation: abcdr X p bcJcr abefr X p eflr aefgr X p fgmr afghrX p ghnr Both a and r are common to all the instances in which p is present, but r is excluded by the fact that it is pres- ent in those in which p is absent. Mill's statement of the Canon of the Joint Method reads : " If two or more instances in which the phe- THE JOINT METHOD,. . 101 nomenon occurs have only one circumstance iji com- mon, while two or more instances in .wMrii it du?s; r;o]fc, occur have nothing in common save the absence of that circumstance, the -circumstance in which alone the two sets of instances differ is the effect or the cause, or an indispensable part of the cause, of the phenomenon." This statement does not quite cover a case like that described above. The instances in which the phenome- non occurs may have more than one circumstance in common, provided that there is only one which is at the same time common to these and absent from those in which the phenomenon does not occur. We might re- state it thus : " If two or more instances in which a phenomenon occurs have in common one circumstance which is at the same time the only circumstance present in these instances and absent from two or more instances in which the phenomenon does not occur, that circum- stance is causally related to the phenomenon." This form of statement avoids the difficulty just mentioned and also another. It is practically impossible to find a set of instances which have nothing in common save the absence of one circumstance. In the example just given, the instances in which typhoid fever did not oc- cur agreed in not being Esquimaux nor octogenarians nor coal-miners, and so on indefinitely. On the other hand it would have been easily possible to find a group of instances in which there would have been fewer cir- cumstances absent from all. One might select a num- ber of individuals from different races, of different ages, occupations, and so on. Fewer circumstances would be absent from all of these than from a homogeneous group of college students. But such instances might be en- 102 INDUCTION tirely insignificant fW the purpose of discovering the C'l-usr. of tlte "disease.' --Of course, if the group of nega- tive instances included examples from all varieties of those who lacked the phenomenon in question, and we could discover the only circumstance lacking in these, and present in the cases where the phenomenon was present, a conclusion could be drawn; but, in the first place, it would be impossible to get such a group, for it would be infinite in extent ; and, secondly, if the group i could be had, the discovery of the only circumstance "lacking from all of them would be an endless task. Most i of such instances might at once be eliminated as irrele- vant, though Mill's canon does not provide for that. .It is important that the instances in which the phe- -nomenon is absent should be similar to those in which :'it is present, for if there are many points of difference Jit will be difficult or impossible to select those which are causally related to the phenomenon. IV. CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. There are still otlier methods of discovering causal relations. Suppose a case in which such instances as are demanded for the application of any of the foregoing methods cannot be obtained; it may be possible to find instances in which the phenomenon occurs in varying degrees or in dif- ferent quantities, while some other phenomenon varies concomitantly. " The effects of heat are known only through proportionate variation. We can not deprive a body of all its heat ; the nature of the agency forbids us. But by making changes in the amount, we ascer- tain concomitant changes in the accompanying cir- cumstances, and can so establish cause and effect. It is thus that we arrive at the law of the expansion of bodies by heat. In the same way we prove the equivalence of CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS 103 heat and mechanical force as a branch of the great law of Conservation of Persistence of Force." " The proof of the First Law of Motion, as given by Newton, assumed the form of Concomitant Varia- tions. On the earth, there is no instance of motion persisting indefinitely. In proportion, however, as the known obstructions to motion friction and the resist- ance of the air are abated, the motion of a body is prolonged. A wheel spinning in an exhausted receiver upon a smooth axle runs a very long time. In Borda's experiment with the pendulum, the swing was prolonged to more than thirty' hours, by diminishing the friction and exhausting the air. Now, comparing the whole series of cases, from speedy exhaustion of movement to prolonged continuance, we find that there is a strict concomitance between the degree of obstruction and the arrest ; we hence infer that if the obstruction were en- tirely absent, motion would be perpetual. The statis- tics of crime reveal causes by the method of Variations. When we find crimes diminishing according as labor is abundant, according as habits of sobriety have in- creased, according to the multiplication of the means of detection, or according to the system of punishments, we may presume a causal connection, in circumstances not admitting of the method of Difference." 7 We may symbolize a Set of instances to which this method is applicable in this way: a bed X p !(2fl) bee X (2p) (4a) bef X (3p), etc. The Canon of the Method of Concomitant Variations 7 Bain, Logic, pp. 62-63. 104 INDUCTION is : " Whatever phenomenon varies in any manner whenever another phenomenon varies in some particular manner, is either a cause or an effect of that phenome- non, or is connected with it through some fact of cau- sation." V. THE METHOD OF RESIDUES. This method is usually included with the others and completes the list. Its canon is : " Subduct from any phenomenon such part as is known by previous inductions to be the effect of certain antecedents, and the residue of the phenom- enon is the effect of the remaining antecedents." Its principle, like that of the other methods, is that of ex- clusion. If we have a complex phenomenon or a group of phenomena represented by the letters xyzlm, and a group of antecedent circumstances represented by abcdf, and if we know that a causes x and b causes /, c causes z and d causes Z, the conclusion will be that the remaining m is the effect of /. This method would be equally applicable in an instance in which the causes were present with the effects instead of being ante- cedent to them only. Thus, if we had a phenomenon m in a group of circumstances, dbcdjxyzlm, and knew as before that a and #, b and y, c and z, and d and I were causally related, the connection of / and m would be evident. We must, of course, be careful to include all the relevant circumstances in the group. If a phenomenon has occurred and all the known ante- cedents of this phenomenon are known not to contain its cause, the cause must be sought for in some phe- nomenon not yet discovered. There were certain per- turbations in the movement of the planet Uranus, not accounted for bjr the attractive force of any known THE METHOD OF RESIDUES 105 heavenly body; they must, then, be due to some body not yet discovered ; this line of reasoning led to the dis- covery of the planet Neptune. Again, the weight of atmospheric nitrogen was found to be greater than that of nitrogen produced chemically ; further examination revealed the presence in the atmosphere of another element, argon. Obviously the method of Residues can be applied only when we have fairly complete knowledge of the field of facts in which the phenomenon is found. We must know the causal relations of all the circumstances involved in the case except the phenomenon under inves- tigation. The following example, though not formally in- cluded under Mill's canon, employs the principle of Residues : If only four men were capable of doing a cer- tain act and if we learned that one of these was tempo- rarily unable to do it, through illness, and that the two others were a thousand miles away when the act was performed, the fourth must have committed the act. If, in any way, we can assure ourselves that of all the possible causes of a phenomenon all but one are ex- cluded, that one must be the cause. The several methods are ways of doing this. EXERCISES Examine the following arguments and criticise the rea- soning as fully as possible; state the method used: 1. The newly discovered painting must be a Rubens; for the conception, the drawing, the tone and the tints are precisely those seen in the authentic works of that master. (Hyslop.) 106 INDUCTION 2. In nine counties, in which the population is from 100 to 150 per square mile, the births to 100 marriages are 396; in sixteen counties, with a population of 150 to 200 per square mile, the births are 390 to 100 marriages. There- fore the number of births per marriage is inversely related to the density of population and contradicts Malthus's theory of the law of population. (Hyslop.) 3. The great famine in Ireland began in 1845 and in- creased until it reached a climax in 1848. During this time agrarian crime increased very rapidly until, in 1848, it was more than three times as great as in 1845. After this it decreased with the return of better crops until, in 1851, it was only 50 per cent, more than in 1845. It is evident from this that a close relation of cause and effect exists between famine and agrarian crime. (Hyslop.) 4. The influence of heat in changing the level of the ground upon which the temple of Jupiter Serapis stands might be inferred from several circumstances. In the first place, there are numerous hot springs in the vicinity, and when we reflect on the dates of the principal oscillations of level this conclusion is made much more probable. Thus, before the Christian era, when Vesuvius was regarded as a spent volcano, the ground on which the temple stood was several feet above water. But after the eruption of Vesu- vius in 79 B. c., the temple was sinking. Subsequently Vesuvius became dormant and the foundations of the tem- ple began to rise. Again Vesuvius became active, and has remained so ever since. During this time the temple has been subsiding again, so far as we know its history. (Hyslop.) 5. Take a bottle of charged water, slightly warmer than a given temperature registered by the thermopile, and mark the deflection it causes. Then cut the string which holds it and the cork will be driven out by the elastic force of the carbonic acid gas. The gas performs its work, and in so doing it consumes heat and the deflection of the thermopile shows that the bottle is cooler than before, heat having been lost in the process. (Hyslop.) 6. As an evidence of the extreme antiquity of highly civilized man, we have the following facts : On one of the remote islands of the Pacific Easter Island two thousand EXERCISES 107 miles from South America, two thousand miles from the' Marquesas, and more than one thousand miles from the; Gambier Islands, are found hundreds of gigantic stone' images, now mostly in ruins. They are often forty feet- high, while many seem to have been larger, the crowns of their heads, cut out of red stone, being sometimes ten feet in diameter, while even the head and neck of one is said to have been twenty feet high. The island containing these remarkable works has an area of about thirty square miles, and as the smallest image is about eight feet high, weighing four tons, and as the largest must weigh over a hundred tons or much more, their existence implies a large population, abundance of food, and an established govern- ment which so small an island could not supply. (Hyslop.) 7. We observe very frequently that very poor handwrit- ing characterizes the manuscripts of able men, while the best handwriting is as frequent with those who do little mental work when compared with those whose penmanship is poor. We may, therefore, infer that poor penmanship is caused by the influence of severe mental occupation. (Hyslop.) 8. In the following instances crystallization takes place: the freezing of water; cooling and solidifying of molten metals and minerals; deposition of salts from solutions; volatilization of solutions; deposition of solids from the gaseous state, as iodine; pressure; slow internal change, as in rocks; the transformation of metals from the tough to the brittle condition, by hammering; vibration, and re- peated heatings and coolings. We may then conclude that the cause of crystallization is the increased scope and oper- ation of the molecular or solid-forming cohesion. (Bain.) 9- When the barometer was carried to the top of the Puy de Dome it was found that the mercury stood lower than before. It was inferred that the pressure of the air was the cause of the rise of mercury in the tube. 10. The chemical action between two substances is much greater when they are in a liquid than when they are in a gaseous state. We may conclude that there is an inverse relation between cohesion and chemical activity. 11. Goldscheider proved that muscular sensations play no considerable part in pur consciousness of the movement 108 INDUCTION* of our limbs, by having his arm suspended in a frame and moved by an attendant. Under these circumstances, where no work devolved on the muscles, he found that he could distinguish as small an angular movement of the arm as when he moved and supported it himself. He also proved that the chief source of movement-con- sciousness is pressure-sensations from the inner surface of the joints, by having his arm held so that the joint sur- faces are pressed more closely together, and finding that a smaller movement was now perceptible. (Creighton.) 12. " That the Tempest belongs to the latest period of Shakespeare's literary activity is shown, inter alia, by the absence of rhyme, the large number of ' run on ' (un- stopped) lines, the high proportion of weak and light end- ings, and the comparative rarity of puns in the low scenes." (Mellone.) 13. That the feeling of effort is largely, if not entirely, of peripheral origin, appears from such experiments as the following: Hold the finger as if to pull the trigger of a pistol. Think vigorously of bending the finger, but do not bend it. An unmistakable feeling of effort results. Re- peat the experiment, and notice that the breath is involun- tarily held, and that there are tensions in the other mus- cles. Repeat the experiment again, taking care to keep the breathing regular and the other muscles passive. Little or no feeling of effort will now accompany the imaginary bending of the finger. (Ferrier, quoted by Hibben.) 14. Sir Charles Lyell, by studying the fact that the rivtr Ganges yearly conveys to the ocean as much earth as would form sixty of the great pyramids of Egypt, was enabled to infer that the ordinary slow causes now in operation upon the earth would account for the immense geological changes that have occurred, without having recourse to the less reasonable theory of sudden catastrophes. (Hibben.) 15. Count Rumford in 1798 proved that the common notion that heat was a substance was false, by boring a large piece of brass, under great pressure of the bore, whilst the brass was in a gallon of water; and at the end of two and one-half hours the water actually boiled. (Hib- ben.) 16. How would you set out to discover the causal rela- EXERCISES 109 tions of the following phenomena? Suggest instances and indicate the method to be used: (1) Heat and expansion. (2) Heat and friction. (3) Mosquitos and malaria. (4) The tubercle bacillus and consumption. (5) Golden-rod and hay fever. (6) A rainy spring and mosquitos. (7) The presence of oxygen and the burning of a candle flame. (8) Cocaine and the absence of pain. (9) Moisture and vegetation. (10) The gulf-stream and climate. (11) The cause of the tides. (12) The cause of the trade winds. (13) The course of a glancing bullet. 17. Cite ten cases of the composition of causes. 18. Cite ten of the plurality of causes. 19. Cite ten cases of counteracting causes. 20. Bring in five cases illustrating each of the methods. CHAPTER VII VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION Verification and Deduction. All these methods are means by which a sound inference may be drawn or an inference already drawn may be verified. They all involve finding certain facts which inevitably follow from the inference in question, and they are not con- clusive if these facts can be shown to be consistent with any rival hypothesis. There is another way of testing the truth of any in- ference ; if we can show that the inference follows from something already known we shall establish the truth of the inference itself. Instead of searching for the consequences of the inferences and trying to determine their truth, we find a law of which our inference is it- self a necessary consequence. Conversely if an infer- ence is inconsistent with a known law it is necessarily false. In applying this it is necessary to remember that many supposed laws have proved to be false and that when an inference disagrees with a supposed law, it may be that the latter or both must be rejected. The fact that an inference is consistent with known laws does not prove its truth, but only its possible truth, for two rival hypotheses may be consistent with all the known facts and laws to which they are related. For proof, the connection must be closer than mere con- sistency. The inference must not only agree with the law, it must follow from it; in other words, the truth of the law must insure the truth of the inference, HP SYSTEMATIC KNOWLEDGE 111 An inference from a law or general principle to some consequence of the principle is a deductive inference. When we reason in this way we reason deductively, we deduce a conclusion, we employ deduction. Systematic Knowledge. -When we show that an in- ductive inference is a reliable statement of the relation of certain phenomena to each other, or when we show that any inference whatever is a consequence of some general principle, we establish the fact that the infer- ence with which we are dealing belongs to a system of facts or truths. 1 In a system all the parts and elements are so related that the truth of one part implies the truth of the rest ; we cannot hold to one part and reject the rest without inconsistency and contradiction. A sys- tem may consist of comparatively few members and be comparatively simple, as in an isolated syllogism, or it may be very broad in its scope and its internal relations may be exceedingly complex. For example, a philo- sophical system attempts to state the laws which hold for all reality. We shall begin our examination of systems with the syllogism. When we argue, to use the most ancient of illustrations, that " Socrates is mortal because all men are mortal and Socrates is a man," we are basing the truth of our conclusion upon a universal proposition, " All men are mortal," and the further proposition, " Socrates belongs to the class men." Criticism of the Syllogism. It might be urged, as an objection to the syllogism, that "it gives us no new l Professor Hibben in his Logic, Deductive and Inductive, makes much use of this conception in discussing the nature of deduction and induction. VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION information ; if the conclusion is really contained in the major premise, 2 as it must be if the reasoning is to be valid, why go to the trouble of making a syllogism? We knew beforehand that all members of the class designated by the subject were included in that desig- nated by the predicate, or possessed the quality, rela- tion, or whatever it may be, for which the predicate stands; if we did not know that Socrates was mortal, how could we say that all men are mortal? Therefore, it is a matter of course that the subject of the conclu- sion, which is included in the subject of the major premise, will have that predicate. This objection would lead to the condemnation of such a science as geom- etry, for all its conclusions are contained in its postu- lates and axioms. Still we do get information by means of such processes. We may know it to be a general law that all iron compounds have certain properties without knowing the chemical composition of a compound we have in our hands ; as soon as we discover that it is a compound of iron, we can draw our conclusion. Of course, if our major premise were not a law, our conclusion would not be trustworthy. If the general statement about iron compounds were an unverified inductive inference, then we could not state it with certainty so long as we were not sure that the present compound, if it proves to be iron, would possess the given properties. If all inductive inferences were simply enumerative or collec- tive judgments (page 86), if "perfect induction" were the ideal form of induction, then there would be ground for the objection we have mentioned. But if 2 The universal proposition on which the reasoning is based, in this case, "All men are mortal." is called the major premise. VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM 113 we may know that whenever a given phenomenon oc- curs, a certain circumstance must inevitably be pres- ent, or that any two properties are invariably con- nected, we have information which will apply to many cases of whose character we may yet be in ignorance. The syllogism is the typical form of reasoning. The quotation which follows is from Professor James's Psy- chology; it states the claim that reasoning is precisely that form of mental activity which does enable us to deal with new situations, with novel data. " A thing inferred by reasoning need neither have been an habitual associate of the datum from which we infer it, nor need it be similar to it. It may be a thing entirely unknown to our previous experience, something which no simple association of concretes could ever have evoked. The great difference, in fact, between that simple kind of rational thinking which consists in the concrete objects of past experience merely suggesting each other and reasoning distinctly so-called is this: that whilst empirical thinking is only reproductive, reasoning is productive. An empirical, or * rule-of- thumb,' thinker can deduce nothing from data with whose behaviour and associates in the concrete he is un- familiar. But put a reasoner amongst a set of con- crete objects, which he has neither seen nor heard of before, and with a little time, if he is a good reasoner, he will make such inferences from them as will quite atone for all his ignorance. Reasoning helps us out of unprecedented situations situations for which all our common associative wisdom, all the * education * which we share in common with the beasts, leaves us without resource." Psychology, Briefer Course, page 114 VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION As soon as we see that the present case belongs to a certain class or is of a certain type, the laws which are known to apply to that class or type may immediately be applied to it. How Propositions are Related to each other The syllogism as illustrated above shows that a univer- sal judgment may be made the basis for certain other statements. There are several kinds of syllogisms, but before discussing these it will be well to examine propo- sitions generally with a view to discovering what rela- tions different kinds of statements bear to each other and whether there may not be other ways than that illustrated in the syllogism, in which one statement may be made the basis for another. We have already dis- cussed four kinds of propositions ; those which are universal and affirmative, universal and negative, par- ticular and affirmative, and particular and negative. It will be remembered that the symbols for these were A, E, I, and O respectively. Their relations to each other are best shown by means of what is known as the " Square of Opposition," a diagram which has remained practically unchanged since the time of Aristotle. (All x is y) (No x is y) A Contraries E 1 * I Subcontraries O (Some x is y) (Some x is not y) RELATIONS OF OPPOSITION 115 Let us take as an illustration of the A proposition, " All men are rational." Its contrary will be " No men are rational." What exactly are the relations between these two propositions? If A be true, it is obvious that E will be false, and if E be true A will be false. But if A be false, what about E? It may be true or false, for the falsity of A leaves those two possibilities ; in other words, the truth or falsity of E is undetermined. Similarly of A, if E be false. If either be false, there is a middle ground; thus, it may be that some men are rational and some are not. Two propositions are con- trary when only one can be true and both can be false. "All men are rational" (A), and " Some men are not rational" (O), are contradictory propositions. If A be true, O will be false, and if A be false, O will be true ; likewise if O be true, A will be false, and if O be false A will be true. There is no middle ground ; there is no third possibility. Only one can be true, and only one can be false, or in other words, both cannot be true and both cannot be false. Two propositions are contradictory when they are exact opposites; one must be true and the other must be -false. Of sub-contrary propositions, both may be true, but only one can be false. The propositions, " Some men are rational " and " Some men are not rational," are in the relation of sub-contraries. If either be false the other must be true, and if one be true the other may be true also ; both may be true, and one must be. The propositions I and O are consistent, whereas contraries and contradictories are inconsistent. 4 Two propositions which are to stand in a relation of op- position to each other must have identical terms. This is true in the traditional treatment, but exceptions will be noted later. 116 VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION In the case of subalterns, both propositions are of the same quality, but they differ in quantity. " All men are rational " and " Some men are rational " are subalterns. // the universal be true the particular will of course be true also; but if the universal be false the other is left indeterminate; it may be true or it may be false. On the other hand, if the particular proposition be false, the universal will necessarily be false too; if it is false that " Some men are rational," it cannot be true that " All men are " ; but if the particular be true it is by no means certain that the other will be. Thus, if we know that some men are rational, that does not give us a right either to affirm or to deny that all men are rational ; in other words, the truth of the universal is left indeterminate. To summarize: contrary propositions are such that only one can be true, and both may be false. Contradictory propositions are so related that one must be true and the other must be false. Sub-contraries may both be true, but only one can be false. Subalterns may both be true or both false. The truth of the universal assures the truth of the par- ticular, but the falsity of the universal does not in- volve the falsity of the particular; the falsity of the particular involves the falsity of the universal, but the truth of the particular does not assure the truth of the universal. Relations of Opposition among Propositions which have not Identical Terms. These relations are most easily detected between propositions which have the same subject and the same predicate, but it is possible RELATIONS OF OPPOSITION 117 to find them in propositions which do not answer to this description. The propositions, " All men are rational " and " All men are idiots," are contraries. Both cannot be true, but both may be false. Or again, " Socrates was the wisest of the Greeks " and " Aristotle was the wisest of the Greeks," are con- trary propositions. Only one of them could be true, while both might be false. This will be found to be the case with a great many inconsistent propositions. In fact all inconsistent propositions which are not contradictories are con- traries. Many pairs of such inconsistent propositions would not fit into the square of opposition, for both might be affirmative or both might be negative. A and E propositions which have identical terms are contra- ries : we need not consider the meaning of the proposition to discover that, for it is evident from their form. In other cases we must take into account the meaning as well. " A is B " and " A is not B " are contraries so long as the meaning of the terms A and B remains the same, no matter what that meaning is ; but the relation between " A is X " and " A is Y " can be determined only after we know the meaning of X and Y. If we learn that X and Y are opposites we can, of course, re- state our second proposition, "A is Y," in the form " A is not X," the contrary of " A is X." If X and Y prove to be the same or similar in meaning the two original propositions are of course consistent. Subject and predicate may both be different; e. g., " Oxygen is heavier than nitrogen " and " Nitrogen is heavier than oxygen." Only one cannot be true ; both might be false. If two propositions, alike in quality, 118 VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION have the same subject but have predicates which are complete opposites, as X and not-X, the propositions will be contradictories. Such pairs of terms as " ra- tional and non-rational," " square and not-square," are examples. Cases sometimes occur in which propositions having the same predicates but different subjects will be con- tradictory in meaning: thus, " Man alone is rational "; " Some being besides man is rational." Similarly, propositions with unlike terms may stand in the relation of sub-contraries. For example : " Some men are rational " and " Some men are irrational," and 66 Simple substances make up a large part of the earth's crust " and " Compound substances make up a large part, etc.," are pairs of sub-contraries. And likewise in the case of subalterns : for example, " All men are vertebrates " and " All men are mam- mals " ; " No mental states can be weighed," " No emo- tions can be weighed." The relation of subaltern may hold between two propositions even if one of them is not universal. Thus, " Most books are worthless " and " Some books are worthless." Of course, " The recent novels are worthless," is not necessarily a subalterna.te of either of these propositions. Singular propositions require special notice. " Soc- rates was the noblest of men " and " Socrates was not the noblest of men " are apparently contrary propo- sitions, but as a matter of fact they are contradictories. Singular propositions which have the same terms are never contraries except in form. On the other hand, " Socrates was an Athenian " and " Socrates was a Spartan " are contraries. Conversion. A proposition is the verbal expression CONVERSION 119 of a judgment, and a judgment is an act of thought wherein we assert that certain relations hold among cer- tain objects of thought, as, A is B, A Is not B, some A is Y, and so on. Now it is often possible to formulate other propositions which are equivalent to these or which are obviously true if the original proposition be true. The proposition, " No conic sections are rectan- gular figures," is equivalent to " No rectangular figures are conic sections." The only difference between the two is in the order of the terms. The original subject and predicate have been interchanged. This process is known as Conversion. The proposition just con- verted was an E proposition and all E propositions can be converted. Again, the proposition, " Some metals are elements " can be converted into " Some elements are metals." Both are I propositions. From the proposition, " Some quadrupeds are horses," we can get only " Some horses are quadrupeds," We happen to know that the same could be said of all horses, but we do not get that knowledge from the original proposition. The original statement is affirmative and affirmative propositions, as we have seen, do not give information about the whole of the predicate. But the statement, "All horses are quadrupeds," being universal, affirms something about the whole class horses. The first general rule of conversion is that no term may be distributed in the converse "which was not dis- tributed in the original proposition. A proposition, then, such as " All A propositions are universal," can have as its converse only an I proposition, " Some uni- versal propositions are A propositions." Each of the propositions dealt with above has had as 120 VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION its converse another proposition having the same quality. In all cases the converse of a proposition must have the same quality as the original proposition. This is a second rule of conversion. From this and the for- mer rule it follows that the proposition can have no converse. Its subject is undistributed and its quality negative ; but in the converse, the original subject, hav- ing become the predicate of a negative proposition, would be distributed, a violation of the first rule. Proposition Converse The converse of A is I: All S is P; Some P is S. The converse of I is I: Some S is P; Some P is S. The converse of E is E: No S is P; No P is S. O has no converse. The use of Euler's circles 5 will help to make these re- A (Pi's) All S is P or (at least) some P is S. E (S) No S is P or no P is S. I ( <~p) (At least) some S is P or some P is S. (?)) Some S is not P but all P may be S, or no P may be S, or some may be and some may not be. lations clear. We see that propositions E and I are converted into E and I ; in technical language they are converted " simply." A can be converted only into I ; 5 The forms here used are taken from Hyslop's Elements of Logic. OBVERSION that is, it is converted into a proposition which is less general than itself, into a particular proposition. Such conversion is known as conversion by limitation or per accidens. Obversion. Again, we may find for all ordinary propositions an equivalent of the opposite quality : " All men are wise " is equivalent to " No men are unwise " \ " Some men are just " can be expressed as " Some men are not unjust " ; " No animals are moral " as " All ani- mals are unmoral " ; " Some men are not honest " as " Some men are dishonest." It will be noticed that in every case the subject is unchanged. (In " All men are wise," and " No men are wise,'"' .the subject is in both cases " All men " ; the " No " belongs to the statement as a whole, not to the subject. The negative of " All men " would be "All who are not men.") This process is called Obversion. The quality of the proposition if changed and the predicate of the obverse is the com- plete opposite of the predicate of the original proposi- tion. Proposition Obverse The obverse of A is EJ All S is P; No S is not-P. The obverse of I is O: Some S is P; Some S is not not-P. The obverse of E is A: No S is P; All S is not-P. The obverse of O is I: Some S is not P; Some S is not-P. If the predicate in the original proposition be nega- tive, as non-conductor, it will be replaced in the obverse by the corresponding positive term, conductor. " Some S is not-P " will have as its obverse " Some S is not P." Difficulty is likely to arise with regard to the predicate and its opposite. For example, the proposi- tion, " No animals are moral," is not equivalent to " All VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION animals are immoral." They may be neither moral nor immoral. The predicate in the new proposition must be completely opposite or contradictory to the original predicate. Sometimes it can not be expressed simply. For example, take the proposition, " The president is the nation's highest executive officer." In the obverse the whole of the predicate must be made negative, not simply " highest " or " executive " or " officer." It might read, " The president is not any one who is not the nation's highest executive officer." The following symbols may be employed to indicate the relations considered in obversion. Suppose we have a proposition with the predicate P or not-P. Every- thing in the universe either has or has not the predicate P, that is, everything has one or the other of the predicates P and not-P. We may represent this fact by a circle divided into two compartments, thus : Then any given thing will fall into one or the other of those compartments. If our proposition asserts that it falls into one, that is tantamount to asserting that it falls outside the other ; the latter assertion would be the obverse of the former. S is P, implies that S is not not-P ; T is not-P, implies that T is not P. Contraposition. These changes in the form of prop- ositions may both be present together and repeatedly. Let us take the proposition, " No men are immortal." CONTRAPOSITION The obverse would be, " All men are mortal " ; the con- verse of this, " Some mortals are men " ; the obverse of this again, " Some mortals are not not-men " (not anything else than men) ; and this, being an O propo- sition, has no converse. We might, of course, have begun with conversion. What is known as Contraposition is equivalent to obversion plus conversion. 6 The contrapositive of " No men are immortal " is " Some mortals are men " ; the contrapositive of " All men are mortal " would be " No immortals are men." In the contrapositive the subject is the opposite of the original predicate, the predicate is the original subject, and the quality of the proposition is the opposite of that of the original prop- osition. An application of the rules for conversion will show that the I proposition has no contrapositive. The contrapositives of the various propositions are as fol- lows: Proposition Contrapositive A, contrapositive E: All S is P; No not-P is S. I, no contrapositive. E, contrapositve I: No S is P; Some not-P is S. O, contrapositive I: Some S is not P; Some not-P is S. In Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition we have found certain variations in the forms in which a given thought content can be expressed. Such varia- tions in the form of expression help to make clearer just what the content of the judgment really is. In these processes the changes in the form of expression are due to a change in the order of subject and predi- 6 Some logicians add a second obversion. See Hibben, Logic. VERIFICATION AND DEDUCTION cate or a change in the quality of predicate and copula s or both. EXERCISES 1. Give contrary, contradictory, and subaltern of each of the propositions in Exercises " 5," pages 62-65 ; where it is not possible to give all, state the reason why. 2. Classify the subjoined propositions into the four fol- lowing groups: 1. Those which can be inferred from (1). 2. Those from which (1) can be inferred. 3. Those which do not contradict (1) but cannot be inferred from it. 4. Those which contradict (1). (1) All just acts are expedient acts.- (2) No expedient acts are unjust. (3) No just acts are inexpedient. (4-) All inexpedient acts are unjust. (5) Some unjust acts are inexpedient. (6) No expedient acts are just. (7) Some inexpedient acts are unjust. (8) All expedient acts are just. (9) No inexpedient acts are unjust. (10) All unjust acts are inexpedient. (11) Some inexpedient acts are just acts. (12) Some expedient acts are just. (13) Some just acts are expedient. (14) Some unjust acts are expedient. (Jevons.) 3. Give the converse, the obverse, and the contrapositive of each of the following propositions : (1) All who were present were unprepared. (2) No wise man would undertake such a task. (3) Not to make the attempt is to confess yourself a coward. (4) Charity begins at home. (5) No statesman could have stooped to such a deed. (6) Only a fanatic believes in panaceas. (7) Discontent is frequently a symptom o ineffi- ciency. EXERCISES 125 (8) A revolution is a surgical operation which self- appointed healers of social diseases are very ready to recommend as a preliminary to every cure. (9) Uneasy rests the head which wears a crown. (10) All organic substances contain carbon. (11) Better late than never. (12) Not many of the metals are lighter than water. 4. State the relation of each of the following proposi- tions to the succeeding one: (1) All the metals are elements. (2) No metals are non-elements. (3) No non-elements are metals. (4) All non-elements are not-metals. (5) All metals are elements. (6) Some elements are metals. (7) Some metals are elements. (8) No metals are elements. (Hyslop.) CHAPTER VIII* THE SYLLOGISM The Principles of Syllogistic Reasoning. Let us re- turn to the examination of the syllogism. Every com- plete syllogism contains three propositions and only three. They are a major premise, a minor premise and a conclusion. In the syllogism, " All men are mortal ; Socrates is a man; therefore Socrates is mortal," the first proposition is the major premise, the second is the minor premise, and the third is, of course, the conclu- sion. The major premise is the broad foundation on which the reasoning rests. It is a universal proposi- tion in syllogisms of this form. It may be either affirm- ative or negative. Thus we may have, " No men are immortal ; Socrates is a man ; therefore Socrates is not immortal." The major premise asserts that the whole of a certain class is included in another class or excluded from it, or it assigns a certain predicate to the whole of a certain subject. 1 The minor premise asserts that certain things are included in the first class; and the conclusion applies to these things the assertion which was made about the first class. *This chapter may be omitted. The traditional treatment is given in chap. ix. iWe have seen that all propositions may be regarded as stat- ing a relation between classes, and that this way of regarding them is most useful and convenient. But other types of rela- tions between subject and predicate exist and should not be forgotten. 126 THE FIRST FIGURE Behind this reasoning lies the principle called the Dictum de Omni et Nullo; i. e., " Whatever state- ment may be made with regard to a class taken gen- erally may be made of each and every member of that class" or " Whatever is true of each of the members of a class will be true of everything found to be a member of that class." The application of this principle in the two syllo- gisms employed for illustration is perhaps obvious, but it may be well to represent the relation of the various terms graphically. For this purpose Euler's diagrams are valuable. The class men is first included in the class mortal; the individual Socrates is then included in the class men and must in consequence be included in the class mortal. In the second case men is excluded from im- mortal and hence Socrates, who is included in men, will necessarily be excluded from immortal. It will readily be seen that (1) the minor premise in a syllogism of this sort cannot be negative. A nega- tive minor premise would assert that something did not belong to the class indicated by the subject of the major premise, and would give no ground for a further con- clusion. The fact that something is true of a whole class of objects does not tell us whether it will or will 128 THE SYLLOGISM not be true of some things not included in that class. Thus the premises, " All men are rational beings ; monkeys are not men," do not warrant the conclusion that monkeys are not rational. 2 Other conclusions are possible and we could not prove this one without using information not contained in our premises. If we tried to prove it by those premises alone, our reasoning would be invalid. An invalid syllogism is one in which the conclusion is not proved or made necessary by the premises. The conclusion may be true, but the func- tion of the syllogism is to furnish a conclusion which must be true if the premises are true. Reasoning which does not prove the conclusion is fallacious, or in other words, it contains a fallacy. We have seen that the minor premise in a syllogism of this form cannot be negative. It will be obvious that () if the major premise be affirmative the conclusion must be affirmative and that if the premise be negative the conclusion must be negative. If we affirm something of a whole class we cannot deny it of a part of the 2 These diagrams may be employed in illustrating the later rules also. THE SECOND FIGURE class, and if we deny it of the whole class we cannot assert it of a part. It is true also that (3) the major premise cannot be particular. If we have the premises, " Some animals can be domesticated ; the wolf is an animal," we are obviously not justified in concluding that the wolf can be domesticated. And again (4) if the minor premise be particular, the conclusion cannot be universal; it must be particular too. From the premises, " All works of art are valu- able; some of the objects in this collection are works of art," we cannot conclude that all the objects in this collection are valuable. In no case can our conclusion contain more than was contained in the premises. Syllogistic Proof. In examining syllogistic reason- ing the first question is not " Is the conclusion true? " but " Does the conclusion follow necessarily from the premises? " If the syllogism of this form correctly applies the Dictum de Omni et Nullo the reasoning is valid. A syllogism of this form is said to be in the First Figure, and this is the only form of syllogism which can be used to prove a universal affirmative prop- osition. A Second Type of Syllogism. There are sev- eral other varieties of syllogisms, each having certain special principles of its own. The one next to be dis- cussed is used to prove that two facts or groups of facts are not the same ; it proves negative conclusions and only those. Its Principle is this: if one of two things is included in a class from which the other is excluded, 3 these things are excluded from each other. To illustrate : " Every college-bred man has read that s Or if one has a predicate which the other lacks. 130 THE SYLLOGISM book; this man has not read the book; therefore, this man is not college-bred." The fact that two subjects are included in the same class or that they possess the same predicate does not, on the other hand, prove that they are the same or that they are related in any other way. They might be even identical, it is true, but in the conclusion of a syllogism we are entitled to include only what must be. Special rules. In this sort of syllogism (1) no con- clusion can be drawn -from two affirmative premises. Either of the premises may be negative and one of them must be. In the illustration given above, the minor premise was negative. We might have " No col- lege man would do this deed; this man has done it; therefore, he is not a college man." On the other hand (2), both premises can not be negative; only one may be negative. If two things both lack the same predicate that fact alone does not warrant any further statement. " No Indians are Cau- casians " and " No Chinamen are Caucasians " does not furnish any basis for a statement concerning the rela- tion between Indians and Chinamen. (3) The major premise in a syllogism of this sort must be universal. If our major premise were " Some college men are informed upon this subject," it would be possible that some were not, and the fact that a given man was ignorant of it would not prove that he was not a college man. (4) The minor premise may be either universal or particular; if it is particular, the conclusion must be particular; if it is universal, the conclusion may be uni- versal. It is obvious that if we make a statement about only a part of the class for which the subject of the MAJOR AND MINOR PREMISES 131 minor premise stands, we cannot make a statement about the whole of it in the conclusion. In every syllo- gism, the information contained in the conclusion must be furnished in the premises. Major and Minor Premises. It is not always easy to know immediately which is the major premise in a syllogism of this form. There is, however, a rule which can be applied to all syllogisms. The major premise is the one which contains the major term. The major term is the predicate of the conclusion. In an affirm- ative conclusion the subject may be regarded as con- tained in the predicate. In the proposition, " All triangles are geometrical figures," the class triangle is included in the class geometrical figures. The latter term is the major because it stands for the wider class. In negative propositions, the predicate is not neces- sarily wider ; in the proposition, " No conic sections are triangles," the predicate is not wider than the subject. Still, for the sake of uniformity, the predicate of the conclusion is always called the major term. The syllo- gism first discussed is a syllogism in the First Figure and the other is in the Second Figure. The Third Figure. In the next type of syllogism, the subject is the same in both premises, but the predi- cates are different, or in other words, the subject is related by inclusion or exclusion to one -class in the major premise and to another in the minor premise. The Principles of the Figure might be stated as follows : 1. // a class (or individual) is included in each of two other*classes those classes include I -T T- each other, at least in part. All X is Y and I all X is Z ; therefore, some Z is Y. 2. // a class (or individual) is excluded from a 132 THE SYLLOGISM second class and included in a third, then a flr ^ at l eas t> f the third is excluded from the second. No X is Y and all X is Z ; therefore, some Z is not Y. 4 In some cases a conclusion is possible if only a part of the subject is described in one of the premises. Some of the special rules which follow state the condi- tions in which this is true. (1) One of the premises must be universal. For example, " No precious metals are soluble in sulphuric acid; some precious metals are soluble in nitric acid; therefore, some things soluble in nitric acid are not soluble in sulphuric acid." If the first makes an assertion about only a part of the class and the second likewise, we can not be certain that the two parts are the same and thus we learn nothing about the relation of their predicates. Thus, " Some triangles are scalene " and " Some triangles are right-angled " are premises which warrant no conclusion regarding the relation of scalene to right-angled figures. (2) The major premise in this Figure may be either affirmative or negative. The conclusion will have the same quality as the major premise. If " No A is B," and " Some (or all) A is C," then " Some C is not B " ; or if " All A is B," and " Some A is C," then " Some C is B." (3) The minor premise can not be negative. If " All deer are herbivorous," and '"' No deer are hollow-horned ani- mals," we cannot conclude that " No hollow-horned animals are herbivorous." (4) The conclusion of a syl- logism in the Third Figure is, in all cases, particular. From " All men are mammals " and*" All men are bi- 4 The student should test each of the special rules by the use of such diagrams. THE FOURTH FIGURE 133 peds " we can not conclude that " All bipeds are mam- mals." The fact that some or all of a certain class are included in another class or possess a given predicate (the minor premise asserts this) does give us infor- mation about a part of that predicate, but not about the whole (it does not distribute the predicate) ; as that predicate becomes the subject of the conclusion, the conclusion must be a particular proposition. The Fourth Figure. "The three figures already dis- cussed were described by Aristotle. The fourth is the invention of later logicians and is usually regarded as much less important than any of the others. In it the minor premise states something about the predicate of the major premise, and the conclusion in turn states something about the conclusion of the minor premise. Thus, " All great poems are the products of genius ; all the products of genius are inimitable ; therefore, some inimitable things are great poems." (If the conclu- sion were, " Great poems are inimitable," we should have a syllogism of the First Figure, and " All the products of genius, etc.," would be the major premise). The Principles of this Figure are: 1. // a class is included in a second class and this in turn is included in a third, then the third will be partly coextensive with the first. All X is Y All Y is Z Some Z is X . If a class is excluded from a second and the lat- ter is included in a third, then a part, at least, of the third will be excluded from the -first. 134 THE SYLLOGISM No Y is X All X is Z Some Z is not Y 3. If a class is included in a second and the latter is excluded from a third, then the third will be excluded from the first. All X is Y No Y is Z No Z is X In the illustration we have used it is obvious that we can not conclude that " All inimitable things are great poems." Our minor premise has not given us any in- formation about the whole of the class, " inimitable things," so we can not have a universal conclusion in this instance. If our syllogism were, " All great poems are the products of genius; some products of genius are inimitable," it would be impossible to draw a con- clusion. Poems might not happen to belong to the things included in the minor premise. The result would be similar if the minor premise were " Some products of genius are not inimitable." If the minor premise were, " No products of genius are inimitable," we could of course conclude that no inimitable things were poems. We can formulate this rule: (1) // the major premise be affirmative the minor premise must be universal. In all these instances, the major premise was the same and it was universal. Suppose we had " Some great poems THE FOURTH FIGURE 135 were the products of genius." It will be seen that the minor premise, " All works of genius, etc.," will give a valid conclusion, but that none of the others will. () // the major premise be affirmative and particular, the minor premise must be universal and affirmative. With the minor premise " No products of genius are inimitable," no conclusion can be drawn; since only some great poems have been included in works of genius, it may well be that some inimitable things may be found among those not so included. (3) The major premise may be negative. " No great statesmen are selfish politicians ; some (or all) selfish politicians amass great fortunes ; therefore, some persons who amass great fortunes are not great statesmen." Some such persons might be great statesmen, so far as our pre- mises are concerned; hence we have no right to con- clude that no persons who amassed great fortunes were great statesmen. EXERCISES State the Figure and point out the errors in reasoning in the following syllogisms: (1) All wisdom is desirable, but a knowledge of slang is not wisdom, and is, therefore, not desirable. (2) Logic and mathematics furnish good mental training, and consequently the latter may be regarded as a branch of the former. (3) Some athletes are susceptible to pneumonia, and as all these men are athletes some of them must be susceptible to pneumonia. (4) Some industrious people are also bright, for there are both bright and industrious students in that group. 136 THE SYLLOGISM (5) Some statues are very lifelike, and no lifelike things are contrary to the laws of nature; hence, nothing contrary to -';he laws of nature is a statue. (6) Some gymnastic exercises are good for increasing strength, but swimming is not, and hence is not a gymnastic exercise. (7) All Democrats voted against the bill, and as most of our Congressmen are Democrats, they must all have voted against the bill. (8) All M is P; No M is S; /.No S is P. (9) Europeans cannot endure that climate; neither can Americans; hence, Americans may be re- garded as a species of European. (10) All ballads are interesting, and some interest- ing things are very old; hence, some very old things are ballads. (11) All text-books are to be had at this store, but some novels are not to be had here, which proves that novels are not text-books. For further examples see page 150 and page 177f. CHAPTER IX TRADITIONAL TREATMENT OF THE SYLLO- GISM THE traditional treatment of the syllogism is sim- ple though very formal. The syllogism is regarded as a form of reasoning in which each of two terms is compared with a third and as a result the two terms are found to be related to each other. Each of the two is compared with the third in a premise. The re- sult of the comparison is stated in the conclusion. is P) > Premises. () is M) ' () is P Conclusion. P and S are found to stand in certain relations to M. In this case and in many others we are justified in as- serting a relation between S and P : S and P are found to be related through M as a medium. For this rea- son M is called the Middle Term and the syllogism is said to embody Mediate Reasoning. The validity of the reasoning is tested by the appli- cation of a number of rules. These rules have to do with the relation and distribution of the several terms in the syllogism. They are as follows: 1. Every syllogism contains three propositions and only three. 2. Every syllogism has three terms and only three. (If any term is ambiguous this rule is violated.) 137 138 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM 3. The middle term must be distributed at least once. 4. No term may be distributed in the conclusion which was not distributed in one of the premises. 5. From two negative premises nothing can be in- ferred. 6. If one premise be negative, the conclusion must be negative ; if both premises be affirmative, the con- clusion must be affirmative. 7. From two particular premises no conclusion can be drawn. 8. If one premise be particular, the conclusion must be particular. Let us examine these rules in the order given. 1. With more than three propositions, we should have more than a syllogism, though our reasoning might be valid. 2. The violation of rule two gives rise to the Fallacy of Four Terms. Unless two of the terms are confused this fallacy is not likely to arise. No one would try to draw a conclusion from the propositions, " Socrates was a philosopher," and " The earth revolves about the sun." But one might be tempted to draw a conclusion from the premises, " Steel is made from iron ; iron is dug from the ground." Still, it would be wrong to con- clude that steel is dug from the ground. The terms here are, " steel," " (something) made from iron," "iron," and " (something) dug from the ground." 3. The violation of rule three gives rise to the Fal- lacy of Undistributed Middle. Thus, the premises, " Some men are brave ; and some men are strong," do not prove anything ; nor do these : " All brave men THE UNDISTRIBUTED MIDDLE 139 should be respected; and, all just men should be re- spected." Let us represent the middle term by M, the minor term (subject of the conclusion) by S, and the major term (predicate of conclusion) by P. We are not jus- tified by the premises in making any statement about the relation of S and P, for they may be wholly or partially identical or they may be mutually exclusive. But if the middle term were distributed we might be able to draw a conclusion. If all M is P and all S is M, we may conclude that all S is P. Or if no M is P and all S is M, then no S is P. An invalid syllogism is one in which it is not possible to determine fully the relation of the circles to each other, since there are conflicting possibilities. In the case of Undistributed Middle cited above, all, some, or none of S may be included in P. 140 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM In valid syllogisms there may sometimes be a margin of indefiniteness (owing to the indefinite character of the "particular" propositions), but a certain amount of definite information regarding the relation of S and P is always given and the relation of the circles sym- bolizing major and minor terms is not left wholly in doubt. The reason for the rule requiring the distribution of the middle term may be stated in this way: If each of two things is related to a part of a third, we can not conclude that they are related to each other, for they may not be related to the same part; but if one (or both) is related to the whole of the third, then it may be possible to assert a relation between the two. Thus : All M is P No M is P All P is M All S is M All S is M All S is M All S is P No S is P No conclusion. and so on Some M is P All S is M No conclusion. 4. The reason for rule four is obvious: if we know something about only part of a class in the premise, ILLICIT MAJOR AND MINOR we can not say something about all of it in the con- clusion. The violation of this rule gives rise to two fallacies : the Illicit Process of the Major Term and the Illicit Process, of the Minor Term. In the syllogism, " All men (M) are vertebrates (P) ; all men (M) are rational (S) ; therefore, all rational beings (S) are vertebrates (P)," we have an illustration of the Illicit Process of the Minor Term, or Illicit Minor, as it is usually called. In the syllogism, " All Chinamen (M) are Mongolians (P) ; no Japanese (S) are Chinamen (M) ; therefore no Japanese (S) are Mongolians (P)," the Illicit Process of the Major Term occurs. Using the circles, we have for the first ; and for the second: The dotted lines indicate possible boundaries of S. The premises do not justify us in including all of S within the circle P in the first, nor of excluding all P from the circle S in the second. S may be outside of M, but still be wholly or partially within P. 5. With two negative premises, both major and TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM minor terms are excluded from the middle term, but that does not tell us whether they are or are not ex- cluded from each other. 6. With one negative premise, either major or minor term is excluded from the middle term, while the other is not; therefore, if any relation can be asserted be- tween major and minor terms, it must be one of ex- clusion. 7-8. The reasons for the two last rules can be more easily understood after we have considered the Moods and Figures of the syllogism. It will then be seen that the violation of these rules means a violation of rule three or rule four or both. The Figure of a syllogism is determined by the posi- tions of the middle term. 1 The Four Figures are as follows: 1. M is P 2. P is M 3. M is P 4. P is M S is M S is M M is S M is S .'.S is P /.S is P /.S is P /.S is P In the First Figure, the Middle Term is the subject of the Major Premise and the predicate of the Minor Premise. In the Second Figure it is the predicate of each. In the Third Figure it is the subject of each. In the Fourth Figure it is the predicate of the Major Premise and the subject of the Minor Premise. The position of the Middle Term in the Third Figure 1 We have already seen that the Figures differ in other ways, but the traditional mode of distinguishing them is the one just mentioned. THE MOODS OF THE SYLLOGISM is the opposite of that which it occupies in the Second ; and in the Fourth it is the opposite of that in the First. The Mood of a syllogism is determined by the quan- tity and quality of the several propositions which it contains. Propositions, as we have seen, are of four kinds with respect to quantity and quality, and are represented by the four letters, A, E, I, and O. The letters AAA would symbolize a syllogism in which each proposition was a universal affirmative. There are sixty- four possible moods : AAA AT? A ATA AHA "F A A T?T? A T?T A TO A Xi.XXjfjL Xl.,l_fXX 3TX -L-TX 'Xi.x-/ZTC ^EjiTCTTC i_!7A-7i"3T J-VX'XTT "iJ7\^/XX -AAE- AEE AIB AGE EAE EEE -EIE EGE- AAI AM- AH -AGt -EAI- -EEJ- -EH- -EGI- AAG AEG -AJO- AGO EAO EEG EIO EGG .IAA -IEA- KA -IGA- -GAA GEA GIA GGA T A T> TT^T^ TTT? TQT^ f\ A T? Q'PT? r>TT? QQT? ~Xi"3r 7 "tL J^J^* "A A "J JT* "A V-/A-J" "\_/"TA^ >V "Vi/ J ^"i-? v^XX-/ vZ/VAE7 TAT TT?T TTT TOT. O AT QT?T QTT HOT. JLXxJ. "J. JJvx" JLJLi ' ivyi" 1 "\_/Xi.A" "V^ J-V"3T "Vy i Jtr \y Vx jr ^AG- (IEO)-G- iGG- GAG GEG GIG GGG Many of these are at once seen to be invalid : thus, ap- plying the rules for negative and particular premises, we can eliminate those moods through which a line is drawn. The mood IEO does not violate any of those rules, but examination will show that it will give a fal- lacy of Illicit Major in each of the Figures. The con- clusion is negative and hence distributes its predicate, the major term. The major premise is an I proposi- tion and hence distributes neither of its terms ; there- 144 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM fore, the major term can not be distributed in the premise, and hence this mood may be eliminated also. There remain only eleven moods which may be valid, but many of those are invalid in some of the figures. We will examine each of these moods in each of the figures. 2 In the First Figure we should have the following re- sults : A. A. A. - P A. @-P I. S - P E. E. x E. x(P) A. (S)- M A. (S)-M E. x O. S x It is evident that the following are invalid in the First Figure: AEE, AEO, AOO, IAI, and OAO. IAI and OAO are invalid because of an Undistributed Middle, the others because of Illicit Majors. The valid moods are AAA, AAI, AH, EAE, EAO, and EIO. AAI and EAO are necessarily valid since AAA and EAE are valid. I and O are called weakened conclusions because they are less general than they 2 To facilitate dealing with them we shall employ the symbols used in the exposition of Conversion and Obversion. THE SECOND FIGURE 145 might be. A comparison of these moods will show that two general statements may be made regarding reason- ing in this figure : 1. The Major premise must be universal. %. The minor premise must be affirmative, Examination of the illustrations given in the pre- vious discussion of this Figure (page 127) will show that every syllogism which violated either of these two rules failed to give a valid conclusion. In the Second Figure the results are different : A. - M O. S x O. Sx(P) A. - M E. x E. x E. x A. - M E. (S)x(P) A.- M E. x O. Sx E. x A. - M O. Sx Here the moods, AAA, AAI, AH, IAI, and OAO are invalid, the last because of Illicit Major, the others be- cause of Undistributed Middle. The valid moods are AEE, AEO, AGO, EAE, EAO, and EIO. O is a weakened conclusion in AEO and EAO. Here we find that in the Second Figure; 146 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM 1. The major premise must be universal. 2. One prem- ise must be negative and the conclusion likewise must be negative. These rules, like those of the First Figure, might have been formulated on the basis of the typical cases presented in the earlier discussion. (See p. 130.) Again in the Third Figure : A. @-P I. M-S I. S - P E. x(g I. M -S O. Sx E. x(P) A. -S O. Sx(P) I. M -P A. -S I. S - P O. Mx(P) A. @-S O. Sx(|) In this case the invalid moods are AAA, AEE, AEO, AOO, EAE. Of these, AAA and EAE are cases of Illicit Minor; and the rest, of Illicit Majors. The valid moods here are AAI, AH, EAO, EIO, IAI, and OAO. In the Third Figure: 1. The conclusion must be particular. 2. The minor premise must be affirmative. In this case, as in the others, the rules might have been discovered, without consideration of the moods, by a direct examination of cases. THE FOURTH FIGURE In the Fourth Figure we have: A. (P)-M A. @-S I. S - P A. (P)-M E. x(S) o. sx E. x(g A - S. O. SxfP) Here the invalid moods are AAA, AH, AGO, EAE, and OAO. AAA and EAE give Illicit Minor, AH and AGO give Undistributed Middle, and OAO gives Illicit Ma- jor. The valid moods are AAI, AEE, AEO, EIO, IAL We get these rules for the Fourth Figure : 1. If the major premise be affirmative, the minor premise must be universal. 2. If the major premise be also particular, the minor premise must be affirmative. 3. // the minor premise be affirmative, the conclusion must be particular. 4. // either premise be negative, the major must be universal. 5. The conclusion may not be a universal affirmative proposition. 148 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM Comparison of all the valid moods shows that the mood AAA is valid in the First Figure only. As this is the only mood in which A appears as a valid con- clusion, it will be evident that a universal affirmative conclusion can be proved in the First Figure only. REDUCTION OF THE MOODS AND FIGURES. The Medieval schoolmen invented a set of menemonic verses to serve as an aid to the memory in recalling the valid modes in the several Figures. The verses consisted of barbarous Latin terms. The words contain also letters for guidance in reduction of the other Figures into the First. These verses, with their interpretation, are as follows: Barbara, Celarent, Dam, Fenoque prioris; Cesare, Camestres Festino, Baroko secundae; Tertia, Darapti, Disarms, Datisi, Felapton, Bokardo, Fm'son, habet, quarta insuper addit Bramanttp, Camenes; Dimaris, Fesapo, Fresison. The moods are indicated by the italicised letters. All the valid moods are included except those in which there are so- called weakened conclusions, i. e., cases in which a particular conclusion is drawn, though a universal would be valid, such as AAI or EAO in the First Figure. The first line indicates the moods of the First Figure, the second line, of the Second, the third and the first half of the fourth indicate those of the Third Figure, and the last line, those of the Fourth Figure. The First Figure was regarded as the Perfect Figure, and the others were transformed into it by making certain changes in their various members. This process was called the Reduction of the Imperfect Figures. These words contain letters which stand for the changes which must be made. The capital letters in the last four lines indicate the mood of the First Figure to which the mood, indicated by the word in which they are found, may be reduced. Thus Cesare may be reduced to Celarent. p indicates that the preceding proposition is to be converted per accidens or by limitation; s indicates that the preceding proposition is to be converted simply, and m indicates that the premises are to be transposed. CAMESTRES CELARENT AH A is C C is not B (All stars are suns) (No suns are planets) No B is C All A is C (No planets are suns) (All stars are suns) Therefore, B is not A Therefore, no A is B. (No planets are stars) (No stars are planets) REDUCTION OF THE FIGURES 149 The minor premise in Camestres is first converted, then the two premises are transposed, and finally the conclusion is con- verted. To reduce Cesare to Celarent we need only convert the major premise. As a second example we may take the reduction of Bramantip to Barbara. BRAMANTIP BARBARA All C is B All B is A All B is A All C is B Some A is C All C is A In this case, the premises are transposed, and the conclusion is converted. This would give AAI. But the conclusion A would be valid from these premises. The p in this case may be taken as indicating that, instead of a conclusion less in quantity than the original proposition, we may have one which is greater in quantity, namely, universal. There is one more significant letter in these words, the letter k. It indicates that the reduction must be made by indirect means. Take, for example, Bokardo which reduces to Bar- bara. BOKARDO BARBARA Some A is not C All B is C All A is B All A is B Therefore, some B is not C Therefore, all A is C In this case the major premise of Bokardo is the contradictory of the conclusion of Barbara; and the conclusion of Bokardo is the contradictory of the major premise of Barbara. Suppose the conclusion of Bokardo to be false ; then its contradictory, " All B is C," will be true; taking this as the major premise of a new syllogism and the proposition, " all A is B," as the minor pre- mise, the conclusion will be the contradictory of the major premise of Bokardo and the new syllogism will be in the mood Barbara. Bokardo may be also be reduced to Darii. First obvert, then con- vert, the major premise; transposing the two premises, we then have Darii. All this mechanism is entirely unscientific and its interest is purely historical. EXERCISES ON THE SYLLOGISM 1. What kinds of propositions are incapable of proof in the Second, Third and Fourth Figures respectively? Give the reasons for your reply. 2. If either premise of a syllogism is O, what must the other be? 3. With I as the major premise, what must the minor premise be? 150 TREATMENT OF THE SYLLOGISM 4. Show that an E proposition is highly efficient as a major premise. (J.) s 5. Show that O is seldom admissible as a minor premise. (j.) 6. Prove that there must always be in the premises one more distributed term than in the conclusion. (J.) 7. Prove from the general rules of the syllogism, that when the major term is the predicate in its premise, the minor premise must be affirmative. (J.) 8. Point out which of the following pairs of premises will give a syllogistic conclusion, and name the obstacle which exists in other cases. (1) No A is B; some B is not C. (2) No A is B; some not C is B. (3) All B is not A; some not A is B. (4) Some not A is B; no C is B. (5) All not B is C; some not A is B. (6) All A is B; all not C is B. (7) All not B is not C; all not A is not B. (8) All A is not B; no B is C. (9) All C is not B ; no A is not B. 3 (J) refers to Jevons, Studies in Deductive Logic, where a great many more questions of this character may be found The following exercise is from the same source. CHAPTER X ABBREVIATED AND COMPLEX FORMS OF REASONING - - HYPOTHETICAL AND DISJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS The Enthymeme. Usually our reasoning does not fall into the form of a perfect syllogism. In the first place it very often happens that one or another of the propositions is omitted. For example, " This object can be magnetized, for it is made of iron," omits the major premise, " All things made of iron can be mag- netized." Again, in " Every member of the jury voted for acquittal, therefore X voted for acquittal," the minor premise, " X was a member of the jury," is omitted. In " All metals are elements ; this is a metal," the conclusion is omitted. Syllogisms from which one proposition is missing are called Enthymemes. The missing premise can usually be found without difficulty. The two propositions which are given contain the three terms of the syllogism ; one of these will be common to the two propositions, and the missing proposition will contain the other two terms. Thus with the proposition, " S is M ; hence, S is P," the missing premise is clearly " M is P," or " P is M." With " M is P ; therefore, S is P," the missing premise will contain S and M. The danger of false reasoning is greater here than in the complete syllogism, since the proposition which is not expressed may be false or inadequate, and if the 151 152 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS proposition is not definitely stated its inadequacy is easily overlooked. The Enthymeme is an incomplete form of syllogistic reasoning ; it is less than a syllogism. There are several complex forms in which we find more than a syllogism. PROSYLLOGISM AND EPISYLLOGISM. Two complete syllogisms may be united by having a proposition in common. Thus : r All the Romance languages are derived from Prosyllogism J v Latl , n; . rrench is a Romance language; ^-Therefore, French is derived from Latin, f This man speaks French; Episyllogism J Therefore, this man speaks a language de- { rived from Latin. In this example the conclusion of the first syllogism is the major premise of the second. This is known as Prosyllogism and Episyllogism, the conclusion of the Prosyllogism being the major premise of the Episyllo- gism. One syllogism might, of course, establish the minor premise of the other: f French is a Romance language; J This man speaks French. 1 ] Therefore, this man speaks a Romance larr- [ guage. f All the Romance languages are derived from Episyllogism J rr Latin ; i . I Hence, this man speaks a language derived [ from Latin, Again, it might have each of its premises established by another syllogism: PROSYLLOGISM AND EPISYLLOGISM 153 Everything which is able to restrain trade is a source of danger; Prosyllogism ^ Every monopoly is able to restrain trade; Hence, every monopoly is a source of danger. A company which has complete control of a certain commodity is a monopoly; Prosyllogism^ This trust has complete control of a cer- tain commodity; Hence, this trust is a monopoly. Conclusion: Therefore, this trust is a source of danger. An enthymeme might take the place of the complete syllogism in the case of either or both of the prosyllo- gisms. Further, the premises of the prosyllogisms might themselves be supported by other syllogisms. A great many syllogisms may be combined into one reasoning process, and most reasoning processes con- tain several syllogisms, complete or abbreviated. 1 i Geometrical reasoning illustrates abbreviated reasoning very clearly. For example take the proof of the proposition that " All straight angles are equal." A S B D I F "Let the angles ACB and DEF be any two straight angles. To prove that the angle ACB equals the angle DEF. " Place the angle ACB on the angle DEF, so that the vertex C shall fall on the vertex E, and the side CB on the side EF. Then CA will fall on ED. Therefore the angle ACB equals the angle DEF." (Wentworth, Plane Geometry, page 14.) This is the proof in an abbreviated form. It might be more fully expressed as follows: (See page 154.) 154 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS We might have a chain of syllogisms in which the conclusion of each was the minor premise of the one following. All ungulates are mammals. All mammals are warm-blooded. All ungulates are warm-blooded. All warm-blooded animals have lungs. All ungulates are warm-blooded animals. All ungulates have lungs. All animals that have lungs require air. All ungulates have lungs. All ungulates require air. " What is true of the angles ACB and DEF will be true of all straight angles. Two angles which can be so placed upon each other that their vertices coincide and their sides coincide are equal, each with the other. ( Any figure may be moved from one place to another ) without altering its shape. (Axiom of superposi- j tion.) Therefore, the figure ACB may be placed upon the figure DEF without altering its shape. Straight angles are such as have their sides ex- tending in opposite directions so as to be in the same straight line. Th'e angles ACB and DEF have their sides so extending. Hence the lines AB and EF are straight lines. Two straight lines which have two points in common coincide and and form but one line. When the figure ACB is super- posed on the figure DEF so that the vertex C shall fall on the ver- tex E, and the side CB on the side EF, the straight line AB falls on the straight line DF and they coincide; the line CA falls on the line ED, and coincides with it, CB coincides with EF, [And C coincides with E]. |^ Therefore the angle ACB and the angle DEF are equal. Therefore all straight angles are equal. Geometrical reasoning is not all syllogistic in the narrowest sense of the word. See chapter xvii. THE SORITES 155 THE SORITES. Now, instead of putting the conclu- sion in words and repeating it in the succeeding propo- sition, we may omit everything except the new premises until we are ready to draw the final conclusion. Thus : All ungulates are mammals. A is B All mammals are warm-blooded. B is C All warm-blooded animals have lungs. C is D All animals that have lungs require air. D is E Hence, All ungulates require air. A is E. This is known as the Sorites; a Sorites may have any number of members. There are two forms. That given above, is an example of the Progressive or Aristotelian Sorites. The premise containing the subject of the conclusion (the Final Minor) comes first in order; that containing its predicate (The Prime Major) comes last; the intermediate propositions serve to connect the two. In the Regressive or Goclenian Sorites, the Prime Major comes first and the Final Minor last among the premises. If expanded into a chain of prosyllogisms and episyllogisms, the conclusion of each syllogism would be the major premise of the one following. For example : A European is a Caucasian. B is A A Frenchman is a European. C is B A Parisian is a Frenchman. D is C This author is a Parisian. E is D Hence, This author is a Caucasian. E is A In both forms of the sorites the reasoning is in the first figure of the syllogism. With the exception of the terms which are contained in the conclusion, every term in the sorites is a middle term. The greatest source of danger in this form of reasoning is to be found in ambiguous terms. 156 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS Only the Final Minor premise may be particular; only the Prime Major may be negative. Hypothetical Reasoning. The forms of reasoning with which we have been dealing in the last three chap- ters have employed only declarative sentences, or Cate- gorical Propositions, as they are called in Logic. A categorical proposition is an unconditional statement. " A is B " or " A is not B " are typical forms. But there are other kinds of propositions ; one of these is the Hypothetical Proposition. A hypothetical prop- osition is one containing a categorical proposition and the statement of a condition on which the truth of the categorical depends. The conditional member of the proposition is .called the Antecedent; the categorical member is called the Consequent. A hypothetical propo- sition may be made the major premise of a syllogism. Such a syllogism would be a HYPOTHETICAL SYLLO- GISM. The Hypothetical syllogism has four forms. 1. If A is B, C is D. If the substance is carbon, it will burn. A is B It is carbon. .*. C is D .'.It will burn. 2. If A is B, C is D. If the substance is carbon, it will burn. A is not B It is not carbon. .*. C is not D .'.It will not burn. 3. If A is B, C is D. If the substance is carbon, it will burn. C is D It will burn. .'.A is B .'.It is carbon. 4. If A is B, C is D. If the substance is carbon, it will burn. C is not D It will irot burn. .'.A is not B .".It is not carbon. THE HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISM 157 The first of these affirms the antecedent, the second denies it; the third affirms the consequent, and the fourth denies it. The second and third are obviously invalid. The fact that the substance is not carbon gives us no further information about qualities ; and the fact that it will burn does not insure its being carbon. These instances are typical and illustrate the general rule that Denying the antecedent or affirming the conse- quent in a hypothetical syllogism are invalid forms of reasoning. 2 We may have a hypothetical syllogism in which the minor premise is also a hypothetical proposition. If A is B, C is D. If he is nominated, he will be elected. If C is D, E is F. If he is elected, this measure will not pass. .'.If A is B, E is F. .'.If he is nominated, this meas- ure will not pass. Disjunctive Reasoning. There is a third kind of so-called syllogism with still another sort of proposi- tion as its major premise. This is the Disjunctive Syllogism and its major premise is a Disjunctive Prop- osition. A disjunctive proposition is one which states an alternative. " A is either B or C " ; " It will either rain or snow." The minor premise either affirms or 2 There are cases, however, in which these forms give true conclusions. If the antecedent is the only one on which the con- sequent would follow then all the forms of the hypothetical syllo- gism would give valid conclusions. For example, if we had the major premise, " If A is B, and in no other case, C will be D," then to deny that A is B would necessitate the conclusion that C is not D. We may take, as a concrete case, " If a triangle is equilateral, and in no other circumstances, it will be equiangular. This triangle is not equiangular; hence it is not equilateral"; or, " This triangle is equilateral, therefore it is equiangular," and so on. 158 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS denies one of the alternatives. The conclusion either denies or affirms the other. A is either B or C It will either rain or snow. A is B It will rain. /.A is not C .'.It will not snow. A is either B or C It will either rain or snow. A is C It will snow. /.A is not B .".It will not rain. A is either B or C It will either rain or snow. A is rrot B It will not rain. .'.A is C /.It will snow. A is either B or C It will either rain or snow. A is not C It will not snow. ,*.A is B /.It will rain. All these forms are valid. The only source of danger is in the major premise. If the alternatives are not true alternatives, the conclusion can not be trusted. If A can be anything else than B or C, or if it can be both at the same time, the denial or affirmation of one alter- native cannot assure us of the truth or falsity of the others. There are more -complex forms of disjunctive reason- ing ; we might, for example, have the proposition, " A is B or C or D, etc." In this case the affirmation of one would mean the denial of the other two ; but the de- nial of one would give as the conclusion a disjunctive proposition containing the two others as alternatives. Thus " A is not B ; A is either C or D, etc." Similarly the assertion " A is B or C " would give the conclusion " A is not D, etc.," and so on. THE DILEMMA 159 There are certain imperfect forms of this syllogism which are sometimes useful. Sometimes we know that A is B or C or, it may be, both. In such a case, if we know that A is not B, then it must be C, but if we know that it is B, we do not know that it is not also C. With such a major premise, the minor premises which are affirmative do not give valid -conclusions. It would be simpler in such cases to state the three possibilities as mutually exclusive, " A is B or C, or both B and C," and proceed as in the perfect forms of the hypothetical syllogism. More Complex Forms. THE DILEMMA. There are more complex forms of reasoning in which hypothetical and disjunctive propositions are combined. Thus we may have: If A is B, C is D or E (or C is D or E is F). A is B. .'. C is D or E (or C is D or E is F). More concretely : If he fails, he will leave college or drop back a class. But he is sure to fail. .". He will leave college or drop back a class. If the antecedent were denied there could be no valid conclusion ; in this and all other respects this syllogism is like a simple hypothetical syllogism except in having a disjunctive consequent, instead of a categorical one. We get more complicated forms when the major pre- mise consists of two hypothetical propositions, in which either the antecedents or the consequents are found to 160 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS be alternative: the minor premise is a disjunctive proposition, and the resulting syllogism is a Di- lemma. If A is B, C is D; aiid if E is F, C is D. But either A is B or E is F. .'. C is D. If a college education gives a student useful information, it is valuable to him. If it gives him mental training it is valuable to him. But it either gives him useful information or mental training. .'.It is valuable to him. This is a Simple Constructive Dilemma: simple be- cause the consequents of the hypothetical propositions in the major premise are the same in both cases; con- structive because it establishes an affirmative conclu- sion. If the consequents were denied we should not have a dilemma, but two simple hypothetical syllogisms. There would be no disjunctive premise. The second form of the dilemma is the Complex Con- structive Dilemma. In this, the consequents of the hypothetical propositions in the major premise are not the same. If A is B, C is D ; and if E is F, G is H. But either A is B or E is F. .'. Either C is D, or G is H. " If a statesman who sees his former opinions to be wrong does not alter his course he is guilty of deceit; and if he does alter his course he is open to a charge of incon- sistency; but either he does not alter his course or he does; therefore, he is either guilty of deceit, or he is open to a charge of inconsistency." (Jevons, Lessons in Logic, p. 168.) THE DILEMMA 161 Unlike the simple dilemma, this has a disjunctive conclusion. The Complex Destructive Dilemma has a negative minor premise and a negative -conclusion, If A is B, C is D; and if E is F, G is H. But either C is not D or G is not H. .". Either A is not B or E is not F. "If this man were wise, he would not speak irreverently of the Scripture in jest; and if he were good he would not do so in earnest; but he does it either in jest or in earnest; therefore, he is either not wise, or not good. (Whately, Elements of Logic.) If the minor premise were " Neither C is D nor G is H " we should not have a dilemma. The minor premise would not be disjunctive and we should have two simple hypothetical syllogisms. Asserting that one or the other of the antecedents was false, or that one or the other of the consequents was true would be fallacious, as in the case of the simple hypothetical syllogism. In practice it is very difficult to find true major premises for a dilemma. Moreover, " a dilemma can often be retorted by producing as cogent a dilemma to a contrary effect. Thus an Athenian mother, accord- ing to Aristotle, addressed her son in the following words : " Do not enter into public business ; for if you say what is just, men will hate you; and if you say what is unjust, the gods will hate you." To which Aristotle suggests the following retort : " I ought to enter into public affairs ; for if I say what is just, the gods will love me; and if I say what is unjust, men will love me." (Jevons.) 162 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS The conclusion of a dilemma, as of any other form of reasoning, may serve as a premise for further rea- soning. Extra-syllogistic Reasoning. Certain other forms of reasoning call for some discussion here. They are not syllogistic, but they are closely related to syllo- gistic reasoning. For example, " A is taller than B ; B is taller than C ; therefore A is taller than C." This is not a syllogism. There are five terms in the reason- ing; A, B, C, taller than B, and taller than C. There is a similar difficulty in this : " M is east of N ; N is east of O, therefore M is east of O." It would, of course, be possible to construct a syllogism which would cover the ground in each of these -cases. Thus, " What- ever is taller than another thing is taller than every- thing which is shorter than that thing; A, B, and C present a case, etc." And similarly in the other example. Some such principles as these are implied, but the rea- soning as stated is not in the form of a simple syllo- gism. We have here a system of relations which is more complicated than that found in the ordinary syllogism. In the latter we need have only our premises and the ordinary laws of reasoning, to assure our conclusion ; in reasoning of the sort illustrated in these examples we must have, besides our premises, a supply of in- formation about the general system of things to which the data in question belong. When such reasoning is thrown into the syllogistic form the major premise states the main principles of the system, as in the ex- ample above. Sometimes our information about the sys- tem would be sufficient to warrant a conclusion and sometimes it would not; sometimes the fact that two EXTRA-SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 163 things are related to a third gives us information re- garding their relations to each other and sometimes it does not. From the statements that " A is the employer or friend or enemy of B " and that " B is the em- ployer or friend or enemy of C," we could not draw any conclusion with regard to A's direct relations to C. Things equal to the same thing are equal to each other, but it is not necessarily true that things unequal to the same thing will be unequal to each other. In the latter case there are two possibilities ; the system is not clearly enough defined to make certain any con- clusion at all. This was true in some of the illustra- tions given above. To decide in any given case we must first determine whether the set of relations involved is completely enough known to justify a conclusion; in other words, Is more than one conclusion possible? Sometimes the system may be very complex, but its parts may be so related to each other and so -completely known as to make a conclusion possible. A conclusion may simply state the relation of the terms in a reverse order. " A is east of B, therefore B is west of A." The' conclusion may represent a pathway through a system from one particular part to another ; while the premise may be merely the same pathway followed from the other end. If A is the son-in-law of the half-sister of B's grandfather, then B is the grandson of the half- brother of A's mother-in-law. The system might have any degree of complication whatever, but if the several relations could be read from either end the pathway could jpe followed in either direction. Reasoning of this sort might be regarded as a broader form of con- sion. 3 See Aikins, Principles of Logic, chap. xi. 164 HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS EXERCISES. 1. Supply the missing proposition's in the following: (1) He is a politician and therefore not to be trusted. (2) They were all brave men and this man was one of them. (3) Whales have warm blood but fish do not. (4) Only members will be admitted; that excludes you. 2. Determine which of the following give valid conclu- sions and which do not; point out the fallacies involved: (1) If he goes, I shall remain; but he will not go. (2) If he goes, I shall remain; and I shall remain. main. (3) I shall remain if he goes; and he will go. (4) If it rains to-morrow, the game will be post- poned; the game will be postponed. (5) If all the sides of this triangle are equal its angles are equal too; now its angles are not equal. (6) If he fails it will be because he has not worked hard ; and he has not worked hard. 3. Criticise the following, stating the form of reasoning in each case: (1) A great man must either have extraordinary natural ability or exceptional capacity for work; this man had extraordinary natural ability, hence we may assume that his capacity or work was rrot unusual. (2) If the government enacts such a law it must either adopt socialism or go into bankruptcy; but it will not enact such a law; so there is iro danger of either socialism or bankruptcy. (Hyslop.) (3) If capital punishment involves cruelty to its victims it ought to be abolished in favor of some other permlty; if it does no good for so- ciety it should also be abolished. But either it involves cruelty to its victims or it does no EXERCISES 165 good to society, and hence it ought to be abol- ished. (Hyslop.) (4) If he sinks he will be drowned, and if he swims he will be captured by the enemy; but he must either sink or swim; therefore, he will either be drowned or captured by the enemy. (5) If he tells the truth he will be forgiven, and if he does not he will escape detection; but either he will be forgiven or he will escape detection; hence he will either tell the truth or he will not. (6) If he did that intentionally he is not wise, and if he did it unintentionally he is not lucky; but he is neither wise nor lucky; therefore, he did it neither intentionally nor unintention- ally. 4. In a sorites why must all the premises except the prime major be affirmative and all except the final minor be universal? CHAPTER XI I. PROOF AND DISPROOF. II. FAILURE TO PROVE I. Various Kinds of Proof. The conclusion of a valid syllogism is proved; and so also is the conclusion of each of the other forms of reasoning which we have examined. A proposition is proved when it is shown to be the necessary consequence of any combination of admitted propositions. All the cases which we have so .far examined are instances of direct proof. In direct proof we show that, granted certain things, the con- clusion necessarily follows. A conclusion is proved only when it is shown that the conclusion must be true. There are several other kinds of proof ; in this chap- ter we shall consider the other kinds, and also the va- rious forms of failure to prove, or fallacy. INDIRECT PROOF. The first to be considered is indirect proof ; we prove a proposition indirectly by dis- proving its contradictory, i. e., by showing that its con- tradictory cannot be true. To disprove a proposition it is necessary to find some ^admitted fact or truth which is inconsistent with it. Tor instance, if we can show that the contrary or con- tradictory of a proposition is true, the proposition must be false. More concretely, if we have an A propo- sition, the contradictory would be an O proposition ; if we can show that O is true, A is necessarily false, and to show the truth of O we need find only one real ex' 166 INDIRECT PROOF 167 ception to A. Showing the truth of E would also dis- prove A; but E is a universal proposition, and it is obviously much more difficult, in ordinary circum- stances, to prove a universal than it is to prove a par- ticular. Similarly the truth of I or of A would mean the falsity of E, etc. In indirect proof, we disprove the contradictory, not the contrary, for the" falsity of the contrary does not prove the truth of the proposition, since both contraries may be false ; but if the contradictory is false, the prop- osition must be true, for one of two contradictories must be true. Suppose then that we wish to prove an A proposition : if we can show, in any way, that the corresponding O proposition would be false or absurd contrary to fact or reason our thesis is proved. The contradictory is usually disproved by show- ing that some of its necessary consequences are ab- surd. Indirect proof is frequently employed in geometry and it is there that the best examples of it are to be found. It is also a frequent resource in political de- bate, but in that field the facts are so complicated and the matter of establishing any proposition so liable to error chat the grounds of any conclusion established in this way must be very carefully examined. We shall consider briefly two other special forms of proof, which are perhaps reducible to direct proof, but they are apparently very different from what we find in the syllogism and they will therefore be considered separately. The first is found in geometrical reasoning. PROOF IN GEOMETRY. In geometrical proof we seem 168 PROOF AND DISPROOF to be founding a universal conclusion upon a single case ; how is it possible for us to have perfect confidence in a conclusion which seems at first sight to be an in- duction from one isolated figure? If the individual peculiarities of the figure had anything to do with sup- porting the conclusion the latter would of course be of very slight value ; we should have no assurance that the next example might not be inconsistent with the conclusion. The certainty of the conclusion rests upon the fact that the figure used in the demonstration is, in all essential respects, like every other figure to which the proof is supposed to apply. The figure employed is purely symbolical ; it stands for certain universal re- lations. If the truth of the conclusion follows from the characteristics which the present figure has in com- mon with all others of the class, then it will be true for all such figures, and the peculiar characteristics will have nothing to do with the case. The major premise underlying demonstration by means of figures is this: " The present figure is an adequate representative of all figures to which the present proof applies." The second special form of proof which we shall examine is found in what is known as mathematical in- duction. PROOF BY MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. The follow- ing illustration is a typical example of reasoning of the sort just mentioned. " If we take the first two consecu- tive odd numbers, 1 and 3, and add them together the sum is 4, or exactly twice two; if we take three such numbers, 1 + 3 + 5, the sum is 9, or exactly three times three; if we take four, namely 1 + 3 + 5 + 7, the sum is MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 169 16, or exactly four times jour; or generally, if we take any number of the series, l + 3 + 5' + 7 + ...., the sum is equal to the number of terms multiplied by itself. Any one who knows a little algebra can prove that this remarkable law is universally true, as follows : Let n be the number of terms, and assume for the moment that this law is true up to n terms, thus: 1+3+5+7+ ____ +(2n-I)=n 2 Now add 2ft + 1 to each side of the equation. It fol- lows that: 1+3+5+T+ ____ But the last quantity, 7& 2 + 2n + l, is just equal to (n + 1) 2 ; so that if the law is true for n terms it is true also for n + 1 terms. We are enabled to argue from each single case of the law to the next case ; but we have already shown that it is true of the first few cases, therefore it must be true of all." L If what is true of any case is true of the one following it, it will be true of all cases whatsoever. It sometimes happens that some- thing is true of a great many successive cases without being really general. To quote again from Jevons: " It was at one time believed that if any integral num- ber were multiplied by itself, added to itself, and then added to 41, the result would be a prime number, that is, a number which could not be divided by any other integral number except unity ; in symbols, x 2 + x + 41 = prime number. This was believed solely on the ground of trial and experience, and it certainly holds l Jevons, Lessons in Logic, pp. 220-221. 170 PROOF AND DISPROOF for a great many values of x . . . . No reason, how- ever, could be given why it should always be true. . . . it fails when x = 40."' " We can perceive no simi- larity between all prime numbers which assures that be- cause one is represented by a certain formula, also another is ; but we do find such similarity between the sums of odd numbers." Here, as elsewhere, if one or a few cases are adequate representatives of a whole class of cases, what is true of the present case or cases will be true of all, and a universal conclusion can be drawn from a single -case. The great difficulty in ordinary inductions is to be sure that the given case is an adequate representative. Or- dinarily the facts are very complex and the inspection of a single case is not sufficient to show us the charac- teristics which an adequate representative of the class should possess. In other words, we do not know what circumstances are relevant. In selecting cases for the application of the several inductive methods, the selec- tion is for the purpose of enabling us to determine what circumstances are relevant. II. Failure to Prove: Fallacies. Let us examine the various ways in which proof may be vitiated, the various fallacies to which reasoning is liable. Some of these have been discussed already, but they will be mentioned again here and the other fallacies not pre- viously noted will be examined. FALLACIES OF LANGUAGE. In the first place we may mistake the meaning of the premises owing to the fact that we have not understood the language in which they are expressed. The Fallacies of Amphiboly, Accent, Figure of Speech (see chapter v), are cases in point. FALLACIES 171 Again, to mistake the general for the specific use o a term,, or the concrete for the abstract, or to use a, term in one sense in one part of the reasoning and ini another sense in another part, would render the con- clusion unsound; the Fallacy of Accident must he- guarded against. (See page 55.) Once more, we may mistake the collective for the dis-- tributive use of a term or vice versa, or we may use a. term in one of these senses in one part of the reasoning; and in the other sense .in another part ; this would in- volve us in a Fallacy of Composition or of Division., (See page 57.) FALLACIES OF ASSUMPTION. Again, if we use as a. premise in our reasoning a proposition which is not established, such as an insufficiently verified inductive inference, our conclusion is not proved. It may be true, or it may not be, but a conclusion is not proved so long as there is a possibility that it may be false. When we use a proposition of this sort to support a conclusion we are said to commit the Fallacy of Begging the Ques- tion, or, to use the scholastic term, Petitio Principii. It is frequent in cases in which one has a thesis to prove and he sees that a certain proposition will enable him to; prove it (it may be either premise in a syllogism or both). He therefore assumes the truth of this proposi- tion on insufficient grounds, sometimes on very slight grounds. To decline to admit a premise because we see that it necessitates an unwelcome conclusion is to commit this fallacy. A false categorical proposition, an incorrect hypo- thetical proposition, or a disjunctive proposition in 172 PROOF AND DISPROOF which the disjunction is not complete, would also, if used as premises, be illustrations of this fallacy. It is not even necessary to use a complete proposition to commit this- fallacy ; the use of a name or an epithet may lead to fallacious conclusions ; the name or epithet does, to be sure, imply a proposition. To argue that this criminal should be punished, because all criminals are a menace to society, begs the question if it has not been shown that this man is a criminal. The epithet is sometimes more dangerous than the implied proposition would be, for we are less likely to notice that something has been assumed when the Droposition is only sug- gested. One form of the Petitio Principii is Arguing in a Circle, or Circulus in Probando. In this, the premise is simply the desired conclusion stated in other words. To say that man is a conscious being because he has mental states, is to argue in a circle, since to be a conscious being is to have mental states. When the argument is short there is little to be feared from this fallacy ; the identity in meaning of the two statements is easily discovered if they come close together ; but in a long argument the first may be only vaguely remembered by the time the second is made, and if the reasoning has not hitherto been questioned the fallacy may escape detection. A language like English, which is very rich in synonyms, offers very many occasions for this fal- lacy. Another closely related fallacy is that known as the Fallacy of Many Questions or sometimes Double Ques- tion. One of the traditional illustrations is, " Have you left off beating your wife? " Whichever answer is FALLACIES 173 given, Yes or No, seems to admit the truth of the im- plication. In this fallacy, the question assumes the truth of something which is not proved or admitted, and which may be false. It demands a direct answer, and no direct answer can be given without an apparent ad- mission of the thing assumed. FORMAL, FALLACIES. There are several fallacies which result from the violation of the principles of syllogistic reasoning. These are usually called the Formal Fallacies, because they are said to result from violating the formal laws of the syllogism, the laws re- lating to the number of terms and the distribution of terms in the syllogism. We might include also, Fal- lacies of Illicit Conversion and Obversion. Creighton includes them in Fallacies of Interpretation. 2 Using four terms instead of three gives the Fallacy of Four Terms. Distributing the major term in the conclusion when it has not been distributed in the premise gives the Fallacy of Illicit Distribution of the Major Term, and distributing the minor term in the -conclusion when it was not distributed in the premise gives the cor- responding Fallacy of the Minor Term. Failing to distribute the middle term gives the Fallacy of Undis- tributed Middle. There are also the Fallacies of Two Negative Premises, and Two Particular Premises. This is the way in which violations of the laws of syllogistic reasoning have usually been classified. As we have already seen, these violations can also be dealt with as failures to comply with the principles of the Four Figures. The latter method is less formal and more in accordance with our ordinary habits of thought. 2 See his Logic, chapter xii. 174 PROOF AND DISPROOF The Fallacies of Hypothetical Reasoning, Denying the Antecedent and Affirming the Consequent, belong in the class just discussed. THE CONCLUSION MAY NOT FOLLOW FROM THE PREMISES. There is a form of false reasoning known as the Non Sequitur. In this the premises may be clear and true and there may be no fallacies of distribution or of negative premises, but the conclusion does not follow from the premises. It may be true enough and provable on other grounds but it does not belong to the propositions on which it has been based. It was origi- nally called the Fallacy of False Consequent and had to do with hypothetical reasoning, but the term Non Sequitur is now applied to categorical reasoning in which the conclusion does not follow from the premises. De Morgan's illustration (quoted by Hyslop) is as fol- lows: Episcopacy is of Scripture origin. The Church of England is the only Episcopal Church in England. Therefore, the church established is the church that should be supported. This fallacy, like the rest, is more likely to pass un- noticed in a long argument than in a short one. A similar fallacy, sometimes treated as a form of the last, is that of False Cause, or Non Causa pro Causa, or Post Hoc ergo Propter Hoc. This consists in argu- ing that because one thing has followed another, it is therefore the effect of that other, as if one should argue that because a panic followed the adoption of a certain measure, it was therefore caused by that measure. MISSING THE POINT. One more fallacy is to be FALLACIES noted ; that in which the argument is not to the point. The reasoning may with entire correctness prove some- thing but it is not the thing which was to be proved. An opponent is sometimes charged with shifting the ground of debate ; that means usually that he is no longer trying to prove the thesis with which he started but something else more or less closely related to it. This is known as the Fallacy of Ignoratio Elenchi. Several forms have been distinguished. One of these is the Ad Hominem argument; in this, instead of being to the point, the argument is directed against the char- acter or consistency, etc., of the opponent or some other person. When an advocate proves the prisoner's good character and assumes that he has proved his in- nocence of the crime with which he is charged, he is guilty of this fallacy. When a debater attacks his op- ponent instead of proving his thesis he commits this fallacy. It is a method of silencing an opponent but not of proving a case. Appeals to authority, to pre- judice, to emotion, are all forms of the fallacy of Ignoratio Elenchi, as is also the argument in which the victory depends upon the fact that the opponent has not the information necessary to enable him to meet the argument. When w r e assume that a proposition is false because the arguments in its support have been discredited, we commit this fallacy. The proposition is only not proved, instead of being disproved. A good cause may suffer from bad arguments because of the widespread tendency to commit this fallacy. In most arguments many of the propositions involved are unexpressed. In such cases it is often difficult to know what fallacy to charge against reasoning which 176 PROOF AND DISPROOF is obviously unsound. Suppose we have the argument, " A classical course is useless because it trains for no profession;" what fallacies might be charged? In the first place we might say that the fallacy was a Non Sequitur; the conclusion does not follow from the grounds which have been stated. It might be replied that there was a further premise understood, namely, " Every college course which does not train for a pro- fession is useless." The fallacy of Non Sequitur would be disposed of, but it would now be possible to charge the fallacy of Begging the Question, in the premise which has been supplied. Or it might be that the pre- mise understood was " Most courses of study which do not train for a profession are useless." That might possibly be true, but even admitting it, the reasoning is not valid, because it violates the principles of syllogistic reasoning. In cases of doubt the only way of being certain that we have been fair to an absent opponent or have met all replies to our criticisms, is to follow some such pro- cedure as that just illustrated and show that if one criticism can be met another cannot, or that, if the con- clusion is to be established, such and such propositions must be shown to be true. These fallacies are usually discussed in connection with the syllogism, but they may occur in the more com- plicated forms of reasoning as well. As we have already seen, the syllogism is the typical form of de- ductive reasoning, but there is much reasoning that is extra-syllogistic: although this might perhaps be put into syllogistic form such an operation is unnecessary if the premises and the steps in the argument are clear. FALLACIES 177 In more complicated trains of reasoning which involve induction as well as deduction we must make sure not only of the reasoning processes, and of the clear state- ment of the premises, but also of the soundness of the premises, and of the grounds on which they are based. EXERCISES In the following exercises,, supply missing premises, state the Figure in which the argument falls, and criticise fully the reasoning, noting the fallacies of every sort: 1. Personal deformity is an affliction of nature; dis- grace is not an affliction of nature; personal deformity is not a disgrace. 2. All paper is useful, and all that is useful is a source of comfort to man ; therefore, all paper is a source of com- fort to man. 3. If Caesar were a tyrant, he deserved to die; but he was not a tyrant, and therefore did not deserve to die. 4. Every one desires his own good; justice and temper- ance are everyone's good; hence, every one desires justice and temperance. 5. Some of the inhabitants of the earth are more civi- lized than others; no savages are more civilized than other races; therefore, no savages are inhabitants of the earth. 6. He must be a Mohammedan, for all Mohammedans hold these opinions. 7. He must be a Christian, for only Christians hold these opinions. 8. All valid syllogisms have three terms; this syllogism has three terms, and is therefore valid. 9. None but despots possess absolute power; the Czar of Russia is a despot; therefore, he possesses absolute power. 10. The right should be enforced by law; the exercise of the suffrage is a right, and should therefore be enforced by law. 11. Nothing is better than wisdom; dry bread is better than nothing; therefore, dry bread is better than wisdom. 12. Every rule has exceptions; this is a rule and there- 178 PROOF AND DISPROOF fore has exceptions; therefore, there are some rules that have no exceptions. 13. For those who are bent on cultivating their minds by diligent study, the incitement of academical honors is unnecessary; and it is ineffectual for the idle and such as are indifferent to mental improvement; therefore, the in- citement of academical honors is either unnecessary or ineffectual. 14. Suicide is not always to be condemned, for it is but voluntary death, and this has been gladly embraced by many of the greatest heroes of antiquity. 15. Theft is a crime; theft was encouraged by the laws of Sparta; therefore, the laws of Sparta encouraged crime. 16. Nothing but the express train carries the mail, and as the last train was an express, it must have carried the mail. 17- Protective laws should be abolished, for they are in- jurious if they produce scarcity and useless if they do not. 18. Whosoever intentionally kills another should suffer death ; a soldier, therefore who kills his enemy should suf- fer death. 1Q. The people of the country are suffering from famine; and as A, B, and C are people of the country, they are therefore suffering from famine. 3 20. Each of the books in the library is large; hence the library is large. 21. Hunger is a sign of health; therefore, famine which causes hunger is a good thing. 22. Arsenic will kill a man ; hence, this medicine will kill you as it contains arsenic. 23. The coat, hat and dress were each in* good taste; therefore, the costume as a whole was in good taste. 24. You can always trust to the majority to do what is right in the long run; this man is a member of the ma- jority, and therefore he can be trusted to do what is right in the long run. 25. Eating opium degrades and brutalizes a man; hence 3 Most of the examples from 1 to 19 were borrowed from Hys- lop's Elements of Logic. A good many of them belong to the common stock. EXERCISES 179 DeQuincy and Coleridge were low and degraded crea- tures. 26. It is wrong to take life of fellow creatures; hence it is wrong to kill a mad dog. 27. Human life will at some time disappear from the earth, for every man must die. 28. America is a Christian country; hence, every Ameri- can is a Christian. 29- The members of the college are students, teachers, and administrative officers. The members of the football team are members of the college, and hence are students, teachers, and administrative officers. 30. If it is admitted that men who are proficient in engraving are of great service to a community, it must be true that the greater the degree of excellence possessed by the counterfeiter, the better for the government. 31. You must allow that this measure will do untold good to the country that the whole community will prosper and that our nation will take its place with the foremost. You say you grant all this and still you maintain that it will ruin your particular section. Is not your section a part of the nation, and will it not be benefited as well as the rest of the country? 32. The population of the United States increased 20% between 1890 and 1900; hence, the population of Vermont must have increased at that rate during the same period. 33. Slavery was harmful to the development of the whole country, and hence to the South. 34. Policemen must arrest all persons who block the highways or interfere with traffic. The policeman at this crowded corner does this, and should therefore be arrested. 35. Kant held that all the proofs for the existence of God were fallacious. He was therefore an atheist. 36. At the time of the Galveston flood men worked six- teen hours a day; hence, to talk of an eight-hour day as a necessity for the working classes is absurd. 37. The evidence of the creator is the thing created. 38. Before you stands the vile wretch who has been accused of murder. 39. Why has man one more rib than woman? 180 PROOF AND DISPROOF 40. The candidate is very fond of children., and so no doubt she would be a good kindergarten teacher. 41. This man's arguments are worthless, for he is no" toriously dishonest. 42. In answer to the argument that women, as intelli- gent human beings, are entitled to all the privileges of citizenship, I ask you: Are not women like our sainted mothers, who never held a ballot in their hands, good enough for us? 43. " Woman as well as man should have a part in the world's political affairs; for government is nothing but national housekeeping." 44. " More coffee is consumed in the United States than anywhere else, and America has become the strongest nation." 45. My opponent presents a formidable array of sta- tistics to prove that the country is financially unfit for war; to which I am proud to reply that the old flag has never yet touched the ground. 46. Agassiz did not accept the theory of Evolution; hence I, who know very little of biology, am not justified in accepting it. 47. This man was a good football player, and hence will be a good man to write up the present football situation. 48. A vacuum is impossible, for if there is nothing be- tween two bodies they must be in contact. 49. The government should be in the hands of the Demo- cratic party, for the country could not help prospering un- der the supervision of the followers of Jefferson. 50. It is indeed an opinion strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a word all sen- sible objects, have an existence, natural or real, distinct from their being perceived by the understanding. But with how great an assurance and acquiescence soever this principle be entertained in the world, yet whoever shall find it in his heart to call it in question may, if I mistake not, perceive it to involve a manifest contradiction. For, what are the fore-mentioned objects but the things we perceire by sense? and what do we perceive besides our own ideas or sensations ? and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of these^ or any combination of them, should exist unper- EXERCISES 181 ceived? Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, Sec. 4. 51. If there were external bodies it is impossible we should ever come to know it; and if there were not we might have the very same reasons to think there were that we have now. Suppose what no one can deny possible an intelligence without the help of external bodies, to be affected with the same train of sensation or ideas that you are, imprinted in the same order arrd with like vividness in his mind. I ask whether that intelligence hath not all the reason to believe in the existence of corporeal sub- stances, represented by his ideas and exciting them in his mind, that you can possibly have for believing the same thing? Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, Sec. 20. 52. In the business of gravitation or mutual attraction, because it appears in many instances, some are straightway for pronouncing it universal; and that it attract and be attracted by every other body is an essential quality inher- ent in all bodies whatsoever. Whereas, it is evident that the fixed stars have no such tendency towards each other; and so far is that gravitation from being essential to bodies that in some instances a quite contrary principle seems to show itself; as in the perpendicular growth of plants in the elasticity of the air. Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, Sec. 106. 53. " The family, the state, religion and morality are all in danger in this country on account of divorces, accord- ing to the speakers at an Episcopal meeting in New York on Sunday. But are things in so bad a way? " In Eng- land, " so ' horrible ' were the revelations of angry discon- tent with the married state made by hundreds of the cor- respondents of a London paper, that it was compelled recently to bring a discussion of the marriage question to an abrupt end." 54. In arguing against the Darwinian Hypothesis, Agassiz is said to have urged the following: " If species do not exist, how can they vary ? " 55. Vegetarianism is a healthy diet, for all vegetarians find it so. 56. No educated, much less a scientific person, who is 182 PROOF AND DISPROOF convinced of the immutable order of things, can now- adays believe in miracles. Buchner, Force and Matter. 57. Either the laws of nature govern, or the eternal reason governs; if both govern together they must be in continual conflict; the government of the latter would render that of the former unnecessary, whilst the action of unalterable laws admits of no personal interference, and can on that account scarcely be called governing. A main point in the proof that the laws of nature are those of reason is, that by thought we are able to deduce other laws of nature from those known to us, so that we find them in experience, and if this does not happen, we naturally con- clude that we have formed erroneous conclusions. Buch- ner, Force and Matter. 58. In all parts of knowledge, rightly so termed, things most general are most strong; thus it must be, inasmuch as the certainty of our persuasion touching particulars de- pendeth altogether upon the credit of those generalities out of which they grow. Hooker, Ecclesiastical Polity, i, 12. 59. A spirit independent of nature cannot exist; for never has an unprejudiced mind, cultivated by science, per- ceived its manifestations. . . . How is it possible that the unalterable order in which things move should ever be disturbed without producing an irremediable gap in the world, without delivering us and everything up to an arbi- trary power, without reducing all science and every earthly endeavor to a vain and childish effort? Buchner, Force and Matter. 60. Order and progress are two incompatible elements. Progress is accompanied by disorder, by anarchy. For what is progress if not precisely the overturning of a given social order so as to institute a new one? Draghicesco, Le probleme de la conscience. 61. Sunshine is necessary for plants; for vegetable or- ganisms can not increase in size, sending roots into the soil and stems into the air, without the light and heat of the great solar luminary. 62. Nothing is so bad that it cannot be worse. 63. " The canals are not so maintained. They are fall- ing into decay and disuse. The old boats are rotting and EXERCISES 183 few new boats are built. The business of the canals falls off, and the city of New York, which thirty years ago had 75 per cent, of the foreign trade of the country, now lias less than 50 per cent." 64. " Philosophy bakes no bread." Then why waste time upon it? 65. Men have a right to vote. Then where is the justice of depriving criminals of this right ? 66. Two and three are even and odd; two and three are five; hence five is even and odd. 67. To inflict capital punishment is to violate one of the commandments in the Decalogue. 68. " The French drink more wine than any other nation and in literature and art they occupy a foremost place." 69. "... it deals with the question exactly when the monstrous tariff is to be tenderly revised by its friends. The answer is ' Never/ The thing cannot be done in pros- perous times, because it would disturb business. In a period of depression, it is out of the question, as we then have troubles enough without opening Pandora's box. When affairs are just betwixt and between, neither very good nor very bad, no sagacious Republican would think of meddling with the tariff. Therefore, we say the exact position of the Republicans is, that an unj ust tariff is crying out for urgent revision, that they are the only ones who can do the work, and that they will do it just one day after never." 70. " The justice complains bitterly that the court has been obliged to resort to subterfuges in order to employ competent process-servers, the eligible lists providing only worn-out soldiers who lack the essentials of youth, deter- mination, agility and vigor. He is therefore in favor of going back to the discredited system of ' pass examina- tions ' or of re-enacting the starchless civil service law." 71. In the domain of physics, to the exploration of which Lord Kelvin has devoted an honored lifetime, he would be a bold man who would cross swords with him. But for dogmatic utterance on biological questions there is no reason to suppose that he is better equipped than any person of average intelligence ... in the latter (organic nature) scientific thought is * compelled to accept the idea of creative power.' That transcends the possibilities of 184 PROOF AND DISPROOF scientific investigation . . . Lord Kelvin, in effect, wipes out by a stroke of the pen the whole position won* for us by Darwin. And in so doing, it can hardly be denied that his present position is inconsistent with the principle laid down in: his British Association address at Edinburgh in 1871. Extracts from letters written to the London Times apropos of Lord Kelvin's assertion regarding the limits of science. (Reprinted in Science.) 72. The fact is so improbable that extremely good evidence is needed to make us believe it; and this evidence is not good, for how can you trust people who believe in such absurdities? 73. The axioms of mathematics and the fundamental moral principles are inborn ; for they are accepted by every- body. Moreover no reasonable being can deny them when he understands what they mean. 74. I may doubt everything except that I think. I think, therefore I exist. 75. A parliamentary government is sure to fail in the long run ; a battle may be won by a poor general but never by a debating society. 76. Can anything be more ludicrous than first to build all our certainty of the assistance of the Holy Ghost upon the certainty of tradition and then afterwards to make the certainty of tradition to rely upon the assistance of the Holy Ghost. Tillotson, Rules of Faith. 77. If men are not likely to be influenced in the per- formance of a known duty by taking an oath to perform it, the oaths commonly administered are superfluous; if they are likely to be so influenced, every one should be made to take an oath to behave rightly throughout his life; but one or the other of these must be the case; therefore either the oaths commonly administered are superfluous or every man should be made to take an oath to behave rightly throughout his life. 4 . 78. Few treatises of science convey important truths, without any intermixture of error, irr a perspicuous and in- teresting form; and therefore, though a treatise would deserve much attention which should possess such excellence, * The exercises from 77 to 90 are from WhatelyV Clements of Logic, EXERCISES iss it is plain that few treatises of science do deserve much attention. 79- No one who lives with another on terms of con- fidence is justified, on any pretense, in killing him; Brutus lived on terms of confidence with Caesar; therefore, he was not justified, on the pretense he pleaded, in killing him. 80. He that destroys a man who usurps despotic power in a free country deserves well of his countrymen; Brutus destroyed Caesar, who usurped despotic power in Rome; therefore, he deserved well of the Romans. 81. Nothing which is of less frequent occurrence than the falsity of testimony can be fairly established by testi- mony; any extraordinary and unusual fact is a thing of less frequent occurrence than the falsity of testimony (that being very common) ; therefore, no extraordinary and un- usual fact can be fairly established by testimony. 82. Testimony is a kind of evidence which is very likely to be false; the evidence on which most men believe that there are pyramids in Egypt is testimony; therefore, the evidence on which most men believe that there are pyramids in Egypt is very likely to be false. 83. He who cannot possibly act otherwise than he does, has neither merit nor demerit in his action; a liberal and benevolent man cannot possibly act otherwise than he does in relieving the poor; therefore, such a man has neither merit nor demerit in his action. 84. The religion of the ancient Greeks and Romans was extravagant fables and groundless superstitions, credited by the vulgar and weak, and maintained by the more en- lightened, from selfish or political views ; the same was clearly the case with the religion of the Egyptians; the same may be said of the Brahminical worship o India, and the religion of Fo, professed by the Chinese; the same, of the mythological systems of the Peruvians, of the stern and bloody rites of the Mexicans, and those of the Britons and Saxons ; hence we may conclude that all systems of religion, however varied in circumstances, agree in being super- stitions kept up among the vulgar, from interested or political views of the more enlightened classes. 85. What happens every day is not improbable; some things against which the chances are many thousands to 186 PROOF AND DISPROOF one, happen every day; therefore, some things against which the chances are many thousands to one are not im- probable. 86. The principles of justice are variable; the appoint- ments of nature are invariable; therefore, the principles of justice are not appointments of nature. 87. Of two evils, the less is to be preferred; occasional turbulence, therefore, being a less evil than rigid despotism, is to be preferred to it. 88. No evil should be allowed that good may come of it; all punishment is arr evil; therefore, no punishment should be allowed that good may come of it. 89. Repentance is a good thing; wicked men abound in repentance; therefore, wicked men abound in what is good. 90. If the exhibition of criminals, publicly executed, tends to heighten in others the dread of undergoing the same fate, it may be expected that those soldiers who have seen the most service, should have the most dread of death in battle; but the reverse of this is the case; therefore, the former is not to be believed. 91. Why does a ball, when dropped from the masthead of a ship in full sail, fall not exactly at the foot of the mast but nearer the stern of the vessel? Davis, Logic. 92. " The impious, whoever he may be, ought not to go unpunished. For do not men regard Zeus as the best and most righteous of the gods? And even they admit that he bourrd his father because he wickedly devoured his sons." Plato, Euthyphro. 93. The soul is unchangeable; the unchangeable is simple; the simple is indissoluble; the indissoluble is in- destructible; therefore, the soul is immortal. See Plato, Phaedo. PART II SUPPLEMENTARY METHODS CHAPTER I. STATISTICS The value of any cnnrlufiinn drpmrh Inrgply the soundness of the premises from which it is drawn; a great many of these premises, as we have seen, are inductions from particular facts. When these inductive inferences have been tested by one or another of the " Inductive Methods " they can be regarded as trust- worthy ; but the successful application of the methods presupposes a fairly complete analysis of the phe- nomena under investigation, for it is by this analysis that we determine the circumstances in which the phenomenon occurs. If we cannot determine the cir- cumstances it is obvious that we cannot apply the Methods. It might seem to follow from this that if the circumstances in which a phenomenon occurs are so complex as to defy analysis, or if the phenomenon itself cannot be separated into its elements, it would be im- possible to make any reliable generalizations regarding the relations of the phenomenon in question. Or if we were quite unable to surmise which of a multitude of circumstances was significant, or to isolate any of them by means of the Methods, we could not decide which was causally related to the phenomenon and which was not. There are many fields in which analysis is possible in only a slight degree ; social phenomena and phenomena of the weather are cases in point. A moment's reflec- 189 190 STATISTICS tion will show the difficulty of applying the Method of Agreement, for instance, in the study of the weather, or of the death rate. The phenomena are so exceed- ingly complex that anything approaching a complete statement of their elements is quite out of the question. The fallibility of most popular generalizations in these fields is evidence of the difficulty of dealing with such facts. Must we be content then simply to guess at the relations of such phenomena, with the slight assistance which is to be gained from so precarious a method as that of Simple Enumeration? In instances of this sort another method, a method which is closely related to the method of Simple Enumeration, becomes important : it is the Method of Statistics. In statistics we have an exact enumeration of cases. If a small number of cases does not enable us to detect the causal relations of a phenomenon, it sometimes happens that a large number, accurately counted, and taken from a field widely ex- tended in time and space, will lead to a solution of the problem. But how can the counting of cases aid in the discov- ery of a causal relation? It does so by showing the relative frequency of the phenomenon, its frequency as compared with some particular circumstance or circum- stances. If we noted only the phenomenon itself, knowl- edge of its frequency would be of little use. But if, in a large number of cases, taken from a wide field, we can find some other phenomenon correlated with the one we are investigating, then we have ground for a con- clusion. We proceed upon the principle that if the con- currence of two phenomena is merely a coincidence, the THE MEANING OF CORRELATION 191 frequency of one should make no difference in the oc- currence of the other, and conversely that if there is a correlation, there must be some causal relation. If the frequency of two phenomena is the same, or if varia- tions in the frequency of one correspond to variations in the frequency of the other, or if any change in the quantity or quality of one corresponds to changes in the frequency of the other, we are usually justified in inferring that something more than a coincidence is present. Correlation may be either positive or negative; in positive correlation the presence of a phenomenon A would mean the presence of the phenomenon B in a certain proportion of cases or in a -certain amount, and so on ; in negative correlation the presence of A would of course mean the absence of B in a certain propor- tion of cases, and so on. The relation between illiteracy and crime would be an instance of the former and the relation between vaccination and smallpox would illus- trate the latter. The total absence of correlation might perhaps be represented by the relation between the weather and the day of the month. Correlation can bq measured mathematically ; that is to say, it is possible to determine just what degree of correlation there is between two phenomena. The number which expresses this is called the coefficient of correlation. Complete positive correlation would be expressed by + 100, com- plete negative correlation by - 100, and absence of correlation by ; A coefficient of + 63 between two phenomena would mean that one was present in 63 per cent, of the cases in which the other was present, or that 192 STATISTICS the amount, or amount of increase, and so on, of one, was 63 per cent, of that of the other. 1 Sometimes 2 a correlation would not prove a direct causal relation ; the fact that the mortality among men is higher than that among women and bears a certain numerical relation to it, or the fact that about 106 boys are born for every 100 girls, are examples of this. But there is nothing peculiar to statistics in this. The same thing appeared in connection with the method of Agreement; here, as there, the concurrence of two phe- nomena may mean that both are connected with some one underlying set of complex or undiscovered con- ditions. And even frequent concurrence may be acci- dental, though a thoroughgoing investigation would eliminate one which was entirely accidental. And even if the cause of a phenomenon is not dis- covered in this way, it may be that its frequency is a matter of interest or of practical importance ; for its frequency may itself be a factor in determining our conduct ; the number of passengers stopping at a given railway station or the comparative number of boys and girls in a city may be worth knowing, even if not understood. The census reports contain a multitude of facts of this kind ; eventually the causal relations of many of them may be discovered. A statistical record like any other enables us to cor- 1 For further discussion, see Thorndike, Mental and Social Measurements; Bowley, Elements of Statistics; Pearson, The Chances of Death. 2 It will be noted that the principles here employed are related to those used in the Methods of Agreement and of Concomitant Variations, but here analysis may be very incomplete; frequency instead of quantity is considered, and principles of the method of Difference may be employed in conjunction with the others. STATISTICS 193 rect mistakes of memory, and so on ; as, for example, in matters such as the increase or decrease of crimes, or the decreasing or increasing coldness of winters. Usually the cause discovered by means of statistics is only a part of the cause of the phenomenon ; the phe- nomenon is the result of a number of circumstances working together (Composition of Causes), and not al- ways of the same circumstances (Plurality of Causes). We may know already that a certain circumstance is causally related to a certain phenomenon but that it is sometimes present without the latter (through the agency of a Counteracting Cause or the absence of necessary supplementing circumstances). In such a case statistics enable us to discover how frequently, in what proportion of instances, the phenomenon will be present along with that circumstance. It must be remembered that the statistical method means more than the mere collection of cases. " With the collection of statistical data, only the first step has been taken. The statistics in that condition are only raw material showing nothing. They are not an in- strument of investigation any more than a kiln of bricks is a monument of architecture. They need to be ar- ranged, classified, tabulated, and brought into connec- tion with other statistics by the statistician. Then only do they become an instrument of investigation, just as a tool is nothing more than a mass of wood or metal* except in the hands of a skilled workman." 3 The processes used in statistical investigations differ widely, but the following are generally given in discus- sions of the subject: (1) The Collection of Material, 3 Mayo-Smith, Statistics .and Sociology, p. 18, 194 STATISTICS (2) its Tabulation, (3) the Summary, and (4) a Criti- cal Examination of its results. " In collection and tabulation common sense is the chief requisite, and ex- perience the chief teacher ; no more than a knowledge of the simplest arithmetic is necessary for the actual processes; but since ... all parts of an investi- gation are interdependent, it is expedient to understand the whole before attempting to carry out a part. For summarizing, it is well to have acquaintance with the various algebraic averages, and with enough geometry for the interpretation of simple curves, though all the operations can be performed without the use of alge- braic symbols." 4 The collection of statistics is carried out by various methods, some of them very technical ; we can note only a few general principles here. In the first place the data should be collected over a wide field. Just as in the non-statistical application of the inductive methods, it is necessary to collect data over a field wide enough to insure us against mistaking a coincidence for a cause or over-emphasizing the importance of one out of a number of cooperating causes, or regarding as the sole cause one which is only one of a number of different causes capable of bringing about the phenomenon. One danger to be guarded against arises from the failure of different observers to use terms in exactly the same sense. If poverty means in some cases in- ability to obtain luxuries and in others, positive want, we can make little use of statistics of poverty. Again, in many statistical investigations, the data are obtained by means of questions addressed to a great *Bowley, Elements of Statistics, p. 17. TABULATION 195 many individuals ; these questions should be so worded as to minimize as far as possible the tendencies to care- less or biased observation, faulty memory, preju- dice, dishonesty, and imperfect description of the facts. Tabulation involves classification, and the scheme of tabulation should be determined by the purposes of the investigation the problems which it is intended to solve. " In general, the scheme of investigation re- quires knowledge of certain groups ; and the totals re- sulting from tabulation should show the number of items in these, so that after tabulation, instead of the chaotic mass of infinitely varying items, we have a definite general outline of the whole group in question." The totals and averages must be so presented as to give a true impression to an inquirer. The subject of averages will be discussed more fully in a later chapter. In the summary, the aim is to present the results in the clearest, most comprehensive, and most suggestive way. The use of averages, and representation by charts and diagrams, are important here. In correlating the results great care is needed to avoid wrong interpreta- tions. An increase in the number of arrests might be causally related to increasing severity in the enforce- ment of law and not to an increase in crime. A critical examination of the results is possible only when the sources of the data, the methods of their tab- ulation, and the mode of summarizing and drawing conclusions, are fully described. There are, of course, many cases in which the use of statistics would be unnecessary : " In order to prove the relation between savagery and fetichism it is not 196 STATISTICS necessary for us to have statistics either of economic condition or of religious confession. The fact stands out of itself simply by the -consensus of observation of travelers and historians.*" 5 Where the law of the data is already known the fre- quency of their occurrence is of no further interest to science. The number of times an acid has combined with a base to form a salt is of no importance to the chemist. If we know the laws and the circumstances, the frequency of the event and the times of its occur- rence can easily be determined. " There was some interest in counting how many eclipses of the moon and sun took place every year, so long as they occurred unexpectedly and inexplicably ; since the rule has been found according to which they occur and can be calcu- lated for centuries past and to come, that interest has vanished. But we still count how many thunderstorms and hailstorms occur at a given place or within a given district, how many persons die, and how many bushels of fruit a given area produces, because we are not in a position to calculate these events from their con- ditions." 6 In other cases the method of statistics may be in- applicable. " It is difficult to express the relation be- tween economic condition or religious feeling and aesthetic development in a civilized state, because music, painting, and sculpture cannot in any way be measured statistically. This is a question of quality and not in any sense of quantity." B Mayo-Smith, Statistics and Sociology, p. 9. 6 Sigwart, Logic, Part III, chap, iv, 3. 7 Mayo-Smith, loc. cit. See, however, page 210 on the ways of applying exact methods in investigating such phenomena. DIFFICULTIES IN USE OF STATISTICS 197 The use of statistics is often severely criticised and there is much popular distrust of the results attained by their employment. There are, of course, many dif- ficulties to be met, and many conclusions based upon statistics may be false. They are liable to most of the errors which occur in connection with the handling of individual facts. The original observations may have been faulty ; in so far as memory was employed, further errors may have entered; ignorance, prejudice or inac- curate statements may have vitiated whatever testimony was employed ; the records may have been faulty or mis- takes may have been made in copying; the facts ob- served may not have been representative ; in comparing different groups and in noting correlations we may mistake a mere coincidence for causal relation. If all the precautions which are employed in a scientific ex- amination of individual facts are made use of here, statistics may furnish a perfectly valid basis for infer- ence. One practical difficulty is the unfamiliarity of the average reader with the use of statistics and his consequent inability to criticise them, and another is the frequent failure on the part of the investigator to furnish data for criticism. 8 s Interesting illustrations of the use of statistics are easy to find. The field of vital statistics is a good one for this purpose. One very interesting study is Dr. Allyn A. Young's A Discussion of Age 'Statistics, Bulletin 13 of the Bureau of the Census. CHAPTER II AVERAGES The Arithmetical Average. In statisti-cal investiga- tions and in all others in which quantitative data are employed, the use of averages is often very important. An average is a single quantity which represents two or more other quantities. There are several kinds of aver- ages ; that with which we are most familiar is the Arith- metical Average. It is obtained by adding together the various quantities to be averaged and dividing their sum by the number of quantities. The weights of the members of a college football team were respectively, ^ 175, 195, 187, 183, 230, 187, 169, 147, 159, 178 and \ V \ 185. The average was 181 4-11. The average is less ^ ^ cumbersome than the whole series of quantities or their | } sum. The greater the number or size of the quantities W" the more important does the average become. The average tells us nothing about the individual ^<- \ 'Le \ Leases. In this example the average is not the same as single one of the quantities averaged. To take an- other case : the death rate of a city gives no informa- jdptnTregarding the death rate of any given ward, nor the number of deaths in any given thousand of the population. An average simply serves as a means for representing the whole series of quantities and for com- paring it with other series. It gives no information regarding the homogeneity of the group : 180 is the average of 179 and 181 and also of 359 and 1. There are many cases in which the simple form of the 198 THE WEIGHTED AVERAGE 199 arithmetical average or mean is inadequate ; sometimes a modified form of it can be used. The "Weighted"Average. Suppose we know that of six groups of men the average weights are respect- ively 180, 148, 172, 164, 156 and 152 pounds. The average is 162. Can we say that this average satis- factorily represents the whole series of groups? That will depend upon the circumstances. If the groups were of approximately the same size it might be suffi- cient, but if in the first group there were 10; in the second, 200 ; in the third, 50 ; in the fourth, 20 ; in the fifth, 100; and in the sixth, 150, our average will be a very imperfect representative of the groups. If, on the other hand, we multiply each of the averages in the series by the number of individuals in the group which it represents and divide the sum of these products by the total number of individuals, we get the average 154 6-53, which is much more accurate than that first given. 180x10+148x900+172x50+164x20+156x100+152x150 = , 10 + 200 + 50 + 20 + 100 + 150 This is an illustration of what is known as a weighted average; it is a special form of arithmetical average. Where the groups represented by a series of averages vary greatly in size we have conditions which call for " weighting the averages." " The classical and most useful application of weights is the formation of an index-number for the change of prices by fitting suit- able weights to the changes measured in the prices of various commodities. It is required to find the change in the value of gold when measured by the prices of other commodities. Suppose that we are given that 200 AVERAGES prices of certain commodities between two years were in the following ratios : Wheat Silver Meat Sugar Cotton First year 100 100 100 100 100 Second year 77 60 90 40 85 The simplest way to estimate for the general fall in price is to take the simple average of the numbers in the second year, viz., 70.4, and say that the general prices in the second year were 70.4 : 100 1 when ex- pressed in commodities. But it is at once clear that we can not allow the commodities given to have equal influences on the result ; wheat is of greater importance than sugar and meat than silver; and again we have taken arbitrarily three items to represent food and one for clothing; we need some means of deciding relative importance. Suppose we decide that wheat, cotton, meat and sugar are respectively 7, 4, 3, times and twice as important as silver, we should get the following table : Commodity Relative prices Weight Product in second year Assigned Wheat 77 7 539 Silver 60 1 60 Meat 90 3 270 Sugar 40 2 80 Cotton 85 4 340 352 17 1289 1289 Weighted average is ==75.3 17 352 Unweighted average is =70.4 2 5 1 That is, prices of commodities have fallen in this rate or the value of gold has increased correspondingly. 2 Bowley, Elements of Statistics, pp. 111-llC. THE MODE 01 It is not always easy to tell what weights should be assigned, but considerable variation is possible without much modification of the result. The Mode. Another sort of average which is often of great importance is what is known as the Mode. It is that quantity which occurs with the greatest fre- quency. It is what we frequently have in mind when we speak of the average man, the average student, etc. If in a class of students, 10 receive the grade A; 20, the grade B; 50, the grade C; 100, the grade D; and 25, the grade F, the mode is D. The mode very often represents the type more accurately than does the aver- age. It gives us no information about any one indi- vidual, but it does indicate the sort of individual which occurs more frequently than any other sort. There might well be two or more modes in a given series of quantities. If a class were made up of very bright and very dull students, the numbers receiving the various grades might be A, 25; B, 50; C, 20; D, 100; and F, 25. The two modes are at B and D. The mode is not always easy to determine. In these examples the grade B, for instance, means a range be- tween the grade which is just high enough to escape C and that which is the smallest fraction short of A. It might well be that of the 50 who were in C, 35 were in the lower half of the group, while of those that were in D 80 were in the upper half of the group, so that the mode was really in a group which might be indicated by the expression D +, C . The degree of accuracy re- quired in the results would determine the degree of exactness with which we should state the mode. The mode is often most useful. " The mode rather than the average in chest-measurements is the number 202 AVERAGES most suitable for the ready-made clothier. For pro- viding a post-office or a store, the mode in postal-orders or prices of tea needs to be known rather than any other average. Even the favorite coin in a collection may show the spirit of the congregation better than the arithmetic average of their contributions." 3 If the series under consideration is very irregular it may be quite impossible to apply the mode. The mode has this advantage over the arithmetical average : it is uninfluenced by extreme cases. In the illustration on page 198, the average weight of the players would be considerably changed if a player weighing 180 pounds were substituted for the one weighing 230 ; let us see what would happen in the case of the mode. More of the quantities fall between 180 and 189 than within any other equal range. This range, 180-189, then, will be the mode. The substitu- tion of the lighter player does not modify the mode. Where the number of quantities is so small as in this illustration, the individual quantities are often men* tioned, but where that is not the case, the mode is often useful either as a supplement to the arithmetical aver- age or as a subsitute for it. The Median. Another kind of average useful in many cases is the Median. The Median is the middle quantity in a series. The weights of the players, in the order of their magnitude, were 147, 159, 169, 175, 178, 183, 185, 187, 187, 195, 230. The median is 183. There are just as many items above it as there are below. The median, like the mode, is unaffected by ex- treme cases. " The existence of any number of million- aires has no more effect on the median income than of sBowley, Elements of Statistics, p. 123c THE MEDIAN 203 an equal number of other persons whose incomes are above the median." 4 The median is very easy to find, since it is only necessary to arrange the items in the order of their magnitude and find which occupies the middle position. If there is an even number of items the median lies between the two middle ones. Even if our information regarding the items is incomplete it is often possible to find the median with a fair degree of accuracy. " It may be that in the ' wage census ' 100,000 persons whose wages were far below the aver- age did not come into the returns at all, and it is ver.y difficult to estimate their effect on the arithmetical aver- age, for want of information as to their earnings ; but to find the median exactly we need only know their num- ber, not their earnings ; and if we can assign a maximum for their number, we still can place the median within narrow limits." One great advantage in the use of the median is to be found in the fact that it can be employed in dealing with quantities for which no accurate measurements can be obtained. This is especially important in deal- ing with psychological phenomena. We may be able to say that A has a better memory than B without being able to measure either, or to state the exact amount in which A is superior to B. The members of a class of any size might be arranged in the order of their excel- lence in any quality whatever and the median found as in the case of numbers. Francis Galton, in his Natural 4 "The magnitudes one-quarter and three-quarters up the series are called the quartels; those one, two, .... nine-tenths of the way up are the deciles; those one, two, ninety-nine hun- dredths up are the percentiles." Bowley, Elements of Statistics, p. 124. 204 AVERAGES Inheritance and in other works, developed and applied this type of average with great effectiveness. The median may be a very imperfect representative of the type. If, in a group of 100 men, the weights of 50 were between 190 and 210 pounds, while the others ranged between 130 and 150 pounds, the median would be 170. " The median is then chiefly useful when we are dealing with a series of objects of which the main part lie fairly close together ; a few extremes do not affect it." 5 The Geometrical Average. Another kind of average useful in certain cases is the Geometrical average. It is related to the arithmetical average somewhat as com- pound is to simple interest. The population of Great Britain and Ireland increased from 12 millions in 1789 to 38 millions in 1890. Obviously it would be unsafe to say that the average increase was the total increase, 26 millions, divided by the number of years. We should expect the annual increase to be greater as the popula- tion became larger, and, other things being equal, the two would vary together. When we have only two quantities to deal with, the geometrical average is easily found. In such a case it is the mean proportional. The geometrical average of 4 and 16 is 8. The geometrical average of 5 and 9 is the square root of 45, or '3 into the square root of 5. If we were dealing with three quantities the geometrical average would be the cube root of their product ; if with five, it would be the fifth root of their product; the general formula for n quantities is the nth root of a^ a 2 . ... a n . With large or numerous quantities logarithms should be used. The name logarithmic mean is sometimes employed for this B Bowley, Elements of Statistics, p. 126. THE GEOMETRICAL AVERAGE 205 kind of average. The geometrical or logarithmic mean is a quantity which can be substituted for each of the quantities when they are multiplied together and give the same product, whereas the arithmetical mean is one which can be substituted for each of them when they are added together. " Which mean we should choose is simply a question of which we believe will best represent the facts. If the growth of cities depended altogether upon the birth of children within their boundaries, we should naturally choose the geometrical mean, for the larger the city (other things being equal) the more children will be born in it. If, on the other hand, the population of a city, like that of a prison or hospital, were made up altogether of certain kinds of people who were sent there from without, there would (?) be no reason why a large city should gain more inhabi- tants than a small one ; and the more appropriate aver- age would be the arithmetical. With most cities the natural rate of growth is only partly geometrical and partly arithmetical; so that neither a series of means of the one sort nor a series of the other would give a wholly satisfactory representation of the mean growth from year to year between one census and another. If in any case or set of -cases we have reason to believe that the true mean lies somewhere between the arith- metical and the geometrical, and if we wish to represent the facts as accurately as they can be represented bj any mean, we must take a mean that does lie between the two." 6 Measuring Deviations from an Average. It is often important when using averages to know something about the closeness with which the several quantities Aikins, The Principles of Logic, p. 315. 206 AVERAGES approximate the average. Suppose for example, that we had a number of different measurements of a given quantity, say the distance between two points: if there was little variation among the measurements we should usually regard their average as a fairly accurate repre- sentation of the real quantity ; but if the variation were very great we might have little or no confidence in the average. We shall need some way of indicating the amount of divergence within the group, or, in other words, the closeness with which the several quantities were grouped about the average. 1. One simple way of doing this is to take the aver- age of the deviations from the mean or average. Eight is the average of 5, 6, 11, and 10, and also of 1, 2, 15, and 14. The deviations in the first series are 3, 2, 3, and 2. The average of these deviations is 1 % or 2/4. The deviations in the second series are 7, 6, 7 and 6; the average deviation is 6%. (The deviations are technically known as " errors," and their average as the Average Error.) The smaller the average error the more closely are the quantities grouped about the average ; and the more closely they are grouped about the average the more homogeneous is the group. 2. Another kind of average frequently employed in this connection is the Median or Probable Error (P. E.). Arrange the errors in the order of their magni- tude ; the Median of these will be the so-called Probable Error, or the quantity within which half of the errors fall. Thus, if we have the quantities, 1, 3, 6, 8, 9, 12, 13, 15, 16, 17, the average will be 10. The errors will be 9, 7, 4, 2, 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, 7. Arranging these in the order of their magnitude we have 1, 2, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 7, PROBABLE ERROR 207 9. The median will fall between 4 and 5, i. e., 4%. In other words, 4% is the quantity below which half the errors fall and above which we will find the other half. Assuming that our data are representative of the class of facts for which they stand, any new number standing for things in the same class is as likely to be within 4J of the average as it is to be beyond it. Exactly half of the quantities already determined lie within that range (in the example, between the numbers 5% and 14%), and those already determined are, according to our supposition, selected from a wide enough field to be regarded as representative of the whole. An average of 10 with a probable error of 4.5 means a series of quantities in which there is a wide range of variation. An average of 100 and a P. E. of .1 would indicate a very homogeneous group. In the case of measure- ments it would mean that there was a close agreement among the different measurements and that the average was therefore a fairly accurate approximation to the true measurement (providing, of course, that constant errors had been eliminated). " An approximation to the probable error for a given series of observations is obtained by arranging all the observations in order of magnitude ; marking the magnitude, say a, above which 25 per cent, of the ob- servations lie, and the magnitude, say &, below which 25 per cent. lie. Half the difference between a and b is the probable error. A useful way of illustrating this is to say that if one observation is chosen at random out of a group, it is as likely as not that it will not lie further from the average than the probable error." 7 7 Bowley, Elements of Statistics, p. 282. 208 AVERAGES Measurement of Phenomena. In the more advanced stages of most sciences the exact measurement of phe- nomena becomes more and more important. To deter- mine the relations of a phenomenon it is not only necessary to know when it happens and what its accom- paniments are, but also how much of it is correlated with given amounts of other phenomena. This is evi- dent in the employment of the methods of Concomitant Variations, for this method deals with cases in which the quantity of the phenomenon varies. In the method of Residues also, quantitative measurements are of great importance; indeed, they are usually necessary. We observe how much of a given phenomenon is due to one cause, how much to a second, and so on ; the remainder is due to something else not previously known to be a cause, etc. The physical sciences are very largely quantitative, and more recently biology has come to employ the methods of exact measurements in many of its investi- gations. 8 Measurement usually means the employment of instruments. Measurements of magnitudes by the unassisted eye are exceedingly .inexact, and measure- ments of degree of quality are even more so. White marble painted in a picture representing an architec- tural view by moonlight seems to be of about the same degree of brightness as the actual moonlit marble would be, but Helmholz has calculated that it is from ten to twenty thousand times as bright. 9 To make measurements it is necessary to fix units in s The name of Karl Pearson is most closely associated with " Biometry." e James, Psychology, Briefer Course, p. 155. MEASUREMENT 209 terms of which the magnitudes are to be expressed. These are usually determined arbitrarily. Units, stand- ards, and instruments of measurement vary with the phenomena to be measured and can not be discussed further here. 10 Many errors may occur in making measurements, and although it is often possible to eliminate some of them, in the vast majority of instances the measurement is almost certainly inexact. Repeated measurements are very seldom in exact agreement. If phenomena were broken up into units of uniform magnitude there would be less difficulty, but most phenomena are continuous. Time is not broken up into minutes, and with the most exact instruments it is impossible to say when a minute has passed. It can be determined within millionths of a second but not with absolute exactness. For most practical purposes rough measurements are sufficient ; thus, for the train dispatcher it may be enough to deter- mine the time to a second, but for astronomical calcu- lations the smallest possible error may be of serious importance. Most measurements are only approxi- mately true ; the problem is to make the approximation as close as possible. There are various conditions to be observed and various methods which can be used in attempting to get exact measurements, but they are too technical to be included here. 11 Constant errors, such as the personal error, 12 can often be determined and allowance can be made for them. But after all such allowances 10 See Jevons, Principles of Science, chap. xiv. 11 See Jevons, Principles of Science, chap. xiii. 12 See page 23. 210 AVERAGES have been made and after all the means for avoiding and minimizing error have been employed, there yet remains a margin of uncertainty. In such cases it is possible to obtain a close approximation to the true measurement by taking a number of measurements and striking an average. After constant errors have been eliminated any given measurement is as likely to be too great as it is to be too small ; hence, in a large number of measurements there will probably be as many of those which exceed the true magnitude as there are of those which fall short of it. If the number of measure- ments is small this is more doubtful, but if a great many measurements have been made, we can rely upon the average with safety. The average of all these measure- ments is the closest approximation which we can get. Different kinds of average are used ac-cording to cir- cumstances. The closeness with which the several meas- urements are grouped about the average will be indicated here, as in all cases of the use of average, by the size of the error. If the error is small, the measurement is reliable, if large, more doubt- ful. The Comparison of Quantities which Cannot be Measured. In the study of many phenomena the prob- lem of quantitative comparison is made very difficult by our inability to find an exact quantitative equivalent for the phenomena. " Many mental phenomena elude altogether direct measurement in terms of amount. How many thefts equal in wickedness a murder? If the piety of John Wesley is 100, how much is the piety of St. Augustine? How much more ability as a dramatist had Shakespeare than Middleton? What per cent, must COMPARISON OF QUANTITIES be added to the political ability of the Jewish race to make it equal to the Irish race? . . . Nevertheless, such phenomena can be measured and subjected to quan- titative treatment." 13 The method to be employed in such cases, as Pro- fessor Thorndike goes on to show, is to arrange the individuals (or other unmeasurable data) according to. their rank. We may not be able to say how much more eminent A is than B, but if we can say that A is in the first rank, whereas B is in the tenth, we have a true basis of comparison. We cannot measure directly the intelligence of students in a class, but we may be able to say that one is in the first group, whereas an- other is in the fourth. Thus, with any number, it would be possible to give each his proper place in the group. This method can be applied to any trait whatever. The great difficulty is in making sure that the ranking is correct. Single observations and individual judgments are subject to the same errors here as in all other cases of observation. EXERCISES. 1. What sort of average should be employed in deter- mining the standard size of an article to be manufactured in large quantities say window shades ? 2. What sort of average should be employed in getting a number to represent the value of articles in a large and varied invoice of merchandise? 3. If a college had 400 students in 1880 and 1000 stu- dents in 1905, how many did it have in the year which falls is Thorndike, An Introduction to the Theory of Mental and Social Measurements, p. 18. This book is an exposition of the methods of measuring individuals, groups, variability of perform- ances, etc., including an exposition of the necessary modes of presenting the facts, making calculations, and so oa AVERAGES half way between, provided that the rate of increase was constant ? 4. What averages might be employed and which would be preferable in comparing the stature of soldiers in the French army with those in the American army? In com- paring the standing of successive classes in college? In comparing the salaries of members of the faculty in two universities? In comparing the rate of growth of a large university and a small college? 5. How would you indicate the degree of closeness with which a series of quantities approached their average? 6. What is the difference between " Average Error " and "Probable Error?" CHAPTER III PROBABILITY THE conclusions at which we arrive by the assistance of statistical methods and the employment of averages often fall far short of the certainty attaching to scien- tific laws. The conditions required for establishing a scientific law are not fully present, and consequently many of such conclusions, if not all of them, lack com- plete verification. It does not follow, however, that these are valueless. As a matter of fact, most of the generalizations which we use in everyday life are in- completely verified; they are extremely valuable as in- struments of knowledge and practice; indeed, in the absence of scientific laws, they are indispensable. So long as their provisional character is remembered, there is no serious danger in using them. A generalization of this character is said to be prob- able or to possess some degree of probability. Proba- bility belongs also to particular propositions. What do we mean by probability, by saying that a statement is probably true, that an event will probably happen? As we use the term ordinarily, it means that we believe we -have a right to accept a statement or expect an event, without feeling perfectly certain of it. This attitude, when it has any justification, is based upon the belief that the grounds for accepting the statement are stronger than those for rejecting it. It may be that we know of no positive reasons against it, but do not regard the reasons in its favor as conclusive ; or it may 213 PROBABILITY be that there are positive reasons against it, but that those in its favor are stronger or more numerous. These reasons or grounds may be of various kinds. There may be many things pointing toward the occurrence of such an event ; as, for example, in the statement that life will probably at some time cease upon the earth. Or conditions at the present time may be similar to those in which the event has happened before ; the out- come of an examination of instances according to the principles of the method of Agreement gives a result which is usually only probable. In all these cases it is impossible not to feel that a great deal of vagueness attaches to our statement that anything is probable. We are not able to say how probable it is. There is such a thing, however, as mathematical or quantitative probability. It is based upon the comparative number of times an event or connection of events has occurred. If a given circumstance A has been observed 1000 times, and if, in 700 cases of its occurrence, a phenomenon B has also been present, we have definite grounds for in- ferring that A will probably be accompanied by B again. Every time A and B have occurred together in the past is an argument in favor of their occurring together in the future, and every time A has occurred without B is an argument against this connection; if the cases of the latter sort are many in comparison with those of the former, we say that the connection in the future is improbable. In the case just mentioned we should express the degree of probability by the frac- tion %o- Now in dealing with the matter in this quan- titative way, the term " probability " has a meaning which is somewhat different from that in which we THE MEANING OF PROBABILITY ordinarily use it. It would mean, in the present case, that in the future we should have a right to expect B along with A in seven cases out of ten. It means noth- ing with regard to the next case; we have no more reason for expecting one outcome than the other; our information has value only for the long run ; we have no right to expect that in the next ten cases B will be present seven or any other particular number of times ; but in the long run we may expect this proportion to hold and the longer the run the closer is the approxi- mation which we may expect. Compare this with one of the former illustrations, " Life will probably cease upon the earth." That does not mean that in a large number of cases of the sort before us life would cease in most of them ; we are here dealing with the particular case and all our arguments apply to it. In quantitative probability we know noth- ing of the circumstances of the particular case ; it is simply one of a certain group, and certain members of this group behave in one way, whereas others behave in a different way, and we cannot determine the circum- stances of their behavior in either case. The fraction expressing the degree of probability tells us that, in the past, the phenomenon has appeared in connection with a certain circumstance in such and such a pro- portion of cases and that we may, unless there are reasons to the contrary, expect this proportion to hold in the future. (We proceed here as elsewhere, upon the assumption that the future will be like the past and that any set of phenomena will behave in the future as it has in the past, in the absence of any new and dis- turbing factor.) 216 PROBABILITY Probability, in this connection, does not necessarily mean favorable odds. The event may have occurred in only one-tenth of the cases ; its probability will then be %o If it has occurred in one-half the number of cases, the probability will be %, etc. The calculations of insurance companies are based upon data showing the number of deaths per year for individuals of various ages, and so on. The great value of vital statistics and of statistics of many other sorts is to enable us to determine the probability of events which we cannot bring entirely under laws. Deducing the Probability of a Phenomenon. There are certain circumstances in which the probability of a phenomenon may be determined deductively. For ex- ample, we can say at once that in tossing a coin the probability of getting heads is % ; we know that there are two possibilities and only two ; if the coin is prop- erly made we know of no reason why one side should, in any particular case or in the long run, fall any oftener than the other. 1 We say that their chances are equal and that the probability of each is %. In the case of a die the proba- bility that any specified side will come uppermost is %. There are six possibilities, all equal. In the long run we expect each side to turn up as frequently as any other, viz., in one-sixth of the cases. The chances of any one are as 1:5; one for, and five against. If we have a bag containing twenty balls, three of which are white and the rest black, the probability of drawing a white ball is %o. In this instance there are twenty pos- i It is essential in such calculations that there be no known factor favoring a given result more than any other, DEDUCING PROBABILITY sibilities, three of which would give the desired result ; drawing a white ball may be brought about by realizing any one of three possibilities; or, out of twenty possi- bilities, three are favorable. In instances of this sort we have a definitely known number of possibilities, with no reason to believe that there is anything tending to bring about one rather than another. The probability of any specified one among them will be expressed by a fraction having 1 as its numerator and the number of possibilities as its denominator. In the case last cited the probability of drawing any particular ball is Ho- If among these possibilities any number of them favor the realization of any particular phenomenon, the probability of that phenomenon will be expressed by a fraction having as its denominator the total num- ber of possibilities and as its numerator the number of possibilities favorable to the occurrence of the phe- nomenon in question. If all the possibilities were fa- vorable (e. g., if all twenty balls were white), the frac- tion would be 2 %o or 1, which is the symbol for cer- tainty, or the upper limit of probability ; if none were favorable, it would be %o of 0, the lower limit, or im- possibility. Suppose we toss the coin twice (or toss two coins), what is the probability of getting heads both times? There are four possibilities, as follows : H H H T T H T T 218 PROBABILITY We might get heads in both, or heads in the first and tails in the second, or tails in the first and heads in the second, or tails in both. In only one of these does heads come in both throws ; the probability is therefore %. It is the same for two tails. For one heads and one tails it is %. For heads in the first throw and tails in the second it is again %, and so on. If we should toss it three times, the probability of getting heads each time would be %. There are eight possibilities : H H H T H H H H T T H T H T T T T H H T H T T T We can get the probability -for any number of throws by multiplying together the probabilities for each of the several throws; for two throws, % x%, or /4 ; for three, y 2 x y 2 x y 2 , O r y s ; for five, y 2 x y 2 x % x % x y>, or y 32 , and so on. The results would be the same if we should throw several coins at once instead of throwing one several times. Suppose we are drawing balls from two bags ; one of them contains three white and seventeen black balls ; the other contains two white and eight black balls. What is the probability of drawing a white ball from each? The probability, in one case, is %o, and in the other %o ; the probability of getting a white from each is therefore %oo or %oo. Each in one bag might be drawn with any one in the other ; hence there are 200 possibilities, only six of which are favor- able ; each of the two whites in one bag might be drawn with each of the three in the other. DETERMINING PROBABILITIES The probability of getting any combination of in- dependent events is thus obtained by taking the product of the probabilities of the several events. If two events are mutually exclusive the probability of getting one or the other would be the sum of their independent probabilities. In tossing a coin, the prob- ability of getting heads is % and that of getting tails is the same ; the probability of getting one or the other is the sum of the two or 1 = certainty. In throwing a die, the probability of getting a five is %, the proba- bility of getting a six is the same, the probability of getting one or the other is %. In tossing a coin twice, " It might be argued that since the probability of throwing heads at the first trial is % and at the second trial also %, the probability of throwing it in the first two throws is 1, or certainty. The true result is %, or the proba- bility of heads at the first throw, added to the exclusive probability that if it does not come at the first, it will come at the second." 2 The probability that it will come in the first is %. The probability that it will not come in the first is also % ; the probability that it will come in the second is also %. The. product of the two last gives the probability that if it does not come in the first, it will in the second. This product, added to the first %, gives the probability that it will come in at least one of the two throws. There are, of course, four possibilities in two throws, and three of them give at least one heads. If we represent the probability that an event will happen by p, then the probability that it will not hap- 2 Jevons, Principles of Science, chap, x, 3. 220 PROBABILITY pen is 1 p. The probability in throwing a die that five will not come up is 1 - % or %. Let us suppose a case in which six coins are tossed (or in which one coin is tossed six times) ; what are the probabilities of 6, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1 and heads respectively? There will be 64 possibilities, as follows : 6 HHHHHH TTTTTT 5 1 HHHHHT HTTTTT HHHHTH THTTTT HHHTHH TTHTTT HHTHHH TTTHTT HTHHHH TTTTHT THHHHH TTTTTH 4 2 HHHHTT HHTTTT HHHTTH THHTTT HHTTHH TTHHTT HTTHHH TTTHHT TTHHHH TTTTHH HHHTHT HTHTTT HHTHTH THTHTT HTHTHH TTHTHT THTHHH TTTHTH HHTHHT HTTHTT HTHHTH THTTHT THHTHH TTHTTH HTHHHT HTTTHT THHHTH THTTTH THHHHT HTTTTH PROBABILITY 221 3 3 HHHTTT HHTHTT HHTTTH HTHTTH HTTTHH THTTHH TTTHHH HTHHTT HHTTHT THHTTH HTTHTH THHTHT TTHTHH THTHHT HTTHHT THTHTH TTHHTH HTHTHT T T H H H T T H H H T T One combination gives six heads, six give five, etc. The probabilities for 6, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, and heads are respectively % 4 , %4, 15 /64, 2 %4, 15 /64, %4, y 64 . In ten throws the number of possibilities would be 1024; the numbers favoring 10, 9, 8, 7, 6, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, and heads would be respectively, 1, 10, 45, 120, 210, 252, 210, 120, 45, 10, 1. Examination will show that these series of numbers (1, 6, 15, 20, etc., and 1, 10, 45, 120, etc.) are the coefficients of the terms of a binominal raised to the power indicated by the number of throws (6, 10, etc.). In these cases the phenomena are not mu- tually exclusive. The fact that heads comes (or does not come) in any throw makes no difference to the other throws. There are important scientific applications of the facts just brought out. 1 " Suppose, for the sake of argument, that all persons were naturally of the equal stature of five feet, but enjoyed during youth seven independent chances of growing one inch in addition* ijevons, Principles of Science, chap, ix, 5. PROBABILITY Of these seven chances, one, two, three, or more, mny happen favorably to any individual; . . . out of every 128 people: 1 person would have the stature of ,5 feet inches. 7 persons " " " " 5 " 1 " O1 it U U U U K 35 " " " " " 5 " 3 " 35 " " " " " 5 " 4 " 4)1 it U U U K (.1 K iy U 4< U U U ")"() " | u a