REESE LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFQRNI MAR 23 1894 ts No GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD A of t^e C^fef BY A. GRATRY ji PROFESSOR OF MORAL THEOLOGY AT THE SORBONNE TRANSLATED BY ABBY LANGDON ALGER WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY WILLIAM ROUNSEVILLE ALGER ( This Work was Crowned by the French Academy ) f& * i CNJ\ -K BOSTOIT ROBERTS BROTHERS 1892 Copyright, 1892, BY ROBERTS BROTHERS. ress: JOHN WILSON AND SON, CAMBRIDGE, U.S.A. TABLE OF CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. PAOE BY WILLIAM ROUNSEVILLE ALGER . . 1-11 first CHAPTER I. EXPLANATORY. A summary of the whole work. Why philosophy begins with a treatise on the knowledge of God, with the knowledge whereby the mind of man rises to God. I. Is it possible and necessary to prove the existence of God? Are there atheists? II. General character of the genuine proof of the existence of God. III. Precise nature of that proof : it is the principal application of one of the two essential processes of reason ; it is the act and fundamental process of the ra- tional and moral life. The study of this proof is the study of phi- losophy in its principle : studied historically, it is the basis of the history of philosophy ; studied speculatively, it places the mind at the point where the roots of ontology, psychology, logic, and morals meet 13-25 CHAPTER II. PLATO'S THEODICY. I. Why it belonged to the school of Socrates to give to the antique world the laws of the chief process of reason, and to attain to the true philosophical proof of the existence of God. II. Platonic dia- lectic : the condition for its exercise ; its point of support, its move- ment, its term. III. Discussion of texts from Plato concerning the nature of the dialectic process. IV. Use which man should vi CONTENTS. PAGE make of this divine gift, to conquer the obstacle, develop the sense of the immortal and the divine. V. Starting-point of the dialectic process in the spectacle of visible objects. VI. full description of the process. VII. Term of the process (re'Xos rijs nopeias). Two degrees of the divine intelligible : shadows of that which is, or divine phantasms : the Divine Being himself. VIII. The idea of the true God as found in Plato. IX. Plato combats the false application of the chief process of reason, sophistry. X. Summary of Plato's Theodicy. XI. What Saint Augustine, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Bossuet, and Thomassin think of the Platonic doctrine . . . 26-61 CHAPTER III. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. I. Relations between Plato and Aristotle. II. Proof of the existence of God given by Aristotle and summed up by Saint Thomas Aquinas. III. Discussion of that proof. Its logical value is doubtful in the form in which it is given. IV. The result of Aristotle's Theodicy : an immutable essence ; a principle whose essence is very act : God pure act; how the motionless motor moves; attraction of the desir- able and intelligible; God is an eternal and perfect living being, Goodness, Thought, and Life. That which is in us is finite, in God exists infinitely. V. Aristotle's error in regard to the eternity of the universe. VI. God's relation to the world, according to Aris- totle. VII. Summary of Aristotle's Theodicy. VIII. Distinction between the two degrees of the divine intelligible. IX. Aristotle's proof of the existence of God is at bottom precisely the same as that of Descartes. Decision in regard to Aristotle 62-94 CHAPTER IV. SAINT AUGDSTINE'S THEODICY. I. Saint Augustine's opinion of philosophy. II. Analogy and differ- ence between Plato and Saint Augustine : Quidqmd a Platone dicitur, vivit in Augustino. III. What Saint Augustine sees in Plato ; what he adds to him. IV. Theory of the method which lifts us to God and the truth, according to Saint Augustine (gradus ad immor- talia faciendux) . V. Elaboration of what precedes. Saint Augus- tine more exact than Plato in regard to the theory of the philosophical method which proves God. VI. Great superiority of Saint Au- gustine over Plato concerning the theory of the divine sense, prin- ciple of the moral and intellectual impulse towards God. VII. The CONTENTS. vii PAGE final term attained by reason, when God lifts it to himself (Ratio perveniens ad Jinem suuni). VIII. Results of Saint Augustine's philosophical method. Idea of the infinite ; doctrine of the creation. IX. Journey of reason towards God, according to Saint Augus- tine : two degrees of the divine intelligible. X. Conclusion : the Temple ; two ways of regarding it 95-142 CHAPTER V. SAINT ANSELM'S THEODICY. I. General sense of Saint Anselm's philosophical works. II. What is Saint Anselm's argument ? III. Fuller analysis of that argu- ment. IV. How far reason can go, according to Saint Anselm 143-157 CHAPTER VI. SAINT THOMAS AQUINAS* THEODICY. I. Relations between Saint Thomas Aquinas and Saint Augustine. II. Literal translation of a Question by Saint Thomas Aquinas, which is an abridged treatise on the existence of God : De Deo an Dem sit (Sum. Theol. l a . q. 11). III. Discussion of this chapter from Saint Thomas. IV. Theory of the method which lifts our mind to God, according to Saint Thomas : 1. The starting-point in the spec- tacle of created beings ; 2. The process, which takes three names : via causalitatis, via eminently vel excellentice, via negationis vel re- motionis ; 3. The moral obstacle : veritatem Dei in. injustitia detinent. V. Distinction between the two degrees of the divine intelligible : visio speculariSy visio per essentiam. Distinction in the higher of the two degrees : light of grace, in via videntium ; light of glory, in pa- tria mdentium. VI. Conclusion 158-184 CHAPTER VII. THEODICY OF THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. Philosophic character of the seventeenth century : unity of mind of its great men ; unity of process. DESCARTES. I. His philosophical character. II. His starting-point to prove the existence of God : unity of his two proofs. III. Double character of the true proof, both rational and experimental. IV. Objective viii CONTENTS. PAGE reality of the idea of God, according to Descartes : this idea is a cer- tain vision of God. This vision is indirect : I possess it by the same faculty by which I know myself. It is the IMAGE of a genuine and immutable nature. That image is only that which we see when the mind conceives, judges, or reasons. V. How Descartes' two proofs are inseparable and form but one. VI. The process of Descartes does not differ from the dialectic of Plato. VII. Hiatus in the ideas of Descartes, or at least in his work. Danger of Cartesianism ill understood. Conclusion. To distinguish between, but not to separate, the two orders of the divine intelligible. PASCAL. I. Part played by Pascal considered as a philosopher. II. His scep- ticism is not genuine scepticism, any more than is Descartes' doubt. He is especially averse to isolated reason. III. Pascal's doctrine concerning the rational knowledge of God. Pascal's deficiency. Conclusion. 2// MALEBRANCHE. I. Merit of Malebranche. Solid side of his doctrine. II. Male- branche's practical and habitual method. III. How he proves the existence of God. IV. Malebranche confounds the two orders of the divine intelligible. This is his error. "*-*J FENELON. I. Fenelon's philosophical character. His superiority. II. Fenelon corrects the exclusive points of view of Pascal and Malebranche. His analysis of reason, the best that has been made, is at the same time the most beautiful of the proofs of the existence of God. III. Profound comparison by which Fenelon explains the nature of ideas and reason : his superiority over Malebranche. IV. His the- ory of the process by which our reason rises to God. Conclusion. PETAU AND THOMASSIN. I. Analysis of an important chapter by Petau, in which he explains his method of demonstrative theology. II. Philosophical character of Thomassin. III. Starting-point of the process which proves God, according to Thomassin. IV. Profoundly original theory given by Thomassin in regard to what has been called the innate idea of God. V. Continuation of that theory. VI. Remarks on the starting-point of the process which lifts our mind to God. VII. Theory of that process. Thomassin's excess of tolerance in regard to Neo-Platonism. VIII. Clear distinction between the two regions of the divine intelligible. CONTENTS. BOSSUET. PAGE I. Bossuet's philosophical character. II. Relations between the question of Quietism and the philosophic proof of the existence of God. III. God proved by the spectacle of nature and by his op- erations in us. IV. God proved by his idea taken in itself. V. Description of the practical process which lifts us to God. THE HIDDEN SPRING. The other light. jL7 L LEIBNITZ. I. Philosophical character of Leibnitz. His chief title to glory. II. Did Leibnitz understand the relation between the infinitesimal process and the corresponding logical process ? III. Leibnitz re- gards as good almost all the means which have been employed to prove the existence of God. He thinks he has reduced the proof of the existence of God to mathematic precision. He remoulds Saint Anselm's proof. IV. Summary of the Theodicy of Leibnitz. V. Analogy between his Theodicy and his geometry. Conclusion 185-303 CHAPTER VIII. ON THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. I. The true proof of the existence of God also gives us the attributes of God. Deduction of all God's metaphysical attributes from any one of those attributes. II. Intellectual and moral attributes. III. Ipsum intelligere Dei est ejus substantia. The various ideas in God. IV. God's providence. Creation. Death. V. To what the triple distinction between the attributes of God corresponds 304-326 CHAPTER IX. INFINITESIMAL PROCESS. I. How the proof of the existence of God is, as Descartes and Leib- nitz assert, mathematically exact. It is the highest application of the general infinitesimal method, of which the geometrical infini- tesimal process is merely a special application. II. Why many minds reverse the process which lifts our mind to God, and direct it in a contrary course. The scientific process of modern atheism is only the infinitesimal process inversely applied. Its result is an ex- act proof, ad absurdum, of the existence of God. III. Conclusion of first part of the Treatise on the Knowledge of God . . . 327-348 CONTENTS. fart econti. CHAPTER I. THE TWO DEGREES OP THE DIVINE INTELLIGIBLE. I. Three states of reason. II. Description of these different states of reason. III. Causes of these different states. IV. Continuation. How reason attains to its highest term : Ratio perveniens ad Jinem suum . ...... . . 349-362 CHAPTER II. RELATIONS BETWEEN REASON AND FAITH. Distinction between the two degrees of the divine intelligible, that to which reason attains, and that which, of itself, it cannot grasp, according to Saint Thomas. II. Comparison between reason and faith, according to Saint Thomas, Thomassin, and Saint Augustine. III. Analogy to this distinction in Saint Paul. IV. What can reason do without faith ? V. Parallel between the two forms of wisdom, natural and supernatural, by Cornelius a Lapide. Reason and faith compared by the Council of Trent. VI. Evident limits of reason. VII. What is natural reason ? Analogy between the evolution of reason and that of faith. VIII. What is sound reason and what perverted reason? Reason conjoined to its principle; reason doubting its principle 363-392 CHAPTER III. RELATIONS BETWEEN REASON AND FAITH (Continued). I. What is sound reason (continued) ? Natural faith. II. Natu- ral faith, divine sense, according to the Holy Scripture. III. Natu- ral faith according to Aristotle, the Alexandrians, and Kant. IV. Natural faith, according to Thomassin. V. Reason supported by its principle, by natural faith. VI. Is there, actually, no super- natural gift mingled with sound natural reason 1 393-410 CONTENTS. xi CHAPTER IV. RELATIONS BETWEEN KEASON AND FAITH (Continued). PAGE I. What can sound reason do ? It may recognize its limitations, and regret that which it lacks : this is its highest capability. II. Exact precision of theological formulas on this subject. The perfection of the rational creature depends upon a certain gift superior to the na- ture of the created being. Geometrical analogy. III. Natural desire to see God, according to Saint Thomas 411-431 CHAPTER V. RELATIONS BETWEEN REASON AND FAITH (Continued). I. Transition from reason to faith. II. Evening light and morning light. III. Genesis of light according to the Gospel . . . 432-417 CHAPTER VI. RELATIONS BETWEEN REASON AND FAITH (Continued). SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION. I. Two degrees of light : Sound reason. Perverted reason. Slug- gish reason. Comparison. II. Theological Summary. III. We must advance, with the help of God, to the higher of the two degrees of the divine intelligible 448-469 UNJVEKblTY INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. BY WILLIAM ROUNSEVILLE ALGER. TN its original language the work here translated has passed through many editions, and has attained the rank of an authoritative classic. It is characterized by such comprehensiveness of scope, such force and beauty of style, such amplitude of learning, such ripeness and pre- cision of thought, such depth of experience, and such catho- licity of spirit that no one can fitly read it without being instructed, stimulated, and edified. The author sweeps with the ease of a consummate mastery through the wisdom of twenty-five centuries, gathers up the chief treasures depos- ited there by the kings of insight, and presents them con- structed into one harmonious whole. The question with which he grapples as strenuously as any one ever has done, is whether the human mind is able to attain to a real knowledge of God. To the examination of this sublime theme he brings both an intense earnestness and an unfail- ing sobriety; while adding to these high qualities all that historic erudition and training can yield from without, or personal acumen and consecration furnish from within. The result, as embodied in the present volume, is one with which, in point of attractiveness and solid value, no work on the same subject within the entire compass of English literature can for a moment stand a comparison. Gratry answers the question, Can man know God ? in the most effective way possible, by setting forth, in systematic i 2 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. outline and with appropriate detail, the experimental and critical conclusions at which a large number of the most illustrious thinkers of our race, from Plato and Aristotle to Fe'nelon and Leibnitz, have actually arrived on that subject. He lays bare the methods they employed, the dif- ficulties they encountered, the arguments they constructed, the aids they received, the results they conquered, and their fundamental agreement through all. He does this with an incisiveness of thought, a summarizing skill, a patience, an impartiality, and a lucidity most admirable and most de- lightful. It is true that as we pass on from name to name there seems to be a good deal of repetition. But there is ever a variety in the sameness, a progressive growth in the exposition, a cumulative gain through the repeatals, which fully reward the reader. As he goes over, in theodicy after theodicy, what appear to be quite identical statements, he will more and more find doubts dissolved, objections an- swered, obscurities illuminated, peace bestowed, assurance and satisfaction breaking in. There are very few, even among professional students of philosophy, who will not find themselves abundantly repaid for a patient perusal of all the repetitions in these freighted pages, so momentous are the themes treated, and so masterly is the treatment. One of the central traits of this work is the appeal the author makes for the action of human nature in its integ- rity as regulated by the sovereign unity of the rational principle. He protests against the division of the soul into a collection of abstracting faculties which operate separ- ately and breed all sorts of error, fiction, and confusion. He quotes approvingly the bold remark of Fenelon, " Eeason is even more wanting on earth than religion." Having also cited the great saying of Saint Thomas, " In the moral order, crimes against nature are worse than sacrilege," he adds, " So in the intellectual order that crime against nature which INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. 3 attacks reason is worse than the sacrilege which attacks faith ; for to ruin reason is to prostrate the religious edifice by undermining the ground." The vindication of the powers and rights of reason, so nobly illustrated in the whole body of the work, has been formally stated by Gratry in the following eloquent passage, which is no less timely than it is just and weighty: " What is the common and natural state of the reason among men 3 We see it all about us. God is still unknown to the ma- jority of men, and almost all are profoundly ignorant of their des- tiny, their nature, and their duty. The majority still reject the unmistakable light thrown upon human questions by universal reason, aided by God, and they are unable to pass this first and natural initiatory step, and far from attaining to the higher initi- ation which God has prepared for all. Very few men even suc- ceed in gaining complete mastery of their body ; nearly all live a fortuitous and turbulent life, conducive to premature old age and untimely death. "How few reasonable beings there are who cultivate in them- selves the sacred gift of reason ! The greater number cultivate the earth ; others cultivate nothing. Throughout humanity, with but rare exceptions, reason, that sacred talent intrusted by God to every man on his entrance into this world, remains sterile or buried. " Bossuet, speaking of reason hidden in the flesh, says : ' What efforts must we not make to distinguish our soul from our body ! How many of us there are who never attain to the knowledge or slightest perception of this distinction ! ' ' How many are there who rise somewhat above this mass of flesh, and clear their soul from it?' " Yes, there are but very few men in whom reason is distinct from the mass of instincts, sensations, and wants, constituting a free force and an independent power. With almost all it is a sorely oppressed force, a power subordinated, not only to the im- agination, the senses, interests, and desires, but also to the cur- rent of the blood and the disposition, the influence of the matter which feeds otir body, and the forces of physical nature. Reason, the logical varnish of a purely animal life, the blind and trivial 4 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. bond of our passions, desires, humors, and sensations, reason, blended with the whole, and carried away by the general move- ment, obeys slavishly, instead of ruling. "There are, among God's creatures, animals belonging to the lower grades of life. Their body is but a uniform mass, without distinct organs. Each point represents as well as any other the essential centres of life, and exercises all its functions vapidly and indifferently. There is no distinct heart or brain ; all is con- founded in the sum total of the mass. Well, just such is the in- tellectual organization of the multitude at the present day. Reason is in the germ, but not developed ; it is spread throughout the mass, but is destitute of distinct central organ. It does not form, let me repeat, a free force and an independent power. The minds of such men may be compared to those inferior organizations in the animal scale which have no distinct brain. "And with those who have developed the germ of reason to some slight degree, how is the development accomplished 1 ? 'We seldom encounter anywhere other than warped intellects,' said A*naud in the seventeenth century. What would he say now? " What is a warped intellect 1 Bacon defines it very "happily : ' It is a mirror without symmetry, irregular, in the beams of the sun.' * Joubert uses the same figure in regard to one of our more excessive thinkers : ' Thomas has a concave head ; it exaggerates and enlarges everything which it reflects.' Now, just as crooked mirrors deform every image, so a warped intellect distorts the data which might raise it to the heights of truth. This one-sided in- telligence falsifies the truth which strikes it; it is addressed in words of truth, it hears falsehood ; beauty and sublimity are held up before it, it sees only deformity. This may be accounted for. Just as unsymmetrical surfaces are fantastic and distorted mirrors which falsify by their unevenly developed dimensions, so a warped intellect is a disproportionately developed intellect. For is not our weak understanding usually employed in the exclusive direc- tion of one ruling passion, one fixed idea or supreme prejudice'? Who is there whose intellectual mirror is a regular surface in every direction, spherical as the vault of heaven, or smooth as the mirror of the waters? "Certainly the majority of minds are strange and distorted reflectors. INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. 5 " Being thus formed, they can derive only error from the spec- tacle of visible things and of the inner actions of the soul, and from that of human events. They gaze, and fancy that they see everything ; they do see everything but the sum total and the pro- portions. It is thus that we observe the world, that we write history, and that we describe mankind. It is thus that, day by day, we retrace present facts visible to every eye ; and the tale is false. We do not deliberately lie, but we give everything facti- tious dimensions, conformed to the desired effect. We enlarge what pleases us, and render imperceptible whatever offends. We are false, and we see things as we ourselves are. " There is another natural infirmity of the reason, which is very apparent at the present time. Even those who think somewhat correctly, think but little and almost fruitlessly, because they are isolated, because each mind sees by itself alone ; union and associa- tion of intellectual forces are yet to come. The confusion of tongues, the antagonism of sects, the subdivision of intellectual persons, and above all, the secret question at the bottom of every heart, 'God or no god,' the question which divides mankind into two camps, is anything more than this needed to keep apart those who think 1 The sphere of the intellectual world is still inhabited on the exterior, not at the centre, where all rays meet, but only on the surface, where all are divided : so that there are, in the world of science and of thought, regions divided by space, subject to different heavens, speaking different languages, and much more foreign to one another than the various races of the earth. Each science is surrounded by a high wall, and so is every intellect. The unity of the human mind is less attained than that of the globe. "If we would save religion, society, and civilization, the first work to undertake is the restoration of public reason. We must re-establish in the minds of men a knowledge of and respect for reason and its laws, and the practice of these laws, logic. It must be known, for it has been forgotten, that there are both error and truth in the world, and that the one may be distinguished from the other; that there is a true method of human thinking, that is to say, there are fixed principles and legitimate processes ; that these principles and processes have been practised in all ages in- stinctively by many persons, and might have been so in a certain sense by all; that they were practised with some conscientious- 6 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. ness and with admirable results by philosophical minds in every century; but that they were ignored and violated by the blind criticism and lawless practice of sophists in all ages ; that the true philosophical method, without being yet very completely defined, has nevertheless, in the course of ages, been determined and de- veloped by the success of its applications and the even clearer sense of those great intellects who made use of it ; but that there exists a false method and a sophistical process, which has never ceased to impede the advance of philosophy by its perturbing action, and that this power of contradiction, ever increasing, seems to borrow strength from the very progress of truth. " This being thoroughly perceived, we must proceed to separate these shadows and this light ; that is, we must at last learn to make a scientific distinction between sophistry and philosophy. We must give their true names, in history, to philosophers and sophists. Moving in a direction contrary to contemporary eclecticism, philo- sophy must at last proceed to the necessary excommunication of its domestic foes, instead of greeting and embracing them. The errone- ous method, and that whicli leads to truth, must be exactly defined j we must recognize, what is manifest enough, that the sophistical process is nothing but the philosophical method inverted. ''The division once accomplished, and the sophists set apart, we must restore the legitimate rule of reason and philosophy among us by the study of genuine philosophers, by the practice and knowledge of their method, as well as by a study of the sophists, considered as a counter proof and demonstration through the absurd. "Philosophy, a universal science, must come forth from its isolation and look face to face at the special branches of science which regard philosophy with contempt. Philosophy, as a wise writer expresses it, must cross the boundary-line, enter the domain of science, and take possession of it. It is right that all these branches of science which philosophy created should be subject to it ; or rather, it is right that the human mind should cease to be divided into regions unknown each to the other, and that the various sciences should resume their natural relations in the unity of philosophy. " Still more must be done, if we are to re-establish the serious education of reason among us. " It is not enough that science should exist, it must become a INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. 7 part of human intelligence ; and reason must be actually developed in every man, or at least in the majority of those who desire to think, and believe that they do so. " Now, so long as we blindly refuse to recognize that the solid and healthy growth of thought proceeds from the growth of the entire soul and will, there can be no mental change. There can be no advance of reason without a corresponding advance in moral strength and freedom. Intellect and will, reason and freedom, are the two wings of the soul, upon which it rises to its only object, which is goodness, and at the same time truth. " Farther yet, and this is the supreme question in the life of the human mind and its history, a vital question for the human intellect, is our reason conjoined to that of God, or is it wholly separate ? Is reason destined to become holy, or to sink into degradation? At which extreme is it to stop] For it will not remain at this sterile and changeable intermediate, which is the end of nothing; it must either fall or rise. " Reason is a force that seeks for its beginning and end. Now, the truth is, that the beginning and the end of reason is God. The human heart seeks God no more unceasingly than reason does. Only in this pursuit the mind, as well as the heart, is subject to change. When the human heart changes, we have moral perversion. \V hen the human mind changes, we have intellectual perversion, the vice of sophists. ' Truth,' says Saint Augustine, ' lies in placing in God these three things, the cause of the world, the supreme good, the fulcrum of reason.' Nothing more profound could be said. Very certainly the whole history of philosophy and sophistry is con- tained in that sentence. Only Saint Augustine makes no mention here of the final abyss irto which the sophist plunges when, setting God apart from reason, he undermines the latter to discover its origin. " But what happens when, far from dividing it from God, we conjoin the two, and reason follows its research to the end? ' Reason/ says Saint Augustine, * reason, attaining its end, be- comes virtue/ But what virtue? Let us see. " There is a height, according to Saint Augustine, where reason stops. This is its end. This is plain to every true philosopher. ' The science of the human mind/ said Royer-Collard, ' will have been carried to the highest degree of perfection which it can attain when it can derive ignorance from its primary source.' 8 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. " There is, therefore, let us say with Saint Augustine, a height where reason stops : this is its end. But there it goes on in something which is not itself; as one river flows into another, or is borne to the ocean. This is the point where the mind of man is continued in the mind of God himself, and is subject to it. This subjection, or rather this high degree of elevation of the human reason, subject to the mind of God, is faith. Faith, that is the virtue to which reason soars when it attains its end. 'Faith is indeed,' says Pascal, 'the last step of reason.' Only we must of course agree as to this capital truth whose admission or rejection decides the destinies of the world and the human mind. " We affirm that this subjection of the human mind to the Spirit of God is not the destruction of reason, but its final perfection. Reason, said Saint Thomas Aquinas, the most exact of philosophers as well as the greatest of theologians, reason is capable of a two- fold perfection ; namely, its proper and natural perfection, resulting from its own principles and its own powers, and the perfection which it borrows from its union and subjection to the Spirit of God himself, a principle higher and greater than it. This is its final and supernatural perfection ; it is the human mind engrafted upon the Divine mind, if we may so express it. Reason then bears fruits which it could not bear; and as the poet says, repeating the words of Nature herself, " 'Admires those fruits which are not hers.' " These fruits are those of the Spirit of God become the directly fertilizing principle of human reason, which none the less retains its individual principles. "Far from diminishing reason, the introduction of the higher principle lifts it to incomparable greatness, vivifies its powers, and increases the fruitfulness of its natural principle. " This alliance, in one sense, may be compared to the divine alliance, to which Saint Thomas Aquinas alludes when he says, ' Divine knowledge in the soul of Christ did not kill human knowl- edge, but made it more luminous.' " It is of this alliance that a holily far-sighted spirit said, early in the seventeenth century : * There are three kinds of knowledge, purely divine knowledge, the purely human knowledge, and knowl- edge at once human and divine, which is indeed the true knowledge of Christians. 9 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. 9 " It was this alliance which the genius of the seventeenth cen- tury, the parent of knowledge, actually sought. Instituted by those great men who were all at once theologians, philosophers, and scientists, from Kepler down to Leibnitz, passing by Pascal, Descartes, Malebranche, Bossuet, and Fenelon, this sacred alli- ance of all departments of intellect one with the other, and of the human mind with the divine mind, was the cause of the greatness and creative fertility of that period, the most luminous in history. But since this tie was severed, we have only dimmed that match- less light, and most of us can no longer even see it. " So that when human reason is conjoined to God through faith, history shows it, besides the new and sublime data which result, its natural powers are increased, its individual prin- ciples bear their rarest natural fruits, mingled with divine fruits. When, on the contrary, reason breaks the alliance always offered to every mind, in every age, this refusal, this reversion to its un- aided self, this isolation and sacrilegious negation, weaken its natural powers, and lead it, from negation to negation, to deny itself, an intellectual suicide whose name is sophistry. " Consider the great and wonderful symbolism, too little under- stood and too little heeded, which the eighteenth century affords us in that final scene when man strove to reject God and to wor- ship himself and his own reason only ! " What did man do when he attempted to place human reason on the altar, to adore that alone ? "Let history speak. He placed a naked prostitute upon the altar. That is, he put upon the altar reason smeared with mud, reason smothered in flesh and blood. " And what was cast down from that altar to make way for this infamous goddess '{ Heed the answer well ! Human reason was cast down, but human reason allied with God. "Men did not know, they do not yet know, that human reason can find place upon a Catholic altar. " What is there, then, on the Catholic altar if it be not Jesus Christ 1 ? And what is Jesus Christ, if he be not God allied to man ? ' The Divine Word,' says our dogma, ' took on, in its incarnation, a human soul, a human soul gifted with reason. 9 "I give the exact statement, in the language of the Church : * Verbura divinum aniniam humanam, eamque rationis participem, assumpsit/ 10 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. " Thus, according to our dogma, human reason, in actual pres- ence, was upon the Catholic altar; it was there conjoined with God. It was driven thence, to be replaced by human reason degraded and dragged through the mud. The holy altar was stripped of the su- preme reason, the reason of Jesus, the reason of the Man-God, and replaced by the feeble reason of a lewd crew. Men were given their choice of alliance, reason allied to filth, or reason conjoined to God. They made their choice. "We will not rest satisfied with this choice. We will reject what we took, and take back what we rejected. Soon, I hope, the majority of us will understand what was so happily and finely ex- pressed in a now famous address : ' The great question, the supreme question, which now absorbs all minds, is the question put by those who recognize and those who do not recognize a supernatural, sure, and supreme order of things. . . . For our present and future safety alike, faith in the supernatural order, submission to the natural order, must re-enter the world, and the human soul must be born again in great minds as well as in simple ones, in the highest as well as in the humblest regions.' " Yes, our present and future safety demand faith in the super- natural order. " At this price reason may resume its sway over us ; the mind may be lifted up and rescued. At this price we may yet see some- thing of Leibnitz's great prediction accomplished: 'Let us hope that a time may come when men will devote themselves to reason more than they have hitherto done.' Upheld by God, and living by faith, far more men will succeed in some degree in freeing their soul and reason from this weight of flesh, and in living, throughout an entire lifetime, by the love of justice and truth alone ; more men will take up, conscientiously and vigorously, literature, science, and philosophy, as sacred instruments to be used for the good of hu- manity, for the increase of light, wisdom, and dignity among men, for the progress of the world towards God." Few works can compare with this one by Professor Gratry as an exhibition of the compass of human reason and of what Saint Thomas Aquinas calls " the much-misappreciated power of reasoning." He clearly shows the truth of the assertion INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. 11 of Descartes and Leibnitz, repeated by Cardinal Gerdil, that the existence of God and his infinite perfections may be as rigorously proved as the solution of any mathematical prob- lem. He shows this with the most brilliant originality, by proving that the demonstration of the existence of God is the supreme achievement of a general process of the reason, of which the infinitesimal methods of geometry are but a special application. The attention of the reader is particularly in- vited to the exposition of this assertion where it occurs in the following pages. It is no less fruitful and illuminating in its consequences than it is startlingly original in itself. The character and life of the illustrious author of this work were in full keeping with his attainments and fame. He was not merely a scholar and a philosopher, but likewise a philanthropist and a saint, who thoroughly lived the doc- trine he taught. In his spiritual will were found, after his death, these touching words : " 1 leave to every human being whom I have ever greeted or blessed, or to whom I have ever spoken any word o'f esteem or affection, the assurance that I love and bless him twice and thrice as much as I said. I entreat all such to pray for me, that I may attain to the kingdom of love, whither I will draw him too through the infinite goodness of our Father." In order to bring the two volumes of the original within the compass of a single larger volume in the translation, the superfluous appendices and some of the foot-notes contain- ing the texts rendered by the author in the body of his work, have been omitted. The prefaces to the first three editions, abounding with personal and local references, as well as a long and polemical Introduction, have likewise been left out. The editor of this translation deems it his duty, in bring- ing the work before the public in its English dress, to add a word of protest against the view which Gratry gives of the German school of philosophy as presented in the culminating 12 INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSLATION. exposition of Hegel. Ecclesiastical prejudice, national bias, differences in points of view and in nomenclature, have pre- vented many Catholic thinkers of the highest ability, includ- ing even Eos mini, from seeing the real depth and the solid result of the speculative movement begun by Kant, advanced by Fichte, and carried through by Hegel. Because the dia- lectic of the transcendental school is that of a negative unity, its foes charge it with being exclusively negative, and ending in nihilism. But Aristotle says, in the first chapter of the last book of his Metaphysics, "All contraries inseparably belong to a subject." Hegel was the first thinker syste- matically to develop this statement through all its implica- tions. He showed, as Fichte had partly done before, that every lower set of contraries is reconciled in a higher cate- gory, whose unity contains and mediates them, the highest category being free self -consciousness. The negative dialectic presupposes the affirmative, as the affirmative dialectic pre- supposes the negative ; because both presuppose the absolute dialectic, without which neither of these could be. Thus the negative phase of the dialectic, when completed, is found to carry also the opposite phase, and to coincide with the whole sphere of a self-determining unity. Hegelianism ends neither with atheism nor pantheism nor nihilism, but with a solidly grounded vision of God, freedom, and immortality. This does not affect the value of the present work in its positive exposition, which unveils a mine of matchless wealth, hidden, for the most part, from the Protestant world by ignorance and prejudice. The central part of the divine wisdom of the Catholic Church, the speculative insight cu- mulatively developed in a broadening and brightening river of tradition by its peerless thinkers and saints through so many centuries, is here freely offered to all who are able to understand it and willing to receive it. GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. CHAPTEE I. EXPLANATOKY. ," says Bossuet, "consists in knowing God and knowing one's self." These words are, in brief, a true definition of philosophy. They mean, at the outset, that philosophy is the search for wisdom; that is, the search, both theoretical and prac- tical, for goodness and truth. They declare that philosophy is not that abstract and purely speculative knowledge of which Bossuet also says elsewhere, "Woe to that barren knowledge which never turns to love, and is false to itself ! " These words, moreover, limit the object of philosophy. That object is God and man; it is man seeking through the intellect and the will to find goodness and truth, which are God. On the other hand, this definition does not divide those things which are incapable of division, and does not exclude from philosophy a knowledge of bodies and of the visible world. "For," says Bossuet, "to know man, we must know that he is made up of two parts, which are the body and the soul." Hence we see that philosophy also treats of visible and material nature, especially in its relation to the soul and to God. 14 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. So that the various divisions of philosophy are I. THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD (Theodicy). II. THE KNOWLEDGE OF THE SOUL, considered in its re- lations to God and the body (Psychology). III. LOGIC, which is a further development of psychology, and which studies the soul through its intelligence, and the laws of that intelligence. IV. MORALS, which is another outgrowth of psychology, and which studies the soul through its will, and the laws of that will. We shall explain these different divisions of philosophy, each in turn, beginning with the theodicy. This order is that of Descartes, Fe'nelon, Malebranche, and Saint Thomas Aquinas. Bossuet followed the inverse order. But we prefer to begin with the theodicy, because in our view it implies the whole of philosophy. It shows it to us as a unity, a totality ; it contains all its roots. Every- thing proceeds from it; it is therefore the starting-point. Moreover, the theodicy, which is the loftiest, most pro- found department of philosophy, is also the simplest. Ideas of infinity and perfection, as Descartes, Bossuet, and the majority of philosophers remark, are the first which awakening reason reveals to us, which proves that reason first impels us towards God. It is the cause of nature, at the same time that it is the absolute order of truths taken in themselves. But by theodicy must not be understood only the knowl- edge of God; it also means most particularly the knowledge of the human mind aspiring towards God. The theodicy is the knowledge of that wonderful process of the reason which soars towards God and aspires to know and prove his existence, nature, and attributes. From this point of view we shall realize later how the theodicy sums up all philosophy in a single question, EXPLANATORY. 15 namely, the proof of the existence of God and his attri- butes, a question which the readers of this book will, I hope, find neither barren nor commonplace, and upon which we must at once enter. Is it possible to prove the existence of God ? Is it essen- tial ? Is not the truth of the existence of God self-evident and indemonstrable as an axiom? Can there- be atheists? It seems at first that this proposition, God is, is identical with the similar proposition, Being is. And so it really is to all who know the meaning of the word God, since that word means " Him who is." This statement, therefore, is one of those which are evident as soon as their terms are known. Its terms imply its truth, for the subject and attri- bute are identical ; and it bears its certainty on its face, as does this, The whole is greater than a part. But all men do not know the meaning of the word God, all not understanding that God is none other than He who is. The truth of God's existence is not clear to all, and it requires to be proved from a basis of universal ideas. The proposition which asserts it is identical, but its identity is not apparent to all eyes. And in fact there are atheists. Atheism, both theoretical and practical, is a profound vice, or rather, the radical vice of the heart and human mind. No age has been free from it. Our own is more fully infected by it than we think. Practical atheism is visible to every eye, and philosophical atheism is revealed under the form of pantheism. More yet, express, exact, avowed, and declared atheism has a school of its own ; and this school of new atheism, more scientific than the old atheism, is built upon a foundation which it calls Modern Science. 16 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. It is not difficult, in truth, to do justice to this would-be modern science. We shall prove, in the proper place, that it is nothing else than the radical vice of the human heart and mind disguised as doctrine, and that its scientific semblance conies from the fact that it applies, though in inverse order, the true method and fundamental process of reason. But first let us assert that the existence of God can be strictly proved, and that no geometrical theorem is more certain. This is, moreover, the opinion of Descartes, as well as of Leibnitz ; the learned Cardinal Gerdil said the same. We shall treat this point, which implies all metaphysics, all morals, all logic, and all the theory of the method, with the fulness which is deserved by this prime question of philosophy, whose basis and summary it is. II. In the first place, if there are true proofs of the existence of God, these proofs must be within the reach of all men ; for the light of God shines, and should shine, upon every man in this world. Therefore, to find useful proofs of the existence of God, we should seek his origin and reality in some ordinary and daily act of the human mind ; and this sublime and simple act being found, it will suffice to describe it, and translate it into philosophical language. We shall then prove its scien- tific value. Now, this ordinary daily act of the human soul, mind, and heart, intellect and will, is no other than the universal fact of prayer ; and I mean, philosophically speaking, by prayer what Descartes defines when he says, " I feel that I am a finite being, unceasingly striving for and aspiring to some- thing better and greater than I am." Prayer is the move- ment of the soul from the finite towards the infinite. EXPLANATORY. 17 Scorn of present reality, so natural to man ; expectation of an ideal future, so habitual to the soul ; instinctive sense of the marvellous, and presentiment of infinity, are the source of this sublime and simple act, which proves God. Who does not know it? The soul of man, especially when it is pure and lofty, in its vigor and youth, conceives and desires without bounds all the beauties and virtues of which it sees any trace. All boundaries, all limits, all im- perfections, are destroyed. Being is conceived in all its plenitude ; the mind conceives of eternal love, happiness without change, truth without shadow, a will stronger than any obstacle, strength and energy that play with time and space, and of wonders, sudden creations realized by a word, a gesture, or a wish. All these premonitions of the heart of man, all these golden dreams of childhood, all these in- toxications of ideal nectar, imply a true and strictly scien- tific method. Analyzed by reason, this poetry, this faith, contain the strict proof of the existence of God and his attributes. In fact, this is the poetic and ordinary process which, with the help of education and tradition, lifts the majority of men to the knowledge of God. The spectacle of the world, the sense of life, the sight of finished beings and created beauties, when the heart and imagination grasp them to enlarge and urge them to infinity, by effacing evil, bounds, and limits, that impulse of the soul towards infinity from the finite, this it is that gives men an idea of God, a natural knowledge and love of him. And this intellectual and moral impulse, of which every human soul is capable, is the act and the fundamental pro- cess of the life of reason and the moral life. We say that the act and fundamental process of a life of reason and a moral life consist, as Bossuet expresses it, in passing without any circuit of reasoning, although by a very justifiable impulse 2 18 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. of the reason, from the finite to the infinite, from the genu- ine finite being which we are, which we see, which we can ac- tually touch, to the infinite Being, really and actually existing, which the existence of the finite implies and supposes. And while the simple, the ignorant, the humble, and the young, by a wholly instinctive and poetic method, perform this chief and necessary act of reason, this natural act of the soul is the foundation of the most scientific of methods, and all the demonstrations of the existence of God, given us by true philosophers of all times, summed up and exactly de- fined by the seventeenth century, are but the philosophical translation of the ordinary process which all men employ. This we shall show by enumerating and analyzing these various demonstrations, the entire substance of which we will afterwards sum up, and will prove their unerring exactness. III. But before entering into details and studying these proofs one by one, referring each to its author, we will set forth, without going into particulars, the nature and conditions of the complete essential proof, to which all others lead back more or less directly, according as they are more or less explicit, solid, and luminous. What we now simply state will be developed and demonstrated later on. We must know that there are two processes of reasoning, the one as exact as the other, syllogism and induction. Syllogism is tolerably familiar. But induction is not the vague process which it is supposed to be, it is a precise process ; it is the chief process of reasoning, and has been practised in all ages by all great minds as well as by the humblest, but it has never yet been sufficiently analyzed by any one. We will attempt this analysis by means of logic. EXPLANATORY. 19 These two processes may also be called the syllogistic process and the dialectic process. They correspond to what Leibnitz called the logic of deduction and the logic of inven- tion, or the analytical part and the inventive part of logic. They correspond to the two kinds of minds which we find among men, and which we may represent by Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle called them syllogism and induction ; Plato calls them syllogism and dialectic. The seventeenth century deserves the credit for establishing the truly mathematical precision of the second process, by bringing it into practical use, as Leibnitz says ; which was done by the works of Descartes, Malebranche, and Fdnelon, and by the great dis- covery of Leibnitz, the invention of the infinitesimal cal- culus, a wonderful invention, which consists of actually introducing into mathematics this chief process of reasoning. This process, which in geometry is carried to mathemati- cal infinity, is also carried, in metaphysics, to the infinite Being, which is God. Exact as geometry, it is also much the simpler and quicker of the two processes of reasoning. Its very simplicity and rapidity have hitherto prevented any complete analysis of it. It consists, any degree of entity, beauty, or perfection being given, which we always have so soon as we are, see, or think, it consists, we say, in instantly destroying in thought the limits of the finite being and the imperfect qualities which we possess, or which we see, in order that we may affirm without other intermediary the infinite existence of the one Being and his perfections, corresponding to those we see. Assuredly the process is a simple one ; any one may use it, and the smallest minds, on certain points, employ it as quickly as others : but it is precise. This is now proved by the works of the seventeenth century, analyzed and compared. This process is not only applicable to the proof of the 20 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. existence of God, but it leads up in everything to principles and ideas ; and as several philosophers, who will be quoted in due time, declare, it is a universal process of invention. Absolutely distinct from syllogism, it is quite as exact ; it alone gives the majors used by syllogism. This process, like syllogism, may rest either upon an ab- straction or a fact, an idea or a reality, upon a conception which is a priori true or false, or upon an experience. If the syllogism depend upon a simple possibility, which does not exist, upon a chimera, or even on a contradiction, which cannot be true, its deductions will be of the nature of the primary cause : a series of non-existent possibilities, or even a series of chimeras or a series of contradictions is deduced, sooner or later ending in downright absurdity, that is to say, in a conspicuous contradiction. But if it rest upon a real postulate, derived from the nature of things, as, for instance, Newton's law, all the deduc- tions drawn from it will be true, genuine, and existent in the nature of things. Now, it is precisely the same with the other process. Whether we take for our starting-point a pure possibility which does not exist, or a contradictory statement, or even, as Descartes says, a conception proceeding from nothing, which does not and cannot exist, the assertion obtained by the dialectic process will be a simple possibility, a chimera, or a contradiction. But if it be based upon an experimental postulate, a reality, or some actual and positive quality exist- ing in things, then its results will be as real as the point of departure, as real as those of the syllogism. If, for in- stance, it depended, as in certain German theories, upon the idea of non-being, it would affirm, as the Germans do, an absolute non-being, and all the resultant absurdities ; it would thus plainly obtain only a chimera and a monster. But if it rest upon some conception of being, a conception EXPLANATORY. 21 which is clearly possible, it asserts the possibility of an infinite Being ; if, moreover, it add to this the experience of any real being whatsoever, actually existing, it concludes in the infinite Being, no longer as merely possible, but as really and actually existing. And these assertions, which proceed from finite reality to infinite reality, are always true ; since in metaphysics, as in geometry, every positive finite has its corresponding infinite. We can always go on asserting to infinity the existence of any real and positive quality, finite though it be, which we see. The assertion is always true, in God. This is because in metaphysics, as in geometry, as Leibnitz observes, "Finite laws always hold good of infinity, and vice versa" But if the process de facto be true, de facto again, all do not always carry it out. Just as every mind does not al- ways infer the consequences of principles with which it is familiar, so, too, every mind does not always move from every finite to the corresponding infinite, or from every phenom- enon to ideas, or from every creature to God. Just as there are minds without any syllogistic impulse, so too there are minds destitute of dialectic force. There are intellects which possess neither the one nor the other, neither deduction nor invention. All are necessarily deductive when they are driven to it. There is a logical constraint which can force any man to see a consequence in a principle ; but all, as a matter of course, are not necessarily inventive ; all do not possess the dialectic impulse, there is no intellectual con- straint possible upon this point. The intellect may lose or recover its strength of impulse towards the infinite. That depends upon the energy, the elasticity, of the soul and moral freedom, this impulse being alike and indissolubly intellectual and moral ; and it cannot be other than a move- ment of the human soul as a unity. The intellectual move- ment towards infinity is always true, always possible, since 22 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. man is endowed with reason ; but as a fact, it cannot take place in the soul without the corresponding moral move- ment. This is why diseased souls can never perform it, even when the words of others assert it and execute it in their presence. A deduction presented from without is not always understood by a mind but slightly developed ; but a moment more, a moment of careful attention, will make it clear. The dialectic passage from the finite to the infinite is still oftener overlooked by weak or diseased minds; a moment of more active attention is not enough, a cure and moral change are requisite. This fact, but too little noted, is most important. It touches on the bond and relation between logic and morals, intellect and will, reason and liberty. There is a bond between rea- son and liberty, this is unquestionable ; there are opinions which are entirely free. Some schools of philosophy admit that all opinions are free and unbiassed : this is evidently a mistake ; for how can deduction be free ? A syllogistic con- clusion is inevitable when the primary causes are given. But still it is false to say that every true opinion is inevi- table. Dialectic advance from the finite to the infinite, and the opinion which results, is both true and free, yet although always true, is never obtained save under conditions which depend upon freedom. The first moral condition of the ex- istence of these dialectic decisions which proceed from every finite to the infinite, is what may be called the sense of in- finity, that divine sense which is always given, which is the omnipresent charm of the Sovereign Good for every soul. Then, according to the free reciprocal adaptation of each soul to this attraction of infinity, it pronounces, or does not pronounce, the true opinion which leads from every finite to infinity. It may even as the whole history of philosophy, especially modern German philosophy, proves pronounce that false opinion which leads from every finite, in an opposite direction from infinity, to nothing. EXPLANATORY. 23 The proof of the existence of God therefore results from one of the two processes essential to reason, but, as a fact, is worked out freely, morally as well as rationally. This, I admit, is quite contrary to our wretched logical habits, which presuppose an absolute separation of logic and morals. But this gratuitous supposition might even be called strange, since it admits that intellect and will, two faculties of a single soul, have no common root where they touch ; this supposition, I say, is as false as it is strange. It has been, it still is, one of the stumbling-blocks of philoso- phy. It is unquestionable that, as a certain intellectual condition, and not only a condition but an act, a voluntary act, attention, is requisite to execute one of the movements of reason, to form or to comprehend a syllogism ; so too we also require a certain moral state, which we may call a right sense, and a voluntary and moral act, to understand and execute the other movement of reason. A right sense which is moreover the same thing as the divine sense is that hidden reason to 'which Pascal refers when he says, " The heart has its reasons which the reason does not know." It is this hidden reason which the fool lacks when he says in his heart, " There is no God." Such, then, is the nature, such are the conditions, of the true proof of the existence of God. In brief, the true proof of the existence of God is nothing else but the use of one of the two processes of reasoning, the chief one, that which gives the majors, and which consti- tutes the logic of invention. Every application of this process involves the proof of the existence of God. Let us repeat: this process consists, starting from every finite being and every finite quality, in affirming, by the sup- pression of finite limits, the infinite Being, or the infinite perfections corresponding to the finite that we see. 24 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. And this assertion is always true, according to the princi- ple laid down by Leibnitz, that finite laws hold good of in- finity, and vice versa ; in other words, that the finite is an image of the infinite, which results, as Leibnitz also re- marks, from the fact that everything is governed by God, who governs all in conformity to himself. This process is as sure as geometry, to which, moreover, it is applied. This application is known as the infinitesimal calculus. On the other hand, this process is never de facto literally carried out, and only reaches God by a simultaneous act of intellect and will, reason and liberty. Its power in the mind is the divine sense, the sense of infinity, or, if you will, the inevitable attraction of the Sovereign Good for every soul. But this power, given to all, acts or ceases to act, or even changes its course, according to the moral state of the soul. We believe that we have proved all this in the totality of the present work in such a manner that it will henceforth be regarded as among the truths acquired by philosophy. We may be opposed at first ; but as all opposition will be vain, we hope our adversaries will soon have recourse to de- claring that these things have been known in every age, particularly in the seventeenth century, and that there is nothing new in what we say. We shall hasten to agree to this, merely reserving to ourselves the honor of having thrown more vivid light upon this central point of philosophy, where all rays meet. This settled, let us turn to details, and proceed to the his- toric study of the proofs of the existence of God. We shall enter most minutely into this question, studying in turn the theodicy of Plato, Aristotle, Saint Augustine, Saint Anselm, and Saint Thomas Aquinas ; then take up the theodicy of the seventeenth century, treating of Descartes, EXPLANATORY. 25 Pascal, Malebranche, Fe'nelon, Bossuet, Leibnitz, and the authors of two Latin Theodicies, unknown even to the trained public, which are the two finest and most complete ever written in any age. We shall linger the more willingly upon this point, be- cause it will at the same time afford us a study of the his- tory of philosophy. The history of the above-named philosophers is very nearly the whole history of philosophy. Now, we know a philoso- pher by his theodicy. The theodicy of a writer contains his method, implies his logic and his ethics, is his system of metaphysics and his theory of ideas also, therefore his psy- chology. In this sense all philosophy may be found in the theodicy. In treating, therefore, of the theodicy of all the great minds, each in its turn, we give at the same time a summary, and a brief history, of philosophy. CHAPTER II. PLATO'S THEODICY. PLATO comes first in chronological order; this is fortu- nate. Of all men who discussed the subject of God previous to the Christian era, he is the greatest. He has been called the divine ; Bossuet so styles him, and this is his distinguishing name among philosophers. Moreover, Plato is the especial representative of one of the two processes of human reason, the chief one, that which leads up to God. 1 If Aristotle was the immortal and perfect lawgiver for the other process, Plato, without actually establishing the laws of that which forms his glory, laws which could not be de- fined exactly until the seventeenth century, Plato at least indicated them, and gave us, besides, the finest example of their use which human reason in the antique world produced. The glory reverted to the school of Socrates. And why ? Because the impulse of reason towards genuine infinity an impulse which constitutes that chief process to which we refer, and which gives us the proof of the existence of God can only be carried out de facto, in consequence of a moral state, under the impelling force of that "power" as Bossuet says, which is the " divine sense ; " or, if you prefer, the "attraction of the desirable and intelligible" as Aristotle expresses it. Now, the Socratic and Platonic school is of all ancient schools the most moral, and the one which best knew, under- 1 Janet's admirable thesis on the "Dialectic of Plato" should be read on this subject. This brilliant work, but too little known, should be one of the first things read by all who desire to study Plato. PLATO'S THEODICY. 27 stood, and described the real attraction of Supreme Good- ness for the soul of man. Socrates is, in fact, as modern sophists very aptly com- plain, the founder of moral philosophy. His doctrine, as has been well said, is little more than a theory of virtue ; " and its only aim, according to the best judges," says Thomassin, " is to purify our affections by means of moral- ity." l Plato therefore claimed and this was the root of his system to rely wholly upon that love of goodness and that moral state without which reason does not apply the dialectic process leading up to God. To him, the beginning of all things was Goodness ; he knew that Goodness is the father of light, that the action of the mind which rises to God depends upon the forces of love, that this process, which he so happily calls the " movement of the soul's wings," implies a moral state, an outburst of love towards God, and that the soul can only put out wings by dint of virtue. This is why Plato knew and practised more than any other man in antiquity the chief process of reasoning. This is why he knew and proved the existence of the true God. Plato knew that there are two processes of reasoning, and not merely one. He knew that the most potent of these two processes, quite as exact as the other, is the scientific truth of which poetry is merely the image. For this very reason he was a poet in thought as well as by nature, like all philosophers who have made especial use of the chief process of reason. He understood that very beautiful meta- phors are true, because they imply the truth of the dialectic method, and that this chief form of philosophical thought is, in its spirit, like poetry itself, simple, easy, and popular. Plato knew above all he repeats it incessantly that sensuality and passion are the obstacle to light in the soul, 1 Thomassin, Dogm. Theol., vol. ii. chap. x. p. 11. 28 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. and that this obstacle must be overcome before we can rise to truth through reason. He knew that there are two courses open to the soul and its love, one of which leads the mind to illusion and error, the other to truth ; that philoso- phy is indivisibly a work of reason and freedom, of intellect and will, far more, a work of sacrifice and virtue. It is for this reason that he so constantly expounds the wonderful Socratic saying : " To philosophize is to learn how to die." And lastly, Plato knew that there are three soul-spheres, three lives, in man ; and he states this as clearly as Pascal. He describes the highest of the three as the contact of God with the roots of the soul ; and this divinity l in the soul, when the obstacle of vice is removed, is the power that lifts the reason to eternal truths. We must acknowlege that true philosophy is not, in Plato, unmixed with error, that is only given to Christians ; but he possessed all philosophy, all its essential features, all its fundamental elements. Plato has all the characteristics of true philosophic ge- nius ; he is the most brilliant instance in antiquity of those perfect minds which, as has been well said, use alike their reason and their heart, their learning and their poetry, their feet and their wings, to attain to truth. It therefore belonged to him to give in the ancient world the great proof of the existence of God. Let us see if he succeeded. II. Let us first recall the nature of the process that gives the true proof of the existence of God arid his attributes. Those visible things being given which beget one another, which are born and die, which change and which pass away, which might not exist, which are limited and imperfect, the mind should exceed these finite and visible beings, and 1 T6 6etoi>. PLATO'S THEODICY. 29 rise through their images to the eternal, invisible, immu- table ideas which correspond to the images. We should rise from every finite object to the corresponding infinite. We shall see later, through the aid of geometry itself, that this is no vague mental action, but an exact process. This process destroys in thought the limits of finite being, and the imperfections of the qualities revealed to it by things, and asserts that the idea formed in our mind by this sup- pression of limits and defects, this idea of infinite being and infinite perfection, corresponds to a reality truer, more ac- tual, than the very object which we touch, and whence dialectic reasoning starts. It asserts that all these supreme realities are in God, and are God. Such is, at least, the duty of the mind in the light of reason ; and, in fact, the mind fulfils this duty whenever the moral obstacle that impedes its progress is removed. Did Plato fully understand this process ? Did he state lit- erally, did he know that the sum total of immutable, eternal, infinite ideas is in God, is the Word of God, which is God ? Some deny this ; we believe that we should affirm it, with Saint Augustine, Bossuet, Leibnitz, and Fe*nelon. In any case, whether Plato himself knew or did not know it, and I believe that he knew it, his dialectic process actually ends in God, in the infinite. This is the nature and the law of the process. Plato really made that supreme use of reason which consists in passing by a simple impulse, which is at the same time scholarly and systematic, from everything to God ; from the finite, the variable, and the uncertain to the infinite, immutable, and inevitable. My readers may judge of this by the brief statement which follows, and which will be verified later by quotations from the text. There is first in the soul a gift of God, which results from contact with God, and which is that voice, that inner tute- 30 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. lary spirit given by God to every soul. This divine element, this sense of immortality and divinity, is the prime and essential element, the principle and very root of the soul, in its triple life. This is the power which proceeds from God and leads us up to God. Now, man does not rise to God by the mind alone, by the reason taken in that abstract sense in which sophists understand it ; man rises to the knowledge of God only through his whole soul; first by his will, by doing good, which directs the eye where it should look, then purifies it, makes it capable* of seeing. Knowledge of God implies a free moral element. The part of the will con- sists in conquering those moral obstacles which prevent us from developing the divine sense within us, or which destroy it. This divine sense is the condition, founded on expe- rience, of a knowledge of God. Such is the moral part of the process that leads us up to God. The intellectual and logical part is properly the dialectic. Dialectic is the process which advances, starting from this visible world, to the idea of Being itself, Goodness itself, absolute Being and Goodness. Thus dialectic, whose motive- power, principle, and force lie in the divine sense set free and made active by virtue, also relies in its action upon the data of the visible world, which stimulate the mind, both by likeness and contrast, to recall the supreme object, wholly different from these as it is, of which they are but the images. Dialectic progress consists in never pausing until Being itself, the Supreme Good which is, is attained. Bea- son starts from sensible things, as a conditional and essential point of departure ; but it goes beyond and aside from these sensible postulates, which stimulate it to recall intelligible things, seeing their unlikeness to the intelligible. From these postulates it passes to the essential ideas which our reason implies, such as geometric truths, which are, as Plato frequently repeats with a depth of meaning which is but too PLATO'S THEODICY. 31 seldom understood, shadows of the light of God. From these shadows it learns to infer the existence of the sun. Let us show all this by quotations. III. In the first place, the most important of philosophical facts that central spring of the moral and rational life which we call the divine sense, and which is the real source of the proof of God's existence was so familiar to Socrates and Plato, and was taught by them with such full con- viction, in so concrete a form, that it was this very thing which produced the misunderstanding relative to the daemon of Socrates. Plato explains the meaning of this word in the most philosophic manner when he shows that this daemon was only the voice of conscience, the innate love of God. In the Apology, Plato puts these words into the mouth of Socrates : " The cause of all is merely what you have often heard me say, ' There is a divine will which speaks to me ' ... (Qeibv TI fcai ^aifioviov). I have heard this voice from my youth up. . . ." This voice is that " of God, which orders rne to live by seeking wisdom and a knowledge of myself. . . . I ought then rather to obey God than you, Athenians ! " It is clear that by daemon (Scupoviov) Socrates here under- stands the voice of God. Cicero understands it in the same way when he asserts that "Socrates' daemon is that something divine which checked him, and which he always obeyed." The dying Socrates said : " Let us go whither God leads ; " and he obeyed that divine voice even in death. Which suggests to a learned author the following thoughts : " That God was the voice which rang in his innermost soul, that light which illumined his intellect and declared to him what he was to do. It is what is commonly known as Socrates' 32 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. daemon. . . . Socrates frequently refers to it as to a sort of spiritual director, sometimes calling it daemon, and sometimes God. He always seems to take it seriously, especially here, where he relies upon it both for life and death. According to some, Socrates understood by this the true God. Others are of a different opinion." Saint Justin has no doubt about it ; Saint Augustine hesitates. Plato, moreover, in his Timseus, explains it in a way which, as it seems to us, leaves no room for contradiction. We will go into the details of this explanation, because it leads us away from the incidental question of Socrates' da?mon, and shows us what may be called the heart of dialectic, the centre of Plato's philosophy, theology, and morals, the true power upon which Platonism depends to prove the existence of God, that motive power which we have called the divine sense. In his fine close to Timseus, Plato expresses himself as follows : " We have already said that the soul possesses a triple life, each part of which has its place and its distinct action. . . . Now, you must know touching the chief of these three lives, that it is the dcemon which God has given to every man. That part of the soul is that which occupies, as they say, the highest realm within us, and which, through its celestial parentage, lifts us from the earth and makes her the fruit of heaven rather than of earth, which is profoundly true ; for at that point which is the very origin of our soul, there the divine holds linked to it our root, our life principle, and uplifts the whole man." a Nothing can be plainer ; the word dcemon (Sai'fi&v) means precisely the divine sense in the soul, that point at which God touches us, the point which is our root, our origin, our source (Trpeor?? the three regions of the soul. Elsewhere Plato speaks of the parts of the soul, two of which, particularly, are distinct, the one rational, \oyi, which are united by the BV/J.OS or Bv/jLoeidts (De Rep. IV.). This distinction doubtless refers to that one of the three faculties, knowledge, will, and feeling, which he establishes in the same book of the Republic. Plato had no more faith in three souls than Saint Thomas, who nevertheless makes a distinction between the rational soul, the sensitive soul, and the vegetative soul. Moreover, in Plato, etSos is often used as a synonym for /ufyos ; we often find eI5os Kai ^pos eidrj nal n^py. Cicero did not believe that Plato spoke of several souls, but of several spheres of the soul : Parfcs animi, secundnm Platonem. As for Aristotle, in his " Book of the Virtues and Vices," in the beginning, he says (Bekker's edition, page 1249): TpijuepoOs 5 rijs faxw XajM/UwopAnfi KO.TO. IlXdrwra, TOV pfv XoyurriKOv dper^i tanv i) Qpbvyffis, TOV dt 0vfj.oiSovs ij re TrppoTTjs /ecu ij dvSpcia, TOV 5t liri6vfjt.r}TiKov tf re GuQpofftivti Ka.1 i] y/cpareia, 6'\?7S 5 XT;? \f/vx?i* 7? TC 6i/cato<7i/j'?7. Aristotle therefore admits here, with Plato, that there are these three parts of the soul, and names them as he does, and in his book on the Soul he none the less maintains the unity of the soul (P- 411). 3 84 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. mount to higher things ; " the triple life which one of the deepest thinkers of this century, Maine de Biran, rediscovered in the soul by his persistent analysis, in spite of the prejudi- ces of his starting-point, which admitted of but one. And when Plato speaks of the highest of the three (fcvpiw- rarov -^U^T)? eZSo?), that which he calls divine (TO delov), and elsewhere the immortal principle of the soul (apxyv ^v^s aOdvarov), when he assigns it an especial place and habita- tion, at the very root (p%a) where God holds us linked to himself (TO delov avaKpefiavvvv), whence the first genesis of the soul proceeds (e/ceWev o6ev rj irpwrif] TT}? tyv%f)s v), Plato then speaks like Bossuet, who, pointing out this particular region of the soul, this inner sanctuary, ex- claims, " Hearken in thy innermost soul ; hearken in that place where the truth makes itself heard, where pure and simple ideas are found." And elsewhere, after saying, " The soul therefore is made for God, it is to him that it should ever be conjoined and as it were linked, through its knowl- edge and affection," Bossuet speaks of " a spot in the soul so deep and so retired that the senses do not suspect its ex- istence, it is so remote from their domain ! " Light is also thrown upon all this in the first Alcibiades, when he is advised by the philosopher, if he would know his soul, to look into that place in the soul where especially resides the virtue of the soul, wisdom, that is to say, the divine element of the soul ; then to consider the object itself, of which this part of the soul is the image, in God. 1 For we can never know ourselves if we look into that part of the soul which is all shadow, and where God is not 2 (et? TO aOeov KOI o-Koreivov). We must look into the divine part ; and that part of the soul is to the soul what the pupil is to the eye, the very centre, the primary sense, the channel itself of vision. 3 And it is by looking into this place in the soul, i Alcibiades, I. 133 C. 2 Ibid., 134 E. 8 Ibid., 133 B, 134 D. PLATO'S THEODICY. 35 where light and divinity dwell (et? TO Oeiov /cal ov) ; that the soul unfolds winged love within itself Thus, finally, it is clear that, according to Plato, there is a region in the soul, a central point of the soul, which he calls its root, its primary cause, its origin, and that this point is divine ; that is to say, it contains a gift which God has be- stowed on every man, by touching him at that point, and linking him to himself. Whether we call this divine attribute divine spirit, or divine sense, or the voice of conscience, or the attraction of supreme goodness, attraction of the desirable and intelligible, innate love of beatitude, innate idea of justice and injustice, natural law written on the heart, whatever name we give to this first, chief fact of all philosophy, which results 'from the fact that the soul only is and exists because God is and touches it, it will always be true that this divine attribute, peculiar to all men, is the principle and power which give its im- pulse to the mind as well as to the whole soul, in all its aspirations towards God. This Plato establishes in every possible way. Let us now proceed to state the use which should be, in his opinion, made of this attribute. IV. This divine attribute is the first cause of every movement of the mind towards God. The secondary cause is man's attempt to purify his soul, and thus remove the obstacle which interferes with the action of that force which God has given us. " Knowledge," says Plato, " is not what some imagine when they declare that they will give it to a mind which has it not, * Alcibiades, I. 135 E. 36 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. which would be like giving sight to a blind man. This is a great mistake. There is within us a force, there is in every mind an organ, by means of which every man may acquire knowledge. We must treat this organ as we should the eye, were it impossible to turn it away from darkness to the light, save by employing our whole body, we must turn away our reason with our whole soul ; we must turn it away from the things which pass, to the One Being, and lift our spiritual vision to that radiant centre of Being which we call Goodness. 1 Instruction can only teach us how to direct the mind, and to turn its attention easily and effectually towards the light; education does not give us sight, it merely strives to direct in the right way the sight which already exists, but which is turned in the wrong direction, and does not look where it should look. " There are, in the soul, qualities which may be acquired by exercise and habit, as the body acquires certain powers and cer- tain habits. But reason shows its divine origin, and proves that it comes from something higher than ourselves, in that it never loses its power, but becomes useful or injurious, according to the way in which we use it. 2 Have you never noticed how quickly and clearly the small soul of the wicked grasps the things upon which it is bent, and what power it acquires in so doing 1 ? It sees very plainly, only it chooses to. direct its vision to evil things. But take those same souls in infancy, cut away and prune all the growth of passions akin to the flesh ; set them free from those heavy clods which cling to the pleasures of the table and similar delights ; take away that weight which drags the mental vision down to everything which is low. Instantly, in that same soul, the eye, set free, turns towards realities, and sees them as clearly as it now sees those things which absorb it." 3 We must therefore purify the whole soul, if we wish our life and its attention to be turned and lifted towards its high- est region, where the divine sense dwells. Those who do not purify themselves, remain in the lowest of the three regions of the soul, rise from there towards the middle realm, again sink back into the lowest, and thus spend their lives in this 1 De Rep., 518 C. 2 Ibid., 518 E. 3 Ibid., 519 B. PLATO'S THEODICY- 37 oscillation between the carnal and the passional, without ever rising to that portion of the soul which God inhabits. "The man without wisdom and without virtue, 1 constantly a prey to and identified with all his fleshly appetites, necessarily falls into the lower region, rises from that to the middle portion, to wander thus his whole life long between the two ; but to pass through both these realms, to rise, indeed, whether by the eye alone or by his life, towards that which is truly high, is a thing which he cannot do." To attain, therefore, by the eye or by the life to that part of the soul where the divine sense dwells, the source of our knowledge of God, when we carry it out in our life and pierce it with our eye, we must first overcome the moral obstacle. " He who surrenders himself to the double slavery of the world and the flesh (eVe^v/xtas rj povtlv ptv aOdvara Kat 0ia), that man must needs attain immortality, in so far as hu- man nature is capable thereof; and since he has cultivated naught save the divine (TO Otlov) within him, and has fed the Divine Spirit in his soul (Scu/xoi/a), which dwells there, he must reach supreme felicity. 1 De Rep., 586. 2 Timseus, 90. 38 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. " Now, every life is nourished by its own proper food, and by the movement which is adapted to it. But universal thoughts and movements are the natural movements of the divine within us. They are the thoughts and actions to which every man should con- form ; all should labor to correct, by contemplation of the harmony and the actions of the whole, those particular and irregular acts which the flesh inspires in the centre of our soul, to the end that the beholder, becoming like the object beheld, resumes his original nature, becomes fit to possess at last the perfect life which God offers to man both now and forever." 1 Thus Plato asserts that there is in every man's soul a di- vine contact at that point where our soul is linked to God. This point is the root, the primary cause, the origin of our soul. Of the three lives which exist in our soul, that which God himself maintains in this part of the soul is plainly the chief, and should direct and lift the entire man towards di- vinity, towards immortality, towards God, in both life and thought. But, moreover, Plato here establishes the fact, which, ap- parent though it be, psychology, with us, so often refuses to note, the fact of the native lawlessness to which we are born. That is to say, that there is really an obstacle to the action of that divine power which labors to lift us to God. This obstacle is the double vice, which Plato calls the lust of the flesh and anger, which is to say, pride and sensuality, a double form of selfishness. The condition upon which we may rise to God, in life or in thought, is that we conquer this obstacle. The obstacle conquered, it at once follows that man de- velops within him the sense of immortality and divinity, and attains to truth. Truth leads bim to immortality and happiness. We reach this end by struggling against the innate law- lessness of our own thoughts and actions, by allying ourselves 1 Timseus, 90. PLATO'S THEODICY. 39 to universal thought and action, by contemplating that uni- versal which is God, by becoming like unto God, who gives us immortality. Thus, so far we clearly perceive the Platonic procedure ; we have, first, a divine attribute within us, the primary cause and motive spring of every impulse towards God. We have, next, on the part of man, moral strength, which breaks, by dint of virtue and sacrifice, the shackles that hinder that impulse. This is the moral side of the dialectic process. Let us now turn to its logical side. V. The mind has a starting-point for every inquiry. This starting-point is not always a principle of deduction, far from it. Where is the human mind first placed? Conse- quently, whence does it ordinarily start ? The spectacle of nature. It sees changes, birth and death. Assuredly it is not from this starting-point, taken as a principle of deduc- tion, that it will derive by syllogism the knowledge of God. But by reason of these things it will think of God ; it emerges, on the contrary, from these things to find God. 1 It certainly starts from the spectacle of visible things. " It is with the senses, not elsewhere, that we begin ; it is with sight, touch, or some other sense; it cannot be otherwise." 2 But how can all these transitory things lift us to God ? Certainly not by their identity with God. Is it by their likeness to God ? Yes, but it is quite as much by their difference and their contrast with his eternal nature. " We see all these things striving to resemble him, yet remaining ever remote from him." 3 And these likenesses and contrasts alike remind us of him. You behold one thing, and in it you comprehend another. Whether this be due to likeness or to contrast, it is the object seen 1 Rep., vii. 525. 2 Phaedo, 75. 8 Ibid., 75. 40 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. that calls up the memory. 1 If we see, if we hear, if we per- ceive any object through any sense, and if, at the same time, besides seeing that object, we conceive another, the idea of which is not the same, but wholly different, should we not say that the second object, to the idea of which we have at- tained, is a memory suggested by the first? 2 A man and a lyre are not the same thing. And yet those who love, recall the loved object if they see the lyre which he has touched. Such is reminiscence. 3 " There is an element in sense, impressions of which in no way stimulate the intellect, because it stops at the senses which are capable of judging it; and there is another element which does, on the contrary, stimulate the intellect, the senses being unable to deal with it." 4 " The sensations which stimulate the intellect are those which imply both likeness and contrast; 5 as, for instance, when the sight of a certain number of objects awakens in us the idea of unity and that of infinite quantity." 6 "It is upon these attributes those which stimulate the intel- lect that the process rests (/xa0>7/xa) which lifts us to the one Being, and which almost no one uses properly '."* VI. Plato gives a full account of this process in the closing pages of the sixth book of the Eepublic, which, I think, has never been fully understood. In this statement of logic as he understands it, Plato defines exactly the two processes of reasoning, one of which takes its starting-point (vTroOeo-is) 8 as its primary source (ap%??), and deduces consequences from it ; the other ad- vances from its point of departure to a universal principle 1 Phsdo, 74. * De Rep., 523 B. 7 Ibid., 522, 523. 2 Ibid., 73 C. 6 Ibid., 523. 8 Ibid., 510 et seq. Ibid., 73 D. 6 ibid., 525. PLATO'S THEODICY. 41 which is not contained in it (eV ap%r)v avwiroOerov ef VTTO- Qeo-eax; lovcra). One is clearly the law of syllogism; he calls the other the dialectic process (iropeia SiaXeKTi/crj). The first process, he says, is that of geometry ; the second is that of true philosophy. 1 Geometricians take their definitions as their starting-point (Troirjo-d/jLevoi V7ro0e(reis avra). These points of departure they take as principles, principles of deduction from which they derive all the rest by means of inference and manifest identity (eV TOVTWV 8' dp^o^evoL rd XOLTTO, ij&rj SiegLovres T6\6VTO)(TiV 6yL60\070U/Z6Z/0?). Yet again, this process, syllogistic deduction, does not go back to the origin of things (OVK eV dp^hv lovcrav) ; evi- dently it can never rise above its starting-point, since it deduces by means of identity (eo? ov ^vva^vrjv TU>V viro- Oea-ewv avwrepw eicftaiveiv). The other, on the contrary, rises above its starting-point (eV oavTa(TfiaTa Oela KOI ovaa? TWV OVTWV), judge that these shadows and these images are produced by a sun which corresponds to them (ovaa? Si eTepov TOLOVTOV <&>TO? 7T/30? ri\ioVj Kplveiv cnTocrKLa^ofJieva^) 1 5 Yes, we can ; we may attain to a vision even of the 1 De Rep., 533. 3 Ibid., 517. 6 Ibid., 532. 2 Ibid., 508 D. 4 ibid., 532. 44 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. essence of things (eV CLVTO o eariv e/cacrrov oppav). 1 We may succeed in seeing the supreme Being of beings (TT/QO? rrjv TOV apiffTOV ev rot? oven Oeav) ; we may reach that high- est intellectual summit (eV avrw T&> TOV vorjrov reXet) ; we may grasp the supreme essential Being himself, through the mind itself (avro o eanv 'Aya6bv avrfj vorjaet, \dftrj) ; we may gain sight of supreme Goodness (rrjv TOV 'AyaQov ISeav). We see it dimly (poyis opdo-dai) ; but we may, we should, see it. We may do all this, says Plato, and we should do it. We should persistently pursue this inquiry, and never pause until we succeed in grasping, through the mind itself, the supreme Goodness itself (ical fj,rj aTroa-rfj irplv av CLVTO o (TTW 'Aya0bv avrfj vorjaei Xa/rty) ; 2 this is the final end of the impulse of the mind, the term of the dialectic (re\o? TT}? Trope/a?). Thus, according to Plato, beyond even that grand knowledge which the dialectic gives us, which is the vision of things illu- mined by the light of supreme Goodness, by the light of Being and of truth itself, beyond this knowledge and this truth re- flected in things, if we may so express it, we have Truth it- self, Being itself ; we have the idea and the sight of supreme Goodness ; we have the principle of all things ; we have the most perfect of beings and the height of the intelligible ; we have the final end and aim of the process, which is the at- tainment of supreme Goodness itself through the mind itself, directly and immediately. But this end, he says elsewhere, is not attained until after death. Plato makes these degrees of knowledge and the course of the process clear to us, by his famous description of the cavern, and the story of the deliverance of the captives. First we have captivity in the cave, and then liberty in the sunshine: which corresponds to the vision of 1 De Kep., 532. 2 ibid., 532. PLATO'S THEODICY. 45 the two worlds, the world of sense, and the world of intellect. In the cave there are shadows (ovaa?) and echoes. At first they can only see by reflected rays, whether of light or of voice. Then there conies a change. They turn away from the shadows to objects and to the light (jMerao-rpo^rj atrb rwv atciwv eVl ra ei$o\a /cal TO c^ft)?). 1 Outside the cave, in the real world, there are, Plato always affirms, many degrees of vision. At first, the captives see shadows (aicids} ; then (/iera TOVTO) we have another degree, they see the images of objects in the water (eV rot? vSacnv et'SwAa) ; then the objects themselves, men, and ani- mals. Then they gaze up at the sky, at first by night, to see the reflected light of the moon. " At last, after all this, they look upon the sun, not indirectly now, apart from itself, in its image reflected in the waters, but the sun itself, by itself, in its proper place." 2 This admirable distinction between seeing shadows, reflec- tions, phantoms, images, and the direct sight of light in its course, this distinction, the vast results of which we shall see later on, was afterwards even more fully established by Saint Augustine when he speaks of reason attaining to its final end (ratio perveniens ad finem suum) ; and by Saint Thomas Aquinas, when he describes the two degrees of the divine intelligible (duplici igitur veritate divinorum intelligibilium existente). We beg the reader to keep this point well fixed in his memory. He will understand the bearing of it later. It is the most important point in all philosophy. For the rest, Plato seems to us to havo seen, or rather expressed, this fundamental distinction in a slightly confused way. This has given rise to discussions of his Theory of Ideas, and of the question whether to him the Word is God i De Rep., 532. 2 Ibid., 516 B. 46 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. or is not God. But is it surprising that a truth which escaped Malebranche, this is the omission in his system, and over which Bossuet hesitates, should be expressed by Plato with some ambiguity ? Moreover, to all who can see clearly the great intellectual fact in dispute, it is evident that Plato saw the truth, although he may waver in his description. What Plato saw is, that truth as man possesses it, or finds it naturally, is only an image of God, but not the direct sight of God. Pascal says, "The truth taken in this sense is not God, but it is his image, and an idol which we should not adore." The essential, eternal, immutable truths of which reason gives us the certainty and the clear sight are, as Plato expresses it, but divine phantoms or shadows of what is, a magnificent expression, of the most fruitful depth, which we cannot sufficiently admire. Even geome- try, according to Plato, sees only shadows, the dream of Being, not waking vision of Being } another statement of deep meaning. But what man desires, and should desire, according to Plato, is to pass from shadows, reflections, echoes, and images. He desires to hurry on ; and he should do so, never pausing until he has grasped very Being, supreme Goodness itself, through his intelligence itself, that is to say, until he has acquired direct and immediate sight of God. Plato, therefore, sees here what Saint Augustine expresses so perfectly when he says, " God is intelligible ; these spec- tacles of scientific truths are so likewise. But what a differ- ence ! 2 The earth is visible, the light of the sun is visible ; but the earth is visible only by the light of the sun. There is all the difference of earth and sky between these phan- toms of assured truths and the intelligible majesty of God/' 3 1 De Rep., 533 C. 8 Ibid., p. 686, 11 (v.). 2 Soliloq., lib. i. p. 608, 14 (vii.). PLATO'S THEODICY. 47 ; 8ft% VIII. U> !TY t Thus, we see, Plato through his dialectic was able to rise to the true God, to very Being, to the most perfect of beings, to the beginnings of all things, to truth itself, to supreme Goodness which is. But did he ever really attain to the knowledge of the true God, to the genuine idea of God and his attributes'? We unhesitatingly answer, Yes. This is the opinion of Saint Augustine, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Bossuet, and also of Fe*nelon and Thomassin. We shall quote these decisive authorities later. Let us first show the fact. In the tenth book of his Laws, Plato, striving to establish that there is a Providence, rises through his dialectic to the idea of God, as follows : " There are in us certain virtues : therefore God possesses fully all virtue. 1 We can do some things : God can at least do all that we can do. 2 In us there may be both good and evil : in God, not." 3 Thus the resemblance and contrast between ourselves and God lift Plato, according to his theory, to the reminiscence of God. These assertions, we see, are nothing but that common and natural dialectic which, in the spectacle of visible things and the sight of the human soul, effaces limits, omissions, and evil, thus elevating goodness to the infinite and affirming it to be of God. But Plato did this scientifically. However this may be, we have already seen that Plato's God is not an abstract God. Plato's God is the absolute Be- ing, without faults ; supreme Goodness ; the Being possessed of all virtue, wisdom, and providence; the sun of the intelligi- ble world, of which the essential and universal truths which we see are the shadow. This God, the author and Father of i Leg., 900 D. 2 Ibid., 901 D. 8 Ibid., 900 D. 48 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. intelligible light, is also the author and parent of the sun and the visible world. He made the sun in his own image to enlighten the world, as he himself enlightens the world of intelligence. 1 He is that Goodness which we scarcely per- ceive, in the centre of the world of intelligence, but which, once seen, appears as the cause of all that is good and beau- tiful. 2 It is towards him that the soul of the true philo- sopher, which alone lias wings, strives to soar. He who is absolutely (rw Traz^reXw? OVTI), who is a living absolute (rw iravT^\el wo>), a perfect and living intelligible (TO> reXewraTft) fcal VOTJTO) foow), the living one who is, in whom the ideas are (evovaas tSea? TW o ecrn faW), the eter- nal essence (diSios ovo-ia), of whom, properly speaking, we cannot say that it has been, or will be, but only that it is (TO eo-ri povov) : it is the God who is forever (6Wo? ael Qeov). 3 It is he who possesses motion in repose, who possesses au- gust and sacred intelligence ; which the sophist denies. " In God's name," exclaims Plato, " shall we be readily persuaded that he who is absolutely, has neither motion, nor life, nor soul, nor thought, that he is inert, that he is without august and sacred intelligence 1 Shall we let men tell us that he has intelligence, but has no life ? Shall we let them tell us that he has both, but not personality ? 4 Shall we let them tell us that he is personal, intelligent, living, but inert? All this would be absurd." 5 Moreover, according to Plato, it is this God who made the world. Everything was made by God (Kara ye Bebv avra jijveo-Oat). The world does not proceed from a blind and spontaneous cause producing without consciousness (a?r6 TWOS atr/a? avTOfjidrr)? real avev Siavoias (frvova-rjs), but it proceeds from a God who creates with knowledge and with * De Rep., 508 C. 2 Ibid., 517 C. 8 Tim., 30 et seq. 4 We cannot here translate otherwise the word ^i/x 7 ?- This is plainly what Plato means. 6 Sophist.. 265 C. PLATO'S THEODICY. 49 divine reason (/jLera \6yov re /cal eTricmjfjLTjs #e/a?, OLTTO Oeov). The beings, which were not at first, afterwards became through the God who made them (Oeov SrjpiovpyovvTos vo-repov ytyveaOat, TTporepov ov/c ovra). 1 Such is the God given by the dialectic of Plato. This God is; he is good; he is the absolute Being, Goodness itself, intelligence and providence, author and Father of the world. He is the true God. But another decisive proof that Plato really knew the true God and his attributes, and that he constantly alludes to them, is that his entire doctrine may be called the doctrine of ideas, and that, according to Plato, ideas exist in God, and are God. That such is the thought of Plato, seems to us well estab- lished, in spite of all contradictions. Thomassin does not hesitate to maintain this thesis ex professo : " Ideas were placed in God by Plato ; that is the unanimous opinion of the Fathers." 2 When Plato says, " Ideas are in the living one who is," it seems to me that this sentence alone should suffice to settle the question. Plato everywhere affirms that the world and all that therein is was made in the likeness of ideas. Now, in the Timseus, he asserts that things were made as they are, "to the end that the world might be as similar as possible to the intelligible and perfect living one (iva roS' o>? o/jboiorarov y Tc5 reXewrarw teal vorjTw fww)." 3 Thus, according to Plato, ideas are actually that intelli- gible and perfect living one, i. e. God. He repeats the same thing elsewhere. "To the end," he says, "that the world may be like unto the living absolute (iva roBe . . . opoiov 1 Sophist., 265 C. 2 Thorn., Dog. Theol. This is the heading to chap. xii. lib. iii. * Tim., 39. 4 50 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. r) TO) 7ravTe\i &>&>)." l In the Timseus, Plato never ceases to consider the eternal exemplar of ideas (d'&Lov TrapdSeiypa) as being the living absolute, which includes all living intelli- gibles, and which is the intelligible, supreme, and perfect beauty of all points (ra yap Be vorjrd 000, Trdvra etcelvo Iv eavTM 7rpi\a/3bv e^et . . . TO> TWV voovfjbevwv Ka\\icrrw KOI Kara irdvra TeXea>)." 2 This is the assertion in exact words that ideas, the eternal example for the world, are precisely God. When Plato speaks of God, who is always (6Wo9 del Oeov), 3 who created the world by gazing at that which is always (TO bv del), that is to say, the eternal exemplar, ideas, does not Plato clearly state that in gazing at that which is always, ideas, he regards only himself, who always is ? The texts in Plato which prove our thesis are superabun- dant. It only remains for us to show the precise cause of the misapprehension. If there be quotations which seem to contradict each other upon this point, it is because Plato, like ourselves, necessarily uses the word idea in two different senses, sometimes to signify the truth as it is in itself (avro TO dXrjOes), sometimes the truth as we see it in ourselves (eTTio-TijfjLrj Kal d\ijOeia). In the first case, according to Plato, ideas are in God and are God ; in the second, Being itself, supreme Goodness, is as superior to them as the sun is superior to the light reflected by the world, and to the vision which we have of that light. 4 here are ideas in God and ideas in us ; and between these two meanings of the word, there is all the difference that Saint Augustine finds between those two lights, of which one is the light that illumines (lu- men illuminans) : this is God, the idea of God ; and of which the other is only the light that is illuminated (lumen illu- minatum) ; that is, we ourselves, the idea in us, created intelligence. 1 Tim., 31. 2 Ibid., 3t). 8 Ibid., 34. 4 De Rep., 508. PLATO'S THEODICY. 51 All the difficulties come from this. With this key we can, I think, settle them. 1 Moreover, we should be well aware that, for some time back, Plato, as well as Aristotle, has been turned to account by Hegelian sophists, who strive to take refuge beneath his wings, and shed their darkness over his light. We will amply prove this in the proper place. IX. Let us now turn from the result to the process. We see, by the fact, that Plato was familiar with the great and chief process of the reason, the only one which rises to God. But what is very remarkable, is that he also knew, de- scribed, and combated its abuse. It seems as if he foresaw the use which the Alexandrians would make of it, and the still more absurd use which German sophists would make of it in the nineteenth century. Plato puts the question and settles it with the utmost precision. It is strange that the importance of his solution of the point is not appreciated ! Leibnitz was struck by it, and quotes it as something of great value. We have, says Plato, the philosopher and the sophist. The philosopher and the sophist are exactly opposite in mind. The first alone deals with the true dialectic, which rises to the splen- dors of the one Being, the object of his inquiry and his con- templation. But what is the sophist's course ? What does he seek, and what does he see ? Hear Plato's answer : The sophist moves towards mere nothingness. He seeks and pursues non-being, and takes refuge in its shadows. 2 That is his dwelling and the habit of his mind. Aristotle notes 1 See, on this point, book iii. de Deo, by Thomassin, and Nourisson's the- sis, " Quid Plato senserit de Idceis," a substantial summary of a great work. 2 Sophist., 254. 52 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. this opinion of Plato. " Plato," he says, " very fitly remarks ' that sophism rests entirely upon non-being.' " The reader will understand later, if he does not already see, the depth of this observation. But this is not the place to develop it. We merely wish to show that Plato by his process, which is the true one, could not obtain an idol, a false god, or the empty and abstract unity of the Alexandrines, a unity without being, goodness, or intelligence, and still less that monster of contemporary pantheism, ontological nonentity. Far from this, Plato declares this tendency to be utterly contrary to philosophy, and uses the right phrase in regard to those who meditate upon non-existence, or, what is the same thing, the teachers of absolute identity. He calls their doctrine monstrous. " If any one call like- ness un likeness, and unlikeness likeness, it seems to me that it would be monstrous" * And he adds an expression which Malebranche seems to have translated when he lays stress upon that kind of identical proposition which strikes him as being fundamental : To perceive nothing, or not to perceive anything, are one and the same thing. " He who says nothing, necessarily, it seems, says nothing." We need not even admit that he says anything ; he says nothing, or rather, he does not speak, who undertakes to put into articulate utterance that which has no existence. 2 In the face of so plain a statement, it is not admissible to take an unfair advantage of certain passages in the Par- menides or any other dialogue, to confound Plato with the sophists, who do not even distinguish nothingness from Being, and whose wholly perverted mind works the void and produces the absurd. If obscure, vague, or even inexact statements occasionally escape him in describing the process which leads to the light of supreme Being and supreme 1 Parmetiid., 129. 2 Sophist., 237 E. PLATO'S THEODICY. 53 Goodness ; if, especially in translations, Plato seems to give a very strange idea of the infinite, we must first care- fully consider all the texts, and see whether sometimes, as certainly there are examples, we have not translated the word which should mean undetermined, or at most indefinite, as infinite, which would be the exact opposite of the true meaning. Then, if we still find errors in Plato's text itself, we should not be surprised. In regard to this difficult and even yet most obscure point, no exact solution was reached until since the seventeenth century, and that solution itself is still but little known. The precise theory of the infinite, before the new era, was scarcely possible; and many Christian sages have themselves used expressions con- cerning this subject which have only been noted and cor- rected by the Catholic Church within the last two hundred years. X. Let us sum up all that we have said. Plato employs the true process of reasoning which leads up to God, and he does indeed attain to the true God. He takes created things as his starting-point, not as the prin- ciple of deduction. He asserts that we should advance from this starting-point, taken merely as a fulcrum for our fliyht, to the universal primary cause which is outside the starting-point ; that reason, by the true dialectic process, rises to absolute Being, which is living, intelligent, personal, and active, which is the cause of all beauty, all goodness, which includes all perfection, with no trace of imperfection, which is supreme Goodness itself, the Father of the world, the creator of all things, who does not produce his work spontaneously and blindly, but with knowledge and divine reason, and creates the beings which are not at first, but which become through him. 54 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. Plato shows that reason, by the other process, which is syllogistic, does not reach this end, and can never rise above its starting-point or depart from it, since it takes it as the principle of deduction by means of identity. And, in fact, it is used by the purified soul only to return to the first pro- cess, wliich alone lias wings and is pre-eminently the philo- sophical process ; intelligence does not spread its wings and turn away from darkness to the light, except with the whole soul ; we must cut and prune within the soul, and, as it were, circumcise it; we must prune the natural instincts of the animal part, which turn the gaze of the soul down- ward ; then only can it change its direction and turn to the truth. Then its gaze is bent upon that which is divine and luminous, while the wicked and the impure have nought for their eye to rest upon but the empty shadows of God. This is precisely why the sophist, moving in the opposite direction from the philosopher, takes not-being as the end and object of his contemplation, and hides himself in the gloom of nothingness. And these two contrary directions of thought depend upon the free use which every man makes of the gift of God ; that is, of the contact of God with the root of the soul, at that point where every soul is joined to God. So Plato says. It is certain that man's reason moves in this way, alike in the humblest minds and in the profoundest philosophers. Reason, moving according to its fundamental law, should find the eternal, perfect, and infinite God, Father of men, Creator of the world. God, as Saint Paul teaches, shows himself sufficiently ; he is known through visible things, and man is inexcusable if he does not recognize and glorify him : this is the duty of reason. But there is a healthy reason and a perverted reason. Healthy reason rules in the soul which enjoys moral freedom, and perverted reason in the PLATO'S THEODICY. 55 soul which is enslaved. The one looks higher than man, the other lower. XL It now remains for us to show that in our so favorable opinion of the Platonic doctrine we have gone no farther than Saint Augustine, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Bossuet, nor perhaps so far as Thomassin. We say what they say, and that is enough. Saint Augustine sees in antiquity one true doctrine and two sects. The two sects are those of Epicurus and Zeno ; the true doctrine is that of Plato. We judge doctrine, according to Saint Augustine, by the point where it places these three things : supreme Goodness (faiem boni), the world-cause (causas rerum), the fulcrum of reason (ratiocinandi fiduciam). Now, Epicurus places these three things in the body and the senses : his sect is impure. Zeno places them in man himself : his sect is arrogant. Plato places them in the true God; his philosophy is the true one. So says Saint Augustine. He asserts that the Platonists " place in the true God the creative force of all things, the light of ideas, and the good of practical life." 1 He asserts that, as Cicero abun- dantly proves, " they place in an immutable, eternal, in no way human, but properly divine wisdom, the original wis- dom, stimulator of the other, these three things : supreme Goodness, the world-cause, and the fulcrum of reason." 2 Saint Paul himself, he says elsewhere, does not accuse them of ignorance of the true God. Elsewhere, again, he declares " that Platonists place God far above the nature of every created spirit. He having created not only visible nature 1 De Civit. Dei, lib. viii. cap. ix. t. vii. p. 320. 2 St. Aug., Epist., c. xviii. t. ii. p. 502. 56 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. but the soul itself, he enlightens every rational nature, such as the human soul is, and blesses it by admitting it to a share in his immaterial and immutable light." 1 " Let all sects," he again says, " yield to the philosophers, who say not that man's blessedness is in his body, or in his soul, but in God alone : not as the mind enjoys the body or itself, or as men find their happiness one in the other, but indeed as the eye enjoys the light. . . . Plato places blessed- ness in virtue, virtue in knowledge and imitation of God ; and this itself is blessedness. He does not hesitate, he asserts that to philosophize is to love God.-" 2 Such is Saint Augustine's opinion of Plato. As for Saint Thomas Aquinas, he 3 defends Plato against Aristotle in regard to a charge which strikes him as odious. He says that it is absurd (videtur absurdum) to impute fol- lies to such men as Socrates and Plato (talibus et tantis viris), to men who were the most virtuous of philosophers (qui fuerunt homines virtutibus dediti super omnes philosopher) ; who established virtue as the chief good of humanity (solas mrtutes bonum hominis ponebant), and all whose philosophy tended to virtue (qui ad componendos mores corrigendosque totam suam philosophiam effluerunt). Thus, according to Saint Thomas Aquinas, Plato is not one of those philosophers whom Saint Paul stigmatizes, when he says that having known God, they have glorified him not, and on account of this have become vain in their imaginations and given themselves up to uncleanness. If the authenticity of the book De Regimine principum be contested, here is another testimony, taken from the Summa, the last work of Saint Thomas Aquinas, the summary of all his teaching. He asserts that Plato established the idea of 1 St. Aug., De Cirit. Dei, lib. viii. cap. i. 2 Ibid., cap. viii. t. vii. p. 320. 3 De regimine principum, cap. iv. t. iv. p. 822. Paris edition. PLATO'S THEODICY. 57 the true God. " He established," he says, " as a being apart, the idea of Being, the idea of the One, which he calls Being by itself, and Unity in itself ; being, unity, whence proceeds by participation all that can be called being or unity. . . . He also established that Being by itself, the One in itself, is supreme Goodness; and as Goodness, Being, and Unity are identical, he said that Goodness was God, in which all that may be called good must share. And all this is true," says Saint Thomas Aquinas ; " it is true that there is a first Being, which is by its very essence, which is Goodness, which is he whom we call God. Aristotle agrees on this point with Plato." 1 Moreover, Saint Thomas Aquinas asserts, with Saint Justin, that Plato knew the book of Genesis and followed it in cer- tain points. We scarcely understand why this should be dis- puted. Is it possible that Plato could be wholly ignorant of Oriental traditions ? Could it be that among these traditions he knew nothing of the Jews, whose zeal and activity bring them to the front everywhere ? His utter ignorance on this point would be very hard to explain. Plato elsewhere, like Socrates, and this is to be carefully noted, everywhere enters into tradition so far as he can. He uses with the deepest respect, and accepts in his philosophy, all the sound doctrines which he encounters, Plato, like every genuine philosopher, sought after truth rather than after the mode of finding it. He had no trace of that strange pedantry, that barren mania known as rationalism, which consists in a de- sire to find the truth in a certain manner and in no other, and of one's self alone, through unaided human reason, without any mixture of tradition, authority, or feeling, or any especial help from God; like a man who plays at showing his strength, and announces that he will lift an enormous weight without a crowbar, with a single hand, and that the left. Does not a 1 Summte, I a , q. iv. a. 4. 58 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. true workman use both hands, and all the crowbars that he can find ? So, too, did Plato, who sought the truth with all his mind and with all his heart and with his whole soul, as he says we should do ; who studied all traditions, and trav- elled far and wide to find every trace of such ; who con- stantly invokes, as we see in his writings, the special and present help of God to know the truth, help which, accord- ing to Thomassin, was not refused him, and through which it was given him to know the true philosophy, that of which a Father of the Church said : " The Greeks found a law of right- eousness in philosophy," 1 a statement which Saint Thomas- quotes and confirms. To know Bocsuet's opinion of Plato, we have only to quote from that chapter of his " Logic " where he treats of eternal essences, 2 and thus expresses himself: "These eternal truths which our ideas present are the true ob- ject of science, and therefore that we may become truly wise, Plato incessantly reminds us of those ideas which present not that which shapes itself, but that which is ; not that which engenders and suf- fers corruption, which is seen and then passes away, which is made and destroyed, but that which eternally subsists." "This is that intellectual world which this divine philosopher has put into the mind of God before the world was formed, and which is the model for that sublime work." "These are the simple, eternal, immutable, imperishable, and in- corruptible ideas to which he refers us if we would comprehend the truth." "This is why he said that our ideas, the images of divine ideas, were also directly derived from them, and did not come through the senses, which do indeed serve, he said, to awaken them, but not to form them in our mind." Let us now come to the testimony of Thomassin, who goes very far in regard to Plato, sometimes perhaps too far in 1 Clement of Alexandria, Strom., lib. i. no. 20. 2 Logic, liv. i. ch. xxxvii. PLATO'S THEODICY. 59 regard to the Platonists. Thomassin sees in the philosophy of Plato what it itself asserts, a doctrine which is both speculative arid moral, a struggle against the flesh and a constant contemplation of death (perpetua mortis meditatio et conflictatio cum corpore) ; l a doctrine which unfolds, by means of reminiscence, the eternal reasons hidden in the soul (latitantes in anima rationes per reminiscentiam exeitarej : a doctrine which does not cast man upon externals, but leads him back from external things to himself, and from himself to that which is higher (nee in externa hominem refundere, sed ab Us ad ipsum, ut ipsum summum contempletur) ; 2 a doctrine which thus found truth, not by chance, but by its very method, as Tertullian says (non tantum casu in verum quandoque incurrisse)" 3 This doctrine, adds Thomassin, strives to purify the affec- tions, to lift our mind to God ; and the very basis of Platon- isrn, according to Saint Augustine, is the placing of ideas in God : the Fathers agree on this point. The contrary error comes from Aristotle tirst, then from the Gnostics and Arians. Plato is the father of philosophy ; and he went to the verge of philosophy, having more than any other philosopher recognized and asserted the fact of the actual intervention of God, by his help and his grace, in the contemplation of immutable truths. 4 And this help was not denied him. The Platonists, again says Thomassin, are praised by Saint Augustine for attributing to divine light whatever was given them in the order of that contemplation. 5 God, in fac^ aided them ; and, moreover, they found help from the Hebrews (Dei auxilio adjuti ; deinde Hebrceorum quandoque contubernio). Thus we praise, we quote, this patrician race 1 Logic, lib. vi. cap. iii. n. i., 2. 2 Ibid., lib. i. cap. ii. n. 2. 3 Ibid., cap. xxiv. n. 1. 4 Dog. Theol., t. iii. lib. iv. cap. ii. n. 10. 5 Ibid., t. ii. lib. iii. cap. v. n. 15. 60 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. of philosophers ; and to make their doctrine harmonize with our dogmas is not a difficult work, still less is it a sterile task, as Saint Bernard himself proved. 1 Finally, in the preface to his Theodicy, Thomassin thus sums up his opinion of Plato: "That which precedes will readily explain to you why, in the first part of this treatise, I have mingled in proof Plato and his disciples with the Fathers of the Church, Greek and Latin. For although for the last five hundred years our most famous teachers have gained their philosophic education in the school of Aristotle, we must remember that all the Fathers acquired theirs in the school of Plato. Baronius might truly say, ' The Academy is the antechamber to the Church ; ' and the admirable Saint Augustine, himself imbued with that patrician philosophy, as Cicero calls it, declares that by changing a very few words and thoughts, a Platonist becomes a Christian. To this I have clung tenaciously (mordicus), showing in every- thing the harmony of their thoughts and expressions with our Scriptures and our holy Fathers, and pointing out the differences where they exist." 2 In the face of these amazing testimonials from the Fathers and from Catholic scholars, testimonials paid to the Pla- tonic philosophy, and of this wonderful agreement between philosophy and theology, this perfect union of philosophers and theologians of the first order, we ask the meaning of that war between religion and philosophy, reason and faith, of which we have heard so much for a century past. For myself, I see but one cause for this unhealthy division of the universal light of the Word in human minds. That cause is a decay of the human mind, and a simultaneous degeneration of reason and faith. The light has grown dim in men's souls, because they are less turned towards God. Winter reigns. Faith, in those who still have it, has a lesser radiance ; 1 Dog. Theol., t. ii. lib. iii. cap. xxiii. n. 9. 2 Prsef., t. iii. n. 10. PLATO'S THEODICY. Cl shrinking and repressed in the innermost heart, it no longer sheds its divine dew upon the mind. Faith does not suffi- ciently seek intelligence, as Saint Augustine urges it to do. On the other hand, reason, in those who cultivate it, no longer leads to any result, and misses the object of its career, as Plato expresses it ; it does not search enough to find. Those who rise highest, pause " at divine phantoms and the shadows of what is," but they do not reach " the sun which casts these shadows." Insufficiently upheld by God, whom it neither seeks nor loves, reason completes its work in but very few men. Its weak and fine-spun thoughts, its partial and broken lights, have ceased to be more than the ruins and fragments of integral philosophy. Better simple ignorance than this ignorance which ignores itself ; better actual night than a gloomy twilight which deems itself broad day, and doubts not that the sun is shining. At the present time, therefore, those souls in whom God has placed through faith the source of light, are like a clouded sky, in which the sun no longer beams ; and those others, destitute of faith, but to whom God still sends a few rays from without, are like the Earth when, in the first glim- mer of dawn which puts out the stars without yet giving us the sun, she no longer sees by any sign that her light cometh to her from Heaven. CHAPTER III. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. LET us understand plainly that the question of the proofs of the existence of God, which includes that of his at- tributes, is not a question of any particular system of philos- ophy, but is the question of philosophy in general. The effort of the intelligence to show that there is a God, is the search after truth, nothing less. In treating this general question, we take up the Theodicy, consequently Metaphysics; we take up Logic, because we are concerned with one of the two processes of reasoning, and that the chief one. We must evidently treat of Morals, since the condition without which nothing can be proved, the existence of God, is a moral question, a free act of our soul ; then we treat of Psy- chology, since we are concerned with the principal acts of both the intelligence and the will : we are at the point where all branches of philosophy meet, at the centre, the root, of philosophy. This is why we are forced first to settle this supreme question. Let us not fear, therefore, to dwell as long as may be needful upon this central point, which includes everything, even the history of philosophy. I. Aristotle arrives at the same results as Plato. For, as we shall see in the course of this work, all geniuses of the first order agree, often even when they seem or believe them- ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 63 selves to be in opposition. In reality, it is the sophists who contradict one another and contradict the philosophers. Cicero declares that the difference between the Academy and the Portico is only a difference of words. 1 And yet it must be said that if, indeed, the great results are the same, there is more than a difference of words, there is a difference in the method, at least so far as regards the statement. There are two processes of reasoning, as we have already said. Now, we may assert and distinctly settle this point : Plato represents the one, and Aristotle the other. Plato is above all else dialectic ; Aristotle is peculiarly syllogistic. It is only unconsciously that he ever handles the dialectic process, and he gives no complete analysis of it. And yet Aristotle could not be ignorant of these two in- tellectual processes, and he calls them syllogism and induc- tion (eiraycoyr)). He says, what is true, that induction gives us primary causes ; syllogism, consequences* He sees, what we have already observed, that a knowledge of primary causes considered, not as possible, but as actual and existing, presupposes experience as the point of support of induction. 2 Thus Aristotle saw the facts. But the great difference between Plato and Aristotle is that the latter, in practice, strove to find everything, or at least to prove everything, by syllogism ; and in theory he knew neither all the conditions nor all the compass of the dia- lectic process. He even denies, in Plato, its legitimacy ; and if he himself makes use of it, it is often without knowing it, and in an implied form. For twenty years the disciple of Plato, he received the results of his work. He had in ad- vance that supreme idea of God given us by the chief pro- cess of reason, used by Plato, and above all brought to us 1 Academ., lib. i. cap. ix. 2 Analyt. prior., lib. i. cap. xxxi. 3. 64 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. by tradition diffused throughout the world, and to which he himself alludes. Aristotle retains all these data, but he en- velops them in syllogisms, so that we lose sight of the way in which the mind obtains them. There occurs, upon this point, in the Theodicy, between Plato and Aristotle, what occurred, at the close of the seven- teenth century, in the domain of geometry, between Leibnitz, the inventor of the Infinitesimal Calculus, and a famous alge- braist, 1 who pretended to deny the discovery, attacked its prin- ciples as inexact and productive of error, and then tried to reproduce and demonstrate, by common algebra, the results which Leibnitz^ obtained by his infinitesimal method. This adversary of Leibnitz kept the Academy of Sciences in sus- pense for several years, twenty years after the discovery. A skilful algebraist, a bold calculator, but as a writer wrapped in obscurity, as Montucla describes him, he reached, or seemed to reach, by vast algebraic circumlocutions, and end- less equations, the same results which Leibnitz found by mere play, and proved with such marvellous simplicity. Obscure and interminable equations enveloped what Leib- nitz analyzed, explained, and made clear in brief and simple formulas. That which Leibnitz found by the infinitesimal method, his adversary could never have found by his alge- braic method, deductive from identity to identity; but the results being given, he sometimes reproduced them by dint of hard work. Only, in his obstinate attempt to reproduce them all, there were instances where he only succeeded by the aid of false calculations and incorrect deductions, forcing a way to attain the wished-for result. And this is what must necessarily happen, in metaphysics, to those who insist upon forcing their way by continuous reasoning, syllogism, and thus reaching from creatures to God, from finite to infinite. Sceptics stop them, and readily 1 See Montucla, Hist, of Mathematics, ii. 360. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 65 show them that the continuity of the deduction is only ap- parent, and covers up voids and gulfs which only the other process of reasoning can bridge over. Our comparison between these philosophers and geometri- cians is faulty, I believe, at but one point : that is, that there was no equality between Leibnitz and his foe, while between the genius of Plato and that of Aristotle, on the contrary, there was parity. But we maintain that those who try to establish by the logic of deduction the results produced by the other process of reasoning, are like the mathematician who denied the infinitesimal calculus, would use nothing but common algebra, and used false figures in order to do without the infinitesimal method. Did Aristotle use false trains of reasoning to establish the same results as Plato, though without succeeding at all points ? We dare not affirm that he did ; we submit the question to those who think themselves competent to answer it. It would be a curious study in logic. But it is certain that Plato is simple and luminous, and Aristotle is involved and obscure ; that the Platonic dialectic is poetic and popu- lar ; and that the Aristotelian syllogisms, on the question of first principles, are so extremely difficult and subtle that the best-equipped intellects would find it a long and difficult task to decide whether the proofs be exact or not. Kant, we are all aware, pronounced them false; only he treats all the rest no better. But when h2 sets forth the type, which, in his opinion, affords the true proof, that type is nothing else, it seems, but the dialectic of Plato with its double logi- cal and moral condition. II. Be this as it may, let us try to face the proofs of the exis- tence of God as set forth by Aristotle. We will not at first refer to the original. We will take Aristotle as explained 66 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. by Saint Thomas Aquinas, whose genius is quite as power- ful, but much more lucid than that of Aristotle. We are fortunate to find such a guide. Saint Thomas Aquinas takes his instances from Aristotle's collective works, he having commented upon them all, and he sums them up as follows in his Summa Contra Gentes. 1 We quote literally : " Having proved that it is possible to demonstrate the exis- tence of God, let us consider such proofs of it as have been given to us." " Here are those of Aristotle, who tries to prove the existence of God in two ways, from the fact of motion." "First proof. Everything which is in motion is moved by something. Now, our senses show us that something moves, the sun, for instance. Therefore it is moved by some other thing which moves it. Moreover, either that other motor is a motion, or it is motionless. If it be motionless, our assertion is proved, namely ; that it is essential to establish a motionless motor, which is God. If, on the contrary, it be in motion, it is moved by some other motor. We must, therefore, either go on in this way forever, or come at last to the motionless motor. But it is impossible to go on thus forever. Accordingly, we must affirm the existence of a primary motionless motor." "But in this proof there are two propositions to be proved, namely : That every moving thing in motion is moved by a motor other than itself, and that we cannot admit of an infinite series of motors." " Aristotle proves the first proposition in three ways : " 1st. If a motor be self-moving, it must contain in itself the primary cause of its motion ; otherwise it is plain that it i& moved by some other motor. It must also be moved by a primary move- ment ; that is to say, by itself, and not by one of its parts, like an animal borne along by the motion of its feet. For in this first case the whole would not be moved by itself, but by its part, and one part by the other. 2 This motor which moves must itself also be divisible, have parts ; for everything that moves is divisible, as 1 Lib. i. cap. iii. 2 Physics, book vii., opening pages. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 67 is proved in the sixth book of the Physics. This settled, the phi- losopher reasons thus : " Everything which we suppose is self-moving is moved by a primary motion. Therefore, inaction of one of its parts involves the inaction of all. For if the inaction of one part leaves the other part in motion, it ceases to be the whole itself which moves by a primary motion ; it is that part alone, since it continues to move while the other part is at rest. But nothing which stops as soon as another thing stops is self-moving ; for that object whose cessa- tion involves the cessation of the other, is also that whose motion involves the motion of the other ; therefore that other is not self- moving. Accordingly, that which we supposed to be self-moving does not actually move of its own impulse. Accordingly, finally, all which is in motion is necessarily moved by some motor other than itself." "We cannot destroy this reasoning by saying that what is supposed to be self-moving can have no part of it in repose ; and again, that the part can neither stop, nor move, save by accident, as Avicenna so scandalously holds (ut Avicenna calum- niatur). In reality, the whole force ot this reasoning lies in the fact that if anything be self-moving by a primary movement, and of itself, not by reason of its parts, it follows that its motion no longer depends upon an outside motor. Now, the movement of the divisible, as well as its being, depends on the being and move- ment of its parts ; hence it cannot move of itself by a primary motion. It is therefore not essential to the truth of the condi- tional proposition inferred here, that we should admit as abso- lutely true that the part moves in the inaction of the whole ; it is enough that the sum-total of this conditional proposition is true ; namely, That if the part be at rest, the whole will be at rest. And it may be true even if the antecedent proposition were impossible ; as in this instance : If a man were an ass, he would be an irrational animal." " 2d. Aristotle again proves the same proposition as follows : a " Everything that moves by accident does not move of itself, but is moved by the movement of some other thing ; this is evi- dent ; neither that which moves naturally, by an inward motion, 1 Physics, text, comm., xxvii. ct infra. 68 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. as the animal whose body is only moved by the soul ; nor that which is moved by nature, by an outward motion, as heavy bodies ; for everything of this kind moves only by the way of generation or else by the removal of an obstacle. Now, all that is moved is moved either by accident or by itself. If by itself, . . . etc." Let us stop here. What will it profit us to prolong this endless chain of propositions, each more obscure and more incomprehensible than the other ? What reader would follow us? Who now believes in this mode of reasoning? The seventeenth century banished it under the name of Aristotelianism. What we have just quoted is but a fourth part of the demonstration. We had yet to finish the second mode in which Aristotle proves his major : All that is in motion is moved by something other than itself. Then we should also be forced to give the third mode of proving that same major. After that there would still remain three other ways of prov- ing the minor, namely : That there is not an infinite series of motors. Then only would the syllogism be demonstrated. Lastly, we should have to set forth the second syllogism, which Aristotle also uses to prove, from motion, the existence of God. We shall not undertake such a task, but shall con- fine ourselves to a closer study of the basis of the line of rea- soning which we have just shown. What we have thus far quoted includes all its postulates. III. Aristotle takes the position, There is motion. And from this he concludes : Therefore there is a first motionless motor. We call this God. Now, there are in this train of reasoning words which can in no wise be filled by the syllogisms which we have just repeated. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 69 What ! from seeing motion shall we infer the motionless, by syllogism, by means of identity ? That is to say that from the variable we infer immuta- bility; from the imperfect, perfection; or from the finite, infinity ! Let any one show us a genuine syllogism which establishes such inference from the fact of motion presented by the senses. Where are the passage and the middle term between these two worlds ? How can we derive immutability from motion by means of deduction ? Clearly, it is impossible. Most assuredly it was none of these arguments that led Aristotle to assert immobility from seeing motion. This conclusion involves a long story in the career of the human mind. Heraclitus spent his life in saying, Every- thing passes, everything slips away (TTCWTCL pee/) ; and amidst these passing waves he never perceived the immutable. This was the cause of his sorrow. And that sublime regret a sense of the imperfection of this changing world, a long- ing for immutability did not lead him up to the conclusion that the immutable exists. He understood motion and its strange significance, but nothing more. Plato also under- stood motion, and he said : All that we see slips away ; everything passes, is born, and dies ; and we behold nothing that does not change. But having said this, Plato did not confine himself to regret. The contrast between this changing spectacle, this perishable nature, and an innate longing for perfection, immutability, and immortality, awoke in his soul that memory of the eternal, unchanging, and per- fect Being which our soul also feels ; and he asserted the existence of the immovable on the occasion of that which passes. And this very point was the basis of his whole pro- cess and his whole doctrine. Aristotle, therefore, was furnished in the advance with this result, which cannot be obtained otherwise. Aristotle pos- 70 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. sesses the truth and strives to set it forth. To explain it he wraps it in syllogisms. This seems clear to those who are beginning to think; and Aristotle taught. These syllogisms, with which it was impossible to find the truth, were no more useful to prove it; they throw no light upon it, they veil it. We can scarce recognize it under this disguise. We may even question whether they do not destroy it, and whether there are not gross faults of logic in this chain of reasoning. Who will prove the contrary ? Who 'will sift all the mean- ings of the words motion, immobility, immutability, and inertia, to learn whether, in one of the links in his chain, Aristotle does not confuse them ? To Aristotle, the idea of motion is identical with that 'of change. 1 He defines motion as the transition from poten- tiality to act? Plato made motion synonymous with life (KLV^CTLV teal %wi]v\ and thence placed motion in the absolute, infinite Being (KLVVJO-IV teal farjv . . . rc3 Traz/reXaK OVTL). Now, Aristotle himself sometimes takes motion in the same sense as Plato, as Saint Thomas Aquinas remarks. Nevertheless, in the proof of the existence of God through motion, it is clear that motion is understood in the sense of change, or of the transition from potentiality to act. This established, let us put Aristotle's reasoning into exact form, and see if it be possible for us to judge from it, to admit it or to deny it. The entire chain of reasoning may be reduced to the two following syllogisms : FIRST SYLLOGISM. Major. Everything in motion is moved by a motor other than itself; in other words, nothing moves of itself. Minor. Now, our eyes show us the fact of motion. 1 Metaph., xi. 11, 12. We quote from the Berlin edition. 2 Ibid., xi. 9. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 71 Conclusion. Therefore, there is something else which moves that -which we see in motion. SECOND SYLLOGISM. Major. There cannot be an infinite series of motors ; in other words, there can only be a finite series of motors ; in other words, there is one first motor. Minor. Now, this motor would not be the first if it were in motion, since it would then be moved by some other thing (as results from the first major). Conclusion. Therefore, there is one first motionless motor. We call this God. These syllogisms are correct in form, but are they true as facts ? We see at the first glance that they are true if the majors be true. But who will prove those majors ? There lie the yawning voids. For instance, how can we prove by syllogism, starting from an obvious general proposition, that nothing moves of itself ? Yet Aristotle tries to do so. It is in this way that he tries to establish the existence of the one first motionless motor ; that is, the existence of God. He makes the attempt ; we have seen his efforts to prove the first major, namely, " that everything in motion is moved ~by a motor other than itself." But his arguments on this point are so subtle and so doubtful that Avicenna claims that the reasoning is false ; and Saint Thomas Aquinas, who considers Avicenna's objection scandalous (ut Avicenna ca- lumniatur), is still forced to confess that the argument rests on a conditional proposition, whose condition may be impos- sible or contradictory, as in this : If man be an ass, he is an irrational animal (Si homo est asinus, est irrationalis). Who shall be the judge ? Is the argument good ? I know not, being unable to understand all parts of it. Is it false, on account of the contradictory conditional ? I dare not say 72 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. so, for even in algebra we introduce and calculate with imagi- nary quantities, that is, impossibilities and contradictions. What I assert is that these syllogisms are, to say the least, not valid ; they do not discover the great truth which they contain ; they do not make it manifest, and if, strictly speak- ing, they demonstrate it, it is because they include the other process of reasoning. Moreover, Aristotle never puts his arguments into such scholastic form as Saint Thomas has done here. But it is certain that he generally tries to deduce everything by syllo- gism from an evident fact or an abstract major. He seldom advances in his statement by any other than the deductive process of reasoning ; and this annoying habit often deprives his reasoning I refer to the reasoning only of its clear- ness, validity, utility, sometimes perhaps its solidity. Does it follow from this that Aristotle's Theodicy contains nothing new or valuable? Far from it; and we will now attempt to show what he accomplished. IV. If Aristotle be syllogistic in his statement, proceeding by abstract majors and deductions, we cannot conclude from this that in his inner mental action he retained nothing of the other process of reasoning. We have already said, and we shall show when we come to logic, that he mentions and clearly distinguishes between the two processes of reasoning, attributing to the one the invention of majors, and to the other deduction. In his profound meditations he made use he could not but make use of the sublime process which leads to God. But he generally managed to use it unawares, like the majority of mankind, and concealed, through a trick of style, his mode of discovery by a very different mode of statement and proof. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 73 Be this as it may, not only did this powerful genius renew in his thought the data of tradition in regard to God, and the results of the Platonic method ; but we may also say that on several points, not on all, he gave clearness and pre- cision to Plato's theology. Had he added to the theodicy nothing but the three words, God is pure act, a formula which has been marvellously commented upon and used in every way by Saint Thomas Aquinas, he would have given the human mind an idea of capital significance. To judge Aristotle, we should know the last chapters of the twelfth book of his Metaphysics. We will try to give an idea of these chapters by quotations and brief commentaries. Our quotations will be given in exactly the order in which they occur in the original. We shall glean the truth from these chapters, setting aside the often inexact reasoning which he brings to bear upon it, as well as his errors in regard to the nature of the physical heavens, the imperishable nature of the stars, and the eter- nity of the world, errors to correspond with which there are other metaphysical errors and inexplicable contradictions. In spite of these exceptions, these chapters are still a truly admirable summary of a theodicy. " There are three essences, two of which are natural, and one immutable. . . . For there must necessarily be one eternal, unchanging essence." 1 Yes, there are two natural or created essences, mind and matter ; one immutable or uncreated, which is God. Saint Thomas Aquinas explains this as follows : " There are two substances which are natural, because there is motion in them ; besides these two substances, there is a third which is immovable or immutable, and no longer natural." Nat- 1 Metaph., xii. 6. It is a mistake to translate this: "There are three es- sences, two physical, the other immutable," for the word physical does not mean natural, but corporeal. Saint Thomas Aquinas translates it with perfect accuracy: ducB quidem naturales. 74 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. ural, mobile, subject to change, are one and the same thing, according to Aristotle ; as also, on the other hand, immobile, immutable, eternal, and supernatural are terms each of which includes the other. Pascal expresses the same truth in other words : " There are three worlds, the world of bodies, the world of mind, and the third, which is supernatural, which is God." This had been established by Genesis long before : " In the beginning God made heaven and earth ; " where we must understand, with the Fourth Council of the Lateran, that heaven and earth signify mind and matter, natural things, which began, which were born. " There must," adds Aristotle, " be a first cause such that its essence is pure act." 1 Otherwise the world could not exist, as Aristotle says. This the sophists ignore, who believe that Being began with a mere potentiality or possibility, which is the same as saying that effects can exist without a cause. " A being which moves without being moved is eternal, is pure essence, is pure act. " 2 The formula God is pure essence ; God is pure act is immensely fruitful. Saint Thomas Aquinas, who develops it by the light of his Christian genius, superior as such to that of Aristotle, extracts genuine treasures from it, discovers wonderful depths of meaning in it. We will only say here, in a few words, that when we know that God is pure essence, that is, that all is essential in God, we know that in him there is no accident, no variable or secondary qualities. His being is his essence, that is to say, it is necessary; his knowl- edge is his essence, his will is his essence, his blessedness is his essence. When we knqw that God is pure act, in other words, that in him everything is act, we know that there is not in him, as in us, virtual and actual, possible and real, potentiality and act, but that with God all that is possible i Metaph., xii. 6. 2 ibid., /. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 75 is actual ; that there is nothing in him to be developed or completed ; that he is already perfect ; that he is not, like his creatures, capable of indefinite development, but that he is already now, if we may so express it, infinitely developed. This establishes absolutely the distinction between the finite and the infinite. To be pure essence and pure act is pre- cisely the divine characteristic of infinity. At least, this is what Saint Thomas Aquinas asserts in these formulas, whether or no Aristotle ever perceived it. What immediately follows in the original is both clear and profound. It is the way in which the one first motionless motor moves the other two essences. " It moves thus. The desirable and the intelligible moves without being moved. ... It moves as the object of love." l " The supreme, desirable, and intelligible are one and the same thing (TOVTWV TO, Trpwra ra avrd)" This essence moves as the object of love; it attracts. Here we have the universal charm or attraction of the desirable and intelligible, which, according to Aristotle, at- tracts everything, material and spiritual, each in its way, and which causes, without exception, all motion, that uni- versal attraction of which physics now knows something, and with which psychology, let us hope, will some day be familiar as the original source of all motion, all facts, the entire history of the soul. And here Aristotle makes this important remark by the way : " The object of desire is the apparition of the Beautiful ; but the object of will is the Beautiful itself." 2 Furthermore : " So soon as there is a being which moves, although motionless, and which is motionless, although in action, that being ceases to be subject to change." " This motor, then, is a necessary being ; and in so far as necessary, is the Good, and is the First Cause." 1 Metaph., xii. 7. 2 Ibid. 76 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. " Such is the First Cause, upon which hang heaven and earth." l This reminds us of Plato's statement that " the divine is bound to us by the very roots of our being ; " and that other Platonic doctrine, that " the First Cause is the Good itself." Here, now, is what the First Cause actually is : " We taste fugitive happiness ; he possesses it forever." " His happiness is his very act ; to be awake, to feel, to think, is our good ; afterwards, memory and hope." 2 But what is his act or his happiness ? It is thought in itself. "But thought in itself is the thought of the best in itself; and the thought above all other thought is that of the Good above all other good. Now, thought thinks itself by grasping the intelligible, and it becomes intelligible by this contact and this thinking ; so that the thought and its object are one and the same thing. To grasp the intelligible, to grasp the essence, is thought : this very possession is its act. And this act, which constitutes all thought, has, it seems, a divine character ; so that contemplation is cer- tainly happiness and perfection." " But if God continually tastes this happiness, of which man can only enjoy the fugitive taste, assuredly his bliss is wonderful ; more wonderful still if this happiness is greater in him than it is in us. Now, it is so. For this very thing, this happiness itself, is his life ; the intelligible in act is life ; now, he is all act ; so the act in itself is his life, eternal and supreme life. We call God a perfect and eternal living being, because continual and eternal life is in him; or rather, that life itself is God." 3 Certainly, this is a truly profound contribution to the The- odicy, full of most fruitful and luminous points, although they are but slightly developed, and thus very remote from our habits of thought, which demand so many explanations. It is plain that we have here a powerful implicit light, and that it is not easy for human reason to go higher, or to see farther. i Metaph., xii. 7. 2 Ibid. 8 Ibid. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 77 In this extract we have some faint vision of deep mys- teries. When Leibnitz observes the amazing phenomenon of the reflection of minds, which consists in the fact " that a mind is itself its own immediate object and acts upon itself, thinking of itself and of what it has done ; " 1 when he recog- nizes " that this reduplication gives in a similar absolute sub- stance an image of two respective substances, that which understands and that which is understood," and when, more- over, he considers that " that which is modal, accidental, imperfect, and changeable in us, is real, essential, complete, and immutable in God," Leibnitz sees in this reduplication, as it were, a trace of the plurality of divine persons in the Unity of God. It seems to us that this is exactly what Aristotle, unconsciously, no doubt, catches a glimpse of here both in the soul and in God. He calls these three principles : 1. Good in itself (TO /ca0 y avro apiorrov). 2. Thought in itself (vorjais 77 /caO' avrrjv). 3. Act or Life in itself (evepyeia Be 77 /caO' avrrjv e/ceivov But thought in itself is thought of the Good in itself (r; Be rj /ca6' avTrjv rov Kad' avro aplcrrov) ; and thought and its object, the Good, are one and the same thing (wo-re TCLVTOV vovs KOii vo^Tov). But this mutual possession of thought and its object is its act (euepyel Se excov) ; this act in itself is the life of God (Ixeivov fw??) ; and this excellent, eternal life is God himself (TOVTO yap 6 eoz>), and he con- cludes : " The first motionless motor is therefore a Unity both as regards form and number." 3 But even after this he falls back into his error concerning several secondary gods, and says that the fabulous mythology of the ancients contains this basis of truth, "That the stars are gods, and that the divine surrounds all nature (OTI 6eoi re cl&iv ovrot KOI Tre/ote^et TO Oeiov rrjv o\r)v );" and these secondary gods are distinguished by Aristotle from the sovereign God, in that he alone is first, in that he alone is immovable loth in himself and accidentally, he alone is all act, has his end in himself, and is entelechy. The others are not all act, they are immovable by themselves, but movable accidentally. He alone, again, is the first desirable and the first intelligible, and the sovereign Good. VL God's relations with the world, according to Aristotle, are these : "We must now consider 4 how universal nature includes the Good, the sovereign Good. Is it as a separate being, existing in i Metaph., xii. 8. * Ibid . 3 Ibid . 4 Ibid<> 10 . ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 83 itself, or rather as the cosmic order, or in both ways at once, as in an army 1 For the good of an army is its order, and it is also, its chief, particularly its chief: order does not constitute the leader, it is the leader who gives order." Aristotle admits both, and shows the absurdities which flow from any other system. Those, for instance, who do not accept the supreme Good as a separate principle existing by itself, those who " derive beings from non-being, or, to escape this necessity, reduce everything to absolute unity." 1 Here Aristotle stigmatizes, as Plato does, the old absur- dity of atheism which derives being from non-being, as well as the old absurdity of pantheism, which refers everything to absolute identity. He thus at once attacks the present German sophists at both ends, those alike who admit non- being and absolute identity, and who still fancy that in Aristotle they have a powerful ally. Aristotle at the same time refutes those who admit of two opposite principles, as these sophists also do, and shows that they " are forced to give an opposite to supreme knowledge and wisdom, an excess which we avoid," 2 says Aristotle. " The first prin- ciple has no opposite (ov yap larlv evavriov rw irpwrtd oi)6ev). The first principle is unique. Those who take for their principle number and an infinite series of essences, each essence having its principle, make the universe a collec- tion of episodes and a host of principles (eVe^ro&wS?; rrjv rov Travrbs ovcriav iroiovcnv . . . KOI ap^a^ TroXXa?). But beings do not wish to be ill-governed. Homer says, "A multiplicity of leaders is of no avail. Let one alone rule : " OVK dyadov TroXvKoipavirj. Eis Koipavos eoro>." 8 Thus closes, with the twelfth book of Aristotle's Meta- physics, this fine abstract of a Theodicy. ""ORNIA. . Metaph., xii. 10. 2 Ibid. II. ii. 204^ ' 84 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. VII. It was doubtless to his Metaphysics that Aristotle alluded, when, on Alexander's reproaching him for having revealed the sublimities of knowledge, he replied, " I have so revealed them as not to reveal them." It is still true that these books, more than any of his others, earned for Aristotle the title of the Dark. In his work on the World he is clearer. 1 After developing his ideas in regard to the world, he adds, " It remains for us to speak briefly of the cause which contains and governs the whole. An old tradition, circulated among all mankind by our fathers, tells us that everything comes from God and through God, that no nature suffices unto itself (ovSe/xta Se vcris avTTj KaO 1 eavrrjv ecrnv aurapKrys), and exists only by his help. . . . God is, in fact, the preserver and Father of all that is in the world, and he acts in everything that acts, not as the workman who labors and grows weary, but as an omnipotent virtue which operates. . . . 2 "We must know of God that his might is irresistible, his beauty complete, his life immortal, his virtue supreme, and that, invisible to any mortal nature, he is visible in his works. And surely all motions and all beings which are in the air, on the earth, or in the waters, are really the works of God, who contains the universe. . . . 3 "God is an immutable law, a law which can be neither changed nor corrected, a law holier and better than the laws written on our tables. Governing all by incessant activity and infallible harmony, he directs and orders the entire universe, heaven and earth, and diffuses himself throughout all beings. . . . 4 " He is One, but he has several names, derived from his various modes of action in the woild. Does it not seem that when we call him both Zena, and Dia we mean Him ~by whom we live ? . . . 5 1 I know that the authenticity of this book is contested. But there is a passion for disputing the authenticity of books to which we should only yield on decisive proof. 2 De Mundo, vi. p. 397. 4 Ibid. p. 401. 8 Ibid., p. 399. . 6 ibid. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 85 "All these names stand for God alone, as the noble Plato re- marks. God therefore, according to ancient tradition, is the be- ginning, end, and middle of all that is, and traverses all nature in a straight line (showing to all things his direct course), ever fol- lowed by justice, the avenger of those who transgress upon this divine line, justice which all should possess who desire to attain in the future to a state of blessedness, and all who desire to be happy in the present." 1 VIII. Certainly all that precedes is grand and beautiful, but we now come to a point where Aristotle's genius seems to us amazing. Saint Thomas Aquinas 2 asserts that Aristotle first called attention to the great distinction between the two degrees of the divine intelligible, which we have already encountered in Plato. Doubtless Aristotle is far from having seen the whole of this vast question: that was impossible in his day. But evidently he saw the truth, and grasped certain features of it with admirable precision. In the first place, he distinguishes in man, with perfect distinctness, the two lights which Saint Augustine calls light which illuminates and the light which is illuminated, and which Fe'nelon describes as the reason which borrows and the reason which gives. " Everywhere in nature," says Aristotle, " we find the distinction between that which is only in the potential state, and that which, being already actual, pro- duces the passage from potentiality to act. This distinction necessarily recurs in the soul. There is a passive intellect capable of becoming anything, and there is an active intellect capable of producing everything. The latter is like the light. Light converts into actual fact colors which only exist in potentiality. So, too, separable intellect (distinct from man), 1 De Mundo, close of the book. 2 Contra Gentes, cap. iii. 3. 86 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. impassive and entirely pure, is act in essence. . . . That in- tellect is Being itself, it alone is immortal, eternal, and with- out it the passive intellect can do nothing." 1 Aristotle, therefore, perceived, in the analysis of reason, that fundamental distinction which Fdnelon develops so finely, between the reason which is within us, and the reason which is God himself. In all his works he recurs to this. He everywhere main- tains that this principle, intelligent and intelligible, pure in- tellect, is not the same thing as the soul, 2 and that neither perception (alaOdvecrOcu), 3 memory, nor ordinary thought (Sofae>), 4 nor reasoning (Xo7irois vrao-t). 12 This latter assertion would correspond with those solemn words of holy Scripture : " The sun of intelligence has not risen upon them." 13 Aristotle, clearly, here refers to the final perfection of in- 1 De Anima, iii. 5. * Ibid. 7 Ibid. 2 Ibid., i. 2. 5 ibid., ii. 3. 8 Ibid., i. 4. 8 Ibid., 5. 6 Ibid. 9 Ibid. 10 De Generat. Amina, ii. 3, and ii. 6. n De Anima, ii. 2. 12 "Intelligence, in the sense in which we understand it, does not seem to exist indifferently in all animals, or even in all men" (De Anima, i. 2). 1 3 Wisdom, v. 6. ARISTOTLE'S THEODICY. 87 telligence, its end and last term, which Plato calls the term of the intellectual procedure, and Saint Augustine, reason attaining its end, a termination which consists, accord- ing to Aristotle, in seeing the intelligible as he sees him- self, in seeing him by touching him (Oiyydvcov /cal vowv), and in becoming one with him (ware ravrbv vov$ /cal VOTJTOV) ; which Saint Augustine also considers as the proper charac- teristic of the vision of God. But this contemplation, says Aristotle, which is happiness, and which, in God, is continu- ous, is only granted to man at rare intervals. 1 Our mind is naturally in respect to this high degree of light as the eye of the owl in respect to the sun. 2 God always sees this pure intelligible light, it is himself : in God intelligence and the intelligible are identical. 3 But with re- gard to us, this divine light is supernatural ; and the soul, in so far as we consider it as illuminated by this light, is not purely natural* This light, according to Aristotle, does not come by generation. The soul, in so far as vegetative, sensi- tive, rational, that is to say, in so far as including life, ani- mality, and humanity, the soul comes by generation, and develops with the total germ. But this light of intelligence alone comes to man otherwise, it only is divine. 5 This light is the end and object of man, and the sovereign good consists in its contemplation. So thinks and says Aristotle. We will consider these extracts further elsewhere. Let the reader ponder well the beautiful words which follow : " If it be true that happiness is virtue in act, it is, above all, the act of the highest virtue ; it is, above all, the act of that which is best in man. Whether this best be the intellect, or any other principle which, by nature, should prevail in man, and which pos- 1 Metaph., xii. 7. 4 Part. Anim., p. 641. 2 Ibid., ii. 1. 5 De Generat. Anim., ii. 2. 8 Ibid., xii. 7. 88 GUIDE TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. sesses in itself the light of the divine and the good; whether this test be the divine itself, or that which is most divine in man, in any case it is the action of that principle, acting in harmony with its own peculiar virtue, which must constitute perfect happiness. We have already said that this action is contemplation. . . . But such a life is superior to the life of man : it is not in that he is man that he mill live thus, but in that a divine principle lives within him ; 1 and inasmuch as this principle differs from that compound which is man, just so much will its action triumph over the action of every other virtue. If the intellect be divine relatively to the man, the life according to its action will be divine relatively to human life. Man, therefore, according to the warning of the wise, must learn to rise above the mere human, to lose all sense of anything mortal, and to live immortally with the life of the higher principle which lives within him." Let the reader take heed lest he forget these fragments from Aristotle. We shall make use of them again. IX. Let us close this study of Aristotle's theodicy with two re- marks, one concerning the method, and the other the result. As regards the method, it is plain that Aristotle used both processes of reasoning. This we have seen. Nothing else was possible ; but Aristotle did not always realize this with sufficient distinctness. Aristotle possessed that profound good sense peculiar to the genius which seeks truth rather than the mere means of finding it. He was particularly free from the unbearable sophistical madness which demands absolute proof of every- thing. " It is ridiculous " (