UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS LIBRARY AT URBANA-C iPAIGN BOOKSTACKi Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign http://www.archive.org/details/pricetakingbehav957mirm o -J*?*??^ i - ' j-. n <-° •5' FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 957 Price Taking Behavior and Trading in Options Leonard J. Mirrnan Nairn Reisman College of Commerce anc Business Aom in istr.nt Ion Bureau of Economic and Business Researcn University of Illinois, Urbara-Cnampaign BEBR FACULTY WORKING PAPER NO. 957 College of Commerce and Business Administration University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign May 1983 Price Taking Behavior and Trading in Options Leonard J. Mirman, Professor Department of Economics Haim Reisman Tulane University We would like to acknowledge the aid of an anonymous referee for remarks helping to clarify the exposition of this paper. Abstract Equilibrium prices of options are abritrage prices in economies in which prices are determined endogenously and all agents are price takers. We show that the price taking assumption in options' markets is unreason- able because by not being a price taker a small agent can gain much. Black and Scholes (1973) considered the problem of option pricing in an economy with two securities. In their model the prices of these securities are given exogenously by (1) B(t) = e rt , S(t) = e at + b w(t) where {W(t); 0<_t<_T} is a standard Brownian Mortion. In this economy it is assumed that traders can trade continously without transaction costs. The Black and Scholes result implies that a generalized option (contingent claim) that pays at date t = T, f(S(T)) dollars, has a unique, reasonable price. One can show that a trader can form a portfolio of the two securities, change this portfolio continously in the interval [0,T], in such a way that buying an additional amount of one security is financed by selling an amount of the other security of equal value (i.e., the trading strategy used is self financing), so that the payoff at date t = T is f(S(T)) dollars with probability one. The value of this portfolio at t = is called the arbitrage price of the claim at date t = 0. A trader in this economy will agree to sell any number of options at prices which are a bit higher than their arbitrage price, knowing that a sure profit can be made by duplicating the cash flow of the option at date t = T by trading continously in the securities 3 and S. Therefore if options are traded in this economy their arbitrage prices will be their equilibrium prices. In the Black and Scholes model it is assumed implicity that the trading in options does not affect the prices of the securities. Since, in this model, the basic securities prices are given exogenously, this assumption is reasonable. However to study the reasonableness as well as the implications of this assumption, a model in which both option prices and security prices are determined endogenously is needed. -2- In this paper we examine the arbitrage method in an economy in which securities prices are the result of the agents efforts to maximize their utility. An example of this type of economy is described by Kreps (1979) or Harrison and Kreps (1979). We shall consider in this paper an economy which is a special case of the economy described by Kreps (1979) . In Kreps (1979) and Harrison and Kreps (1979) an economy in which equi- librium prices of the securities can be given by (1) was developed. In their model all agents are assumed to be price takers. This assumption implies that trading in options does not affect the prices of the securities and also that the equilibrium prices of the options are their arbitrage prices. The assumption that agents are price takers is very strong and inconsistent since it is assumed that the traders are, in all other respects, very sophisticated. Hence one would expect that if prices can be manipulated by options trading these agents will in fact manipulate them. In this paper we consider the problem of whether, in the Harrison- Kreps economy (when a large number of options can be traded) , it is reasonable to assume that agents are price takers believing that prices of the basic securities are determined by (1) . In effect we study whether price taking behavior is reasonable in the sense that by not accepting the "equilibrium" security prices a small agent can gain a lot or even corner the market and thus, in effect, make a pronounced change in the "equilibrium" securities prices . In order to study this question we assume that all agents but one believe that no matter what options they sell, the prices of the basic securities do not change. They are therefore willing to sell any option at a little higher than its arbitrage price on the belief that they can make arbitrage profits. -3- It will be shown that there are certain arbitrarily inexpensive options such that the one remaining agent, by buying one of these options at date t = at its arbitrage price, (or a bit higher) , can gain a lot, to the detriment of those who sold him this option, by not behaving as a price taker after date t = 0. If all agents anticipate this, no agent would sell options at their arbitrage prices, and all agents would want to buy certain options at their arbitrage price (or slightly higher). The key to this argument is that a single agent, investing a small amount of funds, can reap enormous profits, if this agent does not take prices as given. Thus assuming price-taking in a "large-but-finite" economy of this sort is unwarranted. (A similar sort of result is obtained by Hart (1979). Hart shows that when short-selling is permitted in securities markets, firms that are small but not infinites imally small can have large effects on the economy. Hence "price taking" behavior is not appropriate in his model, as well.) Since price taking is shown to be unreasonable, one wonders what is a reasonable way to define equilibrium for such economies. This question is beyond the scope of this paper and will not be discussed. This might be an explanation for the fact that the option pricing model fails to predict prices of options that are well out of the money in real markets. The reason suggested in this paper for the occurrence of this phenomenon is that the behavior of real world traders for well out of the money options is not approximated well by the price taking assumption. In Section 2 we describe an economy which is a special case of the economy described by Kreps. In Section 3 we construct our example. In Section 4 some concluding remarks are made. -4- 2. The Economy Consider an economy with one consumption good that can be consumed only at time t = 1 , with two securities that are actually state contingent claims on the conumption good at t = 1 . A probability space (ft,F,P) is given, and weft represents a state of the world. At time t = 1 , the securities pay P^l.w) = e r , P 2 (1,w) = e a+b W(1 ' w) > where r, a, and b are constants, and W = (W(t); 0<_ t<_1} is a standard Brownian motion on (Q,F,P). Denote by F fc the a algebra generated by (W(u) ; 0£u. rt p /,. \ at + b W(t,w) rr>\ *l(t,w) = e , P 2^» w ^ = © Kd) i Assume agent i can hold at time t, q (t,w) of security j, as long as he is using admissible self-financing trading strategies, as defined in Harrison and Kreps (1979). Agent i will choose an admissible self-financing trading strategy (q 1 ,q 2 ) to maximize U K(1,w)e r + q2(1,w)e a+b W( 1 ' w) ) dP(w), -5- over all the admissible self financing trading strategies, where U, the agent's utility function, is a strictly concave function defined on the real line. We assume further that there exists a function g(h) such that g(h) -*■ as h •*■ and h U(-h" 1 g(h)) -► — , as h + 0. Assume also that prices (2) are equilibrium prices in the sense that N I Qj(t,w) = 1 J * 1,2 0