- ^\ BOOK 180.B179S c 1 3 T1S3 ODOhami a SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY BY CHARLES M. ^KEWELL PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN YALE UNIVERSITY CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS NEW YORK CHICAGO BOSTON Copyright, 1907, by CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS Printed in the United States of Americr. Published September, 1907 K PREFACE Every one who has attempted to introduce students to the study of Philosophy by way of its history must have felt the need of having in compact form the most significant documents upon which the interpretations of that history are based, in order that it may be possible from the first to bring the student into direct contact with the sources, so far at least as that may be done through the medium of translations. The primary aim of this book is to supply this need. It is intended to serve either as a companion volume to any History of Philosophy that may be adopted as a text-book, or as a substitute for such a history where the instructor may prefer through his own lectures to give his own inter- pretation of this philosophical movement. It is hoped that the book may also, as a reference work, prove of value to students of philosophy generally, as well as to all who are interested in the development of ancient thought. No attempt has been made to make an exhaustive Source Book. I have simply brought together the more significant passages from the earlier philosophers, begin- ning with Thales and reaching as far as Plotinus. The book includes most of the fragments of the earliest philosophers, together with the passages from the second- ary sources which are most important in throwing light upon these fragments. In the case of the other philos- ophers it includes a number of brief extracts which may Vi PREFACE serve as texts to hang discussions on, and also some more extended passages selected with the view of bringing one directly into the spirit and method of the several phi- losophers represented. More space has been given to Plotinus than his relative importance would warrant. This, however, needs no apology. Plotinus is perhaps more frequently misrepresented in historical discussions than any other Greek philosopher. Here especially is it necessary to let the philosopher speak for himself. And, besides, Plotinus's works are comparatively in- accessible to English readers, whereas the extracts from Plato and Aristotle, from Lucretius and the later Stoics can be supplemented at will. While most of these sources are already accessible in translation they are^ scattered through so many volumes, and are mixed with so much material that is chiefly of value to the advanced student whose historical interests have become highly specialized, as to be practically unavailable for use in connection with introductory courses. My obligations to others are so numerous that it would be impossible to mention them all. In making the translations I have in each case had before me all of the translations already in the field, whether in English, German, French, or Latin, upon which I could lay my hands; and I have borrowed freely from most of them. In especial, however, I should like to acknowledge my indebtedness to Professors Diels, Burnet, and Fairbanks ; and in the selection of passages I have taken many suggestions from the works of Hitter and Preller, Wallace, Jackson, and Adam. I wish also to express my gratitude to Prof. G. H. Palmer for many valuable suggestions, and for the con- PREFACE vii tribution of his translation of the Hymn of Clean thes; and to Dr. B. A. G. Fuller for the selection and transla- tion of the passages from Plotinus, and the passages from Plutarch in criticism of the Stoic theodicy. My thanks are also due to Mr. T. W. Higginson for permission to quote from his translation of Epictetus, to Dr. W. T. Harris for permission to reprint from The Journal of Speculative Philosophy the translation of the fragments of Parmenides, made by the late Thomas Davidson, and to the Cambridge University Press, the Oxford University Press, Messrs. George Bell & Sons, The Macmillan Company, and Little, Brown & Company, for permission to use translations published by them. Special acknowledgments of borrowed translations are made in foot-notes. The only case where confusion is likely to arise is in the extracts from Plato. I assume responsibility myself for the translation of the Apology; the selections from the Republic are from the translation of Davies and Vaughan, and all the remaining Plato selections are from the latest edition of Jowett's work. CONTENTS PAGE I. — The Milesian School 1 Thales: General standpoint of the early philosophers, and the opinions of Thales, 1, Anaximander: The "bound- less" as first principle, 3. Scientific speculations, 5. Anaximenes: His opinions, 7. J II. — ^The Eleatic School 8 Xenophanes: The fragments, 8. An illustration of Xenoph- anes's scientific reasoning, 10. Parmenides: The frag- ments of his poem "On Nature," 11. Plato and Aristotle on Eleatic philosophy, 20. Zeno: The puzzles of com- position and division, 22. Space not a real thing. 23. The puzzles of motion, 24. The purpose of Zeno's arguments as reported by Plato, 25. III. — Heraclitus 28 The fragments, 28. IV. — ^The Pythagorean Philosophy . . . . . .36 The number philosophy of the Pythagoreans, 36. The Pythagorean " Golden Words," 40. V. — ^Empedocles 43 The fragments, 43. Secondary sources, 46. VI. — Anaxagoras 49 The fragments, 49. Secondary sources, 53. Some of Aristotle's comments on Anaxagoras, 55. VII. — ^The Atomists 57 Leucippus, 57. Leucippus and Democritus, 58. Democ- ritus: The fragments, 59. The "Golden Sayings" of Democritus, 60. The atomists on the soul according to Aristotle, 65. ix X CONTENTS PAGE VIII. — ^The Sophists 67 Two sayings of Protagoras, 67. A saying of Gorgias, 67. An account of the calling and profession of the Sophist from the writings of Plato, 68. Aristotle on the Sophists, 69. The Sophists and the Athenian youth, 69. The Prota- gorean doctrine of relativity as Plato interprets it in the Thecetetus, 78. Gorgias as a rhetorician, 85. IX. — Socrates 86 Aristotle on Socrates's achievement, 86. Xenophon's tribute to Socrates, 86. The sort of questions Socrates was concerned with, 90. Socrates on the Good and the Beautiful, 91, Socrates's method, 95. A bit of his biog- raphy, as reported by Plato, 96. An illustration of his method of showing up ignorance, 101. X. — Socrates's Defence of Himself as Reported by Plato in the APOLOGY 104 XI. — ^The Lesser Socrates 142 The Cyrenaics. Aristippus, 142. The Cynics. Antis- thenes and Diogenes, 145. XII.— Plato 148 Plato's relation to his predecessors according to Aristotle, 148. From the Phcedrus: Dialectic vs. rhetoric, 149. From the Symposium: On love, 152. From the Philebus: Pleasure and the other goods, 157. From the Timceus: The creation of the world, 160. Why it is necessary to assume the existence of the Ideas, 167. From the Par- menides: Puzzles presented by the theory of ideas, 168. XIII.— Plato— Con^inwed 180 From the Republic: The nature of virtue, 180. The four cardinal virtues, 182. The higher education leading up to the Idea of the Good, 186. The Idea of the Good as the source of truth and of reality, 192. Reality and appearance ; knowledge and opinion, 199. The allegory of the den; shadows and realities, 203. Dialectic the coping stone of the sciences, 213. CONTENTS XI PAGS XIV. — ^Aristotle 217 Origin and nature of philosophy, 217. Aristotle's criticism of the theory of ideas, 220. Aristotle's o^n view regard- ing the universal, 223. The four causes, 225. Aristotle's conception of God: Necessity of assuming a first cause or prime mover, 227. Divine reason as the prime mover, 230. Divine reason and its object, 233. XV. — ^Aristotle on Psychology 236 The nature of the soul, 236. The animate and the in- animate, 240. Nourishment the fundamental function, touch the fundamental sense, 242. Sense-perception, 243. Cognition, 244. Creative reason, 246. Reason and judg- ment, 247. Reason and its object, 248. The springs of action, 249. XVI. — ^Aristotle on Ethics 251 The summum bonum, 251. To find it we ask what is man's function, 253. How virtue is acquired, 257. Virtue and vice ahke voluntary, 259. On friendship, 261. Highest happiness found in the vision of truth, 264. How the end is to be reahzed, 266. XVIL— The Stoics 269 The parts of philosophy and the criterion of truth, 269. Ethics: Following nature, 272. The Hymn of Cleanthes, 277. Plutarch's refutation of the Stoic theodicy, 278. XVIII.— Epicurus 290 Theory of knowledge, 290. Physical speculations, 293. The practical philosophy of Epicurus, 296. Some maxims of Epicurus, 302. XIX. — Lucretius 305 The wages of philosophy, 305. The course of the atoms, 307. The unconcerned gods, 309. The nature of mind and soul, 309. DispelUng the dread of death, 313. No designer of nature, 316. xii CONTENTS PAGE XX. — Epictetus 317 Things which are in our power, 317. The essence of good, 320. As Socrates would have done, 322. In harmony with God and His universe, 324. XXI. — Marcus Aurelius 326 Follow nature, 326. The harmony of the universe, 331. Man's insignificance and his grandeur, 336. XXII.— Plotinus 340 The soul, 340. The intellect, 353. The One, 363. The process of emanation, 371. XXIII. — Plotinus — Continued 375 Matter, 357. Sin and salvation, 384. I THE MILESIAN SCHOOL THALES [Flourished 585 B.C.] GENERAL STANDPOINT OF THE EARLY PHILOSOPHERS AND THE OPINIONS OF THALES J — . Most i of the early philosophers were content to seek a material first principle as the cause of all things. For that of which all things consist, from which they arise, into which they pass away, the substance remaining the same through all its changing states — that, I say, is what they mean by the element, or the first principle, of the things that are. And this is why they hold that, strictly speaking, nothing comes into being or perishes, since the primal nature remains ever the same. For instance, when Socrates becomes handsome or cultured we do not just say he comes into being; nor, when he loses these characteristics, do we say that Socrates is no more. Socrates, the subject, remains the same throughout these changes. And it is the same with all things. There must be some natural body ((^uo-t?), one or many, from which all things arise, but which itself remains the same. r But of what sort this first principle is, and how many ^uch there are, this is a point upon which they are not agreed. Thales, the originator of this kind of philosophy, 1 Aristotle, Met. I. 3, 983 b 6 (R. P. 9 a). 1 2 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY declares it to be water. (And this is why he said that the earth floats on water.) Possibly he was led to this opinion by observing that the nourishment of all things is moist, and that heat itself is generated and kept alive by moisture. And that from which all things are generated is just what we mean by their first prin- ciple. This may be where he got his idea, and also from observing that the germs of all things are moist, and that moist things have water as the first principla of their nature. Some indeed hold that those who lived ages ago, long before the present generation, and who were the first to reason about the gods, held a similar view about nature, since they sang of Oceanus and Tethys as the parents of creation, and since the oath by which their gods swore was water, or, as the poets themselves called it, Styx. Now that which is most held in esteem is the object by which men swear; and that which is most ancient is that which is most esteemed. Whether there be any such ancient and primitive opinion about nature is doubtless an obscure question. However, Thales is said to have expressed the opinion above set forth concerning the first cause. * * And 2 some hold that the soul f is diffused through the universe. Perhaps this is what led Thales to say that all things are full of gods. 2 Aristotle, Psychology, I. 5, 411 a 7 (R. P. 10 a). t One must beware of reading later meanings into the word 'soul.* To 'have soul' (i|/wxV ^x^*") means little more than 'to be alive.' 'Vital principle' would perhaps express the meaning better, were it not for the fact that that expression implies a greater degree of abstraction than we can properly attribute to these early thinkers. THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 3 Judging 3 from what is reported of him, Thales appears to have viewed the soul as something having the capacity to set up movement, if it is true that he said that the loadstone has a soul because it moves iron. ANAXIMANDER [Flourished about 570 B.C.] THE "boundless" AS FIRST PRINCIPLE Among 4 those who say that the first principle is one and mobile and boundless is to be reckoned Anaximander of Miletus, the son of Praxiades, the successor and follower of Thales. He said that "the boundless'' (rb aireopov) was the first principle and element of the things that are, being the first to make use of this term in describing the first principle. He says it is neither water nor any of the other elements now recognized, but some other and different natural body which is boundless; and from it arise all the heavens and all the worlds which they contain. That from which things take their origin, into that again they pass away, as destiny orders; for they are punished and give satisfaction to one another for their injustice in the ordering of time, as he puts it in rather poetical language. It is evident that, observing the way in which the ("four elements are transformed into one another, he I thought fit to take for the substratum, not some one 3 Aristotle, 405 a 17 (R. P. 10 b). * Theophr. Fr. 2 ap. Simplic. Phijs., 24 (Dox. 476; R. P. 12). [I use throughout the ^customary abbreviations, — "Dox." for Diels' Doxographi Grceci, and "R. P." for Ritter and Preller, Historia PhilosophicB Grcecce.] 4 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY of them, but rather something else over and above them all. And he did not attribute creation (yeveaL<;) to any change in this element, but rather to the separating of the opposites occasioned by the eternal movement. This is why Aristotle compares his view with that of Anaxagoras. h=** And ^ he says that this principle, which encompasses all worlds, is eternal and ageless. — And besides this, there is eternal movement in which there results the creation of the heavens. *** And ^ there is another point of view from which one does not make the cause any change of matter, nor ascribe creation to any transformation of the substratum, but rather to separation. Anaximander says that the opposites inhering in the substratum, which is a bound- less body, are separated out, — he being the first to name the substratum as first principle. And the '' op- posites" are, hot and cold, moist and dry, etc. *** Everything ^ either is a first principle or arises from a first principle; but of the boundless there is no first principle, for to find a first principle for it would be to give it bounds. Further, it (the boundless) is un- begotten and indestructible, being a first principle. That which is created perishes, and there is a limit to all destruction. Therefore there is no first principle of the boundless, but it is rather the first principle of other things. And it encompasses all things and rules all things, in the opinion of those who do not assume, in 5 Hipp. Ref. I. 6 (Dox. 559; R. P. 13). 6 Simpl. Phys. 150, 29 D (R. P. 14 a). 7 Aristotle, Phys. III. 4, 203 b 6 (R. P. 13). THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 5 addition to the boundless, some other cause such as ''reason/' or ''love." And this is the divine, for it is deathless and indestructible, as Anaximander holds in agreement with most of the physical philosophers. * * But ^ it is not possible that there should be an infinite body which is one and simple; either, as some hold, something over and above the elements and from which they arise, or as one of the elements themselves. For there are some who hold that this (i. e., the something other than the elements) is the boundless, and not air or water, in order that other things may not be destroyed by the boundless. For these (elements themselves) are opposed to one another; air is cold, water moist, fire hot. If one of them were boundless, the rest would have perished ere this. So they say that the boundless is / something other than the elements and that from it ' they arise. SCIENTIFIC SPECULATIONS The ^ earth hangs free, supported by nothing. It keeps its place because it is in the centre (Ht. is equally distant from all things). It is convex and round, like a stone pillar.f There are two surfaces opposite one another, on one of which we are. The stars are circles of fire, separated from the fire which surrounds the world and covered all around with air. But there are breathing holes, certain tube-like openings, through which the stars appear. When these holes close there is an eclipse; and the moon appears now 8 Aristotle, Phys. III. 5, 204 b 22 (R. P. 12 b). 9 Hipp. Ref. I. 6 (Dox. 559-60; R. P. 14 c). t So Diels, Dox. 218, and after him Burnet, p. 72, note. The 'convex' is then taken as referring to the surface of the earth. 6 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY to wax and now to wane through the opening and closing of these holes. . . . The sun is highest of all the heavenly bodies and lowest are the circles of the fixed stars. . . . Rain comes from the vapor drawn up from the earth by the sun. * From 1° the eternal principle was separated at the creation of the world something generative of hot and cold; and from this a sphere of flame grew around the air which surrounds the earth, as the bark grows around the tree. And when the sphere was broken up, and cut into distinct rings, the sun and the moon and the stars came into being. , * Living 11 things sprang from (the moist element!) evaporated by the sun. Man sprang from a different animal, in fact from a fish, which at first he resembled. * * * (Anaximander)i2 says that at first man sprang from a different kind of animal, his reason being that whereas all the other animals are speedily able to find nourish- ment for themselves, man alone requires a long period of suckling; and if he had been at the beginning such as he is now, he would not have survived. * * * The 12 first living things were generated in moisture, and were covered with a hard skin. When they were old enough they came up on the dry banks, and after a while the skin cracked off, and they lived on. 10 Ps. Plut. Strom. 2 (R. P. 14 b; Dox. 579). 11 Hipp. Ref. I. 6 (R. P. 16; Dox. 560). " Ps. Plut. Strom. 2 (R. P. 16; Dox. 579) . i3Aet. Plac. V, 19 (R. P. 16; Dox. 430). t Cf. Diels, Dox., 560, note. THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 7 ANAXIMENES [Flourished about 550 B.C.] THE OPINIONS OF ANAXIMENES Anaximenes ^^ said air was the first principle. * * Anaximenes of Miletus/^ son of Eurystratos, an asso- ciate of Anaximander, agreed with him in holding that the substance of nature was one and boundless; but hei did not agree with him in holding that it was indetermi- nate, for he said it was air. But it differs in rarity and density with different things. When it is very at- tenuated fire arises; when it is condensed wind, then cloud, then, when more condensed, water, earth, stones; and other things come from these. He too holds the movement eternal by which the changes arise. * * Just 1^ as our soul which is air holds us together, so it is breath and air that encompasses the whole world. * * * All 1^ things are generated by a sort of rarefaction and condensation of air. * * * The 18 earth is flat Hke a table top. The 1^ earth is flat and floats on the air. * The 20 stars are fixed like nails in the crystalline vault. " Arist. Met. I 3, 984 a 5. 15 Theophr. Fr. 2, ap. Simplic. Phys., 24 (R. P. 19 b; Dox. 476). 16 Aet. Plac. L 3, 4 (Dox. 278; R. P. 18). 17 Ps. Plut. Strom. Fr. 3 (R. P. 19 a; Dox. 579). 18 Aet. Plac. III. 10, 3 (Dox. 377). 19 Hipp. Ref. I, 7 (R. P. 21; Dox. 560). 20 Aet. 14, 3 (Dox. 344). II THE ELEATIC SCHOOL XENOPHANES [Flourished about 530 B.C.] THE FRAGMENTS j l.t There is one god, supreme among gods and men; resembling mortals neither in form nor in mind. I 2. The whole of him sees, the whole of him thinks, the whole of him hears. f3. Without toil he rules all things by the power of his mind. ^ 4. And he stays always in the same place, nor moves at all, for it is not seemly that he wander about now here, now there. ^; 5. But mortals fancy gods are born, and wear clothes, and have voice and form like themselves. ^ 6. Yet if oxen and lions had hands, and could paint ' with their hands, and fashion images, as men do, they would make the pictures and images of their gods in their own likeness; horses would make them like horses, oxen like oxen. (D. 16) ^Ethiopians tt make their gods black and snub-nosed; Thracians give theirs blue eyes and red hair. \ 34. Xenophanes ^ said it was just as impious to say » Aristotle, Rhet. II. 23. 1399 B 6. t The numbers given the fragments are those of Karsten. tt R. P. 83. Fr. 16 in Diels' arrangement in his Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, a work hereafter referred to as "Diels." 8 THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 9 that the gods are bom as to say that they die. For it follows from either view that at some time or other they do not exist. O^ 7. Homer and Heeiod have ascribed to the gods all deeds that are a shame and a disgrace among men: thieving, adultery, fraud. J 16. The gods did not reveal all things to men at the start; but, as time goes on, by searching, they discover more and more. 4 14. There never was, nor ever will be, any man who knows with certainty the thmgs about the gods and about all things which I tell of. For even if he does happen to get most things right, still he himself does not know it. But mere opinions all may have. i-;»'15. Let these opinions of mine pass for semblances of truths. *** 37. (Upon 2 Empedocles remarking to him (Xeno- phanes) that it was impossible to find a wise man he replied: Very likely; it takes a wise man to know a wise man when he finds one.) f 8. From earth to earth, — the beginning and end of all things. { 9. We all sprang from earth and water. • 10. All things that come into being and grow are earth and water. • 12. The upper limit of the earth we see at our feet, where it strikes against the air; but below it reaches down without limit. • 13. The (rainbow) which men call Iris is also by nature a cloud, of aspect purple and red and green. ^ 19. Let one but win a race through fleetness of foot, or be victorious in the pentathlon, there where lies the 2Diog. Laert. IX. 20. 10 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY sacred field of Zeus, in Olympia, hard by the river of Pisas; or let him be victorious in wrestling, or in a bloody- boxing match, or in the terrible contest called the pancration, — in the eyes of the citizens he will be re- splendent with glory; he will gain a conspicuous seat of honor in the public assemblies, there will be feasting for him at the public expense, and a gift from his city for a token. Yes, if he should win a chariot race, all these things would fall to his lot, though not so deserving as I am. For our wisdom is better than the strength of men or of horses. This is in truth a most heedless custom ; nor is it right thus to prefer strength to precious wisdom. What if there be among the people a good boxer, or one who excels in the pentathlon, or in wrestling, or in fleetness of foot, — which is more highly honored than strength in the contests at the games! The city is not on that account one whit better governed. Small profit does the city get out of it, when one is victorious in contests by the banks of the Pisas. That does not enrich the innermost parts of the state. 20. Having learned from the Lydians useless luxuries, what time they were free from hateful servitude, they used to come swaggering into the place of assembly by the thousand, wearing loose mantles all purple-dyed, glorying in their flowing comely hair, and reeking with the odor of curiously compounded perfumes. AN ILLUSTRATION OF XENOPHANES' SCIENTIFIC REASONING Xenophanes ^ thought that a mixture of land and sea came into being, and that in course of time this was resolved into its parts under the influence of the moist 'Hipp., Ref. I. 14 (R. P. 86 a; Dox. 565). THE ELEATIC SC'HOOL 11 element. And he adduces such proofs as these: Fossils are found in the midst of the land and on mountains; and in the quarries of Syracuse the imprints of a fish and of seals have been found; and at Paros the imprint of a sardine deep in stone; and at Malta traces of all sorts of things of the sea. And he says that these were made when, long ago, all things were mud, and the imprint was dried in the mud. And when the earth, having sunk in the sea, becomes mud once more, all men will disappear. Then a new creation will begin. And this change happens to all worlds. PARMENIDES [Flourished about 495 B.C.] THE FRAGMENTS OF PARMENIDES' POEM " ON NATURE " f /. Introduction Soon as the coursers that bear me and drew me as far as extendeth Impulse, guided me and threw me aloft in the glorious pathway. Up to the Goddess that guideth through all things man that is conscious. There was I carried along, for there did the coursers sagacious. Drawing the chariot, bear me, and virgins preceded to guide them — Daughters of Helios leaving behind them the mansions of darkness — t The translation of Parmenides' poem On Nature that is here given was made by Thomas Davidson, and published in Vol. IV of the Journal of Speculative Philosophy. 12 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Into the light, with their strong hands forcing asunder the night-shrouds, While in its socket the axle emitted the sound of a syrinx, Glowing, for still it was urged by a couple of wheels well- rounded, One upon this side, one upon that, when it hastened its motion. There were the gates of the paths of the Night and the paths of the Day-time. Under the gates is a threshold of stone and above is a lintel. These too are closed in the ether with great doors guarded by Justice — Justice the mighty avenger, that keepeth the keys of requital. Her did the virgins address, and with soft words deftly persuaded, Swiftly for them to withdraw from the gates the bolt and its fastener. Opening wide, they uncovered the yawning expanse of the portal. Backward rolling successive the hinges of brass in their sockets, — Hinges constructed with nails and with clasps; then on- ward the virgins Straightway guided their steeds and their chariot over the highway. Then did the goddess receive me with gladness, and taking my right hand Into her own, thus uttered a word and kindly bespake me: Youth that art mated with charioteers and companions immortal. THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 13 Coming to us on the coursers that bear thee, to visit our mansion, Hail! for it is not an evil Award that hath guided thee hither. Into this path — for, I ween, it is far from the pathway of mortals — Nay, it is Justice and Right. Thou needs must have knowledge of all things, First of the Truth's unwavering heart that is fraught with conviction. Then of the notions of mortals, where no true conviction abide th; But thou shalt surely be taught this too, that every opinion Needs must pass through the ALL, and vanquish the test with approval. //. On Truth Listen, and I will instruct thee — and thou, when thou hearest, shalt ponder — What are the sole two paths of research that are open to thinking. One path is: That Being doth be, and Non-Being is not: This is the way of Conviction, for Truth follows hard in her footsteps. Th' other path is : That Being is not, and Non-Being must be; This one, I tell thee in truth, is an all-incredible pathway. For thou never canst know what is not (for none can conceive it), Nor canst thou give it expression, for one thing are Thinking and Being. 14 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY . . . And to me 'tis indifferent Whence I begin, for thither again thou shalt find me returning. Speaking and thinking must needs be existent, for IS is of being. Nothing must needs not be; these things I enjoin thee to ponder. Foremost of all withdraw thy mind from this path of inquiry. Then likewise from that other, wherein men, empty of knowledge. Wander forever uncertain, while Doubt and Perplexity guide them — Guide in their bosoms the wandering mind; and onward they hurry. Deaf and dumb and blind and stupid, imreasoning cattle — Herds that are wont to think Bemg and Non-Being one and the self-same. Yet not one and the same; and that all things move in a circle. Never I ween shalt thou learn that Being can be of what is not; Wherefore do thou withdraw thy mmd from this path of inquiry. Neither let habit compel thee, while treading this path- way of knowledge, Still to employ a visionless eye or an ear full of ringing, Yea, or a clamorous tongue; but prove this vexed dem- onstration Uttered by me, by reason. And now there remains for discussion THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 15 One path only : That Being doth be — and on it there are tokens Many and many to show that what is is birthless and deathless, Whole and only-begotten, and moveless and ever- enduring : Never it was or shall be; but the ALL simultaneously now is, One continuous one; for of it what birth shalt thou search for? How and whence it hath sprung? I shall not permit thee to tell me, Neither to think: ' Of what is not,' for none can say or imagine How Not-Is becomes Is; or else what need should have stirred it. After or yet before its beginning, to issue from nothing? Thus either wholly Being must be or wholly must not be. Never from that which is will the force of Intelligence suffer Aught to become beyond itself. Thence neither pro- duction Neither destruction doth Justice permit, ne'er slacken- ing her fetters; But she forbids. And herein is contained the decision of these things; Either there is or is not; but Judgment declares, as it needs must. One of these paths to be uncomprehended and utterly nameless. No true pathway at all, but the other to be and be real. How can that which is now be hereafter, or how can it have been? 16 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY For if it hath been before, or shall be hereafter, it is not: Thus generation is quenched and decay surpasseth believing. Nor is there aught of distinct; for the All is self -similar alway. Nor is there anywhere more to debar it from being un- broken ; Nor is there an)rwhere less, for the All is sated with Being; Wherefore the All is imbroken, and Being approacheth to Being. Moveless, moreover, and bounded by great chains' limits it lieth. Void of beginning, without any ceasing, since birth and destruction Both have wandered afar, driven forth by the truth of conviction. Same in the same and abiding, and self through itself it reposes. Steadfast thus it endureth, for mighty Necessity holds it- Holds it within the chains of her bounds and round doth secure it. Wherefore that that which IS should be infinite is not permitted ; For it is lacking in naught, or else it were lacking in all things. Steadfastly yet in thy spirit regard things absent as present; Surely thou shalt not separate Being from clingmg to Bemg, THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 17 Nor shalt thou find it scattered at all through the All of the Cosmos, Nor yet gathered together. One and the same are thought and that whereby there is thinking; Never apart from existence, wherein it receiveth ex- pression, Shalt thou discover the action of thinking; for naught is or shall be Other besides or beyond the Existent; for Fate hath determined That to be lonely and moveless, which all things are but a name for — Things that men have set up for themselves, believing as real Birth and decay, becoming and ceasing, to be and to not-be. Movement from place to place, and change from color to color. But since the uttermost limit of Being is ended and perfect. Then it is like to the bulk of a sphere well-rounded on all sides. Everywhere distant alike from the centre; for never there can be Anything greater or anything less, on this side or that side; Yea, there is neither a non-existent to bar it from coming Into equality, neither can Being be different from Being, More of it here, less there, for the All is inviolate ever. Therefore, I ween, it lies equally stretched in its limits on all sides. 18 SOUROii. BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY And with this I will finish the faithful discourse and tlie thinking Touching the truth ; and now thou shalt learn the notions of mortals. Learn and list to the treach'rous array of the words I shall utter. ' III. On Opinion Men have set up for themselves twin shapes to be named by Opinion (One they cannot set up, and herein do they wander in error), And they have made them distinct in their nature, and marked them with tokens, Opposite each unto each — the one, flame's fire of the ether, Gentle, exceedingly thin, and everywhere one and the self-same. But not the same with the other; the other, self-similar likewise. Standing opposed, by itself: brute night, dense nature and heavy. All the apparent system of these will I open before thee, So that not any opinion of mortals shall ever elude thee. All things now being marked with the names of fight and of darkness. Yea, set apart by the various powers of the one or the other. Surely the AH is at once full of light and invisible darkness, Both being equal, and naught being common to one with the other. THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 19 For out of the formless fire are woven the narrower circlets, Those over these out of night; but a portion of flame shooteth through them. And in the centre of all is the Goddess that govemeth all things: She unto all is the author of loathsome birth and coition, Causing the female to mix with the male, and by mutual impulse Likewise the male with the female. Foremost of gods, she gave birth unto Love; yea, fore- most of all gods. Then thou shalt know the ethereal nature and each of its tokens — Each of the signs in the ether, and all the invisible workings Wrought by the blemishless sun's pure lamp, and whence they have risen. Then thou shalt hear of the orb-eyed moon's circumambi- ent workmgs, And of her nature, and likewise discern the heaven that surrounds them, T\Tience it arose, and how by her sway Necessity boimd it Firm, to encircle the bounds of the stars. . . . How the earth, and the sun, and the moon, and the ether Common to all, and the milk of the sky, and the peak of Ol3nTipus, Yea, and the fervent might of the stars, were impelled into being. 20 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Circling the earth, with its wanderings, a borrowed, a night-gleaming splendor. Wistfully watching forever, with gaze turned toward the sunlight. Even as in each one of men is a union of limbs many- jointed. So there is also in each one a mind; for one and the same are That which is wise and the nature generic of members in mortals. Yea, imto each and to all; for that which prevaileth is thinking. Here on the right hand the youths, and there on the left hand the maidens. Thus by the strength of opinion were these created and now are. Yea, and will perish hereafter, as soon as they grow imto ripeness; Men have imposed upon each one of these a name as a token. PLATO AND ARISTOTLE ON ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY And ^ our Eleatic tribe of philosophers, beginning with Xenophanes — yes and earlier, embodied this truth in a tale, that ''all things," so-called, are really one. * * Some ^ have put forth the opinion that the All is a single natural body (/xta? ova-rj^; (f>v(r€a)^) . But they have » Plato, Soph. 242 D. » Aristotle, Met. T. 5, 986 b 11. THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 21 not all expressed this opinion in the same way: they differ in excellence of statement, and also as to what that natural body is. The account of them lies quite outside our present inquiry into causes ; for they do not, like some of the physical philosophers, first assume that that which is (to op) is a single body, and then produce things from this single body as from a material cause. They speak in a different fashion. The former add motion, in explaining the origin of the universe; whereas these say that it (the first principle) is immov- able. Nevertheless, so much at least is germane to our present inquiry: Parmenides seems to have grasped the rjj^ity as formal cause (Kara rov \6yov), Melissus as I material cause [Kara t7)v vXtjv). Accordingly the former [\ holds it to be bounded, the latter to be boundless. Xenophanes, the first of these men to assert this unity, Parmenides being generally spoken of as his disciple, made nothing very clear, and does not seem to have reached either of the above views of nature ; but, gazing up into the broad heavens, he simply declared : The One is god. And so, as we said, these men we may pass over in our present inquiry, two of them without a further word, as being rather too crude, Xenophanes and Melis- sus; but Parmenides seems to speak at times with keener vision. / For, holding as he does that over and above being / there is no such thing as non-bemg, of necessity he holds \ that being is One, and that there is nothing else existent. |(This subject we have discussed more clearly in our work on nature.) Still, compelled to follow where the plain facts led, he supposes that whereas according to reason things are one, for sense-perception they are more 22 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY than one; and he falls back on the assumption that there are two causes and two principles, heat and cold, to wit, fire and earth; and of these the one, the hot, he classes with being, the other (the cold) with non-being. ZENO [Flourished about 465 B.C.] THE PUZZLES OF COMPOSITION AND DIVISION If ^ that which is, had no magnitude it could not even be. Everything that truly is must needs have magnitude and thickness, and one part of it must be separated from another by a certain interval. And the same may be said of the next smaller part; it too will have magnitude, and a next smaller part. As well say this once for all as keep repeating it forever. For there will be no such part that could serve as a limit. And there will never be one part save in reference to another part. Thus, if the many have being, they must be both large and small — so small as to have no size at all, and so large as to be infinite. * * That '' which has neither magnitude, thickness, nor bulk could not he at all. 'Tor," says Zeno, 'Vere it added to anythmg else that is it would not make it one whit larger, for it is impossible to increase the magnitude of anything by adding that which has no magnitude. And this itself would be enough to show that what was added was nothing. ... f If when it is taken away from « Simpl. 140, 34. (R. P. 105 C. Fr. 2 in Diels' arrangement.) 7 Simpl. 139, 9. (R. P. 105 a. Fr. 1 Dials.) t Assuming with Zeller and Burnet that there is a lacuna here. THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 23 another thing that other will be no less, and when it is added to another thing that other will be no larger, it is clear that what was added and what was taken away was nothing at all." * If 8 the absolute unit is indivisible it would be, ac- cording to Zeno's axiom, nothing at all. For that which neither makes anything larger by its addition, nor makes anything smaller by its subtraction, is not one of the things that are, since it is clear that what is must be a magnitude, and, if a magnitude, corporeal, for the corporeal has being in all dimensions. Other things, such as the surface and the line, when added in one way make things larger, when added in another way do not; but the point and the unit do not make things larger however added. * If 9 things are a many, there must of necessity be just so many as there actually are, neither more nor less. If, however, there are just so many as there actually are, then would they be finite in number. (On the other hand) If things are a many, then the things that are are infinite in number; for, between the things that are are always other things, and between them again still other things. And thus the things that are are infinite in number. SPACE NOT A REAL THING If 1^ space is, it will be in something; for everything that is is in something; and to be in something is to be in space. Space then will be in space, and so on ad infinitum. Therefore space does not exist. 8 Arist. Met. II. 4, 1001 b 7. " Simpl. 140, 27 (R. P. 105 b). loSimpl. 130-. 562, 3 D (R. P. 106). 24 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY THE PUZZLES OF MOTION (1.) You t cannot traverse an infinite number of points in a finite time. You must traverse the half of any given distance before you traverse the whole, and the half of that again before you can traverse it. This goes on ad infinitum, so that {if space is made up of points) there are an infinite number in any given space, and it cannot be traversed in a finite time. (2.) The second argument is the famous puzzle of Achilles and the tortoise. Achilles must first reach the place from which the tortoise started. By that time the tortoise will have got on a little way. Achilles must then traverse that, and still the tortoise will be ahead. He is always coming nearer, but he never makes up to it. (3.) The third argument against the possibility of motion through a space made up of points is that, on this hypothesis, an arrow in any given moment of its flight must be at rest in some particular point. ^^ "Burnet adds: "Aristotle observes quite rightly that this argu- ment depends upon the assumption that time is made up of ' nows/ that is, of indivisible instants. This no doubt, was the Pythagorean view." With the third argument as given above, compare the following saying of Zeno reported by Diogenes Laertius, IX, 72 : " That which moves can neither move in the place where it is, nor yet in the place where it is not." t Zeno's arguments have been preserved by Aristotle, Phys. VI. 9, 230 b. They are, however, given in a much condensed form, being referred to as matters of common information, and are introduced in order to give Aristotle an opportunity to criticise them. In place of giving this passage I have, therefore, repro- duced the arguments in the expanded form given them by Burnet, which is a free paraphrase of Aristotle's statements, with a few interpolations introduced for the benefit of the modern reader, far from the heat of the controversy, which are amply justified by Aristotle's discussions in the Physics. If any doubt should THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 25 (4.) Suppose three parallel rows of points in juxta- position: A B C Fig. 1 Fig. 2 A B . . . . C . . One of these (B) is immovable, while A and C move in opposite directions with equal velocity so as to come into the position represented in Fig. 2. The movement of C relatively to A will be double its movement relatively to B, or, in other words, any given point in C has passed twice as many points in A as it has in B. It cannot, therefore, be the case that an instant of time corresponds to the passage from one point to another. THE PURPOSE OF ZENO's ARGUMENTS AS REPORTED BY PLATO [In the Parmenides Zeno is represented as reading his work to Socrates and a few others. Before the conclu- sion of the reading Parmenides enters. After Zeno has finished reading a discussion ensues, part of which I quote. ^2 Socrates is speaking:] 'Tn all that you say, Zeno, have you any other purpose except to disprove the being of the many ? and is not each division of your treatise intended to furnish a separate proof of this, there being in all as many proofs of the not- being of the many as you have composed arguments? Is that your meaning, or have I misunderstood you?" be raised on this score it could only be with regard to the fourth argument, but it seems to me that Burnet and Tannery have made good their case here. See Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, pp. 331 ff. ; Tannery, Science Hellene, p. 257. " Parmenides, 127 D. Jowett's translation. 26 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY "No/' said Zeno; ''you have correctly understood my general purpose." "1 see, Parmenides," said Socrates, ''that Zeno would like to be not only one with you in friendship but your second seK in his writings too; he puts what you say in another way, and would fain make beheve that he is telling us something which is new. For you, in your poems, say. The All is one, and of this you adduce excel- lent proofs; and he on the other hand says. There is no many; and on behalf of this he offers overwhelming evidence. You affirm unity, he denies plurality. And so you deceive the world into believing that you are saying different things when really you are saying much the same. This is a strain of art beyond the reach of most of us." "Yes, Socrates," said Zeno. "But although you are as keen as a Spartan hound in pursuing the track, you do not fully apprehend the true motive of the composition, which is not really such an artificial work as you imagine ; for what you speak of was an accident; there was no pretence of a great purpose; nor any serious intention of deceiving the world. The truth is, that these arguments of mine were meant to protect the arguments of Par- menides against those who make fun of him and seek to show the many ridiculous and contradictory results which they suppose to follow from the affirmation of the one. My answer is addressed to the partisans of the many, whose attack I return with interest by retorting upon them that their hypothesis of the being of the many, if carried out, appears to be still more ridiculous than the hypothesis of the being of the one. Zeal for my master led me to write the book in the days of my youth, but some one stole the copy; and therefore I had THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 27 no choice whether it should be published or not; the motive, however, of writing, was not the ambition of an elder man, but the pugnacity of a young one. This you do not seem to see, Socrates; though in other respects, as I was saying, your notion is a very just one." HERACLITUS [Flourished about 505 B.C.] THE FRAGMENTS l.f This Word (Xo7oavTa<7lai, some are sensible, and some are not. Those they call sensible, which are derived by us from some one or more senses, and those they call not sensible, which emanate 272 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY directly from the thought, as, for instance, those which relate to incorporeal objects, or any others which are embraced by reason. Again, those which are sensible are produced by a real object, which imposes itself on the intelligence, and compels its acquiescence; and there are also some others, which are simply apparent, mere shadows, which resemble those which are produced by real objects. . . . They say that the proper criterion of truth is the im- pression that comes with convincing force (KaraXTjimfcrf avTacrla) ; that is to say, one which is derived from a real object, as Chrysippus asserts in the tweKth book of his Physics; and he is followed by Antipater and ApoUodorus. For Boethius leaves a great many criteria, such as intellect, sensation, appetite, and knowledge; but Chrysippus dissents from his view, and in the first book of his Treatise on Reason, says that sensation and pre- conception are the only criteria. And preconception is, according to him, a comprehensive physical notion of general principles. But others of the earlier Stoics admit right reason as one criterion of the truth. ETHICS — FOLLOWING NATURE They * say that the first inclination which an animal has is to protect itself, as nature brings herself to take an interest in it from the beginning, as Chrysippus affirms in the first book of his Treatise on Ends; where he says that the first and dearest object to every animal is its own existence, and its consciousness of that existence For that it is not natural for any animal to be aUenated from itself, or even to be brought into such a state as to be indifferent to itself, being neither alienated from nor • From Diogenes Laertius, Yonge's translation, p. 290. I . THE STOICS 273 itself. It remains, therefore, that we must assert that nature has bound the animal to itself by the greatest unanimity and affection; for by that means it repels all that is injurious, and attracts all that is akin to it and desirable. But as for what some people say, that the first inclination of animals is to pleasure, they say what is false. For the Stoics say that pleasure, if there be any such thing at all, is an accessory only, which nature, having sought it out by itseK, as well as those things which are adapted to its constitution, receives incidentally in the same manner as animals are pleased, and plants made to flourish. Moreover, say they, nature makes no difference be- tween animals and plants, when she regulates them so as to leave them without voluntary motion or sense; and some things too take place in ourselves in the same manner as in plants. But, as inclination in animals tends chiefly to the point of making them pursue what is appropriate to them, we may say that their inclina- tions are regulated by nature. And as reason is given to rational animals according to a more perfect principle, it follows, that to live correctly according to reason, is properly predicated of those who live according to na- ture. For nature is as it were the artist who produces the inclination. On which account Zeno was the first writer who, in his Treatise on the Nature of Man, said that the chief good was confessedly to live according to nature; which is to live according to virtue, for nature leads us to this point. And in like manner Clean thes speaks in his Treatise on Pleasure, and so do Posidonius and Hecaton in their essays on Ends and the Chief Good. And again, to live according to virtue is the same thing as living 274 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY according to one's experience of those things which happen by nature; as Chrysippus explains it in the first book of his Treatise on the Chief Good. For our in- -^ dividual natures are all parts of universal nature; on which account the chief good is to live in a manner cor- responding to nature, and that means corresponding to one's own nature and to universal nature; doing none of those things which the common law of mankind is in the habit of forbidding, and that common law is identical with that right reason which pervades everything, being the same with Jupiter, who is the regulator and chief manager of all existing things. Again, this very thing is the virtue of the happy man and the perfect happiness of life when everything is done according to a harmony with the genius of each individual with reference to the will of the universal governor and manager of all things. Diogenes, accordingly, says ex- pressly that the chief good is to act according to sound reason in our selection of things according to our nature. And Archidemus defines it to be living in the discharge of all becoming duties. Chrysippus again understands, that the nature, in a manner corresponding to which we ought to live, is both the common nature, and also human nature in particular; but Clean thes will not admit of any other nature than the common one alone, as that to which people ought to live in a manner corresponding; and repudiates all mention of a particular nature. And he asserts that virtue is a disposition of the mind always consistent and harmonious ; that one ought to seek it out for its own sake, without being influenced by fear or hope of any external influence. Moreover, that it is in it that . happiness consists, as producing in the soul the harmony '^'"^ of a life always consistent with itself, and that if a THE STOICS 275 rational animal goes the wrong way, it is because it allows itself to be misled by the deceitful appearances of exterior things, or perhaps by the instigation of those who surround it; for nature herself never gives us any but good inclinations. . . . And they lay down the position that all offences are equal, as Chrysippus argues in the fourth book of his Ethic Questions, and so say Persseus and Zeno. For if one thing that is true is not more true than another thing that is true, neither is one thing that is false more false than another thing that is false; so, too, one deceit is not greater than another, nor one sin than another. For the man who is a himdred furlongs from Canopus, and the man who is only one, are both equally not in Canopus; and so, too, he who commits a greater sin, and he who commits a less, are both equally not in the right path. . . . They say also that the wise man is free from perturba- tions because he has no strong propensities. But that this freedom from propensities also exists in the bad man, being, however, then quite another thing, inasmuch as it proceeds in him only from hardness and unimpressi- bility of his nature. They also pronounce the wise man free from vanity, since he regards with equal eye what is glorious and what is inglorious. At the same time, they admit that there is another character devoid of vanity, who, however, is only reckoned one of the rash men, being in fact the bad man. They also say that all the virtuous men are austere, because they do never speak with reference to pleasure, nor do they listen to what is said by others with reference to pleasure. At the same time, they call another man austere too, using the term in nearly the same sense as they do when they 276 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY speak of austere wine, which is used in compounding medicines, but not for drinking. ^ They also pronounce the wise to be honest-hearted men, anxiously attending to those matters which may make them better, by means of some principle which conceals what is bad, and brings to light what is good. Nor is there any hypocrisy about them; for they cut off all pretence in their voice and appearance. They also keep aloof from business ; for they guard carefully against doing anything contrary to their duty. They drink wine, but they do not get drunk; and they never yield to frenzy. Occasionally, extraordinary imaginations may obtain a momentary power over them, owing to some melancholy or trifling, arising not according to the principle of what is desirable, but contrary to nature. Nor, again, will the wise man feel grief; because grief is an irrational contraction of the soul, as Apollodorus de- fines it in his Ethics. . . . And they say that virtues reciprocally follow one another, and that he who has one has all; for that the precepts of them all are common. . . . Another doctrine of the Stoics is, that there is nothing intermediate between virtue and vice; while the Peri- patetics assert that there is a stage between virtue and vice, being an improvement on vice which has not yet arrived at virtue. For the Stoics say that as a stick must be either straight or crooked, so a man must be either just or unjust, and cannot be more just than just, or more unjust than unjust; and that the same rule applies to all cases. Moreover, Chrysippus is of opinion that virtue can be lost, but Cleanthes affirms that it cannot; the one saying that it can be lost by drunkenness or melancholy, the other maintaining that it cannot be THE STOICS 277 lost on account of the firm perceptions which it implants in men. They also pronounce it a proper object of choice; accordingly, we are ashamed of actions which we do improperly, while we are aware that what is honorable is the only good. Again, they affirm that it is of itself sufficient for happiness. . . . Again, they say that justice exists by nature, and not because of any definition or principle; just as law does, or right reason, as Chrysippus tells us in his Treatise on the Beautiful; and they think that one ought not to abandon philosophy on account of the different opinions prevailing among philosophers, since on this principle one would wholly quit life. THE HYMN OF CLEANTHES Most ^ glorious of immortals, thou of many names, all-powerful ever, hail ! On thee it is fit all men should call. For we come forth from thee, and have received the gift of imitative speech alone of all that live and move on earth. So will I make my song of thee and chant thy power forever. Thee all this ordered universe, circling around the earth, follows as thou dost guide and ever- more is ruled by thee. For such an engine hast thou in thine unswerving hands — the two-edged, blazing, ever- living bolt — that at its blow all nature trembles. Here- with thou guidest universal Reason — the moving prin- ciple of all the world, joined with the great and lesser lights — which, being born so great, is highest lord of all. Nothing occurs on earth apart from thee, Lord, nor at the airy sacred pole nor on the sea, save what the wicked work through lack of wisdom. But thou canst » I am indebted to Prof. G. H. Palmer for this translation of the Hymn of Cleanthes. 278 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY make the crooked straight, bring order from disorder, and what is worthless is in thy sight worthy. For thou hast so conjoined to one all good and ill that out of all goes forth a single everlasting Reason. This all the wicked seek to shun, unhappy men, who, ever longing to obtain a good, see not nor hear God's imiversal law; which, wisely heeded, would assure them noble life. They haste away, however, heedless of good, one here, one there; some showing unholy zeal in strife for honor, some turning recklessly toward gain, others to looseness and the body's pleasures. But thou, Zeus, giver of all, thou of the cloud, guide of the thunder, deliver men from baleful ignorance! Scatter it, father, from our souls, grant us to win that wisdom on which thou thyself re- lying suitably guidest all; that thus being honored, we may return to thee our honor, singing thy works un- ceasingly; because there is no higher office for a man — nor for a god — than ever rightly singing of imiversal law. PLUTARCH'S REFUTATION OF THE STOIC THEODICY^ In ^ the third book of his Treatise on The Gods Chrysip- pus writes as follows: ^'Just as states which have a sur- plus population send great numbers out to colonies, and stir up wars against their neighbors, so God provides occasions for our destruction." And he cites Euripides and other writers who maintained that the Trojan War 1 Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, §§ 32-37. t For the suggestion to include these interesting and illuminating passages from Plutarch I am indebted to Dr. B. A. G. Fuller, and the translation of them which is here given is his. THE STOICS 279 was brought about by the gods because of the super- abundancy of men. Now leave aside all the other absurdities — for it is not our business here to inquire whether the Stoics have spoken the truth, but only whether they have contradicted themselves — and consider this one point. They are always giving fine and humane names to God, yet they attribute to him savage and barbarous deeds, yea, deeds worthy of the Galatse. For the enormous destruction and wholesale slaughter of men such as was entailed by the Trojan War, or again by the Persian and the Peloponnesian Campaigns, bears no resemblance to colonization, unless the gods were intending to found some underground cities in Hades. Chrysippus rather makes God like one Deiotarus, chief of the Galatse. He had many children born to him, but wished to leave his power and all his property to one alone. So he killed all the rest off, just as one might cut back and prune the new shoots of a vine, in order that some one which was left might grow strong and big. A vine-dresser, it goes without saying, does this, while the twigs are still small and insignificant. And we are merciful to the dog and destroy the surplus puppies just after they are born and before their eyes are yet open. But Zeus not only allows men to grow up ; he even begets them himself and brings them up to manhood, and then, forsooth, carefully contrives occasions for their death and destruction and brutally sends them out of the world. I think he had better not have provided the causes and sources of our birth. This, however, is of minor importance compared to what follows. No war arises among men without vicious- ness behind it. Love of luxury stirs up the one, avarice 2S0 !^URCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY another, ambition a third, lust for power a fourth. Now if it be God who brings wars to pass, he is also the cause of our vices, provoking and perverting mankind as he does. Nevertheless Chrysippus says in his Treatise on Law Procedure, and again in the second book of his Treatise on The Gods, that ''it is not reasonable that the deity should be the cause of base deeds. For just as a law cannot be the cause of its contravention, so neither can the gods be the cause of impiety. It is then reasonable that they should not be the causes of anything base.'' But, I say, can anything be more base than that men should destroy one another? And for this destruction Chrysippus says that God is responsible. I will swear to it, however, that some one will say that he also praises the saying of Euripides : If gods do aught that's base, they are not gods, and Thou say'st an easy thing — to blame the gods, as if we were now doing anything but showing up his contradictory sayings and ideas. This very saying, however, which now meets with approval, 'Thou say'st an easy thing — to blame the gods" — can be urged against Chrysippus not once, or twice, or thrice, but innumerable times. For in the first book in the Treatise on Nature, in hkening the cause of motion to a mixture of things whirling and churning in all directions, he speaks thus, "Since the world- economy proceeds in this fashion, it is due to it that we are as we are at every moment, whether contrary to our proper nature we suffer disease or disability, or be grammarians or musicians." And again a little later he THE STOICS 281 says, ''By this reasoning the same holds true of our virtues and vices, and in general of our skill in the arts or lack of it, as I have said." And a hne or two later, without any ambiguity he remarks, ''No single or slightest thing can happen except in accordance with the common nature and its reason." That the common nature and the common reason of this nature are fate, and providence, and Zeus, is something of which not even the dwellers in the antipodes are unaware, for this truth is noised about by the Stoics everywhere, and Chrysippus remarks ''that Homer rightly said, 'The will of Zeus is done,' referring to that fate and that nature of the universe according to which all things are governed." How now, I ask, can God be the author of nothing base, and yet at the same time not the slightest thing happen otherwise than according to the common nature and its reason? For since evils belong in the sum of events they are, I presume, to be ascribed to God. Even Epicurus turns and twists and thinks up subtleties to free and release the will from the eternal motion of the world- mechanism, in order that vice may not be left blameless. Chrysippus, however, concedes to vice complete hcense, as something which is not only necessary and destined, but also in accordance with the divine reason, and produced agreeably to that nature which is supremely good. Look, for instance, at this statement of his: ''The common nature is spread throughout all things, and hence everything whatsoever which happens in the imiverse and every part thereof happens in accordance with it and its reason, and follows therefrom without any hindrance. For there is nothing outside the universe to oppose its workings, nor can any one of its parts be moved or conditioned otherwise than agreeably to the 282 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY common nature." What, now, are the conditions and motions of its parts? Evidently the conditions are vices and diseases, avarice, luxury, ambition, fear, injustice; and the motions are adultery, theft, treachery, murder, and parricide. None of these, then, great or small, is thought by Chrysippus to exist contrary to the reason, the law, the justice, the providence of Zeus, nor do law- less acts exist contrary to law, nor injustice to justice, nor evil-doing to providence. Chrysippus says, however, ^'that God punishes vice, and does much in the way of punishing wicked men.'' Likewise in the second book of the Treatise on The Gods he says that ' 'misfortunes happen sometimes to good men, not for punishment as with the wicked, but in accordance with some other line of administration, as in the case of cities." Again, his words run as follows: "In the first place evils are to be understood in pretty much the aforesaid way, and secondly as apportioned according to the reason of Zeus, either for punishment, or agreeably to some other scheme of administration to the advantage of the whole." It is, however, a horrible thing that vice should be both produced and punished agreeably to the reason of Zeus. And Chrysippus pushes the contradiction still further when he writes in the second book of the Treatise on Nature, that ''Vice / has a peculiar and reasonable fitness viewed in relation i to terrible calamities. It is produced in a way agreeably to the universal reason, and its production is not without benefit to the universe. For without it, there would be \ no good." And this is the man who reproves those who argue with equal force to the opposite conclusion; this man who, wishing in every case to get off some odd and subtle remark about the universe, maintains that cut- THE STOICS 283 pursing and flattery and foolishness are not without their uses, that the good for nothing are good for something, and the noxious and the miserable are not imbeneficial. Again what kind of a being is Zeus — I mean, of course, Chrysippus's Zeus — to punish what is neither responsi- ble for itself nor uselessly produced? For according to Chrysippus's w^ay of arguing, it is not vice that is to be blamed, but Zeus, either because he made vice to no use, or because, having made it to some use, he punishes it. Once more, in the first book of the Treatise on Justice, Chrysippus says that the gods resist some unjust deeds, yet that ''it is neither possible nor expedient to remove vice from the universe." If, however, it be inexpedient to do away with lawlessness, injustice, and foolishness, it is impossible for him to pursue his present argument. For he himself in doing all he can by philosophizing to do away with vice — which it is not expedient to do away with — is doing something repugnant both to reason and to God. Yet when he says as well that the gods resist some unrighteous deeds, he gives the impression that these sins are impious. In another place where he writes many times that nothing is blameworthy or contemptible in the universe, since everything takes place agreeably to the supremely good nature, there are yet passages where some neglect in small and mean matters is allowed not to be repre- hensible. Thus in the third book of the Treatise on Substance, in reminding us that noble and good men are the victims of such neglect, he asks ''whether some things may not be neglected, just as in great houses some grains of corn and wheat fall unnoticed, though the household as a whole is well managed? Or is this neglect due to the presence in such cases of evil spirits, in whom a 284 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY reprehensible carelessness is naturally inherent?" And he adds that there is a large admixture of necessity in things. Now I pass over the recklessness of Ukening to the unnoticed fall of grains of wheat such misfortunes of good and noble men as the condemnation of Socrates, and the burning alive of Pythagoras by the Cylonians, and the torture and death of Zeno at the hands of the tyrant Demylus, and of Antiphon by Dionysius. But is it not to blame God, to say that evil spirits were prov- identially appointed to such offices? For God in that case would be like a king who handed over his provinces to evil and stupid satraps and generals, and then over- looked their neglect and ill-treatment of his best sub- jects. Finally, if there be a large admixture of necessity in things, God is not all powerful and all things are not administered according to his word. * * But 2 what fault can any one find with what I have said if he keeps in mind the passage in the second book of the Treatise on Nature in which Chrysippus shows that evil is produced to some benefit to the universe? It is worth while to take this doctrine and compare it with those sayings of his in which you will find he accuses Xenocrates and Speusippus of not regarding health as indifferent, and wealth as useless, and in the same place defines vice, and discourses about it. ''Vice," he says, *'is distinguished from other calamities. For it happens agreeably to the rational constitution of nature, and, so to speak, does not happen without some benefit to the universe. For did it not exist there would be no good." There is then nothing good among the gods when there is nothing evil. ^Yhen Zeus shall have consumed ^ De Communihus Notitiis, §§ 13-16. THE STOICS 285 the whole of matter within himself, and shall have become one, having cast out all differences and distinctions, then there will be no good, since there is no evil. Still, one might object, a chorus can sing in harmony, though no one in it sing out of tune; and a body can be healthy even though no part of it be diseased. However, Chrysippus maintains that virtue cannot exist without vice, and that just as the venom of the serpent or the bile of the hyena is necessary to the efficacy of some medicines, so a suitable admixture of the wickedness of Meletus is necessary to the righteous- ness of Socrates, or of the vulgarity of Cleon to the no- bility of Pericles. How, too, could Zeus create Hercules and Lycurgus, unless he also created Sardanapalus and Phalaris for us? Chrysippus might as reasonably add, also, that tuberculosis promotes human health, and gout swiftness of foot; also that Achilles could not have had a fine head of hair unless Thersites had been bald. For what is the difference between such nonsense and drivel, and saying that w^antonness conduces to continence, or unrighteousness to righteousness? And how are we to pray the gods that Lies and oily words and wily ways may be ever evil in their sight, if virtue also vanishes and is destroyed when they are done away with? Would you really like to know, however, the most charming bit of his smoothness and persuav'ion? ''Just as comedians," he says, ''put in ridiculous lines which are poor stuff in themselves but lend a certain charm to the whole piece, so what you censure as evil, taken by itself, is not without its use in relation to other things." Now, in the first place, that vice has been produced by 286 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY divine providence, as a poor line is intentionally writ- ten by the playwright, is the most absurd of opinions. Supposing it were so, how should the gods be any more the g;ivers of good than of evil? How could vice be inimical to the gods, and hateful in their sight? What could we reply to such blasphemy as When God will injure mortals he creates the reason why and Who forced them to fight in the battles of gods? In the second place the poor line adorns the comedy and contributes to its purpose of arousing laughter and pleasing the audience. But surely father Zeus, the most high, the all-just, the all-good creator, as Pindar calls him, did not make this world as a big and varied and clever play, but as a commonwealth of gods and men wherein they might live together as comrades amid righteousness and virtue in concord and blessedness. And to this most beautiful and holy end, I say, what need was there of robbers and murderers, parricides and lyrants ? For in the eyes of God vice is not a charming and clever by-play, nor is unrighteousness inflicted for the sake of coarse joking and laughter and jest, upon human hfe — a life such that it wdll not permit one even to dream of the Stoics' renowned ' 'harmony. '^ Again the poor line is but a trivial part of the play and in all respects occupies but a small place in the comedy. There are not many such lines, and they do not destroy or spoil the charm of such passages as seem well-written. But all things are full of vice, and our whole life from the cradle to the grave is shameful and disgraceful and troublous, and as there is no part of it THE STOICS 287 pure and blameless, as they themselves say, is the basest and saddest of all plays. So it is that I would gladly learn from Chrysippus of what use vice is in the universe. It is of no use to heavenly and divine things, he says. For it would be absurd if for the lack among men of vice and avarice and lying, and for the want of our ravaging one another's lands and slandering and murdering one another, the sun could not accomplish his appointed course, nor the world enjoy its seasons and its cycles, nor the earth keep its central position in the universe and provide the sources of the winds and rains. It is left then for vice to benefit us and our affairs; and this perhaps is what these Stoics mean. But are we healthier for being vicious, or better off as regards the necessities of life? Does vice benefit our beauty or our strength ? They deny it. Yet where is virtue to be found on earth? 'It is," they say, "a, name, an appearance in the night to benighted'' sophists. Vice, however, is exposed to every waking eye, and plain as day to all men. If, however, we cannot 'have a share in anything good for anything, and least of all in virtue, for heaven's sake what is the good of being born? And is it not a terrible thing that though what is of use to the farmer or the pilot or the driver leads and contributes to its proper end, yet that which is created by God for virtue destroys and corrupts virtue? * * * Moreover,^ the Stoic sage doesn't and never will exist anjrwhere in this world. But there are innumerable men as wretched as they can be living in this state and principality of Zeus with its perfect government. What now is more contrary to common sense than that, with • De Communihus Notitiis, § 33, 4-34. 288 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Zeus directing all things for the best, we should be doing all things for the worst? It is a blasphemous thing to say, but if Zeus does not care to be considered as savior and merciful and a guardian against evils, but as rather the opposite of all these noble names, certainly nothing could be added to the evils that now exist either in num- ber or magnitude. For, as the Stoics maintain, all men live in the depths of folly and wickedness, and there can be no addition to their viciousness nor increase to their misery. This, however, is not the worst of the case. Wo read that rather where they find fault with Menander for say- ing in one of his acted plays. No greater source of evils among men is there than too great good . . . This they say is contrary to common-sense. Yet they make God who is good the origin of evil. "Matter," they say, ''cannot produce evil of itself, since it is without 'quahty and gets all the different properties which it is capable of receiving from that which moves and gives it form." The indwelling reason, however, moves and gives it form, and it cannot move or give form to itself. Hence necessarily evil, if it have no cause, comes from not-being, but if it comes through the moving principle, gets its existence from God. For if the Stoics think that Zeus is not the master of his own members, and does not employ each agreeably to his reason, they go contrary to common-sense, and they are inventing an animal whose many members do not obey its will, but employ their several activities and ways of action, with- out any stimulus from the whole organism and without deriving their power of movement from it. What animal, THE STOICS 289 however, is so badly put together that against its will its feet advance, its tongue makes noises, its horns butt, or its teeth bite? God must do most of these things, though, if, contrary to his will, the wicked men who are parts of him lie and misbehave and thieve, and kill one another. And if, as Chrysippus says, ''Not the smallest part exists otherwise than as Zeus wills," and every living thing naturally behaves and moves as Zeus guides and directs and behaves and disposes, then More ruinous than the last, this speech. For it is ten thousand times more decent that the mem- bers of Zeus, deranged by his weakness and impotence, should do many absurd things contrary to his nature and will, than that there should be no wantonness and no wickedness of which he was not the cause. Yet for all that ''the world is a city, the stars its citizens," and, if you like, its tribesmen and rulers — the sun for instance a counsellor, and the evening star the president of a prytany or a magistrate. If this be the case I do not think that they who deny the doctrines we have been discussing, show themselves to be any more absurd than those who maintain and advocate them. XVIII EPICURUS [341-270 B.C.] THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE FiEST 1 of all, then, one must determine with exact- ness the notion comprehended under each separate Word, in order to be able to refer to it, as to a certain criterion, the conceptions which emanate from ourselves, the ulterior researches and the difficulties ; otherwise the judgment has no foundation. One goes on from demon- stration to demonstration ad infinitum; or else one gains nothing beyond mere words. In fact, it is absolutely necessary that in every word we should perceive directly, and without the assistance of any demonstration, the fundamental notion which it expresses, if we wish to have any foundation to which we may refer our researches, our difficulties, and our personal judgments, whatever in other respects may be the criterion which we adopt, whether we take as our standard the impressions pro- duced on our senses, or the actual impression in general; or whether we cling to the idea by itself, or to any other criterion. We must also note carefully the impressions which we receive in the presence of objects, in order to bring our- selves back to that point in the circumstances in which 1 From Diogenes Laertius, Yonge's translation, pp. 437 ff. This and the following division are taken from EdIcutus's letter to Herodotus. 290 EPICURUS 291 it is necessary to suspend the judgment; or even when the question is about things, the evidence of which is not immediately perceived. When these foundations are once laid we may pass to the study of those things, the evidence of which is not immediate. . . . One must not forget that the production of images is simultaneous with the thought; for from the surface of the bodies images of this kind are continually flowing • off in an insensible manner indeed, because they are im- mediately replaced. They preserve for a long time the same disposition, and the same arrangement that the atoms do in the solid body, although, notwithstanding, their form may be sometimes altered. The direct production of images in space is equally instantaneous, because these images are only light substances destitute of depth. But there are other manners in which natures of this kind are produced; for there is nothing in all this which at all contradicts the senses, if one only considers in what way the senses are exercised, and if one is inclined to explain the relation which is established between external objects and ourselves. Also, one must admit \ that something passes from external objects into us m\^ which does not distress a man when it is present, should afflict him when only expected. Therefore, the most formidable of all evils, death, is nothing to us, since, when we exist, death is not present to us; and 298 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY when death is present, then we have no existence. It is no concern then either of the Uving or of the dead; since to the one it has no existence, and the other class has no existence itself. But people in general at times flee from death as the greatest of evils, and at times wish for it as a rest from the evils in life. Nor is the not living a thing feared, since living is not connected with it; nor does the wise man think not living an evil; but, just as he chooses food, not preferring that which is most abundant, but that which is nicest; so, too, he enjoys time, not measuring it as to whether it is of the greatest length, but as to whether it is most agreeable. And he who enjoins a young man to live well, and an old man to die well, is a simpleton, not only because of the con- stantly delightful nature of life, but also because the care to live well is identical with the care to die well. And he was still more wrong who said : 'Tis well to taste of life, and then when born To pass with quickness to the shades below. For if this really was his opinion why did he not quit life? for it was easily in his power to do so, if it really was his belief. But if he was joking, then he was talking foolishly in a case where it ought not to be allowed; and we must recollect that the future is not our own, nor, on the other hand, is it wholly not our own, I mean so that we can never altogether await it with a feeling of certainty that it will be, nor altogether despair of it as what will never be. And we must consider that some of the passions are natural, and some empty; and of the natural ones some are necessary, and some merely natural. And of the necessary ones some are necessary to happiness, others are necessary that the body may be EPICURUS 299 exempt from trouble, and others, again, merely in order that life itself may be; for a correct theory, with regard to these things, can refer all choice and avoidance to the health of the body and the imperturbability of the soul, since this is the end of living happily. For it is for the sake of this that we do everything, wishing to avoid grief and fear; and when once this is the case, with respect to us, then the storm of the soul is, as I may say, put an end to; since the animal is unable to go as if to something deficient, and to seek something different from that by which the good of the soul and body will be perfected. For then we have need of pleasure when we grieve, because pleasure is not present; but when we do not grieve, then we have no need of pleasure; and on this account, we affirm that pleasure is the beginning and end of living happily; for we have recognized this as the first good, being connate with us; and it is with reference to it that we begin every choice and avoidance; and to this we come as if we judged of all good by passion as the standard; and, since this is the first good and connate with us, on this account we do not choose every pleasure, but at times we pass over many pleasures when any difficulty is likely to ensue from them; and we think many pains better than pleasures, when a greater pleasure follows them, if we endure the pain for a time. Every pleasure is therefore a good on account of its own nature, but it does not follow that every pleasure is worthy of being chosen; just as every pain is an evil, and yet every pain must not be avoided; but it is right to estimate all these things by the measurement and view of what is suitable and unsuitable; for at times we may feel the good as an evil, and at times, on the con- 300 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY trary, we may feel the evil as good. And we think contentment a great good, not in order that we may never have but a little, but in order that, if we have not much, we may make use of a little, being genuinely per- suaded that those men enjoy luxury most completely who are the best able to do without it; and that every- thing which is natural is easily provided, and what is useless is not easily procured. And simple flavors give as much pleasure as costly fare, when everything that can give pain, and every feeling of want, is removed; and corn and water give the most extreme pleasure when any one in need eats them. To accustom one's self, therefore, to simple and inexpensive habits is a great ingredient in the perfecting of health, and makes a man free from hesitation with respect to the necessary uses of life. And when we, on certain occasions, fall in with more sumptuous fare, it makes us in a better disposi- tion toward it, and renders us fearless with respect to fortune. '\\Tien, therefore, we say that pleasure is a chief good, we are not speaking of the pleasures of the debauched man, or those which lie in sensual enjoyment, as some think who are ignorant, and who do not enter- tain our opinions, or else interpret them perversely; but we mean the freedom of the body from pain, and of the soul from confusion. For it is not continued drinkings and revels, or the enjoyment of female society, or feasts of fish and other such things as a costly table supplies, that make life pleasant, but sober contemplation, which examines into the reasons for all choice and avoidance, and which puts to flight the vain opinions from which the greater part of the confusion arises which troubles the soul. Now, the beginning and the greatest good of all these I EPICURUS 301 things is prudence, on which account prudence is some- thing more valuable than even philosophy, inasmuch as all the other virtues spring from it, teaching us that it is not possible to live pleasantly unless one also lives prudently, and honorably, and justly; and that one can- not live prudently, and honorably, and justly, without living pleasantly; for the virtues are connate with living agreeably, and living agreeably is inseparable from the virtues. Since, who can you think better than that man who has holy opinions respecting the gods, and who is utterly fearless with respect to death, and who has properly contemplated the end of nature, and who comprehends that the chief good is easily perfected and easily provided; and the greatest evil lasts but a short period, and causes but brief pain? And w^ho has no belief in necessity, which is set up by some as the mistress of all things, but he refers some things to fortune, some to ourselves, because necessity is an irresponsible power, and because he sees that fortune is unstable, while our own will is free ; and this freedom constitutes, in our case, a responsibility which makes us encounter blame and praise. Since it would be better to follow the fables about the gods than to be a slave to the fate of the natural philosopher; for the fables which are told give us a sketch, as if we could avert the wrath of God by paying him honor; but the other presents us with necessity which is inexorable. And he, not thinking fortune a goddess, as the general- ity esteem her (for nothing is done at random by a god), nor a cause which no man can rely on; for he thinks that good or evil is not given by her to men so as to make them live happily, but that the principles of great goods or great evils are supplied by her; thinking it better to 302 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY be unfortunate in accordance with reason, than to be fortunate irrationally; for that those actions which are judged to be the best, are rightly done in consequence of reason. Do you then study these precepts, and those which are akin to them, by all means day and night, pondering on them by yourself, and discussing them with any one like yourself, and then you will never be disturbed by either sleeping or waking fancies, but you will live like a god among men; for a man living amid immortal gods is in no respect like a mortal being. SOME MAXIMS OF EPICURUS No ^ pleasure is intrinsically bad ; but the efficient causes of some pleasures bring with them a great many perturbations of pleasure. If every pleasure were condensed, if one may so say, and if each lasted long, and affected the whole body, or the essential parts of it, then there would be no difference between one pleasure and another. Irresistible power and great wealth may, up to a cer- tain point, give us security as far as men are con- cerned; but the security of men in general depends upon the tranquillity of their souls, and their freedom from ambition. The riches of nature are defined and easily procurable; but vain desires are insatiable. The wise man is but little favored by fortune; but his reason procures him the greatest and most valuable 3 From Diogenes Laertius, Yonge's translation, p. 474. EPICURUS 303 goods, and these he does enjoy, and will enjoy the whole of his life. He who is acquainted with the limits of life knows that that which removes the pain which arises from want, and which makes the whole of life perfect, is easily pro- curable; so that he has no need of those things which can only be attained with trouble. Of all the things which wisdom provides for the happiness of the whole life, by far the most important is the acquisition of friendship. He who desires to live tranquilly without having any- thing to fear from other men, ought to make himself friends ; those whom he cannot make friends of, he should, at least, avoid rendering enemies; and if that is not in his power, he should, as far as possible, avoid all inter- course with them and keep them aloof, as far as it is for his interest to do so. The happiest men are they who have arrived at the point of having nothing to fear from those who surround them. Such men can hve with one another most agree- ably, having the firmest grounds of confidence in one another, enjoying the advantages of friendship in all their fulness, and not lamenting, as a pitiable circum- stance, the premature death of their friends. Natural justice is a covenant of what is suitable, leading men to avoid injuring one another, and being injured. Justice has no independent existence; it results from mutual contracts, and establishes itself wherever there ^ 304 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY is a mutual engagement to guard against doing or sustaining mutual injury. In a general point of view, justice is the same thing to every one; for there is something advantageous in mu- tual society. Nevertheless, the difference of place, and divers other circumstances, make justice vary. From the moment that a thing declared just by the law is generally recognized as useful for the mutual relations of men, it becomes really just, whether it is imiversally regarded as such or not. But if, on the contrary, a thing established by law is not really useful for the social relations, then it is not just. The just man is the freest of all men from disquietude; but the unjust man is a perpetual prey to it. XIX LUCRETIUS [96-55 B.C.] THE WAGES OF PHILOSOPHY For 1 1 will essay to discourse to you of the most high system of heaven and the gods and will open up the first- beginnings of things, out of which nature gives birth to all things and increase and nourishment, and into which nature hkewise dissolves them back after their destruc- tion. These we are accustomed in explaining their reason to call matter and begetting bodies of things and to name seeds of things and also to term first bodies, because from them as first elements all things are. It 2 is sweet, when on the great sea the winds trouble its waters, to behold from land another's deep distress; not that it is a pleasure and delight that any should be afflicted, but because it is sweet to see from what evils you are yourself exempt. It is sweet also to look upon the mighty struggles of war arrayed along the plains without sharing yourself in the danger. But nothing is more welcome than to hold the lofty and serene positions well fortified by the learning of the wise, from which you may look down upon others and see them wandering all 1 The extracts from Lucretius are given in Munro's translation, and the page references are to the translation. P. 2. : 2 lb., p. 28. 305 306 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY abroad and going astray in their search for the path of life, see the contest among them of intellect, the rivalry of birth, the striving night and day with surpassing effort to struggle up to the summit of power and to be masters of the world. miserable minds of men! blinded breasts ! in what darkness of life and in how great dangers is passed this term of life whatever its duration! not choose to see that nature craves for herseK no more than this, that pain hold aloof from the body, and that she in mind enjoy a feeling of pleasure exempt from care and fear! Therefore we see that for the body's nature few things are needed at all, such and such only as take away pain. ;,, For 3 even as children are flurried and dread all things in the thick darkness, thus we in the daylight fear at times things not a whit more to be dreaded than those which children shudder at in the dark and fancy sure to be. This terror therefore and darkness of mind must be dispelled not by the rays of the sun and ghttering shafts of day, but by the aspect and law of nature. Now mark and I will explain by what motion the begetting bodies of matter do beget different things and after they are begotten again break them up, and by what force they are compelled so to do and what velocity is given to them for travelling through the great void: do you mind to give heed to my words. For verily matter does not cohere inseparably ^massed together, since we see that everything wanes and" perceive that all things ebb as it were by length of time and that age with- draws them from our sight, though yet the sum is seen to remain imimpaired by reason that the bodies which 3 Munro's translation, pp. 29-30. LUCRETIUS 307 quit each thing, lessen the things from which they go, gift with increase those to which they have come, compel the former to grow old, the latter to come to their prime, and yet abide not with these. Thus the sum of things is ever renewed and mortals live by a reciprocal dependency. Some nations wax, others wane, and in a brief space the races of living things are changed and like runners hand over the lamp of life. * * But * some in opposition to this, ignorant of matter, believe that nature cannot without the providence of the gods in such nice conformity to the ways of men vary the seasons of the year and bring forth crops, ay and all the other things, which divine pleasure the guide of life prompts men to approach, escorting them in person and enticing them by her fondlings to continue their races through the arts of Venus, that mankind may not come to an end. Now when they suppose that the gods designed all things for the sake of men, they seem to me in all respects to have strayed most widely from true reason. For even if I did not know what first-beginnings are, yet this, judging by the very arrangements of heaven I would venture to affirm, and led by many other cir- cumstances to maintain, that the nature of the world has <^ by no means been made for us by divine power : so great Ure the defects with which it stands encumbered. THE COURSE OF THE ATOMS This ^ point too herein we wish you to apprehend : when bodies are borne downward sheer through void by their own weights, at quite uncertain times and uncertain spots they push themselves a little from their course; * Munro's translation, p. 32. 5 lb., pp. 33-4. 308 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY you just and only just can call it a change of inclination. If they were not used to swerve, they would all fall down, like drops of rain, through the deep void, and no clashing would have been begotten nor blow produced among the first-beginnings : thus nature never would have produced aught. But if haply any one believes that heavier bodies, as they are carried more quickly sheer through space, can fall from above on the lighter and so beget blows able to produce begetting motions, he goes most widely astray from true reason. For whenever bodies fall through water and thin air, they must quicken their descents in proportion to their weights, because the body of water and subtle nature of air cannot retard everything in equal degree, but more readily give way, overpowered by the heavier : on the other hand empty void cannot offer resist- ance to anything in any direction at any time, but must, as its nature craves, continually give way; and for this reason all things must be moved and borne along with equal velocity though of unequal weights through the unresisting void. Therefore heavier things will never be able to fall from above on lighter nor of themselves to beget blows sufficient to produce the varied motions by which nature carries on things. Wherefore again and again I say bodies must swerve a httle; and yet not more than the least possible; lest we be found to be imagining oblique motions and this the reahty should refute. For this we see to be plain and evi- dent, that weights, so far as in them is, cannot travel obhquely, when they fall from above, at least so far as you can perceive; but that nothing swerves in any case from the straight course, who is there that can perceive ? LUCRETIUS 309 THE UNCONCERNED GODS For ^ the nature of gods must ever in itseK of necessity enjoy immortality together with supreme repose, far re- moved and withdrawn from our concerns; since exempt from every pain, exempt from all dangers, strong in its own resources, not wanting aught of us, it is neither gained by favors nor moved by anger. *** If '' you well apprehend and keep in mind these things, nature free at once and rid of her haughty lords is seen to do all things spontaneously of herself without the meddling of the gods. For I appeal to the holy breasts of the gods who in tranquil peace pass a calm time and an unruffled existence. Who can rule the sun, who hold in his hand with controlling force the strong reins of the immeasurable deep? Who can at once make all the differ- ent heavens to roll and warm with ethereal fires all the fruitful earths, or be present in all places at all times, to bring darkness with clouds and shake with noise the heaven's serene expanse, to hurl lightnings and often throw down his own temples, and withdrawing into the deserts there to spend his rage in practising his bolt which often passes the guilty by and strikes dead the innocent and unoffending? THE NATURE OF MIND AND SOUL And s now since I have shown what-hke the beginnings of all things are and how diverse with varied shapes as they fly spontaneously driven on in everlasting motion, and how all things can be severally produced out of these, next after these questions the nature of the mind and «Muiiro's translation, p. 43. «Ib., p. 54. 8lb., p. 58. 310 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY soul should methinks be cleared up by my verses and that dread of Acheron be driven headlong forth, troubling as it does the life of man from its inmost depths and overspreading all things with the blackness of death, allowing no pleasure to be pure and unalloyed. * * Now 9 I assert that the mind and the soul are kept together in close union and make up a single nature, but that the directing principle which we call mind and understanding, is the head so to speak and reigns para- mount in the whole body. It has a fixed seat in the middle region of the breast: here throb fear and ap- prehension, about these spots dwell soothing joys; therefore here is the understanding or mind. All the rest of the soul disseminated through the whole body obeys and moves at the will and inclination of the mind. It by itself alone knows for itself, rejoices for itself, at times when the impression does not move either soul or body together with it. And as when some part of us, the head or the eye, suffers from an attack of pain, we do not feel the anguish at the same time over the whole body, thus the mind sometimes suffers pain by itself or is inspirited with joy, when all the rest of the soul throughout the limbs and frame is stirred by no novel sensation. But when the mind is excited by some more vehement apprehension, we see the whole soul feel in unison through all the limbs, sweats and paleness spread over the whole body, the tongue falter, the voice die away, a mist cover the eyes, the ears ring, the hmbs sink under one; in short we often see men drop down from terror of mind; so that anybody may easily perceive from this that the soul is closely united with the mind, sMunro's translation, pp. 60-2. LUCRETIUS 311 and when it has been smitten by the influence of the mind, forthwith pushes and strikes the body. This same principle teaches that the nature of the mind and soul is bodily; for when it is seen to push the limbs, rouse the body from sleep, and alter the counte- nance and guide and turn about the w^hole man, and when we see that none of these effects can take place without touch nor touch without body, must we not admit that the mind and the soul are of a bodily nature? Again you perceive that our mind in our body suffers together with the body and feels in unison with it. When a weapon with a shudder-causing force has been driven in and has laid bare bones and sinews within the body, if it does not take life, yet there ensues a faintness and a lazy sinking to the ground and on the ground the turmoil of mind which arises, and sometimes a kind of undecided inclination to get up. Therefore the nature of the mind must be bodily, since it suffers from bodily weapons and blow^s. I will now go on to explain in my verses of what kind of body the mind consists and out of what it is formed. First of all I say that it is extremely fine and formed of exceedingly minute bodies. That this is so you may, if you please to attend, clearly perceive from what follows: nothing that is seen takes place with a velocity equal to that of the mind when it starts some suggestion and actually sets it agoing; the mind therefore is stirred with greater rapidity than any of the things whose nature stands out visible to sight. But that which is so passing nimble must consist of seeds ex- ceedingly round and exceedingly minute, in order to be stirred and set in motion by a small moving power. Thus water is moved and heaves by ever so small a force, /^ 312 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY formed as it is of small particles apt to roll. But on the other hand the nature of honey is more sticky, its liquid more sluggish and its movement more dilatory; for the whole mass of matter coheres more closely, because sure enough it is made of bodies not so smooth, fine, and round. A breeze however gentle and light can force, as you may see, a high heap of poppy seed to be blown away from the top downward; but on the other hand Eurus itself cannot move a heap of stones. Therefore bodies possess a power of moving in proportion to their smallness and smoothness; and on the other hand the greater weight and roughness bodies prove to have, the more stable they are. Since then the nature of the mind has been found to be eminently easy to move, it must consist of bodies exceedingly small, smooth, and round. The knowledge of which fact, my good friend, will on many accounts prove useful and be serviceable to you. The following fact too Hkewise demonstrates how fine the texture is of which its nature is composed, and how small the room is in which it can be contained, could it only be collected into one mass: soon as the untroubled sleep of death has gotten hold of a man and the nature of the mind and soul has withdrawn, you can perceive then no diminution of the entire body either in appearance or weight: death makes all good save the vital sense and heat. Therefore the whole soul must consist of very small seeds and be inwoven through the veins and flesh and sinews; inasmuch as, after it has all withdrawn from the whole body, the exterior contour of the limbs preserves itself entire and not a tittle of the weight is lost. Just in the same way when the flavor of wine is gone or when the delicious aroma of a perfume has been dispersed into the air or when the savor has LUCRETIUS 313 left some body, yet the thing itseK does not therefore look smaller to the eye, nor does aught seem to have been taken from the weight, because sure enough many minute seeds make up the savors and the odor in the whole body of the several things. Therefore, again and again I say, you are to know that the nature of the mind and the soul has been formed of exceedingly minute seeds, since at its departure it takes away none of the weight. DISPELLING THE DREAD OF DEATH Death ^^ therefore to us is nothing, concerns us not a jot, since the nature of the mind is proved to be mortal; and as in time gone by we felt no distress, when the Poeni from all sides came together to do battle, and all things shaken by war's troublous uproar shuddered and quaked beneath high heaven, and mortal men were in doubt which of the two peoples it should be to whose empire all must fall by sea and land aUke, thus when we shall be no more, w^hen there shall have been a separa- tion of body and soul, out of both of which we are each formed into a single being, to us, you may be sure, who then shall be no more, nothing whatever can happen to excite sensation, not if earth shall be mingled with sea and sea with heaven. And even supposing the nature of the mind and power of the soul do feel, after they have been severed from our body, yet that is nothing to us who by the binding tie of marriage between body and soul are formed each into one single being. And if time should gather up our matter after our death and put it once more into the position in which it now is, and the light of life be given to us again, this result even would " Miinro's translation, pp. 77-8. 314 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY concern us not at all, when the chain of our self-con- sciousness has once been snapped asunder. So now we give ourselves no concern about any self which we have been before, nor do we feel any distress on the score of that self. For when you look back on the whole past course of immeasurable time and think how manifold are the shapes which the motions of matter take, you may easily credit this too, that these very same seeds of which we now are formed, have often before been placed in the same order in which they now are; and yet we cannot recover this in memory : a break in our existence has been interposed, and all the motions have wandered to and fro far astray from the sensations they produced. For he whom evil is to befall, must in his own person exist at the very time it comes, if the misery and suffering are haply to have any place at all; but since death pre- cludes this, and forbids him to be, upon whom the ills can be brought, you may be sure that we have nothing to fear after death, and that he who exists not, cannot become miserable, and that it matters not a whit whether he has been born into life at any other time, when im- mortal death has taken away his mortal life. Therefore when you see a man bemoaning his hard case, that after death he shall either rot with his body laid in the grave or be devoured by flames or the jaws of wild beasts, you may be sure that his ring betrays a flaw and that there lurks in his heart a secret goad, though he himself declare that he does not believe that any sense will remain to him after death. He does not, methinks, really grant the conclusion which he professes to grant nor the principle on which he so professes, nor does he take and force himself root and branch out of life, but all unconsciously imagines something of self to survive. LUCRETIUS 315 For when any one in life suggests to himself that birds and beasts will rend his body after death, he makes moan for himself, he does not separate himself from that self, nor withdraw himself fully from the body so thrown out, and fancies himself that other self and stands by and impregnates it with his own sense. Hence he makes much moan that he has been born mortal, and sees not that after real death there will be no other self to remain in life and lament to self that his own self has met death, and there to stand and grieve that his own self there lying is mangled or burnt. For if it is an evil after death to be pulled about by the devouring jaw^s of wild beasts, I cannot see why it should not be a cruel pain to be laid on fires and burn in hot flames, or to be placed in honey and stifled, or to stiffen with cold, stretched on the smooth surface of an icy slab of stone, or to be pressed down and crushed by a load of earth above. Then ^^ there is Democritus who, when a ripe old age had warned him that the memory-waking motions of his mind were waning, by his own spontaneous act offered up his head to death. Even Epicurus passed away, when his light of life had run its course, he who surpassed in intellect the race of man and quenched the light of all, as the ethereal sun arisen quenches the stars. Wilt thou then hesitate and think it a hardship to die ? Thou for whom life is well-nigh dead whilst yet thou livest and seest the light, who spendest the greater part of thy time in sleep and snorest wide awake and ceasest not to see visions and hast a mind troubled with groundless terror and canst not discover often what it is that ails thee, when besotted man thou art sore pressed on all • " Munro's translation, p. 82. 316 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY sides with full many cares and goest astray tumbling about in the wayward wanderings of thy mind. NO DESIGNER OF NATURE But 12 in what ways yon concourse of matter founded earth and heaven and the deeps of the sea, the courses of the sun and moon, I will next in order describe. For verily not by design did the first-beginnings of things station themselves each in its right place by keen intel- ligence, nor did they bargain sooth to say what motions each should assume, but because the first-beginnings of things, many in number in many ways impelled by blows for infinite ages back and kept in motion by their own w^eights, have been wont to be carried along and to unite in all manner of ways and thoroughly to test every kind of production possible by their mutual combinations, therefore it is that, spread abroad through great time after trying imions and motions of every kind, they at length meet together in those masses which suddenly brought together become often the rudiments of great things, of earth, sea, and heaven and the race of living thmgs. ^*^ No 13 act is it of piety to be often seen with veiled head to turn to a stone and approach every altar and fall prostrate on the ground and spread out the palms before the statues of the gods and sprinkle the altars with much blood of beasts and link vow on to vow, but rather to be able to look on all things with a mind at peace. 12 Munro's translation, p. 126- "Ib., p. 145. XX EPICTETUS [Flourished about 90 a.d.] THINGS WHICH ARE IN OUR POWER Seek ^ at once, therefore, to be able to say to every unpleasing semblance, ^'You are but a semblance and by no means the real thing.'' And then examine it by those rules which you have; and first and chiefly, by this: whether it concerns the things which are within our own power, or those which are not; and if it concerns anything beyond our power, be prepared to say that it is nothing to you. He Men 2 are disturbed not by things, but by the views which they take of things. Thus death is nothing terri- ble, else it would have appeared so to Socrates. But the terror consists in our notion of death, that it is terrible. When, therefore, we are hindered, or disturbed, or grieved let us never impute it to others, but to ourselves; that is, to our own views. It is the action of an uninstructed person to reproach others for his own misfortimes; of one entering upon instruction, to reproach himself; and of one perfectly instructed, to reproach neither others nor himself. » Ench. I. Higginson, II. 216. The selections from Epictetus are given in T. W. Higginson's translation. I quote from the two- volume edition, published in 1890. 2 lb., V. Higginson II. 218. 317 318 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Demand ^ not that events should happen as you wish; but wish them to happen as they do happen, and you will go on well. * Be ^ assured that the essence of piety toward the gods lies in this, to form right opinions concerning them, as existing; and as governing the universe justly and well. And fix yourself in this resolution, to obey them, and yield to them, and willingly follow them amidst all events, as being ruled by the most perfect wisdom. For thus you will never find fault with the gods, nor accuse them of neglecting you. And it is not possible for this to be effected in any other way than by withdrawing yourself from things which are not within our own power, and by making good or evil to consist only in those which are. * As ^ it was fit, then, this most excellent and superior faculty alone, a right use of the appearances of things, the gods have placed in our own power; but all other matters they have not placed in our power. What, was it be- cause they would not ? I rather think that, if they could, they had granted us these too; but they certainly could not. For, placed upon earth, and confined to such a body and to such companions, how was it possible that, in these respects, we should not be hindered by things outside of us? But what says Zeus? '^0 Epictetus, if it had been possible, I had made this little body and property of thine free, and not liable to hindrance. But now do not mis- take; it is not thy own, but only a finer mixture of clayc 3 Ench. VIII. Higginson, II. 219. *Ib., XXXI. Higginson, II. 229. BTb., XXXI. Disc. I. 1. Higginson, I. p. 4. EPICTETUS 319 Since, then, I could not give thee this, I have given thee a certain portion of myself; this faculty of exerting the powers of pursuit and avoidance, of desire and aversion, and, in a word, the use of the appearances of things. Taking care of this point, and making what is thy own to consist in this, thou wilt never be restrained, never be hindered; thou wilt not groan, wilt not complain, wilt not flatter any one. How, then? Do all these ad- vantages seem small to thee? Heaven forbid! Let them suffice thee, then, and thank the gods." But now, when it is in our power to take care of one thing, and to apply ourselves to one, we choose rather to take care of many and to encumber ourselves with many — body, property, brother, friend, child, and slave — and, by this multiplicity of encumbrances, we are burdened and weighed down. Thus, when the weather does not happen to be fair for sailing, we sit in distress and gaze out perpetually, ^liich way is the wind? North. What good will that do us? When will the west blow? Wlien it pleases, friend, or when^olus pleases; for Zeus has not made you dispenser of the winds, but ^Eolus. What, then, is to be done? To make the best of what is in our power, and take the rest as it occurs. And how does it occur? As it pleases God. * * Do 6 you therefore likewise, being sensible of this, consider the faculties you have, and after taking a view of them say, ''Bring on me now, Zeus, what difficulty thou wilt, for I have faculties granted me by thee, and powers by which I may win honor from every event "? « Ench. XXXI. Disc. I. 6. Higginson, I. 26. ^ 320 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY THE ESSENCE OF GOOD God ^ is beneficial. Good is also beneficial. It should seem, then, that where the essence of God is, there too is the essence of good. What then is the essence of God — flesh? By no means. An estate? Fame? By no means. Intelligence? Knowledge? Right reason? Certainly. Here, then, without more ado, seek the essence of good. For do you seek that quality in a plant ? No. Or in a brute? No. If, then, you seek it only in a rational subject, why do you seek it anywhere but in what distinguishes that from things irrational? Plants make no voluntary use of things, and therefore you do not apply the term good to them. Good, then, im- plies such use. And nothing else? If so, you may say that good and happiness and unhappiness belong to mere animals. But this you do not say, and you are right; for, how much soever they have the use of things, they have not the intelligent use, and with good reason, for they are made to be subservient to others, and not of primary importance. Why was an ass made? Was it as being of primary importance? No; but because we had need of a back able to carry burdens. We had need too that he should be capable of locomotion; therefore he had the voluntary use of things added, otherwise he could not have moved. But here his endowments end; for, if an understanding of that use had been likewise added, he would not, in reason, have been subject to us, nor have done us these services, but would have been like and equal to ourselves. Why will you not, therefore, seek the essence of good in that without which you cannot say that there is good in anything? » Ench. XXXI. Disc. II. 8. Higginson, I. 132-4. EPICTETUS 321 What then? Are not all these hkewise the works of the gods? They are; but not primary existences, nor parts of the gods. But you are a primary existence. You are a distinct portion of the essence of God, and' contain a certain part of him in yourself. Why then are you ignorant of your noble birth? Why do not you consider whence you came ? Why do not you remember, when you are eating, who you are who eat, and whom you feed? When you are in the company of women, when you are conversing, when you are exercising, when you are disputing, do not you know that it is the Divine you feed, the Divine you exercise? You carry a God about with you, poor wretch, and know nothing of it. Do you suppose I mean some god without you of gold or silver ? It is within yourself that you carry him ; and you do not observe that you profane him by impure thoughts and unclean actions. If the mere external image of God were present, you would not dare to act as you do; and when God himself is within you, and hears and sees all, are not you ashamed to think and act thus — insensible of your own nature, and at enmity with God ? * * * Does s any one fear things that seem evils indeed, but which it is in his own power to prevent ? No, surely. If, then, the things independent of our will are neither good nor evil, and all things that do depend on will are in our own power, and can neither be taken away from us nor given to us unless we please, what room is there left for anxiety? But we are anxious about this paltry body or estate of ours, or about what Caesar thinks, and not at all about anything internal. Are we ever anxious » Ench. XXXI. Disc, 11. 13. Higginson, I. 153-4. 322 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY not to take up a false opinion? No; for this is within our own powder. Or not to follow any pursuit contrary to nature? No, nor this. When, therefore, you see any one pale with anxiety, just as the physician pronounces from the complexion that such a patient is disordered in the spleen, and another in the liver, so do you likewise say, this man is disordered in his desires and aversions; he cannot walk steadily; he is in a fever. For nothing else changes the complexion, or causes trembling, or sets the teeth chattering. AS SOCRATES WOULD HAVE DONE When ^ you are going to confer with any one, and especially wuth one w^ho seems your superior, represent to yourself how Socrates or Zeno would behave in such a case, and you will not be at a loss to meet properly what- ever may occur. . . . When you do anything from a clear judgment that it ought to be done, never shrink from being seen to do it, even though the world should misunderstand it; for if you are not acting rightly, shun the action itseK; if you are, why fear those who wrongly censure you ? * * Everything 1° has two handles: one by which it may be borne, another by which it cannot. If your brother acts unjustly, do not lay hold on the affair by the handle of his injustice, for by that it cannot be borne; but rather by the opposite, that he is your brother, that he was brought up with you; and thus you will lay hold on it as it is to be borne. » Ench. XXXIII. and XXXV. Higginson, II. 234-5. 10 lb., XLIII. Higginson, II. 238. EPICTETUS 323 Never ^^ proclaim yourself a philosopher; nor make much talk among the ignorant about your principles, but show them by actions. Thus, at an entertainment do not discourse how people ought to eat; but eat as you ought. For remember that thus Socrates also universally avoided all ostentation. And when persons came to him, and desired to be introduced by him to philosophers, he took them and introduced them; so well did he bear being overlooked. So if ever there should be among the ignorant any discussion of principles, be for the most part silent. For there is great danger in hastily throwing out what is undigested. And if any one tells you that you know nothing, and you are not nettled at it, then you may be sure that you have really entered on your work. For sheep do not hastily throw up the grass, to show the shepherds how much they have eaten; but, inwardly digesting their food, they produce it outwardly in wool and milk. Thus, therefore, do you not make an exhi- bition before the ignorant of your principles; but of the actions to which their digestion gives rise. * * Whatever ^^ rules you have adopted, abide by them as laws, and as if you would be impious to transgress them; and do not regard what any one says of you, for this, after all, is no concern of yours. . . . Let whatever appears to be the best, be to you an inviolable law. And if any instance of pain or pleasure, glory or disgrace, be set before you, remember that now is the combat, now the Olympiad comes on, nor can it be put off; and that by one failure and defeat honor may be lost — or won. Thus Socrates became perfect, improving himself " Ench. XL VI. Higginson, II. 239. "lb., L. Higginson, II. 241. 324 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY by everything, following reason alone. And though you are not yet a Socrates, you ought, however, to live as one seeking to be a Socrates. IN HARMONY WITH GOD AND HIS UNIVERSE All 13 things serve and obey the [laws of the] universe : the earth, the sea, the sun, the stars, and the plants and animals of the earth. Our body likewise obeys the same, in being sick and well, young and old, and passing through the other changes decreed. It is therefore reasonable that what depends on ourselves, that is, our own understanding, should not be the only rebel. For the universe is powerful and superior, and consults the best for us by governing us in conjunction with the whole. And further, opposition, besides that it is un- reasonable, and produces nothing except a vain struggle, throws us into pain and sorrows. Bring ^^ whatever you please, and I will turn it into good. Bring sickness, death, want, reproach, trial for life. All these, by the rod of Hermes, shall turn to ad- vantage. ''What will you make of death ?'' Why, what but an ornament to you ; what but a means of your show- ing, by action, what that man is who knows and follow^s the will of Nature? ''"What will you make of sickness?" I will show its nature. I will make a good figure in it; I will be composed and happy; I will not beseech my physician, nor yet will I pray to die. What need you ask further? Whatever you give me, I will make it happy, fortunate, respectable, and eligible. No, but, "take care not to be sick — it is an evil.'' " Fr. CXXXI. Higginson, II. 276. " Disc. III. 20. Hiffginson, II. 59. EPICTETUS 325 Just as if one should say, 'Take care that the semblance of three being four does not present itself to you. It is an evil." How an evil, man? If I think as I ought about it, what hurt will it any longer do me ? Will it not rather be even an advantage to me ? If then I think as I ought of poverty, of sickness, of political disorder, is not that enough for me ? Why then must I any longer seek good or evil in externals ? * * For 1^ all other pleasures substitute the consciousness that you are obeying God, and performing not in word, but in deed, the duty of a wise and good man. How great a thing is it to be able to say to yourself: ''What others are now solemnly arguing in the schools, and can state in paradoxes, this I put in practice. Those quali- ties which are there discoursed, disputed, celebrated, I have made mine own. Zeus hath been pleased to let me recognize this within myself, and himself to discern whether he hath in me one fit for a soldier and a citizen, and to employ me as a witness to other men, concerning things uncontrollable by will. See that your fears were vain, your appetites vain. Seek not good from without; seek it within yourselves, or you will never find it. For this reason he now brings me hither, now sends me thither; sets me before mankind, poor, powerless, sick; banishes me to Gyaros; leads me to prison; not that he hates me — Heaven forbid! for who hates the most faithful of his servants? — nor that he neglects me, for he neglects not one of the smallest things; but to exercise me, and make use of me as a witness to others. Appointed to such a service, do I still care where I am, or with whom, or what is said of me — instead of being wholly attentive to God and to his orders and commands?" » Disc. III. 24. Higginson. II. 107. XXI MARCUS AURELIUS [120-180 A.D.] FOLLOW NATURE Do 1 thou therefore I say absolutely and freely make choice of that which is best, and stick unto it. Now, that they say is best which is most profitable. If they mean profitable to man as he is a rational man, stand thou to it and maintain it; but if they mean profitable as he is a creature only, reject it; and from this thy tenet and conclusion keep off carefully all plausible shows and colors of external appearance, that thou mayst be able to discern things rightly. * * The end ^ and object of a rational constitution is, to do nothing rashly, to be kindly affected toward men, and in all things willingly to submit unto the gods. Casting therefore all other things aside, keep thyself to these few, and remember withal that no man properly can be said to live more than that which is now present, which is but a moment of time. Whatsoever is besides either is already past, or is uncertain. The time there- fore that any man doth live is but a little, and the place where he liveth is but a very little corner of the earth, and * Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, III. 7. The extracts from Marcus Aurelius are, save for a few unimportant changes, given in the translation made by Casaubon early in the 17th century. 2 lb.. III. 10. 326 MARCUS AURELIUS 327 the greatest fame that can remain of a man after his death, even that is but httle, and that too, such as it is whilst it is, is by the succession of silly mortal men pre- served, who likewise shall shortly die, and even while they live know not what in very deed they themselves are: and much less can know one who long before is dead and gone. ^ Whatsoever ^ is expedient unto thee, World, is expedient unto me. Nothing can either be unseasonable unto me, or out of date, which unto thee is seasonable. Whatsoever thy seasons bear shall ever by me be es- teemed as happy fruit and increase. Nature! from thee are all things, in thee all things subsist, and to thee all tend. Could he say of Athens, Thou lovely City of Cecrops ; and shalt not thou say of the World, Thou lovely City of God? . ^*^ He ^ that seeth the things that are now hath seen all that either was ever or ever shall be, for all things are of one kind and all like one unto another. Meditate often upon the connection of all things in the world, and upon the mutual relation that they have one unto another. For all things are after a sort folded and involved one within another, and by these means all agree well to- gether. For one thing is consequent unto another by local motion, by natural conspiration and agreement, and by substantial union or the reduction of all sub- stances into One. Fit and accommodate thyself to that estate and to those occurrences which by the destinies have been annexed unto thee ; and love those men whom thy fate 3 Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, IV. 19. «Ib., VI. 34-5. 328 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY it is to live with; but love them truly. An instrument, a tool, an utensil, whatsoever it be, if it be fit for the purpose it was made for it is as it should be, though he perchance that made and fitted it be out of sight and gone. But in things natural, that power which hath framed and fitted them is and abideth within them still. For which reason she ought also the more to be respected, and we are the more obliged (if we may live and pass our time according to her purpose and intention) to think that all is well with us and according to our own minds. After this manner also ... He that is all in all doth enjoy his happiness. * We ^ all work to one effect, some willingly and with a rational apprehension of what we do, others without any such knowledge. ^ * * If 6 so be that the gods have deliberated in particular of those things that should happen unto me, I must stand to their deliberation, as discreet and wise. For that a god should be an imprudent god is a thing hard even to conceive. And why should they resolve to do me hurt? For what profit either unto them or the universe (which they specially take care for) could arise from it ? But if so be that they have not deliberated of me in particular, certainly they have of the whole in general, and those things which in consequence and coherence of this general deliberation happen unto me in particular I am bound to embrace and accept of. But if so be that . . . they have not indeed, either in general or particular, deliberated of any of those things that happen unto us in this world, yet God be thanked » Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, VI. 37. •lb., VI. 39. MARCUS AURELIUS 329 that of those things that concern myself it is lawful for me to deliberate myself, and all my deliberation is but concerning that which may be to me most profitable. Now that unto every one is most profitable which is according to his own constitution and nature. And my nature is to be rational in all my actions and, as a good and natural member of a city and commonwealth, toward my fellow-members ever to be sociably and kindly disposed and affected. My city and country as I am Antoninus is Rome; as a man, the whole world. Those things therefore that are expedient and profitable to those cities are the only things that are good and expedient for me. * Either '^ with Epicurus we must fondly imagine the atoms to be the cause of all things, or we must needs grant a nature. Let this then be thy first ground, that thou art part of that universe which is governed by nature. Then, secondly, that to those parts that are of the same kind and nature as thou art thou hast relation of kindred. For of these if I shall always be mindful, first, as I am a part, I shall never be displeased with anything that falls to my particular share of the common chances of the world. For nothing that i^ behooveful unto the whole can be truly hurtful to that which is a part of it. For this being the common privilege of all natures, that they contain nothing in themselves that is hurtful unto them, it cannot be that the nature of the universe (whose privilege beyond other particular natures is that she cannot against her will by any higher external cause be constrained) should beget anything and cherish it in her bosom that should 7 Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, X. 6. 330 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY tend to her own hurt and prejudice. As then I bear in mind that I am a part of such an universe I shall not be displeased with anything that happens. And as I have relation of kindred to those parts that are of the same kind and nature that I am, so I shall be careful to do nothing that is prejudicial to the community, but in all my deliberations shall they that are of my kind ever be ; and the common good shall be that which all my intentions and resolutions shall drive unto, just as that which is contrary unto it I shall by all means endeavor to prevent and avoid. These things once so fixed and concluded, as thou wouldest think him an happy citizen whose constant study and practice were for the good and benefit of his fellow-citizens, and the carriage of the city such toward him that he were well pleased with it — so must it needs be with thee that thou shalt live a happy life. ^*^ Ever s consider and think upon the world as being but ^ one Uving substance and having but one soul; and how all things in the world are terminated into one sensitive power, and are done by one general motion, as it were, and by the deliberation of that one soul; and how all things that are concur in the cause of one another's being, and by what manner of connection and con- catenation all things happen. What art thou, that better and divine part excepted, but as Epictetus well said, a wretched soul appointed to carry a carcass up and down? To suffer change can be no hurt; as no benefit it is by change to attain to being. The age and time of the world is as it were a flood and swift current, consisting « Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, IV. 33-4. MARCUS AURELIUS 331 of the things that are brought to pass in the world. For as soon as anything hath appeared and is passed away another succeeds, and that also will pass presently out of sight. * They ^ will say commonly, Meddle not with many things if thou wilt live cheerfully. Certainly there is nothing better than for a man to confine himself to necessary actions; to such and so many only as reason in a creature that knows itseK born for society will command and enjoin. This will not only procure that cheerfulness, w^hich from the goodness, but that also which from the paucity of actions doth usually proceed. For since it is so, that most of those things which we either speak or do are unnecessary, if a man shall cut them off, it must needs follow that he shall thereby gain much leisure and save much trouble; and therefore at every action a man must privately by way of admonition suggest unto himself, What? may not this that now I go about be of the number of unnecessary actions? Neither must he accustom himself to cut off actions only, but also thoughts and imaginations that are unnecessary ; for so will unnecessary consequent actions the better be prevented and cut off. THE HARMONY OF THE UNIVERSE All 1° parts of the world (all things I mean that are contained within the whole world) must of necessity at some time or other come to corruption. Alteration I should say, to speak truly and properly; but that I may be the better understood I am content at this time to use that more common word. Now, say I, if so be that this " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, IV. 20. »o lb., X. 7. 332 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY be both hurtful unto them and yet unavoidable, would not, thinkest thou, the whole itself be in a sweet case, all the parts of it being subject to alteration — yea and by their making the whole itself fitted for corruption as consisting of things different and contrary? And did nature then either of herself thus project and purpose the affliction and misery of' her parts, and therefore of pur- pose so made them, not only that haply they might, but of necessity that they should fall into evil; or did not she know what she did when she made them? For to say either of these things is equally absurd. But to let pass nature in general, and to reason of things particular according to their own particular natures, how absurd and ridiculous is it, first to say that all parts of the whole are by their proper natural constitution subject to alteration, and then when any such thing doth happen as when one doth fall sick and dieth, to take on and wonder as though some strange thing had happened? Though this besides might move us not to take on so grievously when any such thing doth happen, that whatsoever is dissolved is dissolved into those things whereof it was compounded. For every dissolution is either a mere dispersion of the elements into those elements again whereof everything did consist, or a change of that which is more solid into earth, and of that which is pure and subtile or spiritual into air. So that by this means nothing is lost, but all is resumed again into those rational generative seeds of the universe, and this universe is either after a certain period of time to be consumed by fire or by continual changes to be renewed, and so forever to endure. Now, that solid and spiritual that we speak of, thou must not conceive it to be that very same which at first was when thou wert MARCUS AURELIUS 333 born. For alas! all this that now thou art in either kind, either for matter of substance or of life, hath but two or three days ago, partly from meats eaten and partly from air breathed in, received all its influx, being the same then in no other respect than a running river, maintained by the perpetual influx and new supply of waters, is the same. That therefore which thou hast since received, not that which came from thy mother, is that which comes to change and corruption. But sup- pose that that for the general substance and more solid part of it should still cleave unto thee never so close, yet what is that to the proper qualities and affections of it by which persons are distinguished, which certainly are quite different? * Whatsoever ^^ doth happen in the world is, in the course of nature, as usual and ordinary as a rose in the spring and fruit in summer. Of the same nature is sickness and death, slander and lying in wait, and whatsoever else ordinarily doth unto fools use to be occasion either of joy or sorrow. That, whatsoever it is that comes after, doth always very naturally, and as it were familiarly, follow upon that which was before. For thou must consider the things of the w^orld not as a loose independent number consisting merely of neces- sary events, but as a discreet connection of things orderly and harmoniously disposed. There is then to be seen in the things of the world, not a bare succession, but an admirable correspondence and affinity. *** As^^ we say commonly, the physician hath prescribed unto this man riding; unto another, cold baths; unto a " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, IV. 36. 12 lb., V. 8. 334 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY third, to go barefoot : so it is alike to say, The nature of the universe hath prescribed unto this man sickness or blindness or some loss or damage or some such thing. For as there, when we say of a physician that he hath prescribed anything, our meaning is that he hath ap- pointed this for that, as subordinate and conducing to health; so here, whatsoever doth happen unto any is ordained unto him as a thing subordinate unto the fates, and therefore do we say of such things that they do avfjL^alvecv, that is, happen, or fall together; as of square stones, when either in walls or pyramids in a certain position they fit one another, and agree as it were in an harmony, the masons say that they do avfi^alveiv] as if thou shouldst say, fall together. So that in general though the things be divers that make it, yet the consent or harmony itself is but one. And as the whole world is made up of all the particular bodies of the world, one perfect and complete body of the same nature as par- ticular bodies : so is the destiny of particular causes and events one general one, of the same nature that particular causes are. What I now say even they that are mere idiots are not ignorant of, for they say commonly rovro €(f)6pev avTQ), that is. This his Destiny hath brought upon him. This therefore is by the Fates properly and par- ticularly brought upon this, as that unto this in par- ticular is by the physician prescribed. These therefore let us accept of in like manner as we do those that are prescribed unto us by our physicians. For them also in themselves shall we find to contain many harsh things, but we nevertheless, in hope of health and recovery, accept of them. Let the fulfilling and accomplishment of those things which the common nature hath de- termined be unto thee as thy health. Accept them, MARCUS AURELIUS 335 an(^ be pleased with whatsoever doth happen though otherwise harsh and unpleasing, as tending to that end, to the health and welfare of the universe, and to Jove's happiness and prosperity. For this, whatsoever it be, would not have been produced had it not conduced to the good of the imi verse. For neither doth any ordinary particular nature bring anything to pass that is not agreeable and subordinate to whatsoever is within the sphere of its own proper administration and government. For these two considerations then thou must be well ^ pleased with anything that doth happen unto thee. First, because for thee properly it was brought to pass and unto thee it was prescribed, and from the very beginning, by the series and connection of the first causes, it hath ever had a reference unto thee. And secondly, because the good success and perfect welfare, and indeed the very continuance of Him that is the Administrator of the whole, doth in a manner depend on it. For the whole (because whole, therefore entire and perfect) is maimed and mutilated if thou shalt cut off anything at all whereby the coherence and contiguity (as of parts, so) of causes is maintained and preserved. Of which certain it is that thou dost (as much as lieth in thee) cut off, and in some sort violently take some- what away, as often as thou art displeased with any- thing that happeneth. * Thou ^^ must comfort thyself in the expectation of thy natural dissolution and in the meantime not grieve at the delay, but rest contented in these two things : First, that*^ nothing shall happen unto thee which is not according to the nature of the universe. Secondly, that it is in^- " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, V. 10. -^ 336 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY thy power to refrain from doing anything contrary to thine own proper god and inward spirit. For it is not in any man's power to constrain thee to transgress against him. man's insignificance and his grandeur What 1^ a small portion of vast and infinite eternity it is that is allowed unto every one of us, and how soon it vanisheth into the general age of the world. Of the common substance and of the common soul also, what a small portion is allotted unto us, and in what a little clod of the whole earth it is that thou dost crawl. After thou shalt rightly have considered these things with thyself fancy not anything else in the world any more to be of any weight and moment, but this: to do that only which thine own nature doth require, and to con- form thyself to that which the common nature doth afford. What is the present estate of my understanding? For herein lieth all indeed. As for all other things they are without the compass of mine own will, and if without the compass of my will then are they as dead things unto me and as it were mere smoke. To stir up a man to the contempt of death this among other things is of good power and efficacy, that even they who esteemed pleasure to be happiness and pain misery did nevertheless many of them contemn death as much as any. And can death be terrible to him to whom that only seems good which in the ordinary course of nature is seasonable? to him to whom, whether his actions be many or few, so they be all good, is all one; and who, whether he behold the things of the world being always the same, either for many years or for few years only, is " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, XII. 25. MARCUS AURELIUS 337 altogether indifferent ? man ! as a citizen thou hast lived and conversed in this great City the World. Whether just for so many years or no, what is it unto thee ? Thou hast lived (thou mayst be sure) as long as the laws and orders of the city required; which may be the common comfort of all. Why then should it be grievous unto thee if [not a tyrant nor an unjust judge, but] the same nature that brought thee into the world doth now send thee out of it ? It is as if the praetor should fairly dismiss him from the stage whom he had taken in to act a while. Oh, but the play is not yet at an end, there are but three acts yet acted of it ? Thou hast well said, for in matter of life three acts is the whole play. Now to set a certain time to every man's acting belongs unto him only who as first he was the cause of thy composition so now is he the cause of thy dissolution. As for thyself, thou hast to do with neither. Go thy ways then well pleased and contented, for so is He that dismisseth thee. * * To ^^ live happily is an inward power of the soul when she is affected with indifference toward those things that are by their nature indifferent. To be thus affected she must consider all worldly objects, both divided and whole, remembering withal that no object can of itself beget any opinion in us, neither can come to us, but stands without, still and quiet; but that we ourselves beget, and as it were print in ourselves, opinions con- cerning them. Now it is in our power not to print them; and if they creep in and lurk in some corner, it is in our power to wipe them off. Remembering, more- over, that this care and circumspection of thine is to continue but for a while, and then thy life will be at an " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, XI. 15. 338 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY end. And what should hinder but that thou mayst do well with all these things? For if they be according to nature, rejoice in them and let them be pleasing and acceptable unto thee. But if they be against nature, seek thou that which is according to thine own nature, and whether it be for thy credit or no, use all possible speed for the attainment of it; for no man ought to be blamed for seeking his own good and happiness. * Cast ^^ aw^ay from thee opinion and thou art safe. And what is it that hinders thee from casting it away? When thou art grieved at anything hast thou forgotten that all things happen according to the nature of the universe, and that him only it concerns who is in fault, and moreover that what is now done is that which from ever hath been done in the world and will ever be done, and is now done everywhere ? Hast thou forgotten how closely all men are allied one to another by a kindred, not of blood nor of seed, but of the same mind? Thou hast also forgotten that every man's mind partakes of the Deity and issueth from thence, and that no man can properly call anything his own, no, not his son, nor his body, nor his life, for they all proceed from that One who is the giver of all things: that all things are but opinion ; that no man lives properly but that very instant of time which is now present, and therefore that no man, whensoever he dieth, can properly be said to lose any more than an instant of time. * * How 1^ easy a thing it is for a man to put off from him all turbulent adventitious imaginations, and pres- ently to be in perfect rest and tranquillity! " Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, XII. 19. " lb., V. 2. MARCUS AURELIUS 339 Think thyself fit and worthy to speak or to do any-, thing that is according to nature, and let not the re- proach or report of some that may ensue upon it ever deter thee. If it be right and honest to be spoken or done, undervalue not thyseK so much as to be discouraged from it. As for them, they have their own rational overruling part and their own proper inclination, which thou must not stand and look about to take notice of, but go on straight whither both thine own particular and the common nature do lead thee; and the way of both these is but one. XXII PLOTINUS t [205-270 A.D.] THE SOUL Ake 1 we ail immortal? Or do we utterly perish? Or, a third alternative, does part of us pass way into dissolution and destruction while part — the real self- is everlasting? These are questions which we might naturally investigate and learn to answer, after the following fashion. Man, we might say, is not something simple, but has within him a soul. He has also a body attached to him, it may be as an instrument, it may be in some other capacity. Let us then distinguish the soul from the body and have a look at the nature and character of them both. Evidently a body which is composite cannot in reason be lasting. Moreover our senses perceive its dissolution and disintegration and liability to corruption of every sort, the reversion of its ingredients each to its proper nature, the destruction of one part by another, and their change and corruption into things other than iPlotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, §1, 456 (C. p. 843; V. II. p. 120). The chapters referred to are those of the Creuzer text. Where it seemed advisable to do so page references to this text — abbre- viated as C. — are added, and parallel references to the Volkmann text in the Teubner series — abbreviated as V. t Dr. B. A. G. Fuller has made the selection and the translation f the i>as8ages from Plotinus. 340 PLOTINUS 341 they were. This is particularly noticeable whenever the soul, which puts them in accord, is not present in a mass of matter. Then, too, though each thing in the process of generation becomes an individual, it is not an unit, since it can be resolved into form and matter. Hence even the simple bodies are compound. Again it is a fact that since whatever is corporeal has magnitude and can be divided and broken up into bits, it must for this reason also be subject to corruption. It follows that if the body be a part of us, the whole of us is not immortal. And if it be an instrument, it must be given to us for a certain time as such. But the dominant part and the essential man himself would bear the same relation to the body as form to matter, or as a man to the instrument he uses. In either case, however, the soul is the man's real self. * * What 2 now is the nature of the soul ? If the soul be corporeal, it can be wholly disintegrated, seeing that everything corporeal is, as we have said, composite. If it be not corporeal, but of another nature, we must investigate this, too, either after the old or after some other fashion. In the first place [if the soul be corporeal] we must inquire into what this body which they call the soul can be resolved. For since life is necessarily at hand in the soul, this body — which the soul is — must, if it consist of two or more bodies, have life innate in both or each, or one only, or none of these bodies. If life belongs to one of them this body would be the soul. But what kind of body would that be which was naturally animate? For fire, and water, and air, and earth are naturally inanimate, and whenever any one of 2 Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, § 2. 342 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY them has soul present in it it has possessed itseK of life as of something imported from without. But, besides fire, air, water, and earth there are no bodies. And even such as believe that there are elements different from those enumerated, call them bodies, not souls, and ascribe no life to them. If, however, no one of the bodies [which make up the soul] is possessed of life, it is absurd to think that their conjunction has created life. And if each of them is animate, then one of them is sufficient for our purpose. It is pecuHarly impossible, however, that a combina- tion of bodies should produce life or that intellect should be produced by that which is without it. Moreover, it is not maintained that life is produced by any random commingling. There must be then a principle which is directive and causes the mixture. But this would take the place of the soul. In fine, there could be no com- posite, nor even any simple body in being were there not soul in the universe, if indeed it be a seminal reason entering into matter which makes a body, and a seminal reason can come from nowhere except from soul. . . . * * For 3 there could be no body were there no psychic power existent, since the corporeal is in flux and its nature in motion, and would be immediately destroyed if there were nothing but the corporeal. This would be true even if one gave the name ''soul" to one of these bodies, since this would fare like the others, seeing that they would be of one matter. Or rather, there would be no generation at all, but all things would remain mere matter for the lack of anything to give them form. 'Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, § 3, 458 C (C. p. 847, 1. 15 et seq.; V. II. 122, 1. 17 et seq.). I PLOTINUS 343 Perhaps, too, there would not be even any matter, and this world-all would be dissolved, if one trusted for its existence to the conjunction of the corporeal, and gave to this the place of soul, at any rate, so far as the name went, ascribing it to air and to spirits which are most dissoluble and without any unity of themselves. For, I ask you, in view of the divisibility of all corporeal things, will not the man who confides this universe to any one of them, thereby make it unintelligent and borne about at random? What ordering principle is there in animal spirits which owe their order to soul, or what reason or what intelligence? But if soul exists, then all these things are ministrant to her constitution of the world and of the individual living being, in that one power proceeding from another contributes to the whole. Were she, however, not present in things, they would have no being at all, let alone an orderly ex- istence. ... * That ^ if the soul were corporeal there would be no sensation nor thought nor undertaking nor virtue nor anything beautiful is clear also from the following con- siderations : If one thing is to perceive another it must be one, and grasp everything in the same operation, even though the incoming perception be multiple and enter through several senses, or there be several qualities of one object, or through the oneness there appear a variety, as in the case of a face. For one operation does not perceive a nose, another the eyes, but the same operation perceives all things together. Moreover, if one sensa- tion come through the eyes, another through the hearing, *Plotinu8, Enneads, IV. 7, § 6, 461 A (C. p. 853, 1. 3 et seq.; V. II. 126, 1. 11 et seq.). 344 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY there must be some one thing to which both come. Otherwise, if they did not come both together to thisf same something, how could one say that the perceptions were different? This something must be hke a centre to which the sensations from all sides penetrate like lines converging from the circumference of a circle. Such then is the apperceptive faculty — a real unity. . . . * * We ^ may also see the same thing from the case of pain and the sensation of pain. Whenever a man says that his finger hurts, the pain naturally has to do with his finger, but the sensation of pain, it will of course be agreed, has to do with the ruling faculty. Although the part hurt is different from it, the ruling faculty per- ceives the animal spirits and the whole soul suffers the same pain. Now how does this happen? By trans- mission, it is said, in that first the animal spirits which are connected with the finger suffer and hand on their suffering to the next part in turn, and this to still another, and so on till it reaches the ruling faculty. Necessarily then, if the part hurt first feels, the sensa- tion of the second part will be another sensation — in case, I mean, sensation is by transmission, — and that of the third still another. In this way there will be many, in- deed innumerable sensations of the one pain generated, and finally the ruling faculty will feel them all, and its own pain besides. The truth is that on this theory each one of these parts will not feel the pain in the finger, but the part next the finger will feel that the palm of the hand hurts, and the third that there is a pain somewhere else higher up. » Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, § 7, 462 A (C. p. 865, I. 9 et seq. ; V. II. 128, 1. 3 et seq.). PLOTINUS 345 So there will be many pains, and the ruling faculty will not perceive the pain in the finger but the pain in itself. Only of this last will it be conscious, and will pay no heed to the other pains, and will not understand that it is the finger which is hurting. A sensation then of pain in the finger cannot be generated by transmission, nor can any one part of the body — which is an extended mass — be aware of another's suffering, since in every extended object when one part is in one place the others are in other places. Hence, I say it is necessary to con- ceive the perceiving faculty as throughout identical with itself. But such a conception is not appropriate to body but to some other form of being. * * That ^ thought also is impossible if the soul be a body of any sort is to be proved as follows. If sensation be the soul's perceiving sensible objects with the help of the body, then thought also cannot be comprehension through the instrumentality of the body, since in that case it will be the same as sensation. If then thought be comprehension of objects without the aid of the body, surely that which thinks has even a stronger claim to not being body. Again, if sensation be of sensible objects, thought is of intelligible objects. If our oppo- nents will not grant this, they must at least grant that there are thoughts of some intelligible objects, and ap- prehensions of things which have no extension. But then how can that which has extension think that which has not, and with its divisible nature think the indi- visible? Do you say, with some indivisible portion of itself? In that case, however, that which thinks will not be a body. For under these circumstances there « Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, § 8. 346 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY will be no need of the whole for the contact of thought with its object, but a single part will suffice. Moreover, if it be conceded that the most abstract thoughts are of things in every respect pure of the corporeal, what thinks, also, by virtue of being or be- coming pure of the corporeal, attains knowledge of them. And if it be asserted that thoughts are of forms inhering in matter, then the thoughts of the forms are attained only by abstracting the bodies, and it is intellect which does the abstracting. There is, for instance, no residuum of flesh or of matter of any sort in the abstractions of a circle, a triangle, a line, or a point. The soul then, when at such work, must of necessity abstract herself from the body. It follows that she herself cannot be body. I think also that the beautiful and the right are not extended things, and that hence the thought of them cannot be extended. So, when these things meet her, she will receive them with the indivisible part of herself, and they will lie in her indivisible seK. . . . Again there is the question whether the soul grasp the maxims of virtue and other intelligible objects as things eternal, or virtue be generated and must needs perish again. But what destroys it, and whence does it spring? For this again would abide. Virtue then must belong to the eternal and abiding, as do geometrical entities. But if it belongs to the eternal and the abiding, it is not corporeal. And that in which it resides must also be incorporeal, and cannot be a body. For all corporeal nature abides not, but is in flux. . . . But if the soul be neither body nor any property of body but rather active and creative, and possessed of much, both in and of herself, she must be a separate essence from bodies. What kind of an essence then ? Clearly she must be that I PLOTINUS 347 which we call real essence. For the corporeal might all be called a ^process, but not an essence, seeing that it is in a process of generation and corruption and never for a moment really is anything, but by its participation in being is kept in existence to the degree that it does par- ticipate in it. . . . * There ^ is then another nature that of itseK possesses all real being such as is neither generated nor destroyed. For all things else would pass away and never again come into existence, if this were destroyed, since this it is which preserves them and this universe, keeping them in existence and in order through the mediation of soul. ... * That ^ the soul is akin to the diviner and eternal nature is made clear by the facts that she has been proven to be incorporeal, has neither form nor color, and is intangible. But there are other proofs as well. And since we are agreed that everything divine and possessed of real being enjoys a good and rational life, our next task is to start with our own soul and inquire what her nature is. Let us take then a soul — not one sunk in the body which has laid hold of irrational desires and emotions and received into herself other passions, but one which has sloughed these all off and has as little commerce as possible with the body. Such an one shows clearly that evil is a foreign accretion on the soul, and that in the purified soul everything that is best, wisdom and every other virtue, inheres and is native. TPlotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, 463 A (C. p. 863, 1. 13; V. II. 136, L \2 et seq..). *1D., § 14, 464 A (C. p. 865, 1. I; V. II. 137, 1, 13 et seq.). 348 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY . . . But ^ in investigating the nature of anything one must regard it in its purity, since any accretion always stands in the way of knowing that to which it is super- added. Abstract then in investigating, or rather let him who abstracts look at himself, and he will be per- suaded that he is immortal when he sees himseK on the intelligible and pure plane. For he will see his intellect regarding not any sensible or mortal thing, but with its eternal seK thinking the eternal, and all things which exist in the intelligible world. Nay, he will see his in- tellect itself become intelligible and luminous, resplendent with the truths proceeding from the good which illumi- nates intelligible objects with truth. . . . Again ^^ what sane man could raise a doubt as to the immortality of such a nature, possessed as it is of a self -originated life that cannot be destroyed? . . . For either its essence is life or else Hfe is something super- added to matter. In the first case, this essence will be either self -animated — which is just what we are looking for and we agree is immortal — or may be analyzed as a compound and the process repeated till an imperishable self-moved element be reached which cannot be liable to death. In the second case, if our opponents say that life be a property superadded to matter, they will be forced to confess that the source of this prop- erty of life in matter must itself be immortal, since it cannot be subject to the opposite of what it imparts. There is then one nature whose characteristic activity is life. • Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, 464 E. 10 lb., § 15, 465 (C. p. 867, 1. 11 et seq.; V. II. 139, 1. 10 et seq.). I PLOTINUS 349 Again, 1^ if it be said that all soul is corruptible, then all things would have perished long ago. But if it be said that some soul perishes, other not, as for instance that the world-soul is immortal but our souls mortal, the reason for this distinction must be given. For both are principles of motion, both are self-animated, and both grasp the same objects with the same faculty, thinking both heavenly objects and those which transcend the heavens, and both seek all essential being and mount up to the first principle of all things. Also her ability to classify each thing of herself because of the notion innate within her — an ability produced by reminiscence of the intelligible — gives our soul an existence prior to the body, and since she is in enjoyment of eternal principles, shows that she herself is also eternal. Finally, everything dissoluble has been produced by combination, and is dissolved after the same fashion in which it was combined. But the soul is single and simple, a nature whose characteristic activity consists in living. She cannot then be destroyed by dissolution. But, do you say, she might be destroyed by being divided and broken up ? However, she has no mass or quantity, as has been shown. Or, do you say, by a process of altera- tion she might pass into corruption? Alteration, however, in destroying, though it takes away the form leaves the matter. It is a composite being then, which is liable to it. But if the soul cannot be destroyed after any of these fashions, she must necessarily be immortal. . . . *** We ^2 speak of the soul of each individual as one, because she is present in her entirety throughout the 11 Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 7, § 16. 12 lb., IV. 9, § 1, 477 (C. p. 888; V. II. 153). 350 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY body, and is really one in that she does not have one part here, another there. In sensitive beings, too, the same is true of the sensitive soul, and in plants the whole soul is present throughout in every part. Now are my soul and your soul one, and all souls one in the same way ? And in the universe is one soul present in all things, not divided as a thing which has mass is divided, but everywhere the same ? For why should this soul of mine be one but the soul in the universe not one ? There is no question there either of mass or body. Moreover, if your soul and mine proceed from the world-soul, and it is one, then ours should be one also . And if the world-soul and my soul are derived from one soul, then again they should be one. What sort of a soul would this one then be ? First, however, we must decide whether it be indeed correct to call all souls one, in the sense that the soul of a single individual is one. Now it involves a real absurdity if my soul and the soul of any other person are one. For in that case when I perceived, he too would have to perceive, and if I were good, would have to be good, and if I desired, would also have to desire. And in general we should share the same sensations with one another and with the universe, so that whenever I were affected in any wise, the universe would share in my sen- sation. Again, if all souls be one, how can the rational be different from the irrational soul, or the soul in animals different from that in plants? But on the other hand if we do not posit this unity, the universe will not be one, and no single source of souls will have been found. * * In 13 the first place then, if my soul and the soul of another man be one, it will not follow that both are '3 Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 9, § 2. PLOTINUS 351 reciprocally identical. For although the same thing may be present in both, it will not have the same properties in the two cases. Thus humanity may be present in me who am in motion, and in you who are not in motion. In me humanity will be moved, in you at rest, and still there is nothing absurd or paradoxical in the fact that it is the same humanity which is in you and me. It is not necessary, then, that when I perceive something, another man should have exactly the same experience. For that matter, too, given a single body, one hand does not perceive what the other feels, but rather the soul which resides in the whole body. And had you to know my feelings our bodies would have to merge into one another, and we two become a single individual. Thus knitted together both souls would have identical per- ceptions. We ought also to note the many things of which* the whole is unconscious, even in the case of one and the same body. This is the more noticeable the bigger the body is. For instance, there are huge sea-monsters in which no perception whatever of anything experienced by a part reaches the whole, because of the comparative slightness of the motion excited. We may conclude that no clearly defined experience need be received by the whole organism when one particular part is affected. But that it should be affected sympathetically, though there is not necessarily any definite sensation, is not absurd and cannot be denied. It will not be absurd then that the same thing should be virtuous in me, vicious in you, seeing that it can exist in one man in a state of motion, in another at rest. For after all we do not call the soul one in a sense which altogether excludes plurality. Such imity is to be attributed to the nature which is 352 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY better than soul. Soul, on the contrary, we call one- and-many, and say that it participates in the divisible corporeal nature, and in the indivisible as well, so that again it is one. And just as in my case, whatever is generated by the ruling faculty communicates something to the part, in spite of the fact that the affection of the part does not prevail over the whole; so everything which the universe communicates to the particular is quite manifest because of our manifold sympathetic relations with the universe, whereas we do not know for certain whether our experiences are contributed to the world- all or not. ... * The ^^ question now is. After what fashion is the one essence in the many souls? For either the one essence in them all is a sum total, or else the many are derived from the whole and single essence without disturbing its wholeness or unity. It, however, is one, and the many souls are related to it as the one unity which gives itself to the many, and at the same time does not give itself. For it is able to give itself to all, and yet to remain one. It can penetrate simultaneously all things, and not be severed at all from any one of them. It is one and the same thing in many. There should be no difficulty about believing this. A science exists as a whole, and is related to its parts in such wise that its wholeness is not impaired by the derivation of the parts from it. A seed also is a whole, and the parts are derived from it into which it naturally divides itself, and each of these is a whole, and remains a whole. But the whole is not diminished — it is matter which " Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 9, § 5, 480 A (C. p. 894; V. II. 157). PLOTINUS 353 divides it up — and all the parts are one. Perhaps, how- ever, it will be said that in the case of a science the part is not the whole. It is true, to be sure, in this case, that the part which we are using is at hand and is emphasized. Still, the other parts also follow, latent and potential, and are all contained in the part in question. It is in this sense that one speaks of the whole science and of a part of it. But in the soul all the parts coexist in their actuality. In the case of a science, to revert, each part is ready to which you may wish to put your hand. The readiness for use lies in the part, but it gets its efficacy from its contiguity to the whole. One cannot regard it as empty of the other propositions. Were it, it would not hold either in practice or in theory, but would be mere child's prattle. If it holds theoretically, it is be- cause it contains all the parts potentially. A thinker in thinking, I say, deduces the other parts by implication. A geometer in his analysis makes clear how the one part or proposition contains all the other propositions through which the analysis has proceeded, and also all the con- sequent propositions which follow from it. These things, however, gain no credence because of our weakness and because they are obscured by the body. But in the intelligible world each and every thing is plain. THE INTELLECrr Why 15 now must we use the soul as a stepping-stone to something higher and not posit her as the first prin- ciple? In the first place because intellect is different from and better than soul, and what is better by nature comes first. Intellect is better, because soul does not as "Plotinus, Enneads, V. 9, § 4, 557 E (C. p. 1030, 1. 16; V. II. 251, 1. 9) 354 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY some think generate the intellect of her perfection. For how can the possible become actual, unless there be a cause which makes it actual? Were the process of actualization a matter of chance, perhaps the possible might not become actual. Hence we must regard our first principle as in actual existence, wanting nothing, and perfect. And tha imperfect we must regard as coming later and as perfected by what has produced it, just as parents bring to maturity offspring which they generated in the beginning imperfect. Soul, moreover, is matter in comparison with her first cause, and then is formed and perfected by it. Again since soul is passi- ble, there must be some impassible principle — or else all things in time would be destroyed — and something, too, prior to soul. Finally, since soul is in the world, there must be some principle outside the world, and this, too, must be prior to soul. For if what exists in the world exists in the corporeal and ma- terial, nothing there will preserve its identity. Hence the idea of man and all the forms will be neither eternal nor self-identical. From these considerations as well as from many others, it may be seen that intellect must exist prior to soul. ... * Although 16 then the soul is the kind of thing which our discussion has shown her to be, still she is merely a sort of image of the intellect. In fact, just as a thought expressed in words is an image of the thought in the soul, so she is both the thought of the intellect and the entirety of its activity and the life which it sends forth to constitute a new form of being. An illustration of » Plotinus, Enneads, V. 1, § 3, 484 B (C. p. 900, 1. 4; V. II. 164, I. 19). PLOTINUS 355 what I mean is fire which has both an inherent heat, and a heat which it radiates. . . . *** It ^'^ is the intellect then which makes the soul ever more divine by its fatherhood and companionship. Nor does anything separate them save the fact that they are different, inasmuch as the soul is one lower in rank and is the receptive principle, whereas the intellect is, as it were, the form. Still even the matter of the intellect is beautiful since it is intelligible and simple. And the excellence of the intellect can be clearly estimated by this superiority to soul, which is such as we have de- scribed. * We 1^ should also see the excellence of the intellect, if first admiring the phenomenal universe with an eye to its grandeur and beauty, the orderliness of its eternal motion, its gods both visible and invisible, its spirits, and all its animals and plants, we should then rise to its far truer and more real archetype, and should see how all things there are intelligible and eternal of themselves and dwell in native reason and live with imcorrupted intellect at their head, and unspeakable wisdom and the true life of Chronos which is the offspring of God and the intellect. For the intellect comprehends everything that is immortal, every intellect, every god, every soul, in its eternal peace. Its peace, I say, for why should it in its felicity seek change? And into what could it change, seeing that it has all things of its own self. Nor wiU the intellect seek to develop itself, since it is ab- solutely perfect. Hence everything that shares its "Plotinus, Enneads, V. 1, § 3, 484 D (C. p. 901, 1. 16; V. II. 165, 1. 3). >«Ib., §4. 356 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY existence is perfect, to the end that it may be perfect in every respect, possessed of nothing imperfect and noth- ing which is not the object of its thought. Its thought, however, is not a search but a possession. Its fehcity, too, is not acquired from without. Rather is it eternally all things, and is the true eternity of which time encircling the soul is an image — time which leaves the old things behind and lays hold of new. For, to speak still of time, now one thing now another revolves about the soul, now Socrates, and now a horse, and always some single thing. The intellect, on the other hand, is all things. It contains all things in itself at rest within itself. Only the present exists for it, and is present eternally, and for it there is nothing future, since the future is already present to it, and nothing past. Nothing, I say, is past, but all realities have remained at rest there from eternity, as though content with them- selves as they are. Each of them is intellect and real existence, and the sum of them is all intellect and all real existence. The intellect in the act of thought produces existence, and existence by being thought gives thought and existence to the intellect. Of both existence and thought, however, there is yet another cause. For they exist simultaneously and never desert one another. But though two, they together constitute that unity which is at once intellect and existence, thinking and the object thought. Intellect this imity is qua thinking, existence qua the object thought, for thinking could not arise were there not identity and difference. The first principles then are intellect, existence, difference, identity. The categories of motion and rest, however, must also be included, motion if there is to be thinking. PLOTINUS 357 rest for the sake of identity. Difference must exist that there may be thinking and an object of thought. Take away the category of difference, and the unity which arises from thinking and the object of thought will be given its quietus. The ideas must also differ from one another, and yet be the same in that each is self- identical and all have a common element. Their differ- ence is otherness. These principles by virtue of their plurality generate number and quantity. Quality is generated by the fact that each one of these principles from which all else proceeds has its peculiar and proper character. ... * It 1^ is necessary to understand then by intellect, if we are to attach any true significance to the name, not the potential intellect, or the intellectual knowledge developed out of ignorance. Did we, we should have to seek for yet another intellect prior to this. By intellect we are to understand that which is intellect in actu, and eternally. But if its thought be not im- ported from without, when it thinks anything it must itself be the occasion of its thought, and when it is possessed of any object be the occasion of that possession. But if it be the occasion and source of its thought, it will itself be the object of its thought. For were its essence one thing, and the object of its thought another, its essence w^ould not be an intelligible object, and would exist potentially, not actually. The one then is not separable from the other, though it is our custom drawn from our own experience to think of them as separate. I'Plotinus, Enneads, V. 9, § 5, 558 C (C. p. 1031, 1. 14; V. II. 251, 1. 32). 358 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY What then is the object of the activity and thought of the intellect Hke, that we should regard the intellect as itself the object of its thought? Clearly the intellect, being real existence, must think and support the world of real existences (the ideas). It is then the real ex- istences. It must think of these as existing either else- where than in itself, or in itseK as its own nature. To think them as elsewhere than in itself is impossible. For where could they exist? It thinks them as con- stituting its own nature and existing in itself. We come to this conclusion because the seat of the form is not the sensible object as some think. For in no case is the primary and fundamental the phenomenal. The form in sensible objects imposed upon matter is an image of real existence, and every form in objects comes from something without, refers thither, and is an image thereof. Again, if there must needs be a maker of this universe, he will not think of what does not as yet exist, in order to create it. The forms of things then must exist prior to the world, not indeed as impressions struck from other things, but as archetypes and originals and the very essence of the intellect. If, however, some people talk of seminal reasons as sufficient, evidently they must be talking of the eternal reasons. But if the reasons are eternal and impassible, they must exist in an intellect, and in an intellect such that it is prior to conditioned existence, nature, and soul, seeing that these have a potential existence. The intellect then is all real existences thought as not external to itself. They are neither prior nor subsequent to it, but it is, as it were, the primal lawgiver, or rather the law itself of existence. The saying then is correct PLOTINUS 359 that thinking and existing are one and the same thing, and that the knowledge of immaterial entities is the same as the things themselves — also the saying ^'I sought my- self" [as] one of the real existences; and the doctrine of reminiscence is true too. For no real existence is outside the intellect, or in space. Rather do they exist eternally in themselves, subject neither to change nor destruction, and for this reason are real existences. On the other hand what is generated and destroyed enjoys existence as something superadded. Not they, then, but what is superadded, is real existence. Phenomena exist as defin- able objects through participation, in that their sub- stratum gets its form from without. Thus bronze re- ceives its form from the art of casting statues, and wood from that of carpentry, through the entrance into them of images of the arts in question. At the same time the arts themselves remain outside of matter in their self-identity, and contain the true statue and the true bed. This is also true of corporeal things. The difference between images and real existences is shown likewise by this universe which participates in images. For in the intelligible world real existences are im- mutable (whereas the things of this world are mutable), and being without extension reside in themselves without need of space, and have an intellectual and self-sufficient kind of existence. But the nature of corporeal things wants preservation by something outside itself, while the intellect, which with its wonderful nature supports what naturally tends to fall, itself seeks no support. We 20 grant then that the intellect is real existence and contains all the real existences in itself, not after a 20 Plotinus, Enneads, V. 9, § 6. 360 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY spatial fashion, but as though they were its own self, and it were one with them. All things exist together there, and nevertheless are distinguished from one an- other. For the soul also is possessed of many notions at the same time, without confusing them. Each does its proper work at the proper time without involving the others. So, too, each thought has a pure activity drawn from the thoughts which He within it. After this fashion, and to a far greater extent, the intelligible universe is all things together and yet not together inasmuch as each real existence is an individual and peculiar power. But the whole intellect includes them as a genus contains its species, or as a whole its parts. . . . *** Whatever 21 appears in the phenomenal world as form is contained in the intelligible world, but what does not so appear has no place there. Hence there is nothing contrary to nature there, just as there is nothing con- trary to art in the arts, nor for that matter lameness in the seed, seeing that lameness arises during growth from the failure of the seminal reason to overcome matter, and is a chance mutilation of form. In the intelligible world also are all harmonious quaUties and quantities, numbers and magnitudes, conditions, actions and natural proper- ties, motions and rests, both in whole and in part. In place of time there is eternity, and space there is repre- sented by logical impUcation. ... 22 Are then only phenomena represented in the intelligible world, or are still more things ? First we must inquire about artificial objects. . . . 2» Plotinus, Enneads, V. 9, § 10, 562 (C. p. 1038, 1. 10 et seq. ; V. II. 256, 1. 21). 22 lb., 562 E. PLOTINUS 361 As 23 regards then art and artificial objects. Such arts as are imitative Hke painting and sculpture, dancing and gesticulation, which take their rise in the phenomenal world, and make use of a sensible model and imitate forms and motions, and repeat the symmetries which they behold, could not properly be referred to the intelligible world except as included in the idea of man. But if from the symmetry in animals we be led to reflect upon some condition of living beings in general, our reflection would be part of the power of considering the intelligible world, and beholding the symmetry of all things therein. Every sort of music, too, which is occupied with the concepts of harmony and rhythm, would be in the same class as an art occupied with in- telligible rhythm. Also such arts as fashion sensible objects like architecture and carpentry get their prin- ciples and some of their skill from the intelligible world. But inasmuch as they have mixed their principles up with the phenomenal, they do not reside wholly in the intelligible, but rather in man. Agriculture, however, which deals with sensible things Hke plants does not come from the intelligible, nor medicine which looks to earthly health, and busies itself with keeping people strong and in good condition. For in the intelligible world there is another kind of strength and health by virtue of w^hich all living things are not subject to disturbance and are self- sufficient. Rhetoric and generalship, political economy and statesmanship, if they join beauty to their deeds and have the vision of it, get a portion of their wis- dom from the wisdom on high. Geometry which deals with intelligible entities must be placed there, and also the highest wisdom which is occupied with real 23 Plotinus, Enneads, V. 9, § 11, 563 A. 362 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY existence. So much must suffice for the arts and arti- ficial objects. * Are 24 there then also ideas of particular objects? Let us see. If I and every man can trace ourselves back to the intelligible world, then each man has his separate origin there. And if Socrates and the soul of Socrates are eternal, there will exist in the intelligible world a Socrates in himself as it is called, in so far as the souls of individuals are there. But if what was formerly Socrates becomes at another time another individual like Pythagoras or some one else, then the particular idea of Socrates no longer exists in the intelligible world. Still if the soul of the individual contain the seminal reasons of all those through whom it passes, all will be represented in the intelligible world. For we say also that each soul possesses all the seminal reasons that are in the world. If now the world contains the seminal reasons not only of man, but of particular animals, the soul will possess them too. There will then be an infinite number of seminal reasons, unless indeed they be periodically repeated in world-cycles, and in this way a limit set to their infinity, as often as they are reexemplified. However, if generally speaking there are more partic- ulars produced than there are patterns, why need there be seminal reasons and patterns for everything produced within a single world-cycle? One archetypal man is enough for many men, just as a definite number of souls produce [in their reincarnations] an indefinite number of human beings. Still, different things have not the same seminal reason, nor is a single man sufficient as a pattern for men who differ from one another not only in point 2«Plotinus, Enneads, V. 7, 1. 539 A (C. p. 995; V. II. 228). PLOTINUS 363 of matter, but in countless specific points. For such men are not related as the pictures of Socrates are related to the original, but their differences have to be regarded as due to different reasons or ideas. A world- cycle, however, in its entirety contains all the seminal reasons. And then [in the next world-cycle] the same world is repeated after the same ideas. Infinity in the intelligible world is not to be feared. For its infinity is all contained in the indivisible, and proceeds from it, as it were, when the intelligible world exercises its proper activity. . . . THE ONE Everything 25 which exists, both primary existences and whatsoever is in any way spoken of as being, exists by virtue of its unity. For what would a thing be were it not one thing ? Take away its unity and it is no longer what we define it to be. There is for instance no army except it be a unity, and no chorus or flock which is not one. Nor is there any house or ship which has not unity, since the house is a single thing, and likewise the ship. If this unity be lost, the house is no longer a house nor the ship a ship. Compound and extended bodies then could not exist, unless unity were present in them. And if cut up, so far as they lose their unity they change their existence. So too, the bodies of plants and animals which are each a unit, if in being broken up they escape from unity into plurality, destroy the essence which they had and are no longer what they were, but become something else, and this indeed only in so far as they are still units. Health also exists when the body is organized as a unit, and beauty when the nature of the one holds the parts together, and virtue in the "Plotinus, Enneads, VI. 9, § 1, 757 A (C. p. 1385; V. II. 518). 364 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY soul when she is made a unit and unified in a single harmony. . . . We must now see whether the unity and the being of the individual be the same, and existence in general identical with the One. But if the being of each in- dividual is a plurality, and the one cannot be many, then they must be different. Now man is both an animal and a rational being, and has many parts which in their multiplicity are bound together in unity. Man then is one thing, unity another. Man is divisible, unity in- divisible. Also existence in general, since it comprises wdthin itself all the real existences, is multiple in nature, and different from unity, and by participation possesses and shares in unity. Real existence has both life and intellect — since it is no lifeless corpse. Hence it is multiple. And if the intellect be real existence, it must be multiple, and still more so, if it comprise the ideas. For the idea is not one but is rather a number of things — each individual idea as well as their sum total. They are one in the same sense as the universe is one. Generally speaking, too, unity is fundamental and primal, but the intellect, and the ideas, and real existence are not primal. Each idea is made up of many parts, is composite, and a consequent, inasmuch as what a thing is composed of is prior to it. That intellect cannot be primal is also plain from the following considerations: The intellect necessarily is in thought, and since it regards what is both supremely good and at the same time not external to itself, the object of its thought is prior to itself. For in reverting to itself it reverts to its origin. Moreover, if it be both the thinking and the object of thought, it is dual, not simple, and is not the One. But if it regard another than itself, PLOTINUS 365 it will regard what is in every respect better than and prior to itseK. If, however, it regard itself, it regards [qiia thinking] what is better [qica object of its thought] than itself, and so is a secondary entity. Now we must consider the intellect such that it com- munes with the good and the first of all things, and regards it, and also communes with itself and thinks itself, and thinks itself as the whole world of real ex- istences. Its variety then falls far short of being unity. The One cannot be all things, since in that case it would be no longer One, nor can it be intellect since it would then be all things because the intellect is all things. Nor can it be existence, for existence is all things. What now is the One? WTiat is its nature? It is no wonder that we cannot easily say, in view of the fact that neither existence nor form is easily described. Yet our knowledge is based upon forms and concepts. But the more the soul proceeds into the formless, the more she becomes unable to comprehend it, because it is inde- finable and lacks the impress of variety. Hence she wavers and begins to fear that she has laid hold of blank nothing, and tires at such a height and is glad to descend frequently and to fall back from everything till she has reached the phenomenal world. There she rests from her labors as if on firm ground once more. In the same way our sight when wearied with tiny things gladly falls upon large objects. On the other hand when the soul desires vision absolutely of and by itself, in this vision which comes through communion and union she does not believe that she has attained the object of her search through union with it, just because the object of her thought is not a different thing from herself. We, however, who are going to make the One the 366 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY object of our philosophic meditation must needs do as follows. Since it is the One which we are searching for, and the source of all things, the good and the primal, which we are beholding, we must not depart from the neighborhood of things primal, nor sink to those which come last, but must strive rather to betake ourselves from them and their show of sense to the primal things. We must free ourselves from all vice, too, if we be eager for the good, and must rise to the principle hidden within ourselves, and throwing off our multiplicity become one, and be made that principle and a beholder of the One. We must become then intellect, and intrust our souls to our intellect, and establish them there, so that we may- be conscious of what the intellect beholds, and through it enjoy the vision of the One. We must not add thereto any sense-experience, nor receive into our thought any- thing that comes from sense, but with the pure intellect, and the primal part of the intellect behold the Most Pure. If now, when so prepared, we attribute in our im- agination either extension or form or mass to this nature, it will not be intellect which guides our vision, because these properties are not naturally objects of intellectual vision, but rather of the activity of sense, and opinion which follows sense. We must rather get from the intellect views of what lies within its power. Nov/ the intellect can behold either what is prior to itself, or its own nature, or what comes after it. Pure is its own nature, but still purer and simpler what are or rather is prior to it. This is not intellect but prior to intellect. For intellect is something which exists. But this other nature is not something, but is prior to everything. It is not an existence, for what exists has the form of ex- PLOTINUS 367 istence, and it is formless, even without intelligible form. I say this, because the nature of the One being the creator of all things is itself no one of them. So it is not a thing, nor quahty, nor quantity, nor intellect, nor soul, nor in motion, nor at rest, nor in space, nor in time, but is the absolutely ^^monoform," or rather formless, prior to all form, prior to motion, prior to rest. For these things pertain to existence, and it creates them in their multiplicity. Why now, if it be not in motion is it not at rest? Because either or both of these properties pertain to being, and what is at rest is so by virtue of stability, and is not the same as stability. Hence stability is an at- tribute of it, and it is no longer simple. Also if we call the One a cause, we are not predicating something of it, but rather something of ourselves, inasmuch as we are receiving something from it while it exists in itself. Again, strictly speaking we cannot talk of the One as a *'this," or a ''that," but looking at it from without, may only wish to interpret the ways in which it affects us. Now we get nearer to it, now we fall farther short of it, because of the difficulties that hedge it about. The greatest of these difficulties is that our apprehen- sion of the One does not partake of the nature of either imderstanding or abstract thought as does our knowledge of other intelligible objects, but has the character of presentation higher than understanding. For under- standing proceeds by concepts, and the concept is a multiple affair, and the soul misses the One when she falls into number and plurality. She must then pass beyond understanding, and nowhere emerge from her unity. She must, I say, withdraw from understanding and its objects and from every other thing, even the 368 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY vision of beauty. For everything beautiful comes after it and is derived from it, as all daylight from the sun. It is for this reason that Plato says that the One is ineffable in spoken or written word. We speak and write of it, however, that we may despatch our spirits toward it, and rouse them from the contemplation of mere concepts to the vision of it, pointing out the way, as it were, to one eager for some sight. Instruction goes as far as showing the road and the way. But the vision is the work of him who has already willed to be- hold it. . . . * In 26 what sense now is the One one ? And how is it to be grasped by our thought? I reply, it must be regarded as more one than monad or point. For with these latter entities the soul subtracts magnitude and numerical quantity and stops and rests at the smallest possible remainder — which is indivisible in truth, yet was contained in the divisible and is found in other things. The One, however, is found neither in other things, nor in the divisible, nor is it indivisible in the sense in which the smallest possible remainder is in- divisible. It is the greatest of all things not in extension, but in power, and hence space and extension have noth- ing to do with its power. The real existences which come next to it in rank, are also indivisible and undivided in a dynamic not a spatial sense. We are to understand, too, that it is infinite not by virtue of being immeasurable in extension or number, but because its power cannot be comprehended or circumscribed. When you think of it as intellect or God, it is more. And when you unify "Plotinua, Enneads, VI. 9, § 6, 763 E (C. p. 1397, 1. 17; V. II. 615, 1. 20). PLOTINUS 369 it in your thought it is more — more even than you could imagine God himself to be, if you imagined him to be more one than your thought. For it exists in itself and has no attributes. One would not be wrong perhaps in representing God's unity through the concept of self-sufficiency. For he must be the sufficient and self-sufficing, and free from wants of all things, whereas everything which is mul- tiple and not one wants, since it has been made of many things, and its essence stands in need of unity. But the One does not stand in need of itself, since it is itself. Moreover, a thing which is multiple needs as many things as it is composed of. And all such things are subsequent to their components, and not self- existent, but need other things, and display this need both in their parts and as wholes. If then there must be something which is absolutety self-sufficient, this must be the One, and must be so in this respect alone, namely, that it wants nothing in re- lation either to itself or to other things. The One seeks nothing in order that it may exist or be happy, nor yet anything to support it. Since it is the cause of all else, it owes its own existence to nothing else. For the same reason why should its happiness be an object external to itself? It follows that happiness is not an attribute of the One. The One is happiness. Furthermore, it is not to be found in space, seeing that it needs no space as if it were not able to support itself. What has spatial position is inanimate and is a falling mass if it be not placed in position. Things have position for the same reasons that they coexist, and each has the place to which it has been assigned. What needs, however, a place in space wants something. 370 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Then too the source does not need the things which follow after it, and the source of all things has no need of any. For what wants, w^ants in the sense that it strives after its source. Again if the One needs anything, it is clearly seeking not to be One, and hence needs its own destruction qva One. Everything which wants, however, stands in need of well-being and preservation. It follows that for the One, nothing can be good, nor can it wish anything. It is rather super-good, a good not for itself but for other things, if any of them be able to attain it. Nor can the One be thinking, lest there be difference and motion in it. It is prior to motion and to thinking. For what shall it think? Itself? In that case before it thinks it will be ignorant, and what is self- sufficient will need thought in order to know itself. But it does not follow that because it does not know or think itself, it will be ignorant of itself. For ignorance has to do with an external object, as w^hen one thing is ignorant of another. But the Only One will neither know any- thing, nor have anything to be ignorant of. Being One and united with itself it does not need to think of itself. You cannot even catch a glimpse of it by ascribing to it union with itself. Rather must you take away thinking and the act of being united, and thought of itself and of anything else. It must not be conceived as the thinker, but more after the fashion of mere thought, which does not think but is the cause of thinking in something else. The cause, however, is not the same as the caused, and the cause of all things is no one of them. It must not then be called the good which it gives to other things, but in some other sense the good above all other goods. PLOTINUS 371 THE PROCESS OF EMANATION 'fhe 27 One is all things and yet no one of them. For the origin of all things is itself, not they, yet all things are in their origin inasmuch as they may all be traced back to their som-ce. It is better, perhaps, to say that in their origin they exist not as present but as future things. How then can they proceed from the One in its simplicity, in whose self-identity there is no appearance of variety or duality whatsoever ? I reply, for the very reason that none of them was in the One, are all of them derived from it. Furthermore, in order that they may be real existences, the One is not an existence, but the father of existences. And the generation of existence is as it were the first act of generation. Being perfect by reason of neither seeking nor possessing nor needing anything, the One overflows as it were, and what overflows forms another hypostasis. . . . For ^s whenever anything else comes to perfection we see that it procreates and, un- wilUng to remain in itself, creates another being. This is true not only of beings which possess conscious purpose, but also of things which develop without conscious purpose. Indeed, even inanimate objects share them- selves as far as may be. Thus fire heats and cold chills and drugs have their appropriate effects upon other things, and all things imitate their origins as they are able with a view to their everlasting self-perpetuation and goodness. How then should the most perfect and primal good stay shut up in itself as if it were envious or impotent? And it the power of all things! How could it be the origin of anything? Something then must be begotten of it, if any of the other hypostases which are "Plotinus, Enneads, V. § 2, 493 (C. p. 918; V. II. 176). "lb., V. § 4, 517 (C. p. 958, 1. 17; V. II. 203, 19). 372 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY derived from it are to exist. Necessarily, then, something comes from it. Also what begets all that comes after it must be most worthy of worship, and the hypostasis second to it better than any other created thing. . . . * * * If 29 now there be an hypostasis second to it, and it be unmoved itself, the second hypostasis must come into being without any inclination or will or motion of any sort on the part of the One. How is this accomplished and how are we to think of this second hypostasis that surrounds the abiding and changeless essence of the One ? We are to think of it as a radiance proceeding from the One, and from the One abiding in its changelessness, just as the light about and surrounding the sun is eternally generated from it, without any change or motion in the solar substance. Indeed all things while they last necessarily give of their own power an hypostasis pro- ceeding from their own essence, outside of and surround- ing them, and attached to them — an image as it were of the archetypes which have brought it forth. Fire dis- penses heat from itself, and snow does not keep its cold only within itself. But the best witnesses of this fact are sweet-smelling substances. For as long as they exist there goes forth something from them which surrounds them and is enjoyed by any one w^ho happens to stand near. And everything on attaining perfection generates, and what is eternally perfect eternally generates the eternal; but what is generated is less than the generator. What now are we to say of the most perfect? Nothing comes from it but what is greatest after it. And the greatest after it and second in rank is the intellect. . . . "Plotinus, Enneads, V. § 1, 487 (C. p. 906, 1. 16; V. II. 168, 1. 15). PLOTINUS 373 We 2^ say that the intellect is an image of the One. But we must speak with more precision. In the first place we call it an image because it is begotten of the One, and preserves much of the nature of the One, and is very hke the One, as light is hke the sun. But it is not the One. How then does the One generate the intellect? In this wise — through what is generated by it turning back to behold it. This vision is the intellect. . . . That 31 world of which the One is the possibility, the intellect perceives, separating it as it were from its possibility. Else it w^ould not be intellect, since the essence of intellect consists in a kind of awareness of its possibilities and powers. It defines then through itself its own being by virtue of the possibilities got from the One. It is as it were a part of what comes from the One, and gets its essence thence and is established by the One, and perfected in essence from and of it. It sees that to itself as to the divisible from the indivisible have come life and thought and all things, and that the One is none of them. . . . This ^^ intellect so begotten is worthy of being the purest intellect, and has no other source than the first principle [the One]. In being begotten, it generates everything else with it, all the beauty of the ideas, all the intelligible goods. And it is filled with everything it generates, and swallows them again, so to speak, and contains them within itself lest they fall into matter. ... Now 33 the intellect being like the One follows the example of the One and pom's forth a mighty power. This power is a particular form of itself, as was the case 30 Plotinus, Enneads, V. § 1 488 A. 3i lb., 488 B. 32 ib., 489 A. 33 lb., y. § 2, 494 (C. p. 919, 1. 9; V. II. 176, 1. 18). 374 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY with that which the principle prior to intellect poured forth. And this activity proceeding from essence is soul, begotten without change or motion in the intellect — for intellect was begotten without change or motion in the principle prior to it. But the soul does not create, abiding in her changelessness, but in change and motion she generates an image. Looking to the source of her existence, she is filled with intellect, but when she pro- ceeds to other and opposite motions then she generates an image of herself, sensation and the nature in plants. But none of these things is removed or cut off from what is prior to it. . . . ^ There ^^ is then a procession from the origin of all things to the last and least of them, and each is left in its appropriate position. What is begotten holds another and lower place than what begets, yet each thing remains identified with that which it follows, as long as it seeks after it. 3^ Plotinus, Enneads, V. § 2, 494 A, XXIII VLOTINJJS— Continued MATTER If 1 now the world of real existences and what tran- scends real existence is such as we have described, no evil can inhere either in real existence or in the tran- scendent One. For they are good. If then evil exist, there remains for it the sphere of not-being, and it is as it were a certain form of not-being, and is concerned with things mixed with not-being or having some commerce with it. By not-being I do not mean absolute non- existence, but only what is different from real existence. Nor do I mean not-being in the sense that motion and rest which are attributes of being are not being, but rather in the sense of an image of real existence, or of something which has even less existence than an image. ^Yhsit I am alluding to is the phenomenal universe and all the affections of the sensible world. Or it may be it is either something which follows upon the phenomenal, and is as it were a property thereof, or else is its origin or some one of the things which go to make up the sensi- ble world, such as it is. And one might come to think of it as lack of measure with respect to measure, and as infinity with respect to finitude, and formless with respect to the formative, and eternally wanting with respect to the self-sufficient, as indeterminate, never iPotinus, Enneads, I. 8, § 3, 73 D (C p. 139; V. I 101). 375 376 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY at rest, subject to every affection, insatiate, poverty absolute. These characteristics are not properties of it but its essence, and whatever part of evil you may see you will find has them all. Now whatever else participates in it and is assimilated to it becomes bad, yet is not the principle of evil. What then is the hypostasis in which evil is present not as something extraneous but as the hypostasis itself? For were evil an attribute of something else, there must needs be something prior to it, even if it be not an essence of some sort. Just as there is good the principle, and good the predicate, so there is also evil which exists as a prin- ciple, and evil predicated according to this principle of some other subject. But, do you say, what is measur- edness if it does not consist in being measured, what measure if it does not lie in the measured? I reply that just as there is measure beside what is measured, so there is unmeasuredness which is not merely in the thing unmeasured. For did it exist in some other subject, it must exist either in the unmeasured — which is impossible since it has no need of unmeasuredness, being itself unmeasured — or in the measured, which is impossible since the measured cannot possess unmeasuredness in so far as it is measured. Hence there must be something infinite in itself, and formless in itself and everything else aforesaid which characterized the nature of evil. And if anything else be evil, it either has evil by admixture, or by regarding it, or by performing it. That, then, which underlies figures and forms and structures and measures and bounds, and is adorned with an orderli- ness foreign to it, having nothing good of itself, and being a mere phantom as compared with the soul, the very essence of evil, if evil can have an essence — that, I PLOTINUS 377 say, is discovered by our discourse to be the primal and the absolute evil. . . . * * * We 2 must now consider the meaning of the saying that evil cannot be destroyed but exists of necessity, and that it does not exist among the gods, but ever hovers about this mortal nature of ^^this place." The meaning is that the heaven is pure of evil, and goes with a regular and orderly motion, and that there is no unrighteousness there, nor other vice, nor injury of one part by another in their appointed courses; whereas on earth there is un- righteousness and disorder. This is what Plato means by mortal nature, and the phrase ^^this place.'' And the duty of fleeing hence is not to be taken locally as refer- ring to earthly places. Our flight, he says, does not lie in going away from the earth, but in living on earth in righteousness and holiness and sweet reasonableness, which is as much as to say that we must flee from vice. It is vice then and its consequences that he means by evil. But when Theodorus in the dialogue answers that evil could be removed if only men could be persuaded of the truth of this opinion, Socrates answers that this could not possibly happen, since evil exists of necessity, seeing that there must be some opposite to the good. . . . But ^ in what sense does it follow that if good exists evil also will exist? In this, I say, that there has to be matter in the universe. For this universe is necessarily composed of opposites, and could not exist were there no matter. The nature of the universe is mixed, as Plato says, of reason and necessity. And whatever comes to it from 2 Plotinus, Enneads, I. 8, 75 G (C. p. 144, 1. 6; V. I. 104, 1. 29) »Ib., § 7, 77 B (C. p. 147, 1. 6; V. I. 106, 1. 31). 378 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY God is good, but the evil comes from the primeval nature, by which he means the underlying matter as yet unbeau- tified by form. . . . From ^ what has been said then we can now understand the necessity of evil. Since the good is not soUtary, there must necessarily result from the emanation or, if one prefer, from the degeneration and departure from the good, something ultimate and last, beyond and after which nothing more can be generated. This ultimate and last thing is evil. That something should follow from the first principle is necessary, hence this last thing is necessary. And this is matter which has no remainder of the good and the first in it. Hence the necessity of evil. ^^ That ^ there must be some substratum in bodies differ- ent from the bodies themselves is evidenced by the con- version of the elements into one another. For the destruction of what is converted is not complete since, if it were, a substance would be put out of existence. Nor does what is generated come into being from abso- lute not-being. There is rather a change of form from one form to another. In change that remains change- less which receives the form of what it becomes, and puts off the form of what it previously was. Destruction shows this plainly, for it pertains to compound objects. If this be true, everything is composed of matter and form. Induction bears witness also, in showing that what is destroyed is compound, also analysis. For ex- ample if a cup can be dissolved into gold, and gold into water, analogy demands also that the water be dissoluble. The elements then must be either form or primitive mat- ■ Plotinus, Enneads, I. § 7, 77 E. »Ib., II. 4, § 6, 162 C (C. 288, 1. 3; V. I. 154. I. 30). PLOTINUS 379 ter or a composite of matter and form. It is impossible, however, that they should be form, for how could they have magnitude and extension without having matter? But they cannot be primitive matter, seeing that they are destroyed. They are then a composite of matter and form, form in respect to quality and structure, matter in respect to a substratum which is indeterminate because it has no form. What then is this substratum which we say is one and continuous and without quality like? That it cannot be corporeal if it is without quality is plain enough. If we say that it is the matter of all sensible objects — I don't mean the matter of some, and form in relation to others as clay is matter for the potter yet absolutely speaking not matter, but I do mean matter in relation to every- thing — we ought not to attach to its nature any property perceived in sensible objects. In that case, in addition to qualities like colors and heat and cold, we ought not to attribute to it lightness or heaviness or density or rarity or structure and hence not even extension. For extension is one thing, that which is given extension another, structure one thing, that which is given structure another. It must also not be compound but simple and one in nature. For in this wise is it empty of all at- tributes. And what gives it form will give it a form which is different from and independent of matter, bringing ex- tension and everything else to it from the realm of real existences. Otherwise the formative principle would be conditioned by the extent of matter on hand, and would do not as it wishes but as matter wishes. That its will should coincide with the extent of matter is an absurd supposition. But if the formative principle be prior to 380 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY matter then matter will be entirely such as the principle wishes and will be easily cast into all sorts of forms, and hence into extension. But if it had extension it would also possess a structure, and hence would be more in- tractable. Form then enters into it and brings every- thing to it. The form possesses everything, even ex- tension and everything else which is contained in the seminal reason and exists through its agency. It fol- lows from this that in the case of particular kinds of things their quantity is determined along with their form. For the quantity of a man is different from that of birds, and of this or that bird. It is no more remarkable that quantity should bring a new property to matter than that quality should. Nor could quality be a seminal reason, and quantity, which is measure and number, not a form. ... If,6 however, the substratum were some quality which all the elements had in common, we should have in the first place to say what that quality was, and then to show how a quality could be a substratum, and how quaHty could be seen in the unextended with neither matter nor extension to it ; and yet again, how if quality be determinate it can be matter. On the other hand were it something indeterminate it would not be quality but substratum and the matter which we are looking for. But one may object at this point — granted that matter has no qualities in that its nature is to partake of none, what is still to prevent its being qualified by just this fact, that it partakes of none, and to hinder it from pos- sessing a property in all respects peculiar to itself, and •Plotinus, Enneads, II. 4, § 13, 167 B (C. p. 298, 1. 14; V. I. 162, 1. 8). PLOTINUS 381 from differing from all other qualities in this very point of being an absence or privation of every quality? One who has been deprived of any quality is qualified by his privation, as for example a blind man. If then an absence or privation of qualities be attributed to mat- ter why is it not qualified thereby? And if absolute privation be ascribed to it why is it not even more qualified? That is, of course, if privation be a kind of quality. If, however, a man argue thus, what is he doing but turning everything into qualifications and qualities? Quantity then would be a quality, and essence. But if a thing be qualified, quality is added to it. It is, how- ever, absurd to make a qualified thing of w^hat is different from the qualified and is not qualified. Or do you say that it is qualified by the fact of this difference? But if you mean that matter is sheer absolute difference then it cannot be qualified, since simple quality is not itself a qualified thing. If you mean, on the contrary, that matter is merely different from other things, then it is merely different, not of its own nature but by virtue of difference, and the same by virtue of sameness. Priva- tion then is not quality or a qualified thing, but is a want of quality or of anything else, just as silence is a want of sound or of anything else you please. For privation is negation, and the qualified is found in the sphere of the positive. The peculiar property of matter is not form, but rather not being qualified and not having any form. It is absurd to say that what is not qualified is qualified. That is like saying that a thing has not extension for the very reason that it has. Moreover this peculiar property of matter is nox some- thing different from the essence of matter and is not 382 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY added to it, but lies rather in the relation matter bears to other things, to wit, that it is something different from them. Other things, however, are not merely ''other," but each has an individual form. Matter, on the con- trary, ought properly to be called merely ''an other," or perhaps "other" in the plural, so that you may not de- termine it by using the singular, but by the use of the plural indicate its indeterminate character. . . . * * But ^ if matter be without quality how can it be evil? I reply that it is defined as without quality in the sense that it possesses itself none of those qualities of which it is receptive and which inhere in it as a substratum, but not in the sense that it has no nature. If, however, it have a certain nature, what prevents this nature's being evil? I do not mean evil, as qualified thereby. For quality is that by predication of which something else is qualified. It is then an attribute and is located in a subject other than itself. But matter is not located in a subject different from itself, but is the substratum of which all attributes are predicated. Since then every quality is by nature a predicate, and matter happens to have no predicates, matter is said to be with- out quality. Again if quality is itself unqualified, how could matter which has received no qualities be called qualified? It is correct then to speak of matter both as having no quaUties, and as being evil. For it is not called evil be- cause it has qualities but rather because it has not, lest otherwise it were evil from being form, and not from being the nature opposite to form. 'Plotinus, Enneads, I. 8. § 10, 79 C (C. p. 152; V. I. 110, 1. 8). PLOTINUS 383 Finally ^ how are we to have knowledge of the unex- tended m matter? And how are we to know anything that has no qualities? And what must be the concept thereof, and the starting-point for our reflection? I say, indeterminateness. For if like is known by Uke, then the indeterminate is known by the indeterminate. There might indeed be a definite concept of the indeter- minate, but the point from which we must start toward it is indeterminate. And if each thing be known by means of conception and thought, and here the concept tells what it ought to tell about matter, and still the thought which w^e desire is not a thought but rather the absence thereof, then our representation of matter would be rather a bastard and illegitimate concept, born of the untrue principle of the Other, and mixed with it. Perhaps it is with this in his mind's eye that Plato talks of matter as apprehended by a bastard concept. What, however, is the indeterminateness of the soul? Is it a complete ignorance like an absence of all knowl- edge? No, the indeterminate has a kind of positive- ness, and just as for the eye darkness is the matter of all invisible colors, so the soul when she takes away every- thing from sensible objects as one might take away light, and is left with something which it is no longer possible to define, becomes like the eye in the dark, and finally is in a sense identified with what she sees. AATiat then does she see? Something like formlessness and want of color and absence of light, and also lack of extension. Other- wise this something will present itself in some form or other. But when she sees nothing is she not affected in 'Plotinus, Enneads, II. 4, § 10, 164 D (C. p. 292, 1. 14; V. I. 158, 1. 4). 384 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY the same way? Not at all. For when she sees nothing, she reports nothing, or rather she is not aifected at all. But when she sees matter she is affected as it were by an impression of the formless. And when she thinks of what has form and extension, she thinks of something compound, as colored and as concretely determined. She thinks of the whole, and thinks of it as all belonging together, and her thought or perception of its properties is clear. But her thought of the formless substratum underlying them is obscure, and obscure is the nature of the formless substratum underlying them, for it is with- out form. There is then a residuum in the whole and compound object which is comprehended along with the properties, and is left by reason in its analysis and ab- straction of the properties. And this the soul thinks obscurely as an obscure thing, and darkly as a dark thing, and thinks it by not thinking. But since matter itself does not remain formless but has been given form in concrete things, the soul also immediately adds the form of concrete things to it, being pained by the indeter- minate as if afraid of being beyond the pale of real exist- ence, and not suffering herself to stop long in the realm of not-being. SIN AND SALVATION The ^ soul is not essentially vicious, and again every soul is not vicious. What then is a vicious soul? She, says Plato, who has become the slave of a man whose nature engenders evil in her through the reception of evil and lack of measure and superfluity and deficiency on the part of her irrational form. From these characteris- tics wantonness and cowardice and the rest of the soul's • PlotiQUs, Enneads, I. 8, § 4, 740 (C. p. 141, 1. 3; V. I. 102, 1. 22). PLOTINUS 385 vices arise, as involuntary affections provocative of false opinions and estimations of the good and evil which she shuns and pursues. AVhat, however, is it that is responsible for this viciousness, and after what fashion are we to refer vice to an origin and cause? I reply that in the first place the vicious soul is not outside of matter and is not wholly herself. She is mixed with disproportion, and is without part in the form which brings order and induces proportion. For she is mingled with the body which is material. In the second place, if her reasoning faculty be damaged, her vision is hindered both by her affections, and by being darkened by matter and inclined toward matter, and in general by her looking not toward existence but toward generation. And of transition and generation the nature of matter is the source, a nature so evil that the soul which even looks toward it, though it be not yet in it, is filled with evil. For since matter is wholly without part in the good and is the privation thereof, and pure lack, it makes like to itself everything whatsoever which touches it. The soul, however, which is perfect and ever inclined to the intellect is ever pure and turned from matter, and neither sees nor approaches anything which is indeter- minate, or without measure, or evil. She remains then pure, absolutely determined as she is by the intellect. But if she does not remain so, but goes forth from her- self, then she is on an imperfect and secondary plane of existence, and is a mere shadow of her former self because of her failure in so far as she has failed, and is filled with disproportionateness and sees darkness. At this point she already has hold of matter, seeing what she does not see, just as we talk about '^seeing the dark." 386 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Now 10 often I am roused from the body to my true self, and emerge from all else and enter myself, and be- hold a marvellous beauty, and am particularly persuaded at the time that I belong to a better sphere, and live a supremely good hfe, and become identical with the god- head, and fast fixed therein attain its divine activity, having reached a plane above the whole intelligible realm; and then after this sojourn in the godhead I descend from the intelligible world to the plane of dis- cursive thought. And after I have descended I am at a loss to know how it is that I have done so, and how my soul has entered into my body, in view of the fact that she really is as her inmost nature was revealed, and yet is in the body. ... * * In 11 seeking to learn Plato's teaching concerning our souls, we are forced to inquire in addition into the ques- tion of soul in general, and ask how it comes in the nature of things to have commerce with the body. Also we ought to consider the nature of the universe in which the soul lives. . . . The i^ body of the world, we find, is com- plete and sufficient and self-sufficing, and has nothing in it contrary to nature. Hence it needs but slight ordering, and its soul is eternally as she wishes herself to be, and is without desires or affections. Nothing is absent from her, and nothing is added to her. So it is that Plato says that our soul when in the companionship of that perfect world-soul becomes perfect herself, lives on high and directs the whole universe. Did she not separate herself therefrom and enter into bodies and become the 10 Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 8, § 1, 468 (C. p. 872; V. II. 1. 142). 11 lb., § 2, 470. 12 lb., 470 a PLOTINUS 387 soul of some particular body, she herself like and with the world-soul would easily govern the universe. It is not then under all circumstances an evil thing for the soul to provide the possibility of existence and well- being to a body. For not all providential care of things inferior deprives him who exercises it of living on the best and highest level. . . . * * There ^^ are two ways in which the commerce of the soul with bodies may cause trouble. In the first place it may be a hindrance to thought, and secondly it may fill the soul full of pleasures and desires and griefs. Still neither of these contingencies should occur in the case of a soul that has not sunk into the interior of the body, nor is the soul of a particular body nor has come to be- long to one — a case where rather the body belongs to the soul, and is such as to have no want or deficiency, and hence as not to fill the soul with desires or fears. For nothing to fear occurs to her in connection with such a body, nor does any w^ant of leisure make her incline downw^ard and lead her away from the better and beatific vision. On the contrary the soul of such a body is ever in the higher regions ordering the world with a power free from all care. * * Now,^^ individual souls which are endowed on the one hand with inclination tow^ard the intellect, turning as they do to that which generates them, and on the other possess a power which reaches even to this ter- restrial sphere, just as light both depends on the sun above and yet does not grudge giving itseK to the world " Plotinus, Enneads, IV. 8, § 2, 471 A. »^Ib., 472 A, §4. 888 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY below; individual souls, I say, are without sin so long as they remain with the world-soul in the intelligible world, and in heaven rule things in her company. Like kings associated with the ruler of all things they reign jointly vvith her without descending from their royal thrones. Ajid they are co-regents with her because they are con- joined with her in the same royal state. But if they alter their mode of existence and change from the whole to the part, and take to existing independently and of themselves, and find, so to speak, their association with the world-soul irksome, they revert each to an inde- pendent existence. When they have done this for some time, and have deserted the world-soul and estranged themselves from her through their separation, and no longer regard the intelligible universe, then each be- comes a part and is isolated and weakened and busied Vv^ith many things, and regards the part instead of the whole. And then when each through her separation from the whole has lighted upon some one particular part, and has deserted everything else, and turned to and entered into that one part which is subject to the im- pact and influence of other things, her apostasy from the whole is accomplished, and she directs the individual surrounded as he is by an environment, and is already in contact and concerned with external things, and lives in their presence and has sunk deep into them. Then it is that she is aptly said to have lost her wings and to lie in the bonds of the body — erring as she is from her life of innocence passed in governing the higher world at the side of the world-soul. This prior state is altogether better if she will but return thither, but as it is, she is fallen and fettered, and inasmuch as she exercises her activities through the medium of sense, because pre- 1 PLOTINUS 389 vented in the beginning from exercising them through the intellect, Plato talks of her as buried and in a dark cave. But her return to pure thought when through her recollection of her former state she gets a point of de- parture toward the vision of real existence is called a loosening of her bonds and an ascent to the upper world. For despite her fall the soul has always a higher part. * * The ^^ soul then has naturally a love of God and de- sires to be united with him with the love which a virgin bears to a noble father. But when she has betaken herself to creation, deceived as it were in her nuptials, she exchanges her former love for mortal loA^e, and is bereft of her father and becomes wanton. Still if she begin again to hate the wantonness of earth, she is purified and turns once more to her father and all is well with her. Those to whom this heavenly love is unknown may get some conception of it from earthly love, and what joy it is to obtain possession of what one loves most. Let him then reflect that these objects of his love are mortal and perishable, mere shadows for his love to feed upon, and soon turned to loathly things, because they are not the true beloved, nor our good, nor what we seek; whereas in the higher world we find the true beloved with whom it is possible for us to unite ourselves when we have seized and held it, because it is not clothed with flesh and blood. He who has beheld this beloved knows the truth of what I say, how the soul then receives a new life when she has gone forth to it, and come to it and participated in it, so that in her new condition she knows that the "Plotinus, Enneads, VI. 9, 768 C (C. p. 1406, 1. 10: V. II. 521, 1. 20). 390 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY giver of true life is beside her, and that she needs nothing else. Such an one knows also, however, that we must put all else away, and abide in the beloved alone, and become only it, stripping off all else that wraps us about; and hence that we must hasten to come forth from the things of this world, and be wroth at the bonds which bind us to them, to the end that we may embrace the beloved with all our soul, and have no part of us left with which we do not touch God. It is possible for us even while here in the body to behold both him and our- selves in such wise as it is lawful for us to see. Our- selves we see illumined, full of the light of the intelligible, or rather as that very light itself, pure, without heavi- ness, upward rising. Verily we see ourselves as made, nay, as being God himself. Then it is that we are kin- dled. But when we again sink to earth, we are, as it were, put out. * But ^^ why then do we not remain in the vision? I reply, because we have never wholly come forth from our earthly selves. But there shall come a time for us when the vision will be unbroken, and we are no longer dis- turbed by any unrest of the body. It is not the faculty of vision which is disturbed but some other, when the seer leaves the vision unaccomplished, but deserts not the knowledge which lies in demonstration and belief and the dialectical operation of the soul. The seer and his seeing, however, are no longer reason and reasoning, but su- perior to reason and prior to reason and extraneous to reason, even as is the object of the vision. Now whosoever beholds himself, when he beholds his real self will see it as such a being, or rather he will be " Plotinus, Enneads, VI. 9, S 10. PLOTINUS 391 united with such a being, and feel himself to have be- come such as is wholly simple. Indeed we ought per- haps hardly to say ''he will see himself." Nor should we speak of an object of his vision, if we have to mean thereby a duality of the seer and the seen and do not identify the two as one. It is a bold thing to say, but in the vision a man neither sees, nor if he sees, distinguishes what he sees from himself nor fancies that there are two — the seer and the seen. On the contrary it is by becoming as it were another than himself, and by neither being himself nor belonging to himself that he attains the vision. And having surrendered himself to it he is one with it, as the centre of two circles might coincide. For these centres when they coincide become one, and when the circles are separated there are two centres again. And it is in this sense that we too speak of a difference. It follows that the vision is hard to describe. For how could a man report as something different from himself, what at the time of his vision he did not see as different but as one with himself? This is clearly the intent of that injunction of the mysteries which forbids communication of their secret to the uninitiated. Since it was not communicable it was forbidden to explain the divine secret to any one to whom it had not been vouchsafed to see it of himself. Now since in the vision there were not two, but the seer was made one with the seen, not as with something seen, but as with something made one with himself, he who had been united with it might, if he remembered, have by him some faint image of the divine. He himself was one, with no distinctions within himself either as re- garded himself or outer things. There was no move- ment of any sort in him, nor was emotion or desire of 392 SOURCE BOOK IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY any outer thing present in him after his ascent, no, not any reason or any thought, nor was he himself present to himself, if I may so express it; but as rapt and inspired he rested isolated in his unmoved and untroubled essence, inclining nowhere and not even reflecting upon himself, at rest in all respects, yea, as if he had become rest itself. Nor did he concern himself with the beautiful, but had passed beyond beauty and had transcended the series of virtues as one might penetrate into the interior of the holy of holies, leaving behind in the temple the statues of the gods. And these he would not see again till he came out after having had the vision of what lay within and communion there with what was no statue or image but the divine itself — of which the statues were but second- ary images. And perhaps his experience was not a vision but some other kind of seeing, ecstasy and sim- plification and self-surrender, a yearning to touch and a rest and a thought centred upon being merged in the divine. Perhaps this was his experience if he beheld anything in the holy of holies. Did he look elsewhere, there was nothing there. These are mere figures and only hint to the wise among the prophets of the manner in which that God of whom we spoke is beheld. But the wise priest who reads the riddle aright may when he has entered the sanctuary enjoy the vision there; and even if he has not entered, yet because he has believed the sanctuary to be some- thing invisible and has regarded it as a fountain and a source, he will yet know it as the source of all things, and behold it as such, and be merged with it, by like perceiv- ing like, and will miss no divine thing which the soul is capable of attaining. And before the vision comes, he begs for the remnant and remainder of the vision. But PLOTINUS 393 for him who has transcended all things there remains that which is prior to all things. All that I have said is true, for the nature of the soul never reaches absolute non-existence, but in her descent reaches evil, and in this sense non-existence, but not complete non-existence. And in pursuing the opposite course she reaches no outer object, but herself, and hence she does not dwell in nothing because she is in no outer object, but in herself. But to be in herself and not in ex- istence is to be in God. For a man himself becomes not an essence, but superessential in so far as he clings fast to God. ^Mien now he sees that he has transcended es- sence he is himself an image of God. And when he pro- ceeds out of himself turning from a copy into the original he has reached the goal of his journey. Does he at time fall from the vision, then virtue is aroused within him, and beholding himself adorned in every way, he is again lifted up by the help of virtue to the intelligible world, and thence proceeds through the aid of wisdom back to God. So it is that the life of the gods and of godlike and blessed men is a liberation from the things of earth, a Hfe that takes no joy in them, a flight of the soul isolated from all that exists to the isolation of God. INDEX OF NAMES Alcmseon, 37. Anaxagoras, 4, 48, 49> 97, 118, 229, 244. Anaximander, 3. Anaximenes, 7. Antipater of Tarsus, 272. Antipho, 95. Antisthenes, 145. Apollodorus, 272, 276. Archedemus, 274. Aristippus, 91, 142. Aristotle, 4, 86, 317-368. Boethius, 272. Chrysippus, 269, 271, 272, 274, 275, 276, 277, 378. Cleanthes, 269, 273, 274, 276, 377. Democritus, 48, 58, 59, 315. Diogenes, 143, 147, 274. Empedocles, 43, 48, 229, 247. Epict>etus, 317, 330. Epicurus, 143, 144, 281, 390- 305, 315, 329. Euthydemus, 94. Evenus, 108. Gorgias, 67, 85, 108. Hecatseus, 30. Hecaton, 273. Heraclitus, 38-35. Hippias, 74, 75, 108. Leucippus, 57, 65, 228, 229. Lucretius, 305-316. Marcus Aurelius, 336-339. Melissus, 21, Meno, 85, 101. Parmenides, 11, 21, 57, 170 et seq. Persseus, 275. Phaedrus, 149. Plato, 129, 135, 148-316, 228, 229, 368, 377, 383, 384, 386, 389. Plotinus, 340-393. Plutarch, 278. Posidonius, 273. Prodicus, 74, 76, 108. Protagoras, 67, 68, 78. Pythagoras, 30, 35, 36, 149, 284, 362. Socrates, 1, 86-141, 284, 317, 322, 323, 324, 356, 362, 363. Speusippus, 284. Thales, 1. Theffitetus, 78. Theognis, 267. Timseus, 160. Xenocrates, 284. Xenophanes, 8, 20, 21, 30, 57. Xenophon, 86. Zeno of Citium, 269, 273, 275, 284, 322. Zeno of Elea, 33, 168. 395 t