Return this book on or before the Latest Date stamped below. A charge is made on all overdue books. TT , T T .. U. of I. Library APR 20 194U - “r r . r . - • i i-w‘ VJ r DEC 1 5 DECO 8 1981 ■ JUN o 1 200' 1 17625-S Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2017 with funding from University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign Alternates https://archive.org/details/politicalinstituOOspen Spencer’s Synthetic Philosophy. (1.) FIRST PRINCIPLES I. The Unknowable. II. Laws of the Knowable. (2.) THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. Yol. I. . I. The Data of Biology. 11. The Inductions of Biology. III. The Evolution of Life. . $2.00 (3.) THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. Yol. II. IY. Morphological Development. Y. Physiological Development. YI. Laws of Multiplication. . $2.00 (4.) THE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY. I. The Data of Psychology. II. The Inductions of Psychology. III. General Synthesis. IY. Special Synthesis. Y. Physical Synthesis. Yol. I. . . . $2.00 (5.) THE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY. YI. Special Analysis. YII. General Analysis. YIII. Corollaries. Yol. II. . $2.00 (6.) PRINCIPLES OF SOCIOLOGY. Yol. I. . I. The Data of Sociology. II. The Inductions of Sociology. , v * . III. The Domestic Relations. . $2.00 “(T.) PRINCIPLES OF SOCIOLOGY. Yol. II. I. Ceremonial Institutions * * * * . . . . $1.25 *(8.) PRINCIPLES OF SOCIOLOGY. Yol. III. * * * * (9.) PRINCIPLES OF MORALITY. Yol. I. . I. The Data of Ethics. . * * * * (10.) PRINCIPLES OF MORALITY. Yol. II. * * * * . $1.25 D. APPLETON & CO., Publishers. New York. POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS: BEING PART V OF THE PRINCIPLES OF SOCIOLOGY. (The concluding Portion of Vol. II.) NEW YORK : D. APPLETON AND COMPANY, 1, 3, and 5 BOND STEEET. 1882 . 3 7 " 0 3 ' /WtClvtA.-itv '>v W Qi PREFACE TO PART T. jCHE division of the Principles of Sociology herewith issued, deals with phenomena of Evolution which are, above all others, obscure and entangled. To discover what truths may be affirmed of political organizations at large, is a task beset by difficulties that are at once many and great — difficulties arising from unlikenesses of the various human races, from differences among the modes of life entailed by circum- stances on the societies formed of them, from the numerous contrasts of sizes and degrees of culture exhibited by such societies, from their perpetual interferences with one another’s processes of evolution by means of wars, and from accom- panying breakings-up and aggregations in ever - changing ways. Satisfactory achievement of this task would require the labours of a life. Having been able to devote to it but two years, I feel that the results set forth in this volume must of necessity be full of imperfections. If it be asked why, being thus conscious that far more time and wuder inves- tigation are requisite for the proper treatment of a subject so immense and involved, I have undertaken it, my reply is that I have been obliged to deal with political evolution as a part of the general Theory of Evolution ; and, with due regard to the claims of other parts, could not make a more prolonged preparation. Anyone who undertakes to trace the general laws of transformation wffiich hold throughout all orders of phenomena, must have but an incomplete know- ledge of each order ; since, to acquaint himself exhaustively with any one order, demanding, as it would, exclusive devo- 11 PREFACE. tion of his days to it, would negative like devotion to any of the others, and much more would negative generalization of the whole. Either generalization of the whole ought never to be attempted, or, if it is attempted, it must be by one who gives to each part such time only as is requisite to master the cardinal truths it presents. Believing that generalization of the whole is supremely important, and that no one part can be fully understood without it, I have ventured to treat of Political Institutions after the manner implied : utilizing, for the purpose, the materials which, in the space of fourteen years, have been gathered together in the Descriptive Sociology , and joining with them such further materials as, during the last two years, have been accumulated by inquiries in other directions, made personally and by proxy. If errors found in this volume are such as invalidate any of its leading con- clusions, the fact will show the impolicy of the course I have pursued ; but if, after removal of the errors, the leading conclusions remain outstanding, this course will be justified. Of the chapters forming this volume, the first seven were originally published in the Fortnightly Review in England; and, simultaneously, in monthly periodicals in America, France, and Germany. Chapters VIII and IX were thus published abroad but not at home. Chapters XVII and XVIII appeared here in the Contemporary Review ; and at the same time in the before-mentioned foreign periodicals. The remaining chapters, X, XI, XII, XIII, XIV, XV, XVI, and XIX, now appear for the first time ; with the exception of chapter XI, which has already seen the light in an Italian periodical — La Rivista di Filosofia Scientifica. London , March , 1882. CONTENTS CHAP. I. — PRELIMINARY II. —POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL III. — POLITICAL INTEGRATION IV". — POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION Y. — POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES VI. — POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. VII. — COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS VIII. — CONSULTATIVE BODIES IX. — REPRESENTATIVE BODIES ... X. — MINISTRIES XI. — LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES XII. — MILITARY SYSTEMS XIII. — JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS ... XIV. — LAWS ... XV. — PROPERTY XVI. — REVENUE XVII.— THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY XVIII. — THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY ... XIX. — POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT PAGE ... 229 ... 244 ... 265 ... 288 ... 311 ... 331 v , . 366 „.. 397 ... 415 ... 442 ... 451 ... 473 ... 492 ... 513 ... 538 ... 557 ... 568 ... 603 ... 643 PART Y. POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. PRELIMINARY. § 434. Thought and feeling cannot be completely dis- sociated. Each emotion has a more or less distinct frame- work of ideas; and each group of ideas is more or less suffused with emotion. There are, however, great differences between their degrees of combination under both of these aspects. We have some feelings which are vague from lack of intel- lectual definition ; and others to which clear shapes are given by the associated conceptions. At one time our thoughts are distorted by the passion running through them ; and at another time it is difficult to detect in them a trace of liking or disliking. Manifestly, too, in each particular case these components of the mental state may be varied in their pro- portions. The ideas being the same, the emotion joined with them may be greater or less ; and it is a familiar truth that the correctness of the judgment formed, depends, if not on the absence of emotion, still, on that balance of emotions which negatives excess of any one. Especially is this so in matters concerning human life. There are two ways in which men’s actions, individual or social, may be regarded. We may consider them as groups of phenomena to be analyzed, and the laws of their depen- dence ascertained ; or, considering them as causing pleasures or pains, we may associate with them approbation or repro- bation. Dealing with its problems intellectually, we may 230 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. regard conduct as always the result of certain forces; or, dealing with its problems morally, and recognizing its out- come as in this case good and in that case bad, we may allow now admiration and now indignation to fill our con- sciousness. Obviously, it must make a great difference in our conclusions whether, as in the one case, we study mens doings as those of alien creatures, which it merely concerns us to understand ; or whether, as in the other case, we con- template them as the doings of creatures like ourselves, with whose lives our own lives are bound up, and whose behaviour arouses in us, directly and sympathetically, feelings of love or hate. In an ancillary work, The Study of Sociology , I have de- scribed the various perversions produced in men's judgments by their emotions. Examples are given showing how fears and hopes betray them into false estimates ; how impatience prompts unjust condemnations ; how in this case antipathy, and in that case sympathy, distorts belief. The truth that the bias of education and the bias of patriotism severally warp men’s convictions, is enforced by many illustrations. And it is pointed out that the more special forms of bias — the class bias, the political bias, the theological bias — each originates a predisposition towards this or that view of public affairs. Here let me emphasize the conclusion that in pursuing our sociological inquiries, and especially those on which we are now entering, we must, as much as possible, exclude whatever emotions the facts are calculated to excite, and attend solely to the interpretation of the facts. There are several groups of phenomena in contemplating which either contempt, or disgust, or indignation, tends to arise but must be restrained. § 435. Instead of passing over as of no account, or else regarding as purely mischievous, the superstitions of the primitive man, we must inquire what part they play in PRELIMINARY. 231 social evolution ; and must be prepared, if need be, to re- cognize their usefulness. Already we have seen that the belief which prompts the savage to bury valuables with the corpse and carry food to the grave, has a natural genesis ; that the propitiation of plants and animals, and the “ worship of stocks and stones,” are not gratuitous absurdities ; and that slaves are sacrificed at funerals in pursuance of an idea which seems rational to uninstructed intelligence. Pre- sently we shall have to consider in what way the ghost- theory has operated politically ; and if we should find reason to conclude that it has been an indispensable aid to political progress, we must be ready to accept the conclusion. Knowledge of the miseries which have for countless ages been everywhere caused by the antagonisms of societies, must not prevent us from recognizing the all-important part these antagonisms have played in civilization. Shudder as we must at the cannibalism which all over the world in early days was a sequence of war — shrink as we may from the thought of those immolations of prisoners which have, tens of thousands of times, followed battles between wild tribes — read as we do with horror of the pyramids of heads and the whitening bones of slain peoples left by barbarian invaders — hate, as we ought, the militant spirit which is even now among ourselves prompting base treacheries and brutal ag- gressions ; we must not let our feelings blind us to the proofs that inter-social conflicts have furthered the develop- ment of social structures. Moreover, dislikes to governments of certain kinds must not prevent us from seeing their fitnesses to their circum- stances. Though, rejecting the common idea of glory, and declining to join soldiers and school-boys in applying the epithet “ great ” to conquering despots, we detest despotism — though we regard their sacrifices of their own peoples and of alien peoples in pursuit of universal dominion as gigantic crimes; we must yet recognize the benefits occasionally arising from the consolidations they achieve. Neither the 232 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. massacres of subjects which Roman emperors directed, nor the assassinations of relatives common among potentates in the East, nor the impoverishment of whole nations by the exactions of tyrants, must so revolt us as to prevent appre- ciation of the benefits which have, under certain conditions, resulted from the unlimited power of the supreme man. Nor must the remembrances of torturing implements, and oub- liettes, and victims built into walls, shut out from our minds the evidence that abject submission of the weak to the strong, however unscrupulously enforced, has in some times and places been necessary. So, too, with the associated ownership of man by man. Absolute condemnation of slavery must be withheld, even if w~e accept the tradition repeated by Herodotus, that to build the Great Pyramid relays of a hundred thousand slaves toiled for twenty years ; or even if we find it true that of the serfs compelled to work at the building of St. Petersburg, three hundred thousand perished. Though aware that the un- recorded sufferings of men and women held in bondage are beyond imagination, we must be willing to receive such evidence as there may be that benefits have resulted. In brief, trustworthy interpretations of social arrangements imply an almost passionless consciousness. Though feeling cannot and ought not to be excluded from the mind when otherwise contemplating them, yet it ought to be excluded when contemplating them as natural phenomena to be under- stood in their causes and effects. § 436. Maintenance of this mental attitude will be furthered by keeping before ourselves the truth that in human actions the absolutely bad may be relatively good, and the absolutely good may be relatively bad. Though it has become a common-place that the institutions under which one race prospers will not answer for another, the recognition of this truth is by no means adequate. Men who have lost faith in “ paper constitutions/’ nevertheless PRELIMINARY. 233 advocate such conduct towards inferior races, as implies 4he belief that civilized social forms can with advantage be im- posed on uncivilized peoples ; that the arrangements which seem to us vicious are vicious for them ; and that they would benefit by institutions — domestic, industrial, or political — akin to those which we find beneficial. But acceptance of the truth that the type of a society is determined by the natures of its units, forces on us the corollary that a regime intrinsically of the lowest, may yet be the best possible under primitive conditions. Otherwise stating the matter, we must not substitute our developed code of conduct, which predominantly concerns private relations, for the undeveloped code of conduct, which predominantly concerns public relations. Now that life is generally occupied in peaceful intercourse with fellow-citizens, ethical ideas refer chiefly to actions between man and man ; but in early stages, while the occupation of life was mainly in conflicts with adjacent societies, such ethical ideas as existed referred almost wholly to inter-social actions : men's deeds were judged by their direct bearings on tribal welfare. And since preservation of the society takes precedence of individual preservation, as being a condition to it, we must, in considering social phenomena, interpret good and bad rather in their earlier senses than in their later senses ; and so must regard as relatively good, that 'which furthers sur- vival of the society, great as may be the suffering inflicted on its members. § 437. Another of our ordinary conceptions has to be much widened before we can rightly interpret political evolution. The words “ civilized ” and “ savage ” must have given to them meanings differing greatly from those which are current. That broad contrast usually drawn wholly to the advantage of the men who form large nations, and to the disadvantage of the men who form simple groups, a better knowledge obliges us profoundly to qualify. Characters are to be found 234 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. among rude peoples which compare well with those of the best among cultivated peoples. With little knowledge and but rudimentary arts, there in some cases go virtues which might shame those among ourselves whose education and polish are of the highest. Surviving remnants of some primitive races in India, have natures in which truthfulness seems to be organic. Not only to the surrounding Hindoos, higher intellectually and rela- tively advanced in culture, are they in this respect far superior; but they are superior to Europeans. Of certain of these Hill peoples it is remarked that their assertions may always be accepted with perfect confidence ; which is more than can be said of manufacturers who use false trade-marks, or of diplo- matists who intentionally delude. As having this trait may be named the Santals, of whom Hunter says, “ they were the most truthful set of men I ever met;” and, again, the Sowrahs, of whom Shortt says, “ a pleasing feature in their character is their complete truthfulness. They do not know how to tell a lie.” Noth withstanding their sexual relations of a primitive and low type, even the Todas are described as con- sidering “ falsehood one of the worst of vices.” Though Metz says that they practise dissimulation towards Europeans, yet he recognizes this as a trait consequent on their intercourse with Europeans ; and this judgment coincides with one given to me by an Indian civil servant concerning other Hill tribes, originally distinguished by their veracity, but who are rendered less veracious by contact with the whites. So rare is lying among these aboriginal races when unvitiated by the “ civilized,” that, of those in Bengal, Hunter singles out the Tipperahs as “ the only hill-tribe in which this vice is met with.” Similarly in respect of honesty, some of these peoples classed as inferior read lessons to those classed as superior. Of the Todas just named, ignorant and degraded as they are in some respects, Harkness says, “I never saw a people, civilized or uncivilized, who seemed to have a more religious PRELIMINARY. 235 respect for the rights of meum and tuum ” The Marias (Gonds), “ in common with many other wild races, hear a singular character for truthfulness and honesty.” Among the Khonds “ the denial of a debt is a breach of this principle, which is held to be highly sinful. ‘ Let a man / say they, ‘ give up all he has to his creditors/ ” The Santal prefers to have “ no dealings with his guests ; but when his guests introduce the subject he deals with them as honestly as lie would with his own people : ” “ he names the true price at first.” The Lepchas “are wonderfully honest, theft being scarcely known among them.” And the Bodo and Dhimals are “ honest and truthful in deed and word.” Colonel Dixon dilates on the “ fidelity, truth, and honesty ” of the Carnatic aborigines, who show “ an extreme and almost touching devotion when put upon their honour.” And Hunter asserts of the Chakmas, that “ crime is rare among these primitive people Theft is almost unknown.” So it is, too, with the general virtues of these and sundry other uncivilized tribes. The Santal “ possesses a happy dis- position,” is “ sociable to a fault,” and while the “ sexes are greatly devoted to each other’s society,” the women are “ ex- ceedingly chaste.” The Bodo and the Dhimals are “ full of amiable qualities.” The Lepcha, “ cheerful, kind, and patient,” is described by Dr. Hooker as a most “attractive com- panion ; ” and Dr. Campbell gives “ an instance of the effect of a very strong sense of duty on this savage.” In like manner, from accounts of certain Malayo-Polynesian societies, and certain Papuan societies, may be given instances show- ing in high degrees sundry traits which we ordinarily associate only with a human nature that has been long sub- ject to the discipline of civilized life and the teachings of a superior religion. One of the latest testimonies is that of Signor D’ Albertis, who describes certain Hew Guinea people he visited (near Yule Island) as strictly honest, “ very kind,” “ good and peaceful,” and who, after disputes between villages, “are as friendly as before, bearing no animosity;” but of 236 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. whom the Eev. W. Gf. Lawes, commenting on Signor ©’Albertis’ communication to the Colonial Institute, says that their goodwill to the whites is being destroyed by the whites’ ill-treatment of them : the usual history. Contrariwise, in various parts of the world men of several types yield proofs that societies relatively advanced in organization and culture, may yet be inhuman in their idea's, sentiments, and usages. The Fijians, described by Dr. Pickering as among the most intelligent of unlettered peoples, are among the most ferocious. “ Intense and vengeful malignity strongly marks the Fijian character.” Lying, treachery, theft, and murder, are with them not criminal, but honourable ; infanticide is immense in extent ; strangling the sickly habitual ; and they sometimes cut up while alive the human victims they are going to eat. Nevertheless they have a “ complicated and carefully- conducted political system ; ” well-organized military forces ; elaborate fortifica- tions ; a developed agriculture with succession of crops and irrigation ; a considerable division of labour ; a separate dis- tributing agency with incipient currency ; and a skilled industry which builds canoes that carry three hundred men. Take again an African society, Dahomey. We find there a finished system of classes, six in number; com- plex governmental arrangements with officials always in pairs ; an army divided into battalions, having reviews and sham fights ; prisons, police, and sumptuary laws ; an agri- culture which uses manure and grows a score kinds of plants; moated towns, bridges, and roads with turnpikes. Yet along with this comparatively high social development there goes what we may call organized criminality. Wars are made to get skulls with which to decorate the royal palace ; hundreds of subjects are killed when a king dies ; and great numbers are annually slaughtered to carry messages to the other world. Described as cruel and blood-thirsty, liars and cheats, the people are “void either of sympathy or gratitude, even in their own families;” so that “ not even the appearance PRELIMINARY. 237 of affection exists between husband and wife, or between parents and children.” The New World, too, furnished when it was discovered, like evidence. Having great cities of 120,000 houses, the Mexicans had also cannibal gods, whose idols were fed on warm, reeking, human flesh, thrust into their mouths — wars being made purposely to supply victims for them ; and with skill to build vast and stately temples, there went the immolation of two thousand five hundred persons annually, in Mexico and adjacent towns alone, and of a far greater number throughout the country at- large. Similarly in the populous Central American States, sufficiently civilized to have a developed system of calcula- tion, a regular calendar, books, maps, &c., there were exten- sive sacrifices of prisoners, slaves, children, whose hearts were torn out and offered palpitating on altars, and who, in other cases, were flayed alive and their skins used as dancing- dresses by the priests. Nor need we seek in remote regions or among alien races, for proofs that there does not exist a necessary connexion between the social types classed as civilized and those higher sentiments which we commonly associate with civili- zation. The mutilations of prisoners exhibited on Assyrian sculptures are not surpassed in cruelty by any we find among the most bloodthirsty of wild races ; and Eameses II., who delighted in having himself sculptured on temple-walls throughout Egypt as holding a dozen captives by the hair, and striking off* their heads at a blow, slaughtered during his conquests more human beings than a thousand chiefs of savage tribes put together. The tortures inflicted on cap- tured enemies by Eed Indians are not greater than were those inflicted of old on felons by crucifixion, or on suspected rebels by sewing them up in the hides of slaughtered animals, or on heretics by smearing them over with combustibles and setting fire to them. The Damaras, described as so heartless that they laugh on seeing one of their number killed by a wild beast, are not worse than were the Eomans, who gratified 238 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. themselves by watching wholesale slaughters in their arenas. If the numbers destroyed by the hordes of Attila were not equalled by the numbers which the Roman armies destroyed at the conquest of Selucia, and by the numbers of the Jews massacred under Hadrian, it was simply because the occa- sions did not permit. The cruelties of Hero, Gallienus, and the rest, may compare with those of Zingis and Timour ; and when we read of Caracalla, that after he had murdered twenty thousand friends of his murdered brother, his soldiers forced the Senate to place him among the gods, we are shown that in the Roman people there was a ferocity not less than that which deifies the most sanguinary chiefs among the worst of savages. Nor did Christianity greatly change matters. Throughout Mediaeval Europe, political offences and religious dissent brought on men carefully-devised agonies equalling if not exceeding any inflicted by the most brutal of barbarians. Startling as the truth seems, it is yet a truth to be recog- nized, that increase of humanity does not go on pari passu with civilization ; but that, contrariwise, the earlier stages of civilization necessitate a relative inhumanity. Among tribes of primitive men, it is the more brutal rather than the more kindly who succeed in those conquests which effect the earliest social consolidations ; and through many subsequent stages unscrupulous aggression outside of the society and cruel coercion within, are the habitual concomitants of political development. The men of whom the better organized societies have been formed, were at first, and long continued to be, nothing else but the stronger and more cunning savages ; and even now, when freed from those influences which super- ficially modify their behaviour, they prove themselves to be little better. If, on the one hand, we contemplate the utterly uncivilized Wood-Veddahs, who are described as “ proverbially truthful and honest,” “ gentle and affectionate,” “ obeying the slightest intimation of a wish, and very grateful for attention or assistance,” and of whom Pridham remarks — “ What a lesson in gratitude and delicacy even a Yeddah may teach !” PRELIMINARY. 239 and then if, on the other hand, we contemplate our own recent acts of international brigandage, accompanied by the slaughter of thousands who have committed no wrong against us — accompanied, too, by perfidious breaches of faith and the killing of prisoners in cold blood ; we must admit that be- tween the types of men classed as uncivilized and civilized, the differences are not necessarily of the kinds commonly supposed. Whatever relation exists between moral nature and social type, is not such as to imply that the social man is in all respects emotionally superior to the pre-social man.* § 438. “ How is this conclusion to be reconciled with the conception of progress ? ” most readers will ask. “ How is civilization to be justified if, as is thus implied, some of the highest of human attributes are exhibited in greater degrees by wild people who live scattered in pairs in the woods, than by the members of a vast, well-organized nation, having * What the social man, even of advanced race, is capable of, has been again shown while these lines are standing in type. To justify the destruc- tion of two African towns in Batanga, we are told that their king, wishing to have a trading factory established, and disappointed with the promise of a sub-factory, boarded an English schooner, carried off Mr. Govier, the mate, and refusing to release him when asked, “threatened to cut the man’s head off” : a strange mode, if true, of getting a trading factory established. Mr. Govier afterwards escaped ; not having been ill-treated during his deten- tion. Anchoring the JBoadicea and two gunboats off Kribby’s Town (“Xing Jack’s” residence), Commodore Richards demanded of the king that he should come on board and explain : promising him safety, and threatening serious consequences in case of refusal. Not trusting the promise, the king failed to come. Without ascertaining from the natives whether they had any reason for laying hands on Mr. Govier, save this most improbable one alleged by our people, Commodore Richards proceeded, after some hours’ notice, to clear the beach with shells, to burn the town of 300 houses, to cut down the natives’ crops, and to destroy their canoes ; and then, not satisfied with burning “King Jack’s” town, went further south and burnt “King Long-Long’s” town. These facts are published in the Times of September 10, 1880. In an article on them, this organ of English respectability regrets that “ the punishment must seem, to the childish mind of the savage, wholly disproportionate to the offence:” implying that to the adult mind of the civilized it will not seem disproportionate. Further, this leading journal of ruling classes who hold that, in the absence of established theological dogmas, 240 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. marvellously-elaborated arts, extensive and profound know- ledge, and multitudinous appliances to welfare ? ” The answer to this question will best be conveyed by an analogy. As carried on throughout the animate world at large, the struggle for existence has been an indispensable means to evolution. Not simply do we see that in the competition among individuals of the same kind, survival of the fittest, has from the beginning furthered production of a higher type ; but we see that to the unceasing warfare between species is mainly due both growth and organization. Without univer- sal conflict there would have been no development of the active powers. The organs of perception and of locomotion have been little by little evolved during the inter-action of pursuers and pursued. Improved limbs and senses have furnished better supplies to the viscera, and improved visceral structures have ensured a better supply of aerated blood to the limbs and senses ; while a higher nervous system has at each stage been called into play for co-ordinating the actions of these more complex structures. Among predatory animals death by starvation, and among animals preyed upon death by destruction, have carried off the least-favourably modified individuals and varieties. Every advance in strength, speed, agility, or sagacity, in creatures of the one class, has necessi- tated a corresponding advance in creatures of the other class ; and without never-ending efforts to catch and to escape, with loss of life as the penalty for failure, the progress of neither could have been achieved. there would be no distinction between right and wrong, remarks that “ if it were not for the dark shadow cast over it by this loss of life” [of two of our men], “ the whole episode would be somewhat humorous.” Doubtless, after the “ childish mind of the savage ” has accepted the “glad tidings” brought by missionaries of “ the religion of love,” there is humour, somewhat of the grimmest, perhaps, in showing him the practice of this religion by burning his house. Comments on Christian virtues, uttered by exploding shells, may fitly be accompanied by a Mephistophelian smile. Possibly the king, in declin- ing to trust himself on board an English ship, was swayed by the common Negro belief that the devil is while. PRELIMINARY. 241 Mark now, however, that while this merciless discipline of Nature, “red in tooth and claw” has been essential to the progress of sentient life, its persistence through all time with all creatures must not he inferred. The high organization evolved by and for this universal conflict, is not necessarily for ever employed to like ends. The resulting- power and intelligence admit of being far otherwise employed. Not for offence and defence only are the inherited structures useful, but for various other purposes; and these various other purposes may finally become the exclusive purposes. The myriads of years of warfare which have developed the powers of all lower types of creatures, have bequeathed to the highest type of creature the powers now used by him for countless objects besides those of killing and avoiding being killed. His limbs, teeth and nails are but little employed in fight; and his mind is not ordinarily occupied in devising ways of destroying other creatures, or guarding himself from injury by them. Similarly with social organisms. We must recognize the truth that the struggles for existence between societies have been instrumental to their evolution. Neither the consolida- tion and re-consolidation of small groups into large ones ; nor the organization of such compound and doubly compound groups ; nor the concomitant developments of those aids to a higher life which civilization has brought; would have been possible without inter-tribal and inter-national con- flicts. Social cooperation is initiated by joint defence and offence ; and from the cooperation thus initiated, all kinds of cooperations have arisen. Inconceivable as have been the horrors caused by this universal antagonism which, beginning with the chronic hostilities of small hordes tens of thou- sands of years ago, has ended in the occasional vast battles of immense nations, we must nevertheless admit that with- out it the world would still have been inhabited only by men of feeble types, sheltering in caves and living on wild food. 242 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. But now observe that the inter-social struggle for exist- ence which has been indispensable in evolving societies, will not necessarily play in the future a part like that which it has played in the past. Recognizing our indebtedness to war for forming great communities and developing their structures, we may yet infer that the acquired powers, available for other activities, will lose their original activities. While conceding that without these perpetual bloody strifes, civilized societies could not have arisen, and that an adapted form of human nature, fierce as well as intelligent, was a needful concomitant ; we may at the same time hold that such societies having been produced, the brutality of nature in their units which was necessitated by the process, ceasing to be necessary with the cessation of the process, will disappear. While the benefits achieved during the predatory period remain a permanent inheritance, the evils entailed by it will decrease and slowly die out. Thus, then, contemplating social structures and actions from the evolution point of view, we may preserve that calmness which is needful for scientific interpretation of them, without losing our powers of feeling moral reprobation or approbation. § 439. To these preliminary remarks respecting the mental attitude to be preserved by the student of political institu- tions, a few briefer ones must be added respecting the subject- matters he has to deal with. If societies were all of the same species and differed only in their stages of growth and structure, comparisons would disclose clearly the course of evolution ; but unlikenesses of type among them, here great and there small, obscure the results of such comparisons. Again, if each society grew and unfolded itself without the intrusion of additional factors, interpretation would be rela- tively easy; but the complicated processes of development are frequently re-complicated by changes in the gets of PRELIMINARY. 243 factors. Now the size of the social aggregate is all at once increased or decreased by annexation or by loss of territory ; and now the average character of its units is altered by the coming in of another race as conquerors or as slaves ; while, as a further effect of this event, new social relations are superposed on the old. In many cases the repeated over- runnings of societies by one another, the minglings of peoples and institutions, the breakings up and re-aggregations, so destroy the continuity of normal processes as to make it extremely difficult, if not impossible, to draw conclu- sions. Once more, modifications in the average mode of life pursued by a society, now increasingly warlike and now increasingly industrial, initiate metamorphoses : changed activities generate changes of structures. Consequently there have to be distinguished those progressive re-arrangements caused by the further development of one social type, from those caused by the commencing development of another social type. The lines of an organization adapted to a mode of activity which has ceased, or has been long suspended, begin to fade, and are traversed by the increasingly-definite lines of an organization adapted to the mode of activity which has replaced it; and error may result from mistaking traits belonging to the one for those belonging to the other. Hence we may infer that out of the complex and confused evidence, only the larger truths will emerge with clearness. While anticipating that certain general conclusions are to be positively established, we may anticipate that more special ones can be alleged only as probable. Happily, however, as we shall eventually see, those general conclusions admitting of positive establishment, are the con- clusions of most value for guidance. 2 CHAPTER II. POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. § 440. The mere gathering of individuals into a group does not constitute them a society. A society, in the sociological sense, is formed only when, besides juxtaposition there is co- operation. So long as members of the group do not combine their energies to achieve some common end or ends, there is little to keep them together. They are prevented from sepa- rating only when the wants of each are better satisfied by uniting his efforts with those of others, than they would be if he acted alone. Cooperation, then, is at once that which cannot exist without a society, and that for which a society exists. It may be a joining of many strengths to effect something which the strength of no single man can effect ; or it may be an apportioning of different activities to different persons, who severally participate in the benefits of one another’s activities. The motive for acting together, originally the dominant one, may be defence against enemies ; or it may be the easier ob- tainment of food, by the chase or otherwise ; or it may be, and commonly is, both of these. In any case, however, the units pass from the state of perfect independence to the state of mutual dependence ; and as fast as they do this they become united into a society rightly so called. But cooperation implies organization. If acts are to be effectually combined, there must be arrangements under which they are adjusted in their times, amounts, and characters. § 441. This social organization, necessary as a means to concerted action, is of two kinds. Though these two kinds POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 245 generally co-exist, and are more or less interfused, yet they are distinct in their origins and natures. There is a spon- taneous cooperation which grows up without thought during the pursuit of private ends ; and there is a cooperation which, consciously devised, implies distinct recognition of public ends. The ways in which the two are respectively established and carried on, present marked contrasts. Whenever, in a primitive group, there begins that coopera- tion which is effected by exchange of services — whenever individuals find their wants better satisfied by giving certain products which they can make best, in return for other pro- ducts they are less skilled in making, or not so well circum- stanced for making, there is initiated a kind of organization which then, and throughout its higher stages, results from endeavours to meet personal needs. Division of labour, to the last as at first, grows by experience of mutual facilita,- tions in living. Each new specialization of industry arises from the effort of one who commences it to get profit ; and establishes itself by conducing in some way to the profit of others. So that there is a kind of concerted action, with an elaborate social organization developed by it, which does not originate in deliberate concert. Though within the small sub- divisions of this organization, we find everywhere repeated the relation of employer and employed, of whom the one directs the actions of the other; yet this relation, sponta- neously formed in aid of private ends and continued only at will, is not formed with conscious reference to achievement of public ends : these are not thought of. And though, for regulating trading activities, there arise agencies serving to adjust the supplies of commodities to the demands ; yet such agencies do this not by direct stimulations or restraints, but by communicating information which serves to stimulate or restrain; and, further, these agencies grow up not for the avowed purpose of thus regulating, but in the pursuit of gain by individuals. So unintentionally has there arisen the elaborate division of labour by which production and distri- 246 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. bution are now carried on, that only in modern days has there come a recognition of the fact that it has all along been arising. On the other hand, cooperation for a purpose immediately concerning the whole society, is a conscious cooperation ; and is carried on by an organization of another kind, formed in a different way. When the primitive group has to defend itself against other groups, its members act together under further stimuli than those constituted by purely personal desires. Even at the outset, before any control by a chief exists, there is the control exercised by the group over its members ; each of whom is obliged, by public opinion, to join in the general defence. Very soon the warrior of recognized superiority begins to exercise over each, during war, an in- fluence additional to that exercised by the group ; and when his authority becomes established, it greatly furthers com- bined action. From the beginning, therefore, this kind of social cooperation is a conscious cooperation, and a coopera- tion which is not wholly a matter of choice — is often at variance with private wishes. As the organization initiated by it develops, we see that, in the first place, the fighting division of the society displays in the highest degree these same traits : the grades and divisions constituting an army, cooperate more and more under the regulation, consciously established, of agencies which override individual volitions — or, to speak strictly, control individuals by motives which prevent them from acting as they would spontaneously act. In the second place, we see that throughout the society as a whole there spreads a kindred form of organization — kindred in so far that, for the purpose of maintaining the militant body and the government which directs it, there are esta- blished over citizens, agencies which force them to labour more or less largely for public ends instead of private ends. And, simultaneously, there develops a further organization, still akin in its fundamental principle, which restrains indi- vidual actions in such wise that social safety shall not be POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 247 endangered by the disorder consequent on unchecked pursuit of personal ends. So that this kind of social organization is distinguished from the other, as arising through conscious pursuit of public ends; in furtherance of which individual wills are constrained, first by the joint wills of the entire group, and afterwards more definitely by the will of a regu- lative agency which the group evolves. Most clearly shall we perceive the contrast between these two kinds of organization on observing that, while they are both instrumental to social welfare, they are instrumental in converse ways. That organization shown us by the division of labour for industrial purposes, exhibits combined action ; but it is a combined action which directly seeks and subserves the welfares of individuals, and indirectly subserves the welfare of society as a whole by preserving individuals. Conversely, that organization evolved for governmental and defensive purposes, exhibits combined action ; but it is a com- bined action which directly seeks and subserves the welfare of the society as a whole, and indirectly subserves the wel- fares of individuals by protecting the society. Efforts for self-preservation by the units originate the one form of organization ; while efforts for self-preservation by the aggre- gate originate the other form of organization. In the first case there is conscious pursuit of private ends only ; and the correlative organization resulting from this pursuit of private ends, growing up unconsciously, is without coercive power. In the second case there is conscious pursuit of public ends ; and the correlative organization, consciously established, exercises coercion. Of these two kinds of cooperation and the structures effecting them, we are here concerned only with one. Poli- tical organization is to be understood as that part of social organization which consciously carries on directive and re- straining functions for public ends. It is true, as already hinted, and as we shall see presently, that the two kinds are mingled in various ways — that each ramifies through the 248 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. other more or less according to their respective degrees of predominance. But they are essentially different in origin and nature ; and for the present we must, so far as may be, limit our attention to the last. § 442. That the cooperation into which men have gradually risen secures to them benefits which could not be secured while, in their primitive state, they acted singly; and that, as an indispensable means to this cooperation, political organization has been, and is, advantageous ; we shall see on contrasting the states of men who are not politically organized, with the states of men who are politically organized in less or greater degrees. There are, indeed, conditions under which as good an indi- vidual life is possible without political organization as with it. Where, as in the habitat of the Esquimaux, there are but few persons and these widely scattered ; where there is no war, probably because the physical impediments to it are great and the motives to it feeble ; and where circumstances make the occupations so uniform that there is little scope for division of labour; mutual dependence can have no place, and the arrangements which effect it are not needed. Becog- nizing this exceptional case, let us consider the cases which are not exceptional. The Digger Indians, “ very few degrees removed from the ourang-outang,” who, scattered among the mountains of the Sierra Nevada, sheltering in holes and living on roots and vermin, “ drag out a miserable existence in a state of nature, amid the most loathsome and disgusting squalor/' differ from the other divisions of the Shoshones by their entire lack of social organization. The river-haunting and plain-haunting divisions of the race, under some, though but slight, govern- mental control, lead more satisfactory lives. In South America the Chaco Indians, low in type as are the Diggers, and like them degraded and wretched in their lives, are simi- larly contrasted with the superior and more comfortable POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 249 savages around them in being dissociated. Among the Bedouin tribes, the Sherarat are unlike the rest in being divided and sub-divided into countless bands which have no common chief ; and they are described as being the most miserable of the Bedouins. More decided still is the contrast noted by Baker between certain adjacent African peoples. Passing suddenly, he says, from the unclothed, ungoverned tribes — from the “ wildest savagedom to semi-civilisation ” — we come, in Unyoro, to a country ruled by “an unflinching despot,” inflicting “ death or torture ” for “ the most trivial offences but where they have developed administration, sub-governors, taxes, good clothing, arts, agriculture,, architecture. So, too, concerning New Zealand when first discovered, Cook re- marked that there seemed to be greater prosperity and popu- lousness in the regions subject to a king. These last cases introduce us to a further truth. Not only does that first step in political organization which places individuals under the control of a tribal chief, bring the ad- vantages gained by better cooperation ; but such advantages are increased when minor political heads become subject to a major political head. As typifying the evils which are thereby avoided, I may name the fact that among the Beloo- chees, whose tribes, unsubordinated to a general ruler, are constantly at war with one another, it is the habit to erect a small mud tower in each field, where the possessor and his retainers guard his produce : a state of things allied to, but worse than, that of the Highland clans, with their strongholds for sheltering women and cattle from the inroads of their neighbours, in days when they were not under the control of a central power. The benefits derived from such wider con- trol, whether of a simple head or of a compound head, were felt by the early Greeks when an Amphictyonic council es- tablished the laws that “ no Hellenic tribe is to lay the habi- tations of another level with the ground ; and from no Hellenic city is the water to be cut off during a siege.” How that advance of political structure which unites smaller com- 250 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. munities into larger ones furthers welfare, was shown in our own country when, by the Roman conquest, the incessant fights between tribes were stopped ; and again, in later days, when feudal nobles, becoming subject to a monarch, were de- barred from private wars. Under its converse aspect the same truth was illustrated when, amidst the anarchy which followed the collapse of the Carolingian empire, dukes and counts, resuming their independence, became active enemies to one another : their state being such that " when they were not at war they lived by open plunder.” And the history of Europe has repeatedly, in many places and times, furnished kindred illustrations. While political organization, as it extends itself throughout masses of increasing size, directly furthers welfare by re- moving that impediment to cooperation which the antago- nisms of individuals and of tribes cause, it indirectly furthers it in another way. Nothing beyond a rudimentary division of labour can arise in a small social group. Before commo- dities can be multiplied in their kinds, there must be multi- plied kinds of producers ; and before each commodity can be produced in the most economical way, the different stages in the production of it must be apportioned among special hands. Nor is this all. Neither the required complex com- binations of individuals, nor the elaborate mechanical appli- ances which facilitate manufacture, can arise in the absence of a large community, generating a great demand. § 443. But though the advantages gained by cooperation presuppose political organization, this political organization necessitates disadvantages ; and it is quite possible for these disadvantages to outweigh the advantages. The controlling structures have to be maintained ; the restraints they impose have to be borne ; and the evils inflicted by taxation and by tyranfjy may become greater than the evils prevented. Where, as in the East, the rapacity of monarchs has some- times gone to the extent of taking from cultivators so much POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 251 of their produce as to have afterwards to return part for seed, we see exemplified the truth that the agency which maintains order may cause miseries greater than the miseries caused by disorder. The state of Egypt under the Eomans, who, on the native set of officials superposed their own set, and who made drafts on the country's resources not for local administration only but also for imperial administra- tion, furnishes an instance. Beyond the regular taxes there were demands for feeding and clothing the military, wherever quartered. Extra calls were continually made on the people for maintaining public works and subaltern agents. Men in office were themselves so impoverished by exactions that they “ assumed dishonourable employments or became the slaves, of persons in power.” Gifts made to the government were soon converted into forced contributions. And those who purchased immunities from extortions found them disregarded as soon as the sums asked had been received. More terrible still were the curses following excessive development of political organization in Gaul, during the decline of the Homan empire : — “ So numerous were the receivers in comparison with the payers, and so enormous the weight of taxation, that the labourer broke down, the plains became deserts, and woods grew where the plough had been It were impossible to number the officials who were rained upon every province and town The crack of the lash and the cry of the tortured filled the air. The faithful slave was tortured for evi- dence against his master, the wife to depose against her husband, the son against his sire. .... Not satisfied with the returns of the first enumerators, they sent a succession of others, who each swelled the valuation — as a proof of service done ; and so the imposts went on in- creasing. Yet the number of cattle fell off, and the people died. Nevertheless, the survivors had to pay the taxes of the dead.” And how literally in this case the benefits were exceeded by the mischiefs, is shown by the contemporary statement that “ they fear the enemy less than the tax-gatherer : the truth is, that they fly to the first to avoid the last. Hence the one unanimous wish of the Boman populace, that it was their lot to live with the barbarian.” In the same region during 252 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. later times the lesson was repeated. While internal peace and 'its blessings were achieved in mediaeval France as fast as feudal nobles became subordinate to the king — while the central power, as it grew stronger, put an end to that primitive prac- tice of a blood-revenge which wreaked itself on any relative of an offender, and made the “ truce of God ” a needful miti- gation of the universal savagery ; yet from this extension of political organization there presently grew up evils as great or greater — multiplication of taxes, forced loans, groundless confiscations, arbitrary fines, progressive debasements of coinage, and a universal corruption of justice consequent on the sale of offices : the results being that many people died by famine, some committed suicide, while others, deserting their homes, led a wandering life. And then, afterwards, when the supreme ruler, becoming absolute, controlled social action in all its details, through an administrative system vast in extent and ramifications, with the general result that in less than two centuries the indirect taxation alone “ crossed the enormous interval between 11 millions and 311,” there came the national impoverishment and misery which resulted in the great revolution. Even the present day sup- plies kindred evidence from sundry places. A voyage up the Nile shows every observer that the people are better off where they are remote from the centre of government — that is, where administrative agencies cannot so easily reach them. Nor is it only under the barbaric Turk that this happens. Notwithstanding the boasted beneficence of our rule in India, the extra burdens and restraints it involves, have the effect that the people find adjacent countries preferable: the ryots in some parts have been leaving their homes and settling in the territory of the Nizam and in Gwalior. Not only do those who are controlled suffer from political organization evils which greatly deduct from, and sometimes exceed, the benefits. Numerous and rigid governmental restraints shackle those who impose them, as well as those on whom they are imposed. The successive grades of ruling POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 253 agents, severally coercing grades below, are themselves coerced by grades above ; and even the highest ruling agent is enslaved by the system created for the preservation of his supremacy. In ancient Egypt the daily life of the king was minutely regulated alike as to its hours, its occupations, its ceremonies ; so that, nominally all powerful, he was really less free than a subject. It has been, and is, the same with other despotic monarchs. Till lately in Japan, where the form of organization had become fixed, and where, from the highest to the lowest, the actions of life were prescribed in detail, the exercise of authority was so burdensome that voluntary re- signation of it was frequent: we read that “the custom of abdication is common among all classes, from the Emperor down to his meanest subject.” European states have ex- emplified this re-acting tyranny. “ In the Byzantine palace,” says Gibbon, “ the Emperor was the first slave of the cere- monies he imposed.” Concerning the tedious court life of Louis XIV., Madame de Maintenon remarks — “ Save those only who fill the highest stations, I know of none more un- fortunate than those who envy them. If you could only form an idea of what it is ! ” So that while the satisfaction of men’s wants is furthered both by the maintenance of order and by the formation of aggregates large enough to permit extensive division of labour, it is hindered both by great deductions from the products of their actions, and by the restraints imposed on their actions — usually in excess of the needs. And political control in- directly entails evils on those who exercise it as well as on those over whom it is exercised. § 444. The stones composing a house cannot be otherwise used until the house has been pulled down. If the stones are united by mortar, there must be extra trouble in destroy- ing their present combination before they can be re-combined. And if the mortar has had centuries in which to consolidate, the breaking up of the masses formed is a matter of such 254 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. difficulty, that building with new materials becomes more economical than rebuilding with the old. I name these facts to illustrate the truth that any arrange- ment stands in the way of re-arrangement; and that this must be true of organization, which is one kind of arrange- ment. When, during the evolution of a living body, its com- ponent substance, at first relatively homogeneous, has been transformed into a combination of heterogeneous parts, there results an obstacle, always great and often insuperable, to any considerable further change : the more elaborate and defi- nite the structure the greater being the resistance it opposes to alteration. And this, which is conspicuously true of an individual organism, is true, if less conspicuously, of a social organism. Though a society, formed of discrete units, and not having had its type fixed by inheritance from countless like societies, is much more plastic, yet the same principle holds. As fast as its parts are differentiated — as fast as there arise classes, bodies of functionaries, established administra- tions, these, becoming coherent within themselves and with one another, struggle against such forces as tend to modify them. The conservatism of every long-settled institution daily exemplifies this law. Ee it in the antagonism of a church to legislation interfering with its discipline ; be it in the opposition of an army to abolition of the purchase- system ; be it in the disfavour with which the legal profes- sion at large has regarded law-reform ; we see that neither in their structures nor in their modes of action, are parts that have once been specialized easily changed. As it is true of a living body that its various acts have as their common end self-preservation, so is it true of its com- ponent organs that they severally tend to preserve them- selves in their integrity. And, similarly, as it is • true of a society that maintenance of its existence is the aim of its combined actions, so it is true of its separate classes, its sets of officials, its other specialized parts, that the dominant aim of each is to maintain itself. Not the function to be per- POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 255 formed, but the sustentation of those who perform the func- tion, becomes the object in view : the result being that when the function is needless, or even detrimental, the structure still keeps itself intact as long as it can. In early days the history of the Knights Templars furnished an illustration of this tendency. Down to the present time we have before us the familiar instance of trade-guilds in London, which having ceased to perform their original duties, nevertheless jealously defend their possessions and privileges. The con- vention of Koyal Burghs in Scotland, which once regulated the internal municipal laws, still meets annually though it has no longer any work to do. And the accounts given in The Black Book of the sinecures which survived up to recent times, yield multitudinous illustrations. The extent to which an organization resists reorganization, we shall not fully appreciate until we observe that its resist- ance increases in a compound progression. For while each new part is an additional obstacle to change, the formation oOt ^ involves a deduction from the forces causing change. If, other things remaining the same, the political structures of a society are further developed — if existing institutions are extended or fresh ones set up — if for directing social activities in greater detail, extra staffs of officials are appointed ; the simultaneous results are — an increase in the aggregate of those who form the regulating part, and a corresponding de- crease in the aggregate of those who form the part regulated. In various ways all who compose the controlling and adminis- trative organization, become united with one another and separated from the rest. Whatever be their particular duties, they are similarly related to the governing centres of their departments, and, through them, to the supreme govern- ing centre ; and are habituated to like sentiments and ideas respecting the set of institutions in which they are incorpo- rated. Deceiving their subsistence through the national revenue, they tend towards kindred views and feelings respecting the raising of such revenue. Whatever jealousies 256 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. there may be between their divisions, are over-ridden by sympathy when any one division has its existence or privi- leges endangered; since the interference with one division may spread to others. Moreover, they all stand in similar relations to the rest of the community, whose actions are in one way or other superintended by them ; and hence are led into allied beliefs respecting the need for such superin- tendence and the propriety of submitting to it. No matter what their previous political opinions may have been, men cannot become public agents of any kind without being biassed towards opinions congruous with their functions. So that, inevitably, each further growth of the instrumentalities which control, or administer, or inspect, or in any way direct social forces, increases the impediment to future modifica- tions, both positively by strengthening that which has to be modified, and negatively, by weakening the remainder ; until at length the rigidity becomes so great that change is impos- sible and the type becomes fixed. Nor does each further development of political organization increase the obstacles to change, only by increasing the power of the regulators and decreasing the power of the regulated. For the ideas and sentiments of a community as a whole, adapt themselves to the regime familiar from child- hood, in such wise that it comes to be looked upon as natural. In proportion as public agencies occupy a larger space in daily experience, leaving but a smaller space for other agencies, there comes a greater tendency to think of public control as everywhere needful, and a less ability to conceive of activities as otherwise controlled. At the same time the sentiments, adjusted by habit to the regulative machinery, become enlisted on its behalf, and adverse to the thought of a vacancy to be made by its absence. In brief, the general law that the social organism and its units act and re-act until congruity is reached, implies that every further extension of political organization increases the obstacle to re-organiza- tion, not only by adding to the strength of the regulative APOLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. f 257 part, and taking from the strength of the^part reg&ted, but also by producing in citizens thoughts apd feelings < in harmony with the resulting structure, and out/ of har- mony with anything substantially different. ■ . „ Both France and Germany exemplify this truth. M. Comte, whlRT ' looking forward to an industrial state, was so swayed by the conceptions and likings appropriate to the French form of society, that his scheme of organization for the ideal future, prescribes arrangements characteristic of the militant type, and utterly at variance with the industrial type. Indeed, he had a profound aversion to that individualism which is a product of industrial life and gives the character to industrial institutions. So, too, in Germany, we see that the socialist party, who are regarded and who regard them- selves as wishing to re-organize society entirely, are so in- capable of really thinking away from the social type under which they have been nurtured, that their proposed social system is in essence nothing else than a new form of the system they would destroy. It is a system under which life and labour are to be arranged and superintended by public instrumentalities, omnipresent like those which already exist and no less coercive : the individual having his life even more regulated for him than now. While, then, the absence of settled arrangements negatives cooperation, yet cooperation of a higher kind is hindered by the arrangements which facilitate cooperation of a lower kind. Though without established connexions among parts, there can be no combined actions ; yet the more extensive and elaborate such connexions grow, the more difficult does it become to make improved combinations of actions. There is an increase of the forces which tend to fix, and a decrease of the forces which tend to unfix ; until the fully-structured social organism, like the fully-structured individual organism, becomes no longer adaptable. § 445. In a living animal, formed as it is of aggregated 258 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. units originally like in kind, the progress of organization im- plies, not only that the units composing each differentiated part severally maintain their positions, but also that their progeny succeed to those positions. Bile-cells which, while performing their functions, grow and give origin to new bile- cells, are, when they decay and disappear, replaced by these : the cells descending from them do not migrate to the kid- neys, or the muscles, or the nervous centres, to join in the performance of their duties. And, evidently, unless the specialized units each organ is made of, produced units simi- larly specialized, which remained in the same place, there could be none of those settled relations among parts which characterize the organism, and fit it for its particular mode of life. In a society also, establishment of structure is favoured by the transmission of positions and functions through successive generations. The maintenance of those class-divisions which arise as political organization advances, implies the inherit- ance of a rank and a place in each class. The like happens with those sub-divisions of classes which, in some societies, constitute castes, and in other societies are exemplified by in- corporated trades. Where custom or law compels the sons of each worker to follow their father’s occupation, there result among the industrial structures obstacles to change analogous to those which result in the regulative structures from im- passable divisions of ranks. India shows this in an extreme degree ; and in a less degree it was shown by the craft-guilds of early days in England, which facilitated adoption of a craft by the children of those engaged in it, and hindered adoption of it by others. Thus we may call inheritance of position and function, the principle of fixity in social organization. There is another way in which succession by inheritance, whether to class-position or to occupation, conduces to stability. It secures supremacy of the elder ; and supremacy of the elder tends towards maintenance of the established order. A system under which a chief-ruler, sub-ruler, head of POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 259 clan or house, official, or any person having the power given by rank or property, retains his place until at death it is filled by a descendant, in conformity with some accepted rule of succession, is a system under which, by implication, the young, and even the middle-aged, are excluded from the con- duct of affairs. So, too, where an industrial system is such that the son, habitually brought up to his father’s business, cannot hold a master’s position till his father dies, it follows that the regulative power of the elder over the processes of production and distribution, is scarcely at all qualified by the power of the younger. Now it is a truth daily exemplified, that increasing rigidity of organization, necessitated by the process of evolution, produces in age an increasing strength of habit and aversion to change. Hence it results that suc- cession to place and function by inheritance, having as its necessary concomitant a monopoly of power by the eldest, involves a prevailing conservatism ; and thus further insures maintenance of things as they are. Conversely, social change is facile in proportion as men’s places and functions are determinable by personal qualities. Members of one rank who establish themselves in another rank, in so far directly break the division between the ranks ; and they indirectly weaken it by preserving their family relations with the first, and forming new ones with the second ; while, further, the ideas and sentiments pervading the two ranks, previously more or less different, are made to qualify one another and to work changes of character. Similarly if, between sub-divisions of the producing and dis- tributing classes, there are no barriers to migration, then, in proportion as migrations are numerous, influences physical and mental, following inter-fusion, alter the natures of their units ; at the same time that they check the establishment of differences of nature caused by differences of occupation. Such transpositions of individuals between class and class, or group and group, must, on the average, however, depend on the fitnesses of the individuals for their new places and duties. 260 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Intrusions will ordinarily succeed only where the intruding citizens have more than usual aptitudes for the businesses they undertake. Those who desert their original functions, are at a disadvantage in the competition with those whose functions they assume ; and they can overcome this disad- vantage only by force of some superiority : must do the new thing better than those born to it, and so tend to improve the doing of it by their example. This leaving of men to have their careers determined by their efficiencies, we may therefore call the principle of change in social organization. As we saw that succession by inheritance conduces in a secondary way to stability, by keeping authority in the hands of those who by age are made most averse to new practices, so here, conversely, we may see that succession by efficiency conduces in a secondary way to change. Both positively and negatively the possession of power by the young facilitates innovation. While the energies are overflowing, little fear is felt of those obstacles to improvement and evils it may bring, which, when energies are failing, look formidable ; and at the same time the greater imaginativeness that goes along with higher vitality, joined with a smaller strength of habit, facili- tates acceptance of fresh ideas and adoption of untried methods. Since, then, where the various social positions come to be respectively filled by those who are experimentally proved to be the fittest, the relatively young are permitted to exercise authority, it results that succession by efficiency furthers change in social organization, indirectly as well as 1 ’ ectly. Contrasting the two, we thus see that while the acquire- ment of function by inheritance conduces to rigidity of struc- ture, the acquirement of function by efficiency conduces to plasticity of structure. Succession by descent favours the maintenance of that which exists. Succession by fitness favours transformation, and makes possible something better. § 446. As was pointed out in § 228, “ complication of POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 2G1 structure accompanies increase of mass,” in social organisms as in individual organisms. When small societies are com- pounded into a larger society, the controlling agencies needed in the several component societies must be subordinated to a central controlling agency : new structures are required. Ee- compounding necessitates a kindred further complexity in the governmental arrangements ; and at each of such stages of increase, all other arrangements must become more com- plicated. As Puruy remarks — “By becoming a world in place of a town, Eome could not conserve institutions esta- blished for a single city and a small territory. . . . How was it possible for sixty millions of provincials to enter the narrow and rigid circle of municipal institutions V The like holds where, instead of extension of territory, there is only increase of population. The contrast between the simple administrative system which sufficed in old English times for a million people, and the complex administrative system at present needed for many millions, sufficiently indicates this general truth. But now, mark a corollary. If, on the one hand, further growth implies more complex structure, on the other hand, changeableness of structure is a condition to further growth ; and, conversely, unchangeableness of structure is a concomi- tant of arrested growth. Like the correlative law just noted, this law is clearly seen in individual organisms. Necessarily, transition from the small immature form to the large mature form in a living creature, implies that all the parts have to be changed in their sizes and connexions: every detail of every organ has to be modified ; and this implies the retention of plasticity. Necessarily, also, when, on approaching maturity, the organs are assuming their final arrangement, their increasing definiteness and firmness con- stitute an increasing impediment to growth : the un-building and re-building required before there can be re-adjustment, become more and more difficult. So is it with a society. Augmentation of its mass necessitates change of the pre- 262 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. existing structures, either by incorporation of the increment with them, or by their extension through it. Every further elaboration of the arrangements entails an additional obstacle to this ; and when rigidity is reached, such modifications of them as increase of mass would involve, are impossible, and increase is prevented. Nor is this all. Controlling and administrative instru- mentalities antagonize growth by absorbing the materials for growth. Already when pointing out the evils which accom- pany the benefits gained by political organization, this effect has been indirectly implied. Governmental expenditure, there represented as deducting from the lives of producers by taking away their produce, has for its ulterior result de- ducting from the life of the community : depletion of the units entails depletion of the aggregate. Where the abstrac- tion of private means for public purposes is excessive, the impoverishment leads to decrease of population ; and where it is less excessive, to arrest of population. Clearly those members of a society who form the regulative parts, together with all their dependents, have to be supplied with the means of living by the parts which carry on the processes of pro- duction and distribution ; and if the regulative parts go on increasing relatively to the other parts, there must eventually be reached a point at which they absorb the entire surplus, and multiplication is stopped by innutrition. Hence a significant relation between the structure of a society and its growth. Organization in excess of need, pre- vents the attainment of that larger size and accompanying higher type which might else have arisen. § 447. To aid our interpretations of the special facts presently to be dealt with, we must keep in mind the fore- going general facts. They may be summed up as fol- lows : — Cooperation is made possible by society, and makes society POLITICAL ORGANIZATION IN GENERAL. 263 possible. It pre-supposes associated men ; and men remain associated because of the benefits cooperation yields them. But there cannot be concerted actions without agencies by which actions are adjusted in their times, amounts, and kinds; and the actions cannot be of various kinds without the co- operators undertaking different duties. That is to say, the cooperators must become organized, either voluntarily or involuntarily. The organization which cooperation implies, is of two kinds, distinct in origin and nature. The one, arising directly from the pursuit of individual ends, and indirectly conducing to social welfare, develops unconsciously and is non-coercive. The other, arising directly from the pursuit of social ends, and indirectly conducing to individual welfare, develops consciously and is coercive. While, by making cooperation possible, political organiza- tion achieves benefits, deductions from these benefits are entailed by the organization. Maintenance of it is costly ; and the cost may become a greater evil than the evils escaped. It necessarily imposes restraints ; and these restraints may become so extreme that anarchy, with all its miseries, is preferable. An established organization is an obstacle to re-organiza- tion. Self-sustentation is the primary aim of each part as of the whole ; and hence parts once formed tend to continue, whether they are or are not useful. Moreover, each addition to the regulative structures, implying, other things equal, a simultaneous deduction from the rest of the society which is regulated, it results that while the obstacles to change are increased, the forces causing change are decreased. Maintenance of a society’s organization implies that the units forming its component structures shall severally be re- placed as they die. Stability is favoured if the vacancies they leave are filled without dispute by descendants ; while change is favoured if the vacancies are filled by those who 264 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. are experimefn tally proved to be best fitted for them. Suc- cession by inheritance is thus the principle of social rigidity ; while succession by efficiency is the principle of social plasticity. Though, to make cooperation possible, and therefore to facilitate social growth, there must be organization, yet the organization formed impedes further growth; since further growth implies re-organization, which the existing organiza- tion resists ; and since the existing organization absorbs part of the material for growth. So that while, at each stage, better immediate results may be achieved by completing organization, they must be at the expense of better ultimate results. CHAPTER III. POLITICAL INTEGRATION. § 448. Tiie analogy between individual organisms and social organisms, which holds in so many respects, holds in respect to the actions which cause growth. We shall find it instructive to glance at political integration in the light of this analogy. Every animal sustains itself and grows by incorporating either the materials composing other animals or those com- posing plants ; and from microscopic protozoa upwards, it has been through success in the struggle thus to incorporate, that animals of the greatest sizes and highest structures have been evolved. This process is carried on by creatures of the lowest kinds in a purely physical or insentient way. Without nervous system or fixed distribution of parts, the rhizopod draws in fragments of nutritive matter by actions which we are obliged to regard as unconscious. So is it, too, with simple aggregates formed by the massing of such minute creatures. The sponge, for example, in that framework of fibres familiar to us in its dead state, holds together, when living, a multitude of separate monads ; and the activities which go on in the sponge, are such as directly further the separate lives of these monads, and indirectly further the life of the whole: the whole having neither sentiency nor power of movement. At a higher stage, however, the process of taking in nutritive materials by a composite organism, 266 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. comes to be carried on in a sentient way, and in a way differing from the primitive way in this, that it directly furthers the life of the whole, and indirectly furthers the lives of the component units. Eventually, the well-consoli- dated and organized aggregate, which originally had no other life than was constituted by the separate lives of these minute creatures massed together, acquires a corporate life predominating over their lives ; and also acquires desires by which its activities are guided to acts of incorporation. To which add the obvious corollary that as, in the course of evolution, its size increases, it incorporates with itself larger and larger aggregates as prey. Analogous stages may be traced in the growth of social organisms, and in the accompanying forms of action. At first there is no other life in the group than that seen in the lives of its members ; and only as organization increases does the group as a whole come to have that joint life constituted by mutually-dependant actions. The members of a primi- tive horde, loosely aggregated, and without distinctions of power, cooperate for immediate furtherance of individual sustentation, and in a comparatively small degree for corpo- rate sustentation. Even when, the interests of all being simultaneously endangered, they simultaneously fight, they still fight separately — their actions are uncoordinated ; and the only spoils of successful battle are such as can be indi- vidually appropriated. Eut in the course of the struggles for existence between groups thus unorganized, there comes, with the development of such political organization as gives tribal individuality, the struggle to incorporate one another, first partially and then wholly. Tribes which are larger, or better organized, or both, conquer adjacent tribes and annex .them, so that they form parts of a compound whole. And as political evolution advances, it becomes a trait of the larger and stronger societies that they acquire appetites prompting them to subjugate and incorporate weaker societies. Full perception of this difference will be gained on looking POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 267 more closely at the contrast between the wars of small groups and those of large nations. As, even among dogs, the fights that arise between individuals when one attempts to take another's food, grow into fights between packs if one tres- passes upon the feeding haunts of another (as is seen in Constantinople) ; so among primitive men, individual con- flicts for food pass into conflicts between hordes, when, in pursuit of food, one encroaches on another’s territory. After the pastoral state is reached, such motives continue with a difference. “ Eetaliation for past robberies," is the habitual plea for war among the Bechuanas : “ their real object being always the acquisition of cattle." Similarly among European peoples in ancient days. Achilles says of the Trojans — “ They are blameless as respects me, since they have never driven away my oxen, nor my horses." And the fact that in Scotland during early times, cattle-raids were habitual causes of inter- tribal fights, shows us how persistent have been these struggles for the means of individual sustentation. Even where the life is agricultural, the like happens at the outset. “ A field or a farrow’s breadth of land is disputed upon the border of a district, and gives rise to rustic strife between the parties and their respective hamlets," says Macpherson of the Khonds; and “ should the tribes to which the disputants belong be disposed to hostility, they speedily embrace the quarrel." So that competition in social growth is still re- stricted to competition for the means to that personal welfare indirectly conducive to social growth. In yet another way do we see exemplified this general truth. The furthering of growth by that which furthers the multiplication of units, is shown us in the stealing of women — a second cause of primitive war. Men of one tribe who abduct the women of another, not only by so doing directly increase the number of their own tribe, but, in a greater degree, indirectly conduce to its increase by after- wards adding to the number of children. In which mode of growing at one another’s expense, common among existing 3 268 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. tribes of savages, and once common among tribes from which civilized nations have descended, we still see the same trait : any augmentation of the group which takes place, is an indi- rect result of individual appropriations and reproductions. Contrariwise, in more advanced stages the struggle between societies is, not to appropriate one another’s means of sus- tentation and multiplication, but to appropriate one another bodily. Which society shall incorporate other societies with itself, becomes the question. Under one aspect, the history of large nations is a history of successes in such struggles ; and down to our own day nations are being thus enlarged. Part of Italy is incorporated by France ; part of France is incorporated by Germany ; part of Turkey is incorporated by Russia ; and between Russia and England there appears to be a competition -which shall increase most by absorbing uncivilized and semi-civilized peoples. Thus, then, with social organisms as with individual organisms, it is through the struggle for existence, first, by appropriating one another’s means of growth, and then by devouring one another, that there arise those great aggre- gates which at once make possible high organization, and require high organization. § 449. Political integration is in some cases furthered, and in other cases hindered, by conditions, external and internal. There are the characters of the environment, and there are the characters of the men composing the society. We will glance at them in this order. How political integration is prevented by an inclemency of climate, or an infertility of soil, which keeps down popu- lation, was shown in §§ 14 — 21. To the instances there named may be added that of the Seminoles, who “ being so thinly scattered over a barren desert, they seldom assemble to take black drink, or deliberate on public matters and, again, that of certain Snake Indians, of whom Schoolcraft says, “ the paucity of game in this region is, I have little POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 269 doubt, tlie cause of the almost entire absence of social organi- zation ” We saw, too, that great uniformity of surface, of mineral products, of flora, of fauna, are impediments ; and that on the special characters of the flora and fauna, as con- taining species favourable or unfavourable to human welfare, in part depends the individual prosperity required for social growth. It was also pointed out that structure of the habitat, as facilitating or impeding communication, and as rendering escape easy or hard, has much to do with the size of the social aggregate formed. To the illustrations before given, showing that mountain-haunting peoples and peoples living in deserts and marshes are difficult to consolidate, while peoples penned in by barriers are consolidated with facility, I may here add two significant ones not before noticed. One occurs in the Polynesian islands — Tahiti, Hawaii, Tonga, Samoa, and the rest — where, restrained within limits by surrounding seas, the inhabitants have become united more or less closely into aggregates of con- siderable sizes. The other is furnished by ancient Peru, where, before the time of the Tncas, semi-civilized com- munities had been formed in valleys separated from each other “ on the coast, by hot, and almost impassable deserts, and in the interior by lofty mountains, or cold and trackless 'punas!' And to the implied inability of these peoples to escape governmental coercion, thus indicated by Squier as a factor in their civilization, is ascribed, by the ancient Spanish writer Cieza, the difference between them and the neighbour- ing Indians of Popoyan, who could retreat, “ whenever attacked, to other fertile regions.” How, conversely, the massing of men together is furthered by ease of internal communication within the area occupied, is sufficiently mani- fest. The importance of it is implied by the remark of Grant concerning Equatorial Africa, that “no jurisdiction extends over a district which cannot be crossed in three or four days,” And such facts, implying that political integra- tion may increase as the means of going from place to place 270 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. become better, remind us how, from Roman times down- wards, the formation of roads has made larger social aggre- gates possible. Evidence that a certain type of physique is requisite, was given in § 16 ; where we saw that the races which have evolved large societies, had previously lived under conditions fostering vigour of constitution. I will here add only that the constitutional energy needed for continuous labour, with- out which there cannot be civilized life and the massing of men presupposed by it, is an energy not to be quickly acquired ; but is to be acquired only by inherited modifica- tions slowly accumulated. Good evidence that in lower types of men there is a physical incapacity for work, is supplied by the results of the Jesuit government over the Paraguay Indians. These Indians were reduced to indus- trious habits, and to an orderly life which was thought by many writers admirable ; but there eventually resulted a fatal evil: they became infertile. Not improbably, the infertility commonly observed in savage races that have been led into civilized activities, is consequent on taxing the physique to a degree greater than it is constituted to bear. Certain moral traits which favour, and others which hinder, the union of men into large groups, were pointed out when treating of “ The Primitive Man — Emotional.” Here I will re-illustrate such of these as concern the fitness or unfitness of the type for subordination. “ The Abors, as they them- selves say, are like tigers, two cannot dwell in one den;” and “ their houses are scattered singly, or in groups of two and three.” Conversely, some of the African races not only yield when coerced but admire one who coerces them. Instance the Damaras, who, as Galton says, “ court slavery” and “ follow a master as spaniels would.” The like is alleged of other South Africans. One of them said to a gentleman known to me — “ You’re a pretty fellow to be a master ; I’ve been with you two years and you’ve never beaten me once.” Obviously on the dispositions thus strongly contrasted, the POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 271 impossibility or possibility of political integration largely depends. There must be added, as also influential, the presence or the absence of the nomadic instinct. Varieties of men whose wandering habits have been unchecked during countless generations of hunting life and pastoral life, show us that even when forced into agricultural life, their tendency to move about greatly hinders aggregation. It is thus among the hill-tribes of India. “ The Kookies are naturally a mi- gratory race, never occupying the same place for more than two or, at the utmost, three years and the like holds of the Mishmees, who “ never name their villages the existence of them being too transitory. In some races this migratory instinct survives and shows its effects, even after the forma- tion of populous towns. Writing of the Bachassins in 1812, Burchell says that Litakun, containing 15,000 inhabitants, had been twice removed during a period of ten years. Clearly, peoples thus characterized are less easily united into large societies than peoples who love their early homes. Concerning the intellectual traits which aid or impede the cohesion of men into masses, I may supplement what was said when delineating u The Primitive Man — Intellectual,” by two corollaries of much significance. Social life being co- operative life, presupposes not only an emotional nature fitted for cooperation, but also such intelligence as perceives the benefits of cooperation, and can so regulate actions as to effect it. The unreflectiveness, the deficient consciousness of causation, and the lack of constructive imagination, shown by the uncivilized, hinder combined action to a degree difficult to believe until proof is seen. Even the semi-civilized exhibit in quite simple matters an absence of concert which is astonishing.* Implying, as this does, that cooperation can * The behaviour of Arab boatmen on the Nile displays, in a striking way, this inability to act together. When jointly hauling at a rope, and begin- ning to chant, the inference one draws is that they pull in time with their words. On observing, however, it turns out that their efforts are not com- bined at given intervals, but are put forth without any unity of rhythm. Similarly when using their poles to push the dahabeiah off a sand-bank, the 272 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. at first be effective only where there is obedience to peremp- tory command, it follows that there must be not only an emotional nature which produces subordination, but also an intellectual nature which produces faith in a commander. That credulity which leads to awe of the capable man as a pos- sessor of supernatural power, and which afterwards,- causing dread of his ghost, prompts fulfilment of his remembered injunctions — that credulity which initiates the religious con- trol of a deified chief, re-inforcing the political control of his divine descendant, is a credulity which cannot be dispensed with during early stages of integration. Scepticism is fatal while the character, moral and intellectual, is such as to necessitate compulsory cooperation. Political integration, then, hindered in many regions by environing conditions, has in many races of mankind been prevented from advancing far by unfitnesses of nature — phvsical, moral, and intellectual. § 450. Besides fitness of nature in the united individuals, social union requires a considerable homogeneity of nature among them. At the outset this needful likeness of kind is insured by greater or less kinship in blood. Evidence meets us everywhere among the uncivilized. Of the Bushmen, Lichtenstein says, “families alone form associations in single small hordes — sexual feelings, the instinctive love to children, or the customary attachment among relations, are the only ties that keep them in any sort of union.” Again, “the Ptock Yeddahs are divided into small clans or families asso- ciated for relationship, who agree in partitioning the forest succession of grunts they severally make, is so rapid that it is manifestly impossible for them to give those effectual united pushes which imply appreciable intervals of preparation. Still more striking is the want of con- cert shown by the hundred or more Nubians and Arabs employed to drag the vessel up the rapids. There are shoutings, gesticulations, divided actions, utter confusion ; so that only by accident does it at length happen that a sufficient number of efforts are put forth at the same moment. As was said to me, with some exaggeration, by our Arab dragoman, a travelled man — “ Ten Englishmen or Frenchmen would do the thing at once.” POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 273 among themselves for hunting grounds.” And this rise of the society out of the family, seen in these least organized groups, re-appears in the considerably organized groups of more advanced savages. Instance the New Zealanders, of whom we read that “ eighteen historical nations occupy the country, each being sub-divided into many tribes, originally families, as the prefix Ngati, signifying offspring (equivalent to 0 or Mac) obviously indicates.” This connexion between blood relationship and social union is well shown by Humboldt’s remarks concerning South American Indians. “ Savages,” he says, “ know only their own family, and a tribe appears to them but a more numerous assemblage of rela- tions.” When Indians who inhabit the missions see those of the forest, who are unknown to them, they say — “ They are no doubt my relations ; I understand them when they speak to me.” But these same savages detest all who are not of their tribe. “ They know the duties of family ties and of relationship, but not those of humanity.” When treating of the domestic relations, reasons were given for concluding that social stability increases as kinships become more definite and extended; since development of kinships, while insuring the likeness of nature which furthers cooperation, involves the strengthening and multiplication of those family bonds which check disruption. Where pro- miscuity is prevalent, or where marriages are temporary, the known relationships are relatively few and not close ; and there is little more social cohesion than results from habit and vague sense of kinship. Polyandry, especially of the higher kind, produces relationships of some definiteness, which admit of being traced further : so serving better to tie the social group together. And a greater advance in the nearness and the number of family connexions results from polygyny. But, as was shown, it is from monogamy that there arise family connexions which are at once the most definite and the most wide-spreading in their ramifications ; and out of monogamic families are developed the largest and 274 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. most coherent societies. In two allied, yet distinguishable, ways, does monogamy favour social solidarity. Unlike the children of the polyandric family, who are something less than half brothers and sisters (see § 300, note), and unlike the children of the polygynic family, most of whom are only half brothers and sisters, the children of the monogamic family are, in the great majority of cases, all of the same blood on both sides. Being thus themselves more closely related, it follows that their clusters of children are more closely related ; and where, as happens in early stages, these clusters of children when grown up continue to form a community, and labour together, they are united alike by their kinships and by their industrial interests. Though with the growth of a family group into a gens which spreads, the industrial interests divide, yet these kinships prevent the divisions from becoming as marked as they would otherwise become. And, similarly, when the gens, in course of time, develops into the tribe. Nor is this all. If local cir- cumstances bring together several such tribes, which are still allied in blood though more remotely, it results that when, seated side by side, they are gradually fused, partly by inter- spersion and partly by intermarriage, the compound society formed, united by numerous and complicated links of kin- ship as well as by political interests, is more strongly bound together than it would otherwise be. Dominant ancient societies illustrate this truth. Says Grote — “All that we hear of the most ancient Athenian laws is based upon the gentile and phratric divisions, which are treated throughout as extensions of the family.” Similarly, according to Momm- sen, on the “ Boman Household was based the Boman State, both as respected its constituent elements and its form. The community of the Boman people arose out of the junc- tion (in whatever way brought about) of such ancient clan- ships as the Bomilii, Yoltinii, Fabii, &c.” And Sir Henry Maine has shown in detail the ways in which the simple family passes into the house -community, and eventually the POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 275 village-community. Though, in presence of the evidence furnished by races having irregular sexual relations, we cannot allege that sameness of blood is the primary reason for political cooperation — though in numerous tribes which have not risen into the pastoral state, there is com- bination for offence and defence among those whose different totems are recognized marks of different bloods ; yet where there has been established descent through males, and especially where monogamy prevails, sameness of blood becomes largely, if not mainly, influential in determining political cooperation. And this truth, under one of its aspects, is the truth above enunciated, that combined action, requiring a tolerable homogeneity of nature among those who carry it on, is, in early stages, most successful among those who, being descendants of the same ancestors, have the greatest likeness. An all-important though less direct effect of blood-relation- ship, and especially that more definite blood-relationship which arises from monogamic marriage, has to be added. J mean community of religion — a likeness of ideas and senti- ments embodied in the worship of a common deity. Begin- ning, as this does, with propitiation of the deceased founder of the family ; and shared in, as it is, by the multi- plying groups of descendants, as the family spreads ; it becomes a further means of holding together the compound cluster gradually formed, and checking the antagonisms that arise between the component clusters : so favouring integra- tion. The influence of the bond supplied by a common cult everywhere meets us in ancient history. Each of the cities in primitive Egypt was a centre for the worship of a special divinity ; and no one who, unbiassed by foregone conclusions, observes the extraordinary development of ancestor-worship, under all its forms, in Egypt, can doubt the origin of this divinity. Of the Greeks we read that — “Each family had its own sacred rites and funereal commemoration of ancestors, celebrated by the master of the house, to which none hut members of the family were admissible : the extinction of a family, 276 POLITICAL INSTITUTION'S, carrying with it the suspension of these religious rites, was held by the Greeks to be a misfortune, not merely from the loss of the citizens composing it, but also because the family gods and the manes of deceased citizens were thus deprived of their honours and might visit the country with displeasure. The larger associations, called Gens, Phratry, Tribe, were formed by an extension of the same principle — of the family considered as a religious brotherhood, worshipping some common god or hero with an appropriate surname, and recognizing him as their joint ancestor.” A like bond was generated in a like manner in the Roman community. Each curia, which was the homologue of the phratry, had a head, “ whose chief function was to preside over the sacrifices.” And, on a larger scale, the same thing held with the entire society. The primitive Roman king was a priest of the deities common to all : “ he held intercourse with the gods of the community, whom he consulted and whom he appeased.” The beginnings of this religious bond, here exhibited in a developed form, are still traceable in India. Sir Henry Maine says, “ the joint family of the Hindoos is that assemblage of persons who would have joined in the sacrifices at the funeral of some common ancestor if he had died in their lifetime.” So that political integration, while furthered by that likeness of nature which identity of descent involves, is again furthered by that like- ness of religion simultaneously arising from this identity of descent. Thus is it, too, at a later stage, with that less-pronounced likeness of nature characterizing men of the same race who have multiplied and spread in such ways as to form adjacent small societies. Cooperation among them continues to be furthered, though less effectually, by the community of their natures, by the community of their traditions, ideas, and sentiments, as well as by their community of speech. Among men of diverse types, concert is necessarily hindered both by ignorance of one another’s words, and by unlike- nesses of thought and feeling. It needs but to remember how often, even among those of the same family, quarrels arise from misinterpretations of things said, to see what POLITICAL INTEGRATION - . 277 fertile sources of confusion and antagonism must be the partial or complete differences of language which habitually accompany differences of race. Similarly, those who are widely unlike in their emotional natures or in their intellec- tual natures, perplex one another by unexpected conduct — a fact on which travellers habitually remark. Hence a further obstacle to combined action. Diversities of custom, too, become causes of dissension. Where a food eaten by one people is regarded by another with disgust, where an animal held sacred by the one is by the other treated with contempt, where a salute which the one expects is never made by the other, there must be continually generated alienations which hinder joint efforts. Other things equal, facility of coopera- tion will be proportionate to the amount of fellow fueling ; and fellow feeling is prevented by whatever prevents men from behaving in the same ways under the same conditions. The working together of the original and derived factors above enumerated, is well exhibited in the following passage from Grote : — “The Hellens were all of common blood and parentage, were ail descendants of the common patriarch Hellen. In treating of the his- torical Greeks, we have to accept this as a datum ; it represents the sentiment under the influence of which they moved and acted. It is placed by Herodotus in the front rank, as the chief of those four ties which bound together the Hellenic aggregate : 1. Fellowship of blood ; 2. Fellowship of language ; 3. Fixed domiciles of gods, and sacrifices common to all ; 4. Like manners and dispositions.” Influential as we thus find to be the likeness of nature which is insured by common descent, the implication is that, in the absence of considerable likeness, the political aggre- gates formed are unstable, and can be maintained only by a coercion which, some time or other, is sure to fail. Though other causes have conspired, yet this has doubtless been a main cause of the dissolution of great empires in past ages. At the present time the decay of the Turkish Empire is largely, if not chiefly, ascribable to it. Our own Indian ‘Empire too, held together by force in a state of artificial 278 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. equilibrium, threatens some day to illustrate by its fall the incohesion arising from lack of congruity in components. § 451. One of the laws of evolution at large, is that inte- gration results when like units are subject to the same force or to like forces (First Principles , § 169) ; and from the first stages of political integration up to the last, we find this law illustrated. Joint exposure to uniform external actions, and joint reactions against them, have from the beginning been the leading causes of union among members of societies. Already in § 250 there has been indirectly implied the truth that coherence is first given to small hordes of primitive men during combined opposition to enemies. Subject to the same danger, and joining to meet this danger, the members of the horde become, in the course of their cooperation against it, more bound together. In the first stages this relation of cause and effect is clearly seen in the fact that such union as arises during a war, disappears when the war is over : there is loss of all such slight political combination as was begin- ning to show itself. But it is by the integration of simple groups into compound groups in the course of common re- sistance to foes, and attacks upon them, that this process is best exemplified. The cases before given may be reinforced by others. Of the Karens, Mason says: — “Each village, being an independent community, had always an old feud to settle with nearly every other village among their own people. But the common danger from more powerful enemies, or having common injuries to requite, often led to several villages uniting together for defence or attack ” According to Kolben, “ smaller nations of Hottentots, which may be near some powerful nation, frequently enter into an alliance, offensive and defensive, against the stronger nation.” Among the New Caledonians of Tanna, “ six, or eight, or more of their villages unite, and form what may be called a district, or county, and all league together for mutual protection In war two or more of these districts unite.” Samoan “ villages, in POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 279 numbers of eight or ten, unite by common consent, and form a district or state for mutual protection f and during hosti- lities these districts themselves sometimes unite in twos and threes. The like has happened with historic peoples. It was during the wars of the Israelites in David’s time, that they passed from the state of separate tribes into the state of a consolidated ruling nation. The scattered Greek communi- ties, previously aggregated into minor confederacies by minor wars, were prompted to the Pan-Hellenic congress and to the subsequent cooperation, when the invasion of Xerxes was impending ; and of the Spartan and Athenian confederacies afterwards formed, that of Athens acquired the hegemony, and finally the empire, during continued operations against the Persians. So, too, was it with the Teutonic races. The German tribes, originally without federal bonds, formed occasional alliances for opposing enemies. Between the first and fifth centuries these tribes massed themselves into great groups for resistance against, or attack upon, Rome. During the subsequent century the prolonged military con- federations of peoples “ of the same blood ” had grown into States, which afterwards became aggregated into still larger States. And, to take a comparatively modern instance, the wars between France and England aided each in passing from that condition in which its feudal divisions were in considerable degrees independent, to the condition of a con- solidated nation. As further showing how integration of smaller societies into larger ones is thus initiated, it may be added that at first the unions exist only for military pur- poses. Each component society retains for a long time its independent internal administration ; and it is only when joint action in war has become habitual, that the cohesion is made permanent by a common political organization. This compounding of smaller communities into larger by military cooperation, is insured by the disappearance of such smaller communities as do not cooperate. Barth remarks that “the Fiilbe [Fulahs] are continually advancing, as they 280 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. have not to do with one strong enemy, but with a number of small tribes without any bond of union.” Of the Damaras, Galton says — “ If one werft is plundered, the adjacent ones rarely rise to defend it, and thus the Namaquas have de- stroyed or enslaved piecemeal about one-half of the whole Damara population.” Similarly with the Ynca conquests in Peru : “ there was no general opposition to their advance, for each province merely defended its land without aid from any other.” This process, so obvious and familiar, I name because it has a meaning which needs emphasizing. For we here see that in the struggle for existence among societies, the survival of the fittest is the survival of those in which the power of military cooperation is the greatest ; and mili- tary cooperation is that primary kind of cooperation which prepares the way for other kinds. So that this formation of larger societies by the union of smaller ones in war, and this destruction or absorption of the smaller un-united societies by the united larger ones, is an inevitable process through which the varieties of men most adapted for social life, supplant the less adapted varieties. Respecting the integration thus effected, it remains only to remark that it necessarily follows this course — necessarily begins with the formation of simple groups and advances by the compounding and re-compounding of them. Impulsive in conduct and with rudimentary powers of concerted action, savages cohere so slightly that only small bodies of them can maintain their integrity. Not until such small bodies have severally had their members bound to one another by some slight political organization, does it become possible to unite them into larger bodies; since the cohesion of these implies greater fitness for concerted action, and more de- veloped organization for achieving it. And similarly, these composite clusters must be to some extent consolidated before the composition can be carried a stage further. Pass- ing over the multitudinous illustrations occurring among the uncivilized, it will suffice if I refer to those given in § 226, POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 281 and reinforce them by some which historic peoples have supplied. There is the fact that in primitive Egypt, the numerous small societies (which eventually became the “ nomes ”) first united into the two aggregates, Upper Egypt and Lower Egypt, which were afterwards joined into one ; and the fact that in ancient Greece, villages became united to form towns before the towns became united into states, while this change preceded the change which united the states with one another ; and the fact that in the old English period, small principalities were massed into the divisions constitut- ing the Heptarchy, before these passed into something like a whole. It is a principle in physics that, since the force with which a body resists strains increases as the squares of its dimensions, while the strains which its own weight subject it to increase as the cubes of its dimensions, its power of maintaining its integrity becomes relatively less as its mass becomes greater. Something analogous may be said of societies. Small aggregates only can hold together while cohesion is feeble ; and successively larger aggregates become possible only as the greater strains implied are met by that greater cohesion which results from an adapted human nature and a resulting development of social organization. § 452. As social integration advances, the increasing aggre- gates exercise increasing restraints over their units — a truth which is the obverse of the one just set forth, that the main- tenance of its integrity by a larger aggregate implies greater cohesion. The forces by which aggregates keep their units , together are at first feeble ; and becoming strenuous at a certain stage of social evolution afterwards relax — or rather, change their forms. Originally the individual savage gravitates to one group or other, prompted by sundry motives, but mainly by the desire for protection. Concerning the Patagonians, we read that no one can live apart : “ if any of them attempted to do it, they would undoubtedly be killed, or carried away as slaves, as 282 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. soon as they were discovered.” In North America, among the Chinooks, “ on the coast a custom prevails which autho- rizes the seizure and enslavement, unless ransomed by his friends, of every Indian met with at a distance from his tribe, although they may not be at war with each other.” At first, however, though it is necessary to join some group, it is not necessary to continue in the same group. When oppressed by their chief, Kalmucks and Mongols desert him and go over to other chiefs. Of the Abipones Dobrizhoffer says : — “ With- out leave asked on their part, or displeasure evinced on his, they remove with their families whithersoever it suits them, and join some other cacique ; and when tired of the second, return with impunity to the horde of the first.” Similarly in South Africa, “ the frequent instances which occur [among the Balonda] of people changing from one part of the country to another, show that the great chiefs possess only a limited power.” And how, through this process, some tribes grow while others dwindle, we are shown by M‘Culloch’s remark respecting the Kukis, that “ a village, having around it plenty of land suited for cultivation and a popular chief, is sure soon, by accessions from less favoured ones, to become large.” With the need which the individual has for protection, is joined the desire of the tribe to strengthen itself; and the practice of adoption, hence resulting, constitutes another mode of integration. Where, as in tribes of North American Indians, “ adoption or the torture were the alternative chances of a captive” (adoption being the fate of one admired for his bravery), we see re-illustrated the tendency which each society has to grow at the expense of other societies. That desire for many actual children whereby the family may be strengthened, which Hebrew traditions show us, readily passes into the desire for factitious children — here made one with the brotherhood by exchange of blood, and there by mock birth. As was implied in § 319, it is probable that the practice of adoption into families among Greeks and Romans, arose during those early times when the wandering POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 283 patriarchal group constituted the tribe, and when the wish of the tribe to strengthen itself was dominant ; though it was doubtless afterwards maintained chiefly by the wish to have someone to continue the sacrifices to ancestors. And, indeed, on remembering that, long after larger societies were formed by unions of patriarchal groups, there continued to be feuds between the component families and clans, we may see that there had never ceased to operate on such families and clans, the primitive motive for strengthening themselves by increas- ing their numbers. Kindred motives produced kindred results wdthin more modern societies, during times when their parts were so im- perfectly integrated that there remained antagonisms among them. Thus we have the fact that in mediaeval England, while local rule was incompletely subordinated to general rule, every free man had to attach himself to a lord, a burgh, or a guild : being otherwise “ a friendless man,” and in a danger like that which the savage is in when not belonging to a tribe. And then, on the other hand, in the law that “ if a bondsman continued a year and a day within a free burgh or municipality, no lord could reclaim him,” we may recognize an effect of a desire on the part of industrial groups to strengthen themselves against the feudal groups around — an effect analogous to that of adoption, here into the savage tribe and there into the family as it existed in more ancient societies. Naturally, as a whole nation becomes more in- tegrated, local integrations lose their separateness, and their divisions fade ; though they long leave their traces, as among ourselves in the law of settlement, and as, up to 1824, in the laws affecting the freedom of travelling of artisans. These last illustrations introduce us to the truth that while at first there is little cohesion and great mobility of the units forming a group, advance in integration is habitually accom- panied not only by decreasing ability to go from group to group, but also by decreasing ability to go from place to place within the group. Of course the transition from the 284 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. nomadic to the settled state partially implies this ; since each person becomes in a considerable degree tied by his material interests. Slavery, too, effects in another way this binding of individuals to locally-placed members of the society, and therefore to particular parts to it ; and, where serfdom exists, the same thing is shown with a difference. But in highly-integrated societies, not simply those in bondage, but others also, are tied to their localities. Of the ancient Mexicans, Zurita says : — “ The Indians never changed their village nor even their quarter. This custom was observed as a law.” In ancient Peru, “ it was not lawful for any one to remove from one province, or village, to another ; ” and “ any who travelled without just cause were punished as vagabonds.” Elsewhere, along with that development of the militant type accompanying aggregation, there have been imposed restraints on transit under other forms. Ancient Egypt had a system of registration ; and all citizens periodi- cally reported themselves to local officers. “ Every Japanese is registered, and whenever he removes his residence, the Nanushi, or head man of the temple gives a certificate.” And then, in despotically-governed European countries we have passports-systems, hindering the journeys of citizens from place to place, and in some cases preventing them from going abroad. In these, as in other respects, however, the restraints which the social aggregate exercises over its units, decrease as the industrial type begins greatly to qualify the militant type ; partly because the societies characterized by industralism are amply populous, and have superfluous members to fill the places of those who leave them, and partly because, in the absence of the oppressions accompanying a militant regime , a sufficient cohesion results from pecuniary interests, family bonds, and love of country. § 453. Thus, saying nothing for the present of that political evolution manifested by increase of structure, and restricting POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 285 ourselves to that political evolution manifested by increase of mass, here distinguished as political integration, we find that this has the following traits. While the aggregates are small, the incorporation of materials for growth is carried on at one another’s expense in feeble ways — by taking one another’s game, by robbing one another of women, and, occasionally by adopting one another’s men. As larger aggregates are formed, incorporations pro- ceed in more wholesale ways ; first by enslaving the separate members of conquered tribes, and presently by the bodily annexation of such tribes, with their territory. And as com- pound aggregates pass into doubly and trebly compound ones, there arise increasing desires to absorb adjacent smaller societies, and so to form still larger aggregates. Conditions of several kinds further or hinder social growth and consolidation. The habitat may be fitted or unfitted for supporting a large population ; or it may, by great or small facilities for intercourse within its area, favour or impede co- operation ; or it may, by presence or absence of natural barriers, make easy or difficult the keeping together of the individuals under that coercion which is at first needful. And, as the antecedents of the race determine, the indi- viduals may have in greater or less degrees the physical, the emotional, and the intellectual natures fitting them for combined action. While the extent to which social integration can in each case be carried, depends in part on these conditions, it also depends in part upon the degree of likeness among the units. At first, while the nature is so little moulded to social life that cohesion is small, aggregation is largely dependent on ties of blood : implying great degrees of likeness. Groups in which such ties, and the resulting congruity, are most marked, and which, having family traditions in common, a common male ancestor, and a joint worship of him, are in these further ways made alike in ideas and sentiments, are groups in which the greatest social cohesion and power of co- 286 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. operation arise. For a long time the clans and tribes de- scending from such primitive patriarchal groups, have their political concert facilitated by this bond of relationship and the likeness it involves. Only after adaptation to social life lias made considerable progress, does harmonious cooperation among those who are not of the same stock become practi- cable ; and even then their unlikenesses of nature must be small. Where their unlikenesses of nature are great, the society, held together only by force, tends to disintegrate when the force fails. Likeness in the units forming a social group being one condition to their integration, a further condition is their joint reaction against external action : cooperation in war is the chief cause of social integration. The temporary unions of savages for offence and defence, show us the initiatory step. When many tribes unite against a common enemy, long continuance of their combined action makes them coherent under some common control. And so it is subse- quently with still larger aggregates. Progress in social integration is both a cause and a con- sequence of a decreasing separableness among the units. Primitive wandering hordes exercise no such restraints over their members as prevent them individually from leaving one horde and joining another at will. Where tribes are more developed, desertion of one and admission into another are less easy — the assemblages are not so loose in composition. And throughout those long stages during which societies are being enlarged and consolidated by militancy, the mobility of the units becomes more and more restricted. Only with that substitution of voluntary cooperation for compulsory co- operation which characterizes developing industrialism, do the restrictions on movement disappear : enforced union being in such societies adequately replaced by spontaneous union. A remaining truth to be named is that political integration, as it advances, obliterates the original divisions among the POLITICAL INTEGRATION. 287 united parts. In the first place there is the slow disappear- ance of those non-topographical divisions arising from rela- tionship, as seen in separate gentes and tribes : gradual inter- mingling destroys them. In the second place, the smaller local societies united into a larger one, which at first retain their separate organizations, lose them by long cooperation : a common organization begins to ramify through them. And in the third place, there simultaneously results a fading of their topographical bounds, and a replacing of these by the new administrative bounds of the common organiza- tion. Hence naturally results the converse truth, that in the course of social dissolution the great groups separate first, and afterwards, if dissolution continues, these separate into their component smaller groups. Instance the ancient empires successively formed in the East, the united kingdoms of which severally resumed their autonomies when the coercion keeping them together ceased. Instance, again, the Carolingian empire, which, first parting into its large divisions, became in course of time further disintegrated by subdivision of these. And where, as in this last case, the process of dissolution goes very far, there is a return to some- thing like the primitive condition, under which small preda- tory societies are engaged in continuous warfare with like small societies around them. CHAPTER IV. POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION § 454. As was pointed out in First Principles , § 154, it is true of a social aggregate, as of every other aggregate, that the state of homogeneity is an unstable state; and that where there is already some heterogeneity, the tendency is towards greater heterogeneity. Lapse from homogeneity, however, or rather, the increase of such heterogeneity as usually exists, requires that the parts shall be heterogeneously conditioned; and whatever prevents the rise of contrasts among the conditions, prevents increase of heterogeneity. One of the implications is that there must not be continual changes in the distribution of the parts. If now one part and now another, occupies the same position in relation to the whole, permanent structural differences cannot be produced. There must be such cohesion among the parts as prevents easy transposition. We see this truth exemplified in the simplest individual organisms. A low Rhizopod, of which the substance has a mobility approaching to that of a liquid, remains almost homogeneous ; because each part is from moment to moment assuming new relations to other parts and to the environ- ment. And the like holds with the simplest societies. Concerning the members of the small unsettled groups of Fuegians, Cook remarks that “ none w r as more respected than another.” The Veddahs, the Andamanese, the Australians, the Tasmanians, may also be instanced as loose assemblages •POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 289 which present no permanent unlikenesses of social position ; or if unlikeness exist, as some travellers allege, they are so vague that they are denied by others. And in such wander- ing hordes as the Coroados of South America, formed of individuals held together so feebly that they severally join one or other horde at will, the distinctions of parts are but nominal. Conversely, it is to be anticipated that where the several parts of a social aggregate are heterogeneously conditioned in a permanent way, they will become proportionately hetero- geneous. We shall see this more clearly on changing the point of view. § 455. The general law that like units exposed to like forces tend to integrate, was in the last chapter exemplified by the formation of social groups. Here the correlative general law, that in proportion as the like units of an aggregate are exposed to unlike forces they tend to form differentiated parts of the aggregate, has to be observed in its application to such groups, as the second step in social evolution. The primary political differentiation originates from the primary family differentiation. Men and women being by the unlikenesses of their functions in life, exposed to unlike influences, begin from the first to assume unlike positions in the community as they do in the family : very early they respectively form the two political classes of rulers and ruled. And how truly such dissimilarity of social positions as arises between them, is caused by dissimilarity in their relations to surrounding actions, we shall see on observing that the one is small or great according as the other is small or great. When treating of the status of women, it w 7 as pointed out that to a considerable degree among the Chippe- wayans, and to a still greater degree among the Clatsops and Chinooks, “ who live upon fish and roots, which the women are equally expert with the men in procuring, the former have a rank and influence very rarely found among Indians.” We 290 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. saw also that in Cueba, where the women join the men in war, “ fighting by their side,” their position is much higher than usual among rude peoples; and, similarly, that in Dahomey, where the women are as much warriors as the men, they are so regarded that, in the political organization, “ the woman is officially superior.” On contrasting these excep- tional cases with the ordinary cases, in which the men, solely occupied in war and the chase, have unlimited authority, while the women, occupied in gathering miscellaneous small food and carrying burdens, are abject slaves, it becomes clear that diversity of relations to surrounding actions initiates diversity of social relations. And, as we saw in § 327, this truth is further illustrated by those few uncivilized societies which are habitually peaceful, such as the Bodo and the Dhimals of the Indian hills, and the ancient Pueblos of North America — societies in which the occupations are not, or were not, broadly divided into fighting and working, and severally assigned to the two sexes ; and in which, along with a com- paratively small difference between the activities of the sexes, there goes, or went, small difference of social status. So is it when we pass from the greater or less political differentiation which accompanies difference of sex, to that which is independent of sex — to that which arises among men. Where the life is permanently peaceful, definite class- divisions do not exist. One of the Indian Hill-tribes to which I have already referred as exhibiting the honesty, truthfulness, and amiability, accompanying a purely indus- trial life, may be instanced. Hodgson says, “ all Bodo and all Dhimals are equal — absolutely so in right or law — * wonderfully so in fact.” The like is said of another unwar- like and amiable hill tribe : “ the Lepchas have no caste dis- tinctions.” And among a different race, the Papuans, may be named the peaceful Arafuras as displaying “ brotherly love with one another,” and as having no divisions of rank. § 456. As, at first, the domestic relation between the sexes POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 291 passes -into a political relation, such that men and women become, in militant groups, the ruling class and the subject class ; so does the relation between master and slave, origin- ally a domestic one, pass into a political one as fast as, by habitual war, the making of slaves becomes general. It is with the formation of a slave-class, that there begins that political differentiation between the regulating structures and the sustaining structures, which continues throughout all higher forms of social evolution. Kane remarks that “ slavery in its most cruel form exists among the Indians of the whole coast from California to Behring’s Straits, the stronger tribes making slaves of all the others they can conquer. In the interior, where there is but little warfare, slavery does not exist.” And this statement does but exhibit, in a distinct form, the truth everywhere obvious. Evidence suggests that the practice of enslavement diverged by small steps from the practice of cannibalism. Concerning the Nootkas, we read that “ slaves are occasion- ally sacrificed and feasted upon and if we contrast this usage wfith the usage common elsewhere, of killing and devouring captives as soon as they are taken, we may infer that the keeping of captives too numerous to be immediately eaten, with the view of eating them subsequently, leading, as it w r ould, to the employment of them in the meantime, caused the discovery that their services might be of more value than their flesh, and so initiated the habit of preserving them as slaves. Be this as it may, however, we find that very generally among tribes to which habitual militancy has given some slight degree of the appropriate structure, the enslavement of prisoners becomes an established habit. That women and children taken in war, and such men as have not been slain, naturally fall into unqualified servitude, is mani- fest. They belong absolutely to their captors, who might have killed them; and who retain the right afterwards to kill them if they please. They become property, of which any use whatever may be made. 292 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Tlie acquirement of slaves, which is at first an incident of war, becomes presently an object of war. Of the Nootkas we read that “ some of the smaller tribes at the north of the island are practically regarded as slave-breeding tribes, and are attacked periodically by stronger tribes ” and the like happens among the Chinooks. It was thus in ancient Yera Paz, where periodically they made “an inroad into the enemy’s territory . . . and captured as many as they wanted and it was so in Honduras, where, in declaring war, they gave their enemies notice “ that they wanted slaves.” Similarly with various existing peoples. St. John says that “ many of the Dyaks are more desirous to obtain slaves than heads ; and in attacking a village kill only those who resist or attempt to escape.” And that in Africa slave-making wars are common needs no proof. The class-division thus initiated by war, afterwards main- tains and strengthens itself in sundry ways. Very soon there begins the custom of purchase. The Chinooks, besides slaves who have been captured, have slaves who were bought as children from their neighbours ; and, as we saw when dealing with the domestic relations, the selling of their children into slavery is by no means uncommon with savages. Then the slave-class, thus early enlarged by purchase, comes afterwards to be otherwise enlarged. There is voluntary acceptance of slavery for the sake of protection ; there is enslavement for debt ; there is enslavement for crime. Leaving details, we need here note only that this political differentiation which war begins, is effected, not by the bodily incorporation of other societies, or whole classes belonging to other societies, but by the incorporation of single members of other societies, and by like individual accretions. Com- posed of units who are detached from their original social relations and from one another, and absolutely attached to their owners, the slave-class is, at first, but indistinctly separated as a social stratum. It acquires separateness only as fast as there arise some restrictions on the powers of the POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 293 owners. Ceasing to stand in the position of domestic cattle, slaves begin to form a division of the body politic when their personal claims begin to be distinguished as limiting the claims of their masters. § 457. It is commonly supposed that serfdom arises by mitigation of slavery ; but examination of the facts shows that it arises in a different way. While, during the early struggles for existence between them, primitive tribes, growing at one another’s expense by incorporating separately the individuals they capture, thus form a class of absolute slaves, the formation of a servile class considerably higher, and having a distinct social status, accompanies that later and larger process of growth under which one society incorporates other societies bodily. Serfdom originates along with conquest and annexa- tion. For whereas the one implies that the captured people are detached from their homes, the other implies that the subju- gated people continue in their homes. Thomson remarks that, “ among the New Zealanders whole tribes sometimes became nominally slaves when conquered, although permitted to live at their usual places of residence, on condition of paying tribute, in food, &c.” — a statement which shows the origin of kindred arrangements in allied societies. Of the Sandwich Islands government when first known, described as consisting of a king with turbulent chiefs, who had been sub- jected in comparatively recent times, Ellis writes: — “The common people are generally considered as attached to the soil, and are transferred with the land from one chief to another.” Before the late changes in Fiji, there were enslaved districts ; and of their inhabitants we read that they had to supply the chiefs’ houses “ with daily food, and build and keep them in repair.” Though conquered peoples thus placed, differ widely in the degrees of their subjection (being at the one extreme, as in Fiji, liable to be eaten when wanted, and at the other extreme called on only to give specified pro- 294 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. portions of produce or labour) ; yet they remain alike as being undetached from their original places of residence. That serfdom in Europe originated in an analogous way, there is good reason to believe. In Greece we have the case of Crete, where, under the conquering Dorians, there existed a vassal population, formed, it would seem, partly of the aborigines and partly of preceding conquerors ; of which the first were serfs attached to lands of the State and of individuals, and the others had become tributary landowners. In Sparta the like relations were established by like causes. There were the helots, who lived on, and cultivated, the lands of their Spartan masters, and the perioeci, who had probably been, before the Dorian invasion, the superior class. So was it also in the Greek colonies afterwards founded, such as Syracuse, where the aborigines became serfs. Similarly in later times and nearer regions. When Gaul was overrun by the Romans, and again when Romanized Gaul was overrun by the Franks, there was little displacement of the actual cultivators of the soil, but these simply fell into lower positions : certainly lower political positions, and M. Guizot thinks lower indus- trial positions. Our own country yields illustrations. “ Among the Scottish Highlanders some entire septs or clans are stated to have been enslaved to others ; and on the very threshold of Irish history we meet with a distinction between free and rent-paying tribes, which may possibly imply the same kind of superiority and sub- ordination.” In ancient British times, writes Pearson, “ it is probable that, in parts at least, there were servile villages, occupied by a kindred but conquered race, the first occupants of the soil.” More trustworthy is the evidence which comes to us from old English days and Norman days. Professor Stubbs says — “ The ceorl had his right in the common land of his township ; his Latin name, villanus, had been a symbol of freedom, but his privileges were bound to the land, and when the Norman lord took the land he took the villein with it. Still the villein retained his customary rights, his house and land and rights of wood and hay ; his lord’s demesne depended for cultivation on his services, and he had in his lord’s sense of self- interest the sort of protection that was shared by the horse aud the ox.” POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 285 And of kindred import is the following passage from Innes : — “ I have said that of the inhabitants of the Grange, the lowest in the scale was the ceorl, bond , serf \ or villein, who was transferred like the land on which he laboured, and who might be caught and brought back if he attempted to escape, like a stray ox or sheep. Their legal name of nativus, or neyf which I have not found but in Britain, seems to point to their origin in the native race, the original possessors of the soil. ... In the register of Dunfermline are numerous ‘ genealogies/ or stud-books, for enabling the lord to trace and reclaim his stock of serfs by descent. It is observable that most of them are of Celtic names .’ 7 Clearly, a subjugated territory, useless without cultivators, was left in the hands of the original cultivators, because nothing was to be gained by putting others in their places ; even could an adequate number of others be had. Hence, while it became the conqueror’s interest to tie each original cultivator to the soil, it also became his interest to let him have such an amount of produce as to maintain him and enable him to rear offspring, and it further became his interest to protect him against injuries which would incapacitate him for work. To show how fundamental is the distinction between bondage of the primitive type and the bondage of serfdom, it needs but to add that while the one can, and does, exist among savages and pastoral tribes, the other becomes possible only after the agricultural stage is reached ; for only then can there occur the bodily annexation of one society by another, and only then can there be any tying to the soil. § 458. Associated men who live by hunting, and to whom the area occupied is of value only as a habitat for game, can- not well have anything more than a common participation in the use of this occupied area : such ownership of it as they have, must be joint ownership. Naturally, then, at the outset all the adult males, who are at once hunters and warriors, are the common possessors of the undivided land, encroach- ment on which by other tribes they resist. Though, in the earlier pastoral state, especially where the barrenness of the 296 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. region involves wide dispersion, there is no definite pro- prietorship of the tract wandered over ; yet, as is shown us in the strife between the herdsmen of Abraham and those of Lot respecting feeding grounds, some claims to exclusive use tend to arise; and at a later half-pastoral stage, as among the ancient Germans, the wanderings of each division fall within prescribed limits. I refer to these facts by way of showing the identity esta- blished at the outset between the militant class and the land- owning class. For whether the group is one which lives by hunting or one which lives by feeding cattle, any slaves its members possess are excluded from land-ownership : the free- men, who are all fighting men, become, as a matter of course, the proprietors of their territory. This connexion in variously modified forms, long continues ; and could scarcely do other- wise. Land being, in early settled communities, the almost exclusive source of wealth, it happens inevitably that during times in which the principle that might is right remains unqualified, personal power and ownership of the soil go together. Hence the fact that where, instead of being held by the whole society, land comes to be parcelled out among component village-communities, or among families, or among individuals, possession of it habitually goes along with the bearing of arms. In ancient Egypt “ every soldier was a land- owner ” — “ had an allotment of land of about six acres.” In Greece the invading Hellenes, wresting the country from its original holders, joined military service with territorial endow- ment. In Rome, too, “ every freeholder from the seventeenth to the sixtieth year of his age, was under obligation of service ... so that even the emancipated slave had to serve who, in an exceptional case, had come into possession of landed property.” The like happened in the early Teutonic community. Joined with professional warriors, its army included “ the mass of freemen arranged in families fighting for their homesteads and hearths such freemen, or markmen, owning land partly in common and partly as individual pro- POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 297 prietors. Or as is said of this same arrangement among the ancient English, “ their occupation of the land as cognationes resulted from their enrolment in the field, where each kindred was drawn up under an officer of its own lineage and appoint- ment and so close was this dependence that “ a thane for- feited his hereditary freehold by misconduct in battle.” Beyond the original connexion between militancy and land- owning, which naturally arises from the joint interest which those who own the land and occupy it, either individually or collectively, have in resisting aggressors, there arises later a further connexion. As, along w T ith successful militancy, there progresses a social evolution which gives to a dominant ruler increased power, it becomes his custom to reward his leading soldiers by grants of land. Early Egyptian kings “ bestowed on distinguished military officers” portions of the crown domains. When the barbarians were enrolled as Roman soldiers, “ they were paid also by assignments of land, accord- ing to a custom which prevailed in the Imperial armies. The possession of these lands was given to them on condition of the son becoming a soldier like his father.” And that kindred usages were general throughout the feudal period, is a familiar truth: feudal tenancy being, indeed, thus constituted; and inability to bear arms being a reason for excluding women from succession. To exemplify the nature of the relation established, it will suffice to name the fact that “ William the Conqueror . . . distributed this kingdom into about 60,000 parcels, of nearly equal value [partly left in the hands of those who previously held it, and partly made over to his followers as either owners or suzerains], from each of which the service of a soldier was due and the further fact that one of his laws requires all owners of land to “ swear that they become vassals or tenants,” and w T ill “ defend their lord’s territories and title as well as his person ” by “ knight- service on horseback.” That this original relation between landowning and mili- tancy long survived, we are shown by the armorial bearings 298 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of county families, as well as by the portraits of family ances- tors, who are mostly represented in military costume. § 459. Setting out with the class of warriors, or men bear- ing arms, who in primitive communities are owners of the land, collectively or individually, or partly one and partly the other, there arises the question — How does this class dif- ferentiate into nobles and freemen ? The most general reply is, of course, that since the state of homogeneity is by necessity unstable, time inevitably brings about inequalities of positions among those whose positions were at first equal. Before the semi-civilized state is reached, the differentiation cannot become decided ; because there can be no large accumulations of wealth, and because the laws of descent do not favour maintenance of such accumulations as are possible. But in the pastoral, and still more in the agri- cultural, community, especially where descent through males has been established, several causes of differentiation come into play. There is, first, unlikeness of kinship to the head mam Obviously, in course of generations, the younger descendants of the younger become more and more remotely related to the eldest descendant of the eldest ; and social inferiority arises. As the obligation to execute blood-revenge for a mur- dered member of the family does not extend beyond a certain degree of relationship (in ancient France not beyond the seventh), so neither does the accompanying distinction. From the same cause comes inferiority in point of possessions. Inheritance by the eldest male from generation to genera- tion, works the effect that those who are the most distantly connected in blood with the head of the group, are also the poorest. Then there cooperates with these factors a consequent factor; namely, the extra power which greater 'wealth gives. For when there arise disputes within the tribe, the richer are those who, by their better appliances for defence and their greater ability to purchase aid, naturally have the advantage over the poorer. Proof that this is a POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 299 potent cause is found in a fact named by Sir Henry Maine. “ The founders of a part of our modern European aristocracy, the Danish, are known to have been originally peasants who fortified their houses during deadly village struggles and then used their advantage.” Such superiorities of position, once initiated, are increased in another way. Already in the last chapter we have seen that communities are to a certain extent increased by the addition of fugitives from other com- munities — sometimes criminals, sometimes those who are oppressed. While, in places where such fugitives belong to races of superior types, they often become rulers (as among many Indian hill- tribes, whose rajahs are of Hindoo extrac- tion), in places where they are of the same race and cannot do this, they attach themselves to those of chief power in their adopted tribe. Sometimes they yield up their freedom for the sake of protection : a man makes himself a slave by breaking a spear in the presence of his wished for master, as among the East Africans, or by inflicting some small bodily injury upon him, as among the Fulahs. In ancient Eome the semi-slave class distinguished as clients, originated by this voluntary acceptance of servitude with safety. But where his aid promises to be of value in war, the fugitive offers himself as a warrior in exchange for maintenance and refuge. Other things equal, he chooses for master some one marked by superiority of power and property ; and thus enables the man already dominant to become more dominant. Such armed dependents, having as aliens no claims to the lands of the group, and bound to its head only by fealty, answer in position to the comites as found in the early German commu- nities, and as exemplified in old English times by the “ Huscarlas” (Housecaris), with whom nobles surrounded themselves. Evidently, too, followers of this kind, having certain interests in common with their protector and no inte- rests in common with the rest of the community, become, in his hands, the means of usurping communal rights and ele- vating himself while depressing the rest. 300 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Step by step the contrast strengthens. Beyond such as have voluntarily made themselves slaves to a head man, others have become enslaved by capture in the wars mean- while going on, others by staking themselves in gaming, others by purchase, others by crime, others by debt. And of necessity the possession of many slaves, habitually accom- panying wealth and power, tends further to increase that wealth and power, and to mark off still more the higher rank from the lower. And then, finally, the inferior freeman finds himself so much at the mercy of the superior freeman, or noble, and his armed followers of alien origin, that it becomes needful for safety’s sake to be also a follower ; and, at first voluntary, the relation of dependence grows more and more compulsory. “ The freeman might choose his Lord, he might determine to whom, in technical phrase, he should commend himself ; but a Lord he must have, a Lord to act at once as his pro- tector and as his surety.” § 460. Certain concomitant influences generate differences of nature, physical and mental, between those members of a community who have attained superior positions, and those who have remained inferior. Unlikenesses of status once initiated, lead to unlikenesses of life, which, by the constitutional changes they work, presently make the unlikenesses of status more difficult to alter. First there comes difference of diet and its effects. In the habit, common among primitive tribes, of letting the women subsist on the leavings of the men, and in the accompanying habit of denying to the younger men certain choice viands which the older men eat, we see exemplified the inevitable proclivity of the strong to feed themselves at the expense of the weak ; and when there arise class-divisions, there habit- ually results better nutrition of the superior than of the inferior. Forster remarks that in the Society Islands the lower classes often suffer from a scarcity of food which never POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 301 extends to the upper classes. In the Sandwich Islands the flesh of such animals as they have, is eaten principally by the chiefs. Of cannibalism among the Fijians, Seeman says — “ the common people throughout the group, as well as women of all classes, were by custom debarred from it.” These instances sufficiently indicate the contrast that every- where arises between the diets of the ruling few and of the subject many. Naturally by such differences in diet, and accompanying differences in clothing, shelter, and strain on the energies, are eventually produced physical differences. Of the Fijians we read that “ the chiefs are tall, well made, and muscular ; while the lower orders manifest the meagre- ness arising from laborious service and scanty nourish- ment.” The chiefs among the Sandwich Islanders “ are tall and stout, and their personal appearance is so much superior to that of the common people, that some have imagined them a distinct race.” Ellis, verifying Cook, says of the Tahitians, that the chiefs are, “ almost without exception, as much superior to the peasantry ... in physical strength as they are in rank and circumstances and Erskine notes a parallel contrast among the Tongans. That the like holds of the African races may be inferred from Reade’s remark that — “ The court lady is tall and elegant ; her skin smooth and transparent ; her beauty has stamina and longevity. The girl of the middle classes, so frequently pretty, is very often short and coarse, and soon becomes a matron ; while, if yon descend to the lower classes, you will find good looks rare, and the figure angular, stunted, sometimes almost de- formed.”* Simultaneously there arise between rulers and ruled, un- likenesses of bodily activity and skill. Occupied, as those of higher rank commonly are, in the chase when not occupied in war, they have a life-long discipline of a kind conducive to various physical superiorities ; while, contrariwise, those occupied in agriculture, in carrying burdens, and in other # While writing I find, in the recently-issued “ Transactions of the Anthro- pological Institute,” proof that even now in England, the professional classes are both taller and heavier than the artizan classes. 302 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. drudgeries, partially lose what agility and address they natu- rally had. Class-predominance is thus further facilitated. And then there are the respective mental traits produced by daily exercise of power and by daily submission to power. The ideas, and sentiments, and modes of behaviour, perpetu- ally repeated, generate on the one side an inherited fitness for command, and on the other side an inherited fitness for obedience; with the result that, in course of time, there arises on both sides the belief that the established relations of classes are the natural ones. § 461. By implying habitual war among settled societies, the foregoing interpretations have implied the formation of compound societies. Such class-divisions as have been described, are therefore usually complicated by further class- divisions arising from the relations established between those conquerors and conquered whose respective groups already contain class-divisions. This increasing differentiation which accompanies increas- ing integration, is clearly seen in such semi-civilized societies as that of the Sandwich Islanders. Their ranks are — “ 1. King, queens, and royal family, along with the councillor or chief minister of the king. 2. The governors of the different islands, and the chiefs of several large divisions. Many of these are descendants of those who were kings of the respective islands in Cooks time, and until subdued by T-amehameha. 3. Chiefs of districts or villages, who pay a regular rent for the land, cultivating it by means of their depen- dants, or letting it out to tenants. This rank Includes also the ancient priests. 4. The labouring classes — those renting small portions of land, those working on the land for food and clothing, mechanics, musicians, and dancers.” And, as shown elsewhere, these labouring classes are other- wise divisible into — artizans, who are paid wages; serfs, attached to the soil ; and slaves. Inspection makes it tolera- bly clear that the lowest chiefs, once independent, were re- duced to the second rank when adjacent chiefs conquered them and became local kings ; and that they were reduced to the third rank at the same time that these local kings becamo POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 303 chiefs of the second rank, when, by conquest, a kingship of the whole group was established. Other societies in kindred stages show us kindred divisions, similarly to be accounted for. Among the New Zealanders there are six grades ; there are six among the Ashantees ; there are five among the Abyssinians ; and other more or less compounded African States present analogous divisions. Perhaps ancient Peru furnishes as clear a case as any of the superposition of ranks resulting from subjugation. The petty kingdoms which were massed together by the conquering Yncas, were severally left with the rulers and their subordinates undisturbed ; but over the whole empire there was a superior organization of Ynca rulers of various grades. That kindred causes produced kindred effects in early Egyptian times, is inferable from traditions and remains which tell us both of local struggles which ended in consolidation, and of conquests by invading races ; whence would naturally result the numerous divisions and sub-divisions which Egyptian society presented : an in- ference justified by the fact that under Roman dominion, there was a re-complication caused by the superposing of Roman governing agencies upon native governing agencies. Passing over other ancient instances, and coming to the familiar case of our own country, we may note how, from the followers of the conquering Norman, there arose the two ranks of the greater and lesser barons, holding their land directly from the king, while the old English thanes were reduced to the rank of sub-feudatories. Of course where perpetual wars produce, first, small aggregations, and then larger ones, and then dissolutions, and then re-aggregations, and then unions of them, various in their extents, as happened in mediaeval Europe, there result very numerous divisions. In the Merovingian kingdoms there were slaves having seven different origins ; there were serfs of more than one grade ; there were freedmen — men who, though emancipated, did not rank with the fully free ; and there were two other classes less than free — the liten and the coloni. Of the free there 304 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. were three classes — independent landowners ; freemen in relations of dependence with other freemen, of whom there were two kinds ; and freemen in special relations with the king, of whom there were three kinds. And here, while observing in these various cases how greater political differentiation is made possible by greater political integration, we may also observe that in early stages, while social cohesion is small, greater political integration is made possible by greater political differentiation. For the larger the mass to be held together, while incoherent, the more numerous must be the agents standing in successive degrees of subordination to hold it together. § 462. The political differentiations which militancy origi- nates, and which for a long time increase in definiteness, so that mixture of ranks by marriage is made a crime, are at later stages, and under other conditions, interfered with, traversed, and partially or wholly destroyed. Where, for ages and in varying degrees, war has been pro- ducing aggregations and dissolutions, the continual breaking up and re-forming of social bonds, obscures the original divisions established in the ways described: instance the state of things in the Merovingian kingdoms just named. And where, instead of conquests by kindred adjacent societies, which in large measure leave standing the social positions and properties of the subjugated, there are conquests by alien races carried on more barbarously, the original grades may be practically obliterated, and, in place of them, there may come grades established entirely by appointment of the despotic conqueror. In parts of the East, where such over-runnings of race by race have been going on from the earliest recorded times, we see this state of things substantially realized. There is little or nothing of hereditary rank ; and the only rank recognized is that of official position. Besides the different grades of appointed state-functionaries, there are no class-distinctions having political meanings. POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 305 A tendency to subordination of the original ranks, and a substitution of new ranks, is otherwise caused : it accompanies the progress of political consolidation. The change which occurred in China illustrates this effect. Gutzlaff says — “ Mere title was afterwards (on the decay of the feudal system) the reward bestowed by the sovereign . . . and the haughty and powerful grandees of other countries are here the dependant and penurious servants of the Crown. . . . The revolutionary principle of levelling all classes has been carried, in China, to a very great extent. . . . This is introduced for the benefit of the sovereign, to render his authority supreme.” The causes of such changes are not difficult to see. In the first place the subjugated local rulers, losing, as integration advances, more and more of their power, lose, consequently, more and more of their actual, if not of their nominal, rank : passing from the condition of tributary rulers to the condition of subjects. Indeed, jealousy on the part of the monarch sometimes prompts positive exclusion of them from influential positions ; as in France, where “ Louis XIY. systematically excluded the nobility from ministerial functions.” Presently their distinction is further diminished by the rise of com- peting ranks created by State-authority. Instead of the titles inherited by the land-possessing military chiefs, which were descriptive of their attributes and positions, there come to be titles conferred by the sovereign. Certain of the classes thus established are still of military origin ; as the knights made on the battle-field, sometimes in large numbers before battle, as at Agincourt, when 500 were thus created, and sometimes afterwards in reward for valour. Others of them arise from the exercise of political functions of different grades ; as in France, where, in the seventeenth century, hereditary nobility was conferred on officers of the great council and officers of the chamber of accounts. The administration of law, too, originates titles of honour. In France, in 1607, nobility was granted to doctors, regents, and professors of law ; and “ the superior courts obtained, in 1644, the privileges of nobility of the first degree.” So that, as Warnkcenig remarks, “ the 30G POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. original conception of nobility was in the course of time so much widened that its primitive relation to the possession of a fief is no longer recognizable, and the whole institution seems changed.” These, with kindred instances which our own country and other European countries furnish, show us both how the original class-divisions become blurred, and how the new class-divisions are distinguished by being de- localized. They are strata which run through the integrated society, having, many of them, no reference to the land and no more connexion with one place than with another. It is true that of the titles artificially conferred, the higher are habitually derived from the names of districts and towns : so simulating, but only simulating, the ancient feudal titles ex- pressive of actual lordship over territories. The other modern titles, however, which have arisen with the growth of political, judicial, and other functions, have not even nominal references to localities. This change naturally accompanies the growing integration of the parts into a whole, and the rise of an or- ganization of the whole which disregards the divisions among the parts. More effective still in weakening those primitive political divisions initiated by militancy, is increasing industrialism. This acts in two ways — firstly, by creating a class having power derived otherwise than from territorial possessions or official positions; and, secondly, by generating ideas and sentiments at variance with the ancient assumptions of class- superiority. As we have already seen, rank and wealth are at the outset habitually associated. Existing uncivilized peoples still show us this relation. The chief of a kraal among the Koranna Hottentots is “ usually the per- son of greatest property.” In the Bechuana language “ the word kosi . . . has a double acceptation, denoting either a chief or a rich man.” Such small authority as a Chinook chief has, “ rests on riches, which consists in wives, children, slaves, boats, and shells.” Eude European peoples, like the Albanians, yield kindred facts : the heads of their communes POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 307 “ sont en general les gens les plus riches.” Indeed it is manifest that before the development of commerce, and while possession of land could alone give largeness of means, lord- ship and riches were directly connected; so that, as Sir Henry Maine remarks, “ the opposition commonly set up between birth and wealth, and particularly wealth other than landed property, is entirely modern. 1 ” When, however, with the arrival of industry at that stage in which wholesale transactions bring large profits, there arise traders who vie with, and exceed, many of the landed nobility in wealth ; and w T hen by conferring obligations on kings and nobles, such traders gain social influence ; there comes an occasional removal of the barrier between them and the titled classes. In France the process began as early as 1271, when there were issued letters ennobling Eaoul the goldsmith — “the first letters conferring nobility in existence” in France. The precedent once established is followed with increasing fre- quency; and sometimes, under pressure of financial needs, there grows up the practice of selling titles, in disguised ways or openly. In France, in 1702, the king ennobled 200 persons at 3,000 livres a-liead ; in 1706, 500 persons at 6,000 livres a-head. And then the breaking down of the ancient political divisions thus caused, is furthered by that weakening of them consequent on the growing spirit of equality fostered by industrial life. In proportion as men are habituated to maintain their own claims while respect- ing the claims of others, which they do in every act of exchange, whether of goods for money or of services for pay, there is produced a mental attitude at variance with that which accompanies subjection ; and, as fast as this happens, such political distinctions as imply subjection, lose more and more of that respect which gives them strength. § 463. Class-distinctions, then, date back to the beginnings of social life. Omitting those small wandering assemblages which are so incoherent that their component parts are 308 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ever changing their relations to one another and to the environment, we see that wherever there is some coherence and some permanence of relation among the parts, there begin to arise political divisions. Eelative superiority of power, first causing a differentiation at once domestic and social, between the activities of the sexes and the consequent positions of the sexes, presently begins to cause a differentia- tion among males, shown in the bondage of captives : a master-class and a slave-class are formed. Where men continue the wandering life in pursuit of wild food for themselves or their cattle, the groups they form are debarred from doing more by war than appropriate one another’s units individually; but where men have passed into the agricultural or settled state, it becomes possible for one community to take possession bodily of another com- munity, along with the territory it occupies. When this happens there arise additional class-divisions. The conquered and tribute-paying community, besides having its headmen reduced to subjection, has its people reduced to a state such that, while they continue to live on their lands, they yield up, through the intermediation of their chiefs, part of the produce to the conquerors : so foreshadowing what eventually becomes a serf-class. From the beginning the militant class, being by force of arms the dominant class, becomes the class which owns the source of food — the land. During the hunting and pastoral stages, the warriors of the group hold the land collectively. On passing into the settled state, their tenures become partly collective and partly individual in sundry ways, and eventually almost wholly individual. But throughout long stages of social evolution, landowning and militancy con- tinue to be associated. The class-differentiation of which militancy is the active cause, is furthered by the establishment of definite descent, and especially male descent, and by the transmission of posi- tion and property to the eldest son of the eldest continually. POLITICAL DIFFERENTIATION. 309 This conduces to inequalities of position and wealth between near kindred and remote kindred ; and such inequalities once initiated, tend to increase ; since it results from them that the superior get greater means of maintaining their power by accumulating appliances for offence and defence. Such differentiation is augmented, at the same time that a new differentiation is set up, by the immigration of fugitives who attach themselves to the most powerful member of the group : now as dependants who work, and now as armed followers — armed followers who form a class bound to the dominant man and unconnected with the land. And since, in clusters of such groups, fugitives ordinarily flock most to the strongest group, and become adherents of its head, they are instrumental in furthering those subsequent integrations and differentiations which conquests bring about. Inequalities of social position, bringing inequalities in the supplies and kinds of food, clothing, and shelter, tend to establish physical differences ; to the further advantage of the rulers and disadvantage of the ruled. And beyond the physical differences, there are produced by the respective habits of life, mental differences, emotional and intellectual, strengthening the general contrast of nature. When there come the conquests which produce compound societies, and, again, doubly compound ones, there result superpositions of ranks. And the general effect is that, while the ranks of the conquering society become respectively higher than those which existed before, the ranks of the con- quered society become respectively lower. The class-divisions thus formed during the earlier stages of militancy, are traversed and obscured as fast as many small societies are consolidated into one large society. Eanks referring to local organization are gradually replaced by ranks referring to general organization. Instead of deputy and sub-deputy governing agents who are the militant owners of the sub-divisions they rule, there come governing agents who more or less clearly form strata running throughout the POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. 310 society as a whole — a concomitant of developed political administration. Chiefly, however, we have to note that while the higher political evolution of large social aggregates, tends to break down the divisions of rank which grew up in the small com- ponent social aggregates, by substituting other divisions, these original divisions are still more broken down by grow- ing industrialism. Generating a wealth that is not connected with rank, this initiates a competing power; and at the same time, by establishing the equal positions of citizens before the law in respect of trading transactions, it weakens those divisions which at the outset expressed inequalities of position before the law. As verifying these interpretations, I may add that they harmonize with the interpretations of ceremonial insti- tutions already given. When the conquered enemy is made a slave, and mutilated by taking a trophy from his body, we see simultaneously originating the deepest political distinction and the ceremony which marks it ; and with the continued militancy that compounds and re-coinpounds social groups, there goes at once the development of political distinctions and the development of ceremonies marking them. And as we before saw that growing industrialism diminishes the rigour of ceremonial rule, so here w 7 e see that it tends to destroy those class- divisions which militancy originates, and to establish quite alien ones which indicate differences of position consequent on differences of aptitude for the various functions which an industrial society needs. CHAPTER V. POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. § 464 . The conceptions of biologists have been greatly en- larged by the discovery that organisms which, when adult, appear to have scarcely anything in common, were, in their first stages, very similar ; and that, indeed, all organisms start with a common structure. Recognition of this truth has re- volutionized not only their ideas respecting the relations of organisms to one another, but also their ideas respecting the relations of the parts of each organism to one another. If societies have evolved, and if that mutual dependence of their parts which cooperation implies, has been gradually reached, then the implication is that however unlike their developed structures become, there is a rudimentary structure with which they all set out. And if there can be recognized any such primitive unity, recognition of it will help us to interpret the ultimate diversity. We shall understand better how in each society the several components of the political agency have come to be what we now see them; and also how those of one society are related to those of another. Setting out with an unorganized horde, including both sexes and all ages, let us ask what must happen when some public question, as that of migration, or of defence against enemies, has to be decided. The assembled individuals will fall, more or less clearly, into two divisions. The elder, the stronger, and those whose sagacity and courage have been proved by experience, will form the smaller part, who carry 312 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. on the discussion ; while the larger part, formed of the young, the weak, and the undistinguished, will be listeners, who usually do no more than express from time to time assent or dissent. A further inference may safely be drawn. In the cluster of leading men there is sure to be one whose weight is greater than that of any other — some aged hunter, some distinguished warrior, some cunning medicine-man, who will have more than his individual share in forming the resolution finally acted upon. That is to say, the entire assemblage will resolve itself into three parts. To use a biological metaphor, there will, out of the general mass, be differentiated a nucleus and a nucleolus. These first traces of political structure which we infer a priori must spontaneously arise, we find have arisen among the rudest peoples : repetition having so strengthened them as to produce a settled order. When, among the aborigines of Victoria, a tribe plans revenge on another tribe supposed to have killed one of its members, “ a council is called of all the old men of the tribe. . . The women form an outer circle round the men. . . The chief [simply ‘ a native of influence ’] opens the council.” And what we here see hap- pening in an assemblage having no greater differences than those based on strength, age, and capacity, happens when, later, these natural distinctions have gained definiteness. In illustration may be named the account which Schoolcraft gives of a conference at which the Chippewas, Ottawas, and Pottowattomies met certain United States’ Commissioners : Schoolcraft being himself present. After the address of the head commissioner had been delivered, the speaking on be- half of the Indians was carried on by the principal chiefs : the lead being taken by “ a man venerable for his age and standing.” Though Schoolcraft does not describe the as- semblage of undistinguished people, yet that they were pre- sent is shown by a passage in one of the native speeches : — “ Behold ! see my brethren, both young and old — the warriors and chiefs — the women and children of my nation.” And POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 313 that the political order observed on this occasion was the usual order, is implied by its recurrence even in parts of America where chiefs have become marked off by ascribed nobility ; as instance the account of one of the Central American tribes, who “ have frequent reunions in their council-house at night. The hall is then lighted up by a large fire, and the people sit with uncovered heads, listening respectfully to the observations and decisions of the ahuales — men over forty years of age, who have occupied public positions, or distinguished themselves in some way.” Among peoples unlike in type and remote in locality, we find, modi- fied in detail but similar in general character, this primitive governmental form. Of the Hill tribes of India may be in- stanced the Khonds, of whom we read that — u Assemblies of the whole tribe, or of any of its sub-divisions, are con- vened, to determine questions of general importance. The members of every society, however, have a right to be present at all its councils, and to give their voices on the questions mooted, although the patri- archs alone take a part in their public discussion” . . . “ The federal patriarchs, in like manner, consult with the heads of tribes, and assemble when necessary the entire population of the federal group.” In New Zealand, too, the government was conducted in accordance with public opinion expressed in general assem- blies ; and the chiefs “ could not declare peace or war, or do anything affecting the whole people, without the sanction of the majority of the clan.” Of the Tahitians, Ellis tells us that the king had a few chiefs as advisers, but that no affair of national importance could be undertaken without consult- ing the land-holders or second rank, and also that public assemblies were held. Similarly of the Malagasy. “ The greatest national council in Madagascar is an assembly of the people of the capital, and the heads of the provinces, towns, villages, &c.” The king usually presides in person. Though in these last cases we see considerable changes in the relative powers of the three components, so that the inner few have gained in authority at the expense of the outer many, yet all three are still present ; and they continue to 314 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. be present when we pass to sundry historic peoples. Even of the Phoenicians, Movers notes that “ in the time of Alex- ander a war was decided upon by the Tyrians without the consent of the absent king, the senate acting together with the popular assembly.” Then there is the familiar case of the Homeric Greeks, whose Agora, presided over by the king, was “ an assembly for talk, communication and discussion to a certain extent by the chiefs, in presence of the people as listeners and sympathisers,” who were seated around ; and that the people were not always passive is shown by the story of Thersites, who, ill-used though he was by Odysseus and derided by the crowd for interfering, had first made his harangue. Again, the king, the senate, and the freemen, in early Roman times, stood in relations which had manifestly grown out of those existing in the original assembly ; for though the three did not simultaneously co-operate, yet on important occasions the king communicated his proposals to the assembled burgesses, who expressed their approval or dis- approval, and the clan-chiefs, forming the senate, though they did not debate in public, had yet such joint power that they could, on occasion, negative the decision of king and bur- gesses. Concerning the primitive Germans, Tacitus, as trans- lated by Mr. Freeman, writes — " On smaller matters the chiefs debate, on greater matters all men ; but so that those things whose final decision rests with the whole people are first handled by the chiefs. . . . The multitude sits armed in such order as it thinks good ; silence is proclaimed by the priests, who have also the right of enforcing it. Presently the king or chief, according to the age of each, according to his birth, according to his glory in war or his eloquence, is listened to, speaking rather by the influence of persuasion than by the power of commanding. If their opinions give offence, they are thrust aside with a shout ; if they approved, the hearers clash their spears.” Similarly among the Scandinavians, as shown us in Iceland, where, besides the general Al-thing annually held, which it was “ disreputable for a freeman not to attend,” and at which “ people of all classes in fact pitched their tents,” there were local assemblies called Var-things “ attended by all the free- POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 315 men of the district, with a crowd of retainers . . . both for the discussion of public affairs and the administration of jus- tice . . . Within the circle [formed for administering justice] sat the judges, the people standing on the outside.” In the ac- count given by Mr. Freeman of the yearly meetings in the Swiss cantons of Uri and Appenzell, we may trace this primitive political form as still existing ; for though the presence of the people at large is the fact principally pointed out, yet there is named, in the case of Uri, the body of magistrates or chosen chiefs who form the second element, as well as the head magis- trate who is the first element. And that in ancient England there was a kindred constitution of the Witenagemot, is in- directly proved; as witness the following passage from Freeman’s Growth of the English Constitution : — “ No ancient record gives us any clear or formal account of the constitu- tion of that body. It is commonly spoken of in a vague way as a gathering of the wise, the noble, the great men. But, alongside pas- sages like these, we find other passages which speak of it in a way which implies a far more popular constitution. King Eadward is said to be chosen King by ‘ all folk.’ Earl Godwine 6 makes his speech before the king and all the people of the land. ; ” And the implication, as Mr. Freeman points out, is that the share taken by the people in the proceedings was that of expressing by shouts their approval or disapproval. This form of ruling agency is thus shown to be the funda- mental form, by its presence at the outset of social life and by its continuance under various conditions. Not among peoples of superior types only, such as Aryans and some Semites, do we find it, but also among sundry Malayo-Poly- nesians, among the red men of North America, the Dravidian tribes of the Indian hills, the aborigines of Australia. In fact, as already implied, governmental organization could not possibly begin in any other way. On the one hand, no con- trolling force at first exists save that of the aggregate will as manifested in the assembled horde. On the other hand, lead- ing parts in determining this aggregate will are inevitably taken by the few whose superiority is recognized. And of 5 316 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. these predominant few, some one is sure to be most pre- dominant. That which we have to note as specially significant, is not that a free form of government is the primitive form ; though this is an implication which may be dwelt upon. Nor are we chiefly concerned with the fact that at the very begin- ning there shows itself that separation of the superior few from the inferior many, which becomes marked in later stages ; though this, too, is a fact which may be singled out and emphasized. Nor is attention to be mainly directed to the early appearance of a man whose controlling power is greater than that of any other ; though the evidence given may be cited to prove this. But here we have to note, particularly, the truth that at the outset may be discerned the vague out- lines of a tri-une political structure. § 465. Of course the ratios among the powers of these three components are in no two cases quite the same ; and, as implied in sundry of the above examples, they everywhere undergo more or less change — change determined here by the emotional natures of the men composing the group ; there by the physical circumstances as favouring or hindering inde- pendence ; now by the activities as warlike or peaceful ; and now by the exceptional characters of particular individuals. Unusual sagacity, skill, or strength, habitually regarded by primitive men as supernatural, may give to some member of the tribe an influence which, transmitted to a successor sup- posed to inherit his supernatural character, establishes an authority subordinating both that of the other leading men and that of the mass. Or from a division of labour such that while some remain exclusively warriors the rest are in a measure otherwise occupied, it may result that the two supe- rior components of the political agency get power to over-ride the third. Or the members of the third, keeping up habits which make coercion of them difficult or impossible, may maintain a general predominance over the other two. And then the relations of these three governing elements to the POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 317 entire community may, and ordinarily do, undergo change by the formation of a passive class excluded from their delibera- tions — a class at first composed of the women and afterwards containing also the slaves or other dependents. War successfully carried on, not only generates this passive class, but also, implying as it does subjection to leaders, changes more or less decidedly the relative powers of these three parts of the political agency. As, other things equal, groups in which there is little subordination are subjugated by groups in which subordination is greater, there is a ten- dency to the survival and spread of groups in which the con- trolling power of the dominant few becomes relatively great. In like manner, since success in war largely depends on that promptitude and consistency of action which singleness of will gives, there must, where warfare is chronic, be a tendency for members of the ruling group to become more and more obedient to its head : failure in the struggle for existence among tribes otherwise equal, being ordinarily a consequence of disobedience. And then it is also to be noted that the over-runnings of societies one by another, repeated and re- repeated as they often are, have the effect of obscuring and even obliterating the traces of the original structure. While, however, recognizing the fact that during political evolution these three primitive components alter their propor- \ tions in various ways and degrees, to the extent that some of them become mere rudiments or wholly disappear, it will greatly alter our conception of political forms if we remember that they are all derived from this primitive form — that a despotism, an oligarchy, or a democracy, is a type of govern- ment in which one of the original components has greatly developed at the expense of the other two; and that the various mixed types are to be arranged according to the degrees in which one or other of the original components has the greater influence. § 466. Is there any fundamental unity of political forces 318 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. accompanying this fundamental unity of political forms? While losing sight of the common origin of the structures, have we not also become inadequately conscious of the common source of their powers ? How prone we are to forget the ultimate while thinking of the proximate, it may be worth while pausing a moment to observe. One who in a storm watches the breaking-up of a wreck or the tearing down of a sea-wall, is impressed by the immense energy of the waves. Of course, when it is pointed out that in the absence of winds no such results can be produced, he recognizes the truth that the sea is in itself powerless, and that the power enabling it to destroy vessels and piers is given by the currents of air which roughen its surface. If he stops short here, however, he fails to identify the force which works these striking changes. Intrinsically, the air is just as passive as the water is. There would be no winds were it not for the varying effects of the Sun’s heat on different parts of the Earth’s surface. Even when he has traced back thus far the energy which undermines cliffs and makes shingle, he has not reached its source ; for in the absence of that con- tinuous concentration of the solar mass caused by the mutual gravitation of its parts, there would be no solar radiations. The tendency here illustrated, which all have in some degree and most in a great degree, to associate power with the visible agency exercising it rather than with its incon- spicuous source, has, as above implied, a vitiating influence on conceptions at large, and, among others, on political ones. Though the habit, general in past times, of regarding the powers of governments as inherent, has been, by the growth of popular institutions, a good deal qualified ; yet, even now, there is no clear apprehension of the fact that governments are not themselves powerful, but are the instrumentalities of a power. This power existed before governments arose ; governments were themselves produced by it ; and it ever continues to be that which, disguised more or less completely, works through them. Let us go back to the beginning. POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 319 The Greenlanders are entirely without political control; having nothing which represents it more nearly than the deference paid to the opinion of some old man, skilled in seal- catching and the signs of the weather. But a Greenlander who is aggrieved by another, has his remedy in what is called a singing combat. He composes a satirical poem, and challenges his antagonist to a satirical duel in face of the tribe : “ he who has the last word wins the trial.” And then Crantz adds — “ nothing so effectually restrains a Greenlander from vice, as the dread of public disgrace.” Here we see operating in its original unqualified way, that governing influence of public sentiment which precedes more special governing influences. The dread of social reprobation is in some cases enforced by the dread of banishment. Among the otherwise unsubordinated Australians, they “ punish each other for such offences as theft, sometimes by expulsion from the camp.” Of one of the Columbian tribes we read that “ the Salish can hardly be said to have any regular form of government and then, further, we read that “ criminals are sometimes punished by banishment from their tribe.” Certain aborigines of the Indian hills, widely unlike these Columbians in type and in mode of life, show us a similar relation between undeveloped political restraint and the restraint of aggregate feeling. Among the Bodo and the Dhimals, whose village heads are simply respected elders with no coercive powers, those who offend against customs “ are admonished, fined, or excommunicated, according to the degree of the offence.” But the controlling influence of public sentiment in groups which have ^little or no organization, is best shown in the force with which it acts on those who are bound to avenge murders. Concerning the Australian aborigines, Sir George Grey writes : — “ The holiest duty a native is called on to perform is that of avenging the death of his nearest relation, for it is his peculiar duty to do so ; until he has fulfilled this task, he is constantly taunted by the old women ; his wives, if he is married, would soon quit him ; if he is un- married, not a single young woman would speak to him ; his mother 320 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. would constantly cry, and lament that she should ever have given birth to so degenerate a son ; his father would treat him with contempt, and reproaches would constantly be sounded in his ear.” We have next to note that for a long time after political control has made its appearance, it remains conspicuously subordinate to this control of general feeling ; both because, while there are no developed governmental structures, the head man has but little ability to enforce his will, and because such ability as he has, if unduly exercised, causes desertion. All parts of the world furnish illustrations. In America among the Snake Indians “ each individual is his own master, and the only control to which his conduct is subjected, is the advice of a chief supported by his influence over the opinions of the rest of the tribe.” Of a Chinook chief w~e are told that his ability to render service to his neighbours, and the popularity which follows it, is at once the foundation and the measure of his authority.” If a Dakota “ wishes to do mis- chief, the only way a chief can influence him is to give him something, or pay him to desist from his evil intentions. The chief has no authority to act for the tribe, and dare not do it.” And among the Creeks, more advanced in political organiza- tion though they are, the authority of the elected chiefs “ con- tinues during good behaviour. The disapproval of the body of the people is an effective bar to the exercise of their powers and functions.” Turning to Asia, we read that the bais or chiefs of the Khirgiz “ have little power over them for good or evil. In consideration of their age and blood, some deference to their opinions is shown, but nothing more.” The Ostyaks “ pay respect, in the fullest sense of the word, to their chief, if wise and valiant, but this homage is voluntary, and founded on personal regard.” And of the Naga chiefs Butler says — “ Their orders are obeyed so .far only as they accord with the wishes and convenience of the com- munity.” So, too, is it in parts of Africa ; as instance the Koranna Hottentots. “ A chief or captain presides over each clan or kraal, being usually the person of greatest pro- POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 321 perty; but his authority is extremely limited, and only obeyed so far as it meets the general approbation.” And even among the more politically-organized Kaffirs, there is a kindred restraint. The king “ makes laws and executes them according to his sole will. Yet there is a. power to balance his in the people: he governs only so long as they choose to obey.” They leave him if he governs ill. In its primitive form, then, political power is the feeling of the community, acting through an agency which it has either informally or formally established. Doubtless, from the beginning, the power of the chief is in part personal : his greater strength, courage, or cunning, enables him in some degree to enforce his individual will. But, as the evidence shows, his individual will is but a small factor ; and the autho- rity he wields is proportionate to the degree in which he expresses the wills of the rest. § 467. While this public feeling, which first acts by itself and then partly through an agent, is to some extent the feeling spontaneously formed by those concerned, it is to a much larger extent the opinion imposed on them or prescribed for them. In the first place, the emotional nature prompting the general mode of conduct is derived from ancestors — is a product of all ancestral activities ; and in the second place, the special desires which, directly or indirectly, determine the courses pursued, are induced during early life by seniors, and enlisted on behalf of beliefs and usages which the tribe inherits. The governing sentiment is, in short, mainly the accumulated and organized sentiment of the past. It needs but to remember the painful initiation which, at a prescribed age, each member of a tribe undergoes (submitting to circumcision, or knocking out of teeth, or gashing of the flesh, or tatooing) — it needs but to remember that from these imperative customs there is no escape; to see that the directive force which exists before a political agency arises, and which afterwards makes the political agency its organ, 322 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. is the gradually-formed opinion of countless preceding gene- rations ; or rather, not the opinion, which, strictly speaking, is an intellectual product wholly impotent, but the emotion associated with the opinion. This w^e everywhere find to be at the outset the chief controlling power. The notion of the Tupis that “ if they departed from the customs of their forefathers they should be destroyed,” may be named as a definite manifestation of the force with which this transmitted opinion acts. In one of the rudest tribes of the Indian hills, the Juangs, less clothed than even Adam and Eve are said to have been, the women long adhered to their bunches of leaves in the belief that change was wrong. Of the Koranna Hottentots we read that “ when ancient usages are not in the way, every man seems to act as is right in his own eyes.” Though the Damara chiefs “have the power of governing arbitrarily, yet they venerate the tradi- tions and customs of their ancestors.” Smith says, “laws the Araucanians can scarcely be said to have, though there are many ancient usages which they hold sacred and strictly observe.” According to Brooke, among the Dyaks custom simply seems to have become law, and breaking the custom leads to a fine. In the minds of some clans of the Malagasy, “ innovation and injury are .... inseparable, and the idea of improvement altogether inadmissible.” This control by inherited usages is not simply as strong in groups of men who are politically unorganized, or but little organized, as it is in advanced tribes and nations, but it is stronger. As Sir John Lubbock remarks — “No savage is free. All over the world his daily life is regulated by a complicated and apparently most inconvenient set of customs (as forcible as laws), of quaint prohibitions and privileges.” Though one of these rude societies appears structureless, yet its ideas and usages form a kind of invisible framework for it, serving rigorously to restrain certain classes of its actions. And this invisible framework has been slowly and unconsciously shaped, during daily activities impelled by pre- POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 323 vailing feelings and guided by prevailing thoughts, through generations stretching back into the far past. In brief, then, before any definite agency for social control is developed, there exists a control arising partly from the public opinion of the living, and more largely from the public opinion of the dead. § 468. But now let us note definitely a truth implied in some of the illustrations above given — the truth that when a political agency has been evolved, its power, largely de- pendent on present public opinion, is otherwise almost wholly dependent on past public opinion. The ruler, in part the organ of the wills of those around, is in a still greater degree the organ of the wills of those who have passed away ; and his own will, much restrained by the first, is still more restrained by the last. For his function as regulator is mainly that of enforcing the inherited rules of conduct which embody ancestral senti- ments and ideas. Everywhere we are shown this. Among the Arafuras such decisions as are given by their elders, are “according to the customs of their forefathers, which are held in the highest regard.” So is it with the Khirgiz : “ the judg- ments of the Bis, or esteemed elders, are based on the known and universally-recognized customs.” And in Sumatra “ they are governed, in their various disputes, by a set of long- established customs ( adat ), handed down to them from their ancestors. . . . The chiefs, in pronouncing their decisions, are not heard to say, "so the law directs/ but "such is the custom/ ” As fast as custom passes into law, the political head be- comes still more clearly an agent through whom the feelings of the dead control the actions of the living. That the power he exercises is mainly a power which acts through him, we see on noting how little ability he has to resist it if he wishes to do so. His individual will is practically in- operative save where the overt or tacit injunctions of departed 324 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. generations leave him free. Thus in Madagascar, “ in cases where there is no law, custom, or precedent, the word of the sovereign is sufficient/' Among the East Africans, “ the only limit to the despot's power is the Ada or precedent/’ Of the J avans, Raffles writes — “ the only restraint upon the will of the head of the government is the custom of the country, and the regard which he has for his character among his sub- jects/’ In Sumatra the people “do not acknowledge a right in the chiefs to constitute what laws they think proper, or to repeal or alter their ancient usages, of which they are extremely tenacious and jealous.” And how imperative is con- formity to the beliefs and sentiments of progenitors, is shown by the fatal results apt to occur from disregarding them. 66 ‘ The King of Ashantee, although represented as a despotic monarch .... is not in all respects beyond control/ He is under an 4 obliga- tion to observe the national customs which have been handed down to the people from remote antiquity ; and a practical disregard of this obligation, in the attempt to change some of the customs of their fore- fathers, cost Osai Quamina his throne/ ” Which instance reminds us how commonly, as now among the Hottentots, as in the past among the ancient Mexicans, and as throughout the histories of civilized peoples, rulers have engaged, on succeeding to power, not to change the esta- blished order. § 469. Doubtless the proposition that a government is in the main but an agency through which works the force of public feeling, present and past, seems at variance with the many facts showing how great may be the power of a ruling man himself. Saying nothing of a tyrant's ability to take lives for nominal reasons or none at all, to make groundless confiscations, to transfer subjects bodily from one place to another, to exact contributions of money and labour without stint, we are apparently shown by his ability to begin and carry on wars which sacrifice his subjects wholesale, that his single will may over-ride the united wills of all others. In what way, then, must the original statement be qualified ? POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 325 While holding that, in unorganized groups of men, the feeling manifested as public opinion controls political con- duct, just as it controls the conduct distinguished as cere- monial and religious; and while holding that governing agencies, during their early stages, are at once the products of aggregate feeling, derive their powers from it, and are restrained by it ; we must admit that these primitive re- i lations become complicated when, by war, small groups are compounded and re-compounded into great ones. Where the society is largely composed of subjugated people held down by superior force, the normal relation above described no longer exists. We must not expect to find in a rule coercively established by an invader, the same traits as in a rule that has grown up from within. Societies formed by conquest may be, and frequently are, composed of two societies, which are in large measure, if not entirely, alien ; and in them there cannot arise a political force from the aggregate wilL Under such conditions the political head either derives his power exclusively from the feeling of the dominant class, or else, setting the diverse feelings originated in the upper and lower classes, one against the other, is enabled so to make his indi- vidual will the chief factor. After making which qualifications, however, it may still be contended that ordinarily, nearly all the force exercised by the governing agency originates from the feeling, if not of the £ whole community, yet of the part which is able to manifest its feeling. Though the opinion of the subjugated and un- armed lower society becomes of little account as a political factor, yet the opinion of the dominant and armed upper society continues to be the main cause of political action. What we are told of the Congo people, that “ the king, who reigns as a despot over the people, is often disturbed in the exercise of his power by the princes his vassals,” — what we are told of the despotically-governed Dahomans, that “ the ministers, war-captains, and feetishers may be, and often are, individually punished by the king : collectively they are too 326 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. strong for him, and without their cordial cooperation he would soon cease to reign is w r hat we recognize as having been true, and as being still true, in various better-known societies where the supreme head is nominally absolute. From the time when the Koman emperors were chosen by the soldiers and slain when they did not please them, to the present time w T hen, as we are told of Kussia, the desire of the army often determines the will of the Czar, there have been many illustrations of the truth that an autocrat is politically strong or weak according as many or few of the influential classes give him their support ; and that even the sentiments of those who are politically prostrate occasionally affect political action ; as instance the influence of Turkish fanaticism over the decisions of the Sultan. A number of facts must be remembered if v r e are rightly to estimate the power of the aggregate will in comparison with the power of the autocrat’s will. There is the fact that the autocrat is obliged to respect and maintain the great mass of institutions and laws produced by past sentiments and ideas, which have acquired a religious sanction ; so that, as in ancient Egypt, dynasties of despots live and die leaving the social order essentially unchanged. There is the fact that a serious change of the social order, at variance w r ith general feeling, is likely afterwards to be reversed ; as when, in Egypt, Amenhotep IV., spite of a rebellion, succeeded in establishing a new religion, which was abolished in a succeeding reign ; and there is the allied fact that laws much at variance with the general will prove abortive, as, for instance, the sumptuary laws made by medieval kings, which, continually re-enacted, continually failed. There is the fact that, supreme as he may be, and divine as the nature ascribed to him, the all-powerful monarch is often shackled by usages which make his daily life a slavery : the opinions of the living oblige him to fulfil the dictates of the dead. There is the fact that if he does not conform, or if he otherwise produces by his acts much adverse feeling, his servants, civil and military, refuse to act, POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 327 or turn against him ; and in extreme cases there comes an example of “ despotism tempered by assassination.” And there is the final fact that habitually in societies where an offending autocrat is from time to time removed, another autocrat is set up : the implication being that the average sentiment is of a kind which not only tolerates but desires autocracy. That which some call loyalty and others call servility, both creates the absolute ruler and gives him the power he exercises. But the cardinal truth, difficult adequately to appreciate, is that while the forms and laws of each society are the consoli- dated products of the emotions and ideas of those who lived throughout the past, they are made operative by the subordi- nation of existing emotions and ideas to them. We are familiar with the thought of “ the dead hand ” as controlling the doings of the living in the uses made of property ; but the effect of “ the dead hand ” in ordering life at large through the established political system, is immeasureably greater. That which, from hour to hour in every country, governed despotically or otherwise, produces the obedience making political action possible, is the accumulated and organized sentiment felt towards inherited institutions made sacred by tradition. Hence it is undeniable that, taken in its widest acceptation, the feeling of the community is the sole source of political power : in those communities, at least, which are not under foreign domination. It was so at the outset of social life, and it still continues substantially so. § 470. It has come to be a maxim of science that in the causes still at work, are to be identified the causes which, similarly at work during past times, have produced the state of things now existing. Acceptance of this maxim, and pur- suit of the inquiries suggested by it, lead to verifications of the foregoing conclusions. For day after day, every public meeting illustrates afresh this same differentiation characterizing the primitive political 328 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. agency, and illustrates afresh the actions of its respective parts. There is habitually the great body of the less distin- guished, forming the audience, whose share in the proceed- ings consists in expressing approval or disapproval, and say- ing aye or no to the resolutions proposed. There is the smaller part, occupying the platform — the men whose wealth, rank, or capacity, give them influence — the local chiefs, by whom the discussions are carried on. And there is the chosen head, commonly the man of greatest mark to be obtained, who exercises a recognized power over speakers and audience — the temporary king. Even an informally-summoned assemblage soon resolves itself into these divisions more or less distinctly ; and when the assemblage becomes a perma- nent body, as of the men composing a commercial company, or a philanthropic society, or a club, definiteness is quickly given to the three divisions — president or chairman, board or committee, proprietors or members. To which add that, though at first, like the meeting of the primitive horde or the modern public meeting, one of these permanent associations voluntarily formed, exhibits a distribution of powers such that the select few and their head are subordinate to the mass ; yet, as circumstances determine, the proportions of the respective powers usually change more or less decidedly. Where the members of the mass besides being much interested in the transactions, are so placed that they can easily co- operate, they hold in check the select few and their head ; but where wide distribution, as of railway-shareholders, hinders joint action, the select few become, in large measure, an oligarchy, and out of the oligarchy there not unfrequently grows an autocrat : the constitution becomes a despotism tempered by revolution. In saying that from hour to hour proofs occur that the force possessed by a political agency is derived from aggregate feeling, partly embodied in the consolidated system which has come down from the past, and partly excited by immediate circumstances, I do not refer only to the proofs that among POLITICAL FORMS AND FORCES. 329 ourselves governmental actions are habitually thus determined, and that the actions of all minor bodies, temporarily or per- manently incorporated, are thus determined. I refer, rather, to illustrations of the irresistible control exercised by popular sentiment over conduct at large. Such facts as that, while general opinion is in favour of duelling law does not prevent it, and that sacred injunctions backed by threats of damnation, fail to check iniquitous aggressions on foreign peoples when the prevailing passions prompt them, alone suffice to show that legal codes and religious creeds, with the agencies en- forcing them, are impotent in face of an adverse state of mind. On remembering the eagerness for public applause and the dread of public disgrace which stimulate and restrain men, we cannot question that the diffused manifestations of feeling habitually dictate their careers, when their immediate neces- sities have been satisfied. It requires only to contemplate the social code which regulates life, down even to the colour of an evening neck-tie, and to note how those who dare not break this code have no hesitation in smuggling, to see that an unwritten law enforced by opinion is more peremptory than a written law not so enforced. And still more on ob- serving that men disregard the just claims of creditors, who for goods given cannot get the money, while they are anxious to discharge so-called debts of honour to those who have rendered neither goods nor services, we are shown that the control of prevailing sentiment, unenforced by law and reli- gion, may be more potent than law and religion together when they are backed by sentiment less strongly manifested. Looking at the total activities of men, we are obliged to admit that they are still, as they were at the outset of social life, guided by the aggregate feeling, past and present ; and that the political agency, itself a gradually-developed product of such feeling, continues still to be in the main the vehicle for a specialized portion of it, regulating actions of certain kinds. Partly, of course, I am obliged here to set forth this general truth as an essential element of political theory. My excuse 330 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. for insisting at some length on what appears to be a trite con- clusion, must be that, however far nominally recognized, it is actually recognized to a very small extent. Even in our own country, where non- political agencies spontaneously produced and worked are many and large, and still more in most other countries less characterized by them, there is no due con- sciousness of the truth that the combined impulses which work through political agencies, can, in the absence of such agencies, produce others through which to work. Politicians reason as though State-instrumentalities have intrinsic power, which they have not, and as though the feeling which creates them has not intrinsic power, which it has. Evidently their actions must be greatly affected by reversal of these ideas. CHAPTEE VI. POLITICAL HEADS— CHIEFS, KINGS, etc. § 471. Of the three components of the tri-une political struc- ture traceable at the outset, we have now to follow the develop- ment of the first. Already in the last two chapters something has been said, and more has been implied, respecting that most important differentiation which results in the establish- ment of a headship. What was there indicated under its general aspects has here to be elaborated under its special aspects. “ When Eink asked the Nicobarians who among them was the chief, they replied laughing, how could he believe that one could have power against so many V I quote this as a reminder that there is, at first, resistance to the assumption of supremacy by one member of a group — resistance which, though in some types of men small, is in most considerable, and in a few very great. To instances already given of tribes practically chief less may be added, from America, the Haidahs, among whom “ the people seemed all equal the Californian tribes, among whom “ each individual does as he likes the Navajos, among whom "each is sovereign in his own right as a warrior and from Asia the Angamies, who “ have no recognized head or chief, although they elect a spokesman, who, to all intents and purposes, is powerless and irrespon - sible” Such small subordination as rude groups show, occurs only 332 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. when the need for joint action is imperative, and control is required to make it efficient. Instead of recalling before- named examples of temporary chieftainship, I may here give some others. Of the Lower Californians we read — “ In hunt- ing and war they have one or more chiefs to lead them, who are selected only for the occasion.” Of the Flatheads’ chiefs it is said that “ with the war their power ceases/ 5 Among the Sound Indians the chief “has no authority, and only directs the movements of his band in warlike incursions.” As observed under another head, this primitive insubordi- nation has greater or less play according as the environment and the habits of life hinder or favour coercion. The Lower Californians, above instanced as chiefless, Baegert says resemble “ herds of wild swine, which run about according to their own liking, being together to-day and scattered to- morrow, till they meet again by accident at some future time.” “ The chiefs among the Chipewyans are now totally without power,” says Franklin; and these people exist as small migratory bands. Of the Abipones, who are “ impatient of agriculture and a fixed home,” and “ are continually moving from place to place,” Dobrizhoffer writes — “they neither revere their cacique as a master, nor pay him tribute or attendance as is usual with other nations.” The like holds under like conditions with other races remote in type. Of the Bedouins Burckhardt remarks “ the sheikh has no fixed authority and according to another writer “ a chief, who has drawn the bond of allegiance too tight, is deposed or abandoned, and becomes a mere member of a tribe or remains without one.” And now, having noted the original absence of political control, the resistance it meets with, and the circumstances which facilitate evasion of it, we may ask what causes aid its growth. There are several ; and chieftainship becomes settled in proportion as they cooperate. § 472. Among the members of the primitive group, slightly unlike in various ways and degrees, there is sure to be some POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 333 one who has a recognized superiority. This superiority may be of several kinds which we will briefly glance at. Though in a sense abnormal, the cases must be recognized in which the superiority is that of an alien immigrant. The headmen of the Khonds “ are usually descended from some daring adventurer” of Hindoo blood. Forsyth remarks the like of “ most of the chiefs ” in the highlands of Central Asia. And the traditions of Bochica among the Ghibchas, Amalivaca among the Tamanacs, and Quetzalcoatl among the Mexicans, imply kindred origins of chieftainships. Here, however, we are mainly concerned with superiorities arising within the tribe. The first to be named is that which goes with seniority. Though age, when it brings incapacity, is often among rude peoples treated with such disregard that the old are killed or left to die, yet, so long as capacity remains, the greater expe- rience accompanying age generally insures influence. The cliiefless Esquimaux show “ deference to seniors and strong men.” Burchell says that over the Bushmen, old men seem to exercise the authority of chiefs to some extent ; and the like holds true with the natives of Australia. Among the Fuegians “ the word of an old man is accepted as law by the young people.” Each party of Bock Veddahs “has a head- man, the most energetic senior of the tribe,” who divides the honey, &c. Even with sundry peoples more advanced the like holds. The Dyaks in North Borneo “ have no established chiefs, but follow the counsels of the old man to whom they are related;” and Edwards says of the ungoverned Caribs that “ to their old men, indeed, they allowed some kind of authority.” Naturally, in rude societies, the strong hand gives predomi- nance. Apart from the influence of age, “bodily strength alone procures distinction among ” the Bushmen. The leaders of the Tasmanians were tall and powerful men : “ instead of an elective or hereditary chieftancy, the place of command was yielded up to the bully of the tribe.” A remark of 334 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Sturt’s implies a like origin of supremacy among the Austra- lians. Similarly in South America. Of people on the Tapajos, Bates tells us that “ the footmarks of the chief could be distinguished from the rest by their great size and the length of the stride.” And in Bedouin tribes “ the fiercest, the strongest, and the craftiest obtains complete mastery over his fellows.” During higher stages physical vigour long con- tinues to be an all-important qualification; as in Homeric Greece, where even age did not compensate for decline of strength : “ an old chief, such as Peleus and Laertes, cannot retain his position.” Everyone knows that throughout Mediaeval Europe, maintenance of headship largely depended on bodily prowess. And even but two centuries ago in the Western Isles of Scotland, “ every Heir, or young Chieftain of a Tribe, w r as oblig’d in Honour to give a publick Specimen of his Valour, before he was own’d and declar’d Governor.” Mental superiority, alone or joined with other attributes, is a common cause of predominance. With the Snake Indians, the chief is no more than “the most confidential person among the warriors.” Schoolcraft says of the chief acknow- ledged by the Creeks that “ he is emiuent with the people only for his superior talents and political abilities and that over the Comanches “the position of a chief is not hereditary, but the result of his own superior cunning, knowledge, or success in war.” A chief of the Coroados is one “ who by his strength, cunning, and courage had obtained some command over them.” And the Ostiaks “ pay respect, in the fullest sense of the word, to their chief, if wise and valiant; but this homage is voluntary, and not a prerogative of his position.” Yet another source of governmental power in primitive tribes is largeness of possessions: wealth being at once an indirect mark of superiority and a direct cause of influence. With the Tacullies “any person may become a minty or chief who will occasionally provide a village feast.” “ Among the Tolewas, in Del Norte Country, money makes the chief.” The Spokanes have “ no regularly recognized chief,” “ but an POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 335 intelligent and rich man often controls the tribe by his influence.” Of the chiefless ISTavajos we read that “ every rich man has many dependants, and these dependants are obedient to his will, in peace and in war.” And to other evidence that it is the same in Africa, may be added the state- ment of Heuglin that “ a Dor chief is generally the richest and most reputable man of the village or neighbourhood.” But, naturally, in societies not yet politically developed, acknowledged superiority is ever liable to be competed with or replaced by superiority arising afresh. “ If an Arab, accompanied by his own relations only, has been suc- cessful on many predatory excursions against the enemy, he is joined by other friends ; and if his success still continues, he obtains the repu- tation of being i lucky f and he thus establishes a kind of second, or inferior agydship in the tribe.” So in Sumatra — “A commanding aspect, an insinuating manner, a ready fluency in discourse, and a penetration and sagacity in unravelling the little in- tricacies of their disputes, are qualities which seldom fail to procure to their possessor respect and influence, sometimes, perhaps, superior to that of an acknowledged chief.” And supplantings of kindred kinds occur among the Tongans and the Dyaks. At the outset then, what we before distinguished as the principle of efficiency is the sole principle of organization. Such political headship as exists, is acquired by one whose fitness asserts itself in the form of greater age, superior prowess, stronger will, wider knowledge, quicker insight, or larger wealth. But evidently supremacy which thus depends exclusively on personal attributes is but transitory. It is liable to be superseded by the supremacy of some more able man from time to time arising; and if not superseded, is ended by death. We have, then, to inquire how permanent chieftainship becomes established. Before doing this, how- ever, we must consider more fully the two kinds of superiority which especially conduce to chieftainship, and their modes of operation. 336 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. § 473. As bodily vigour is a cause of predominance within the tribe on occasions daily occurring, still more on occasions of war is it, when joined with courage, a cause of predomi- nance. War, therefore, tends to make more pronounced any authority of this kind which is incipient. Whatever reluctance other members of the tribe have to recognize the leadership of any one member, is likely to be over-ridden by their desire for safety when recognition of his leadership furthers that safety. This rise of the strongest and most courageous warrior to power is at first spontaneous, and afterwards by agreement more or less definite: sometimes joined with a process of testing. Where, as 'in Australia, each “ is esteemed by the rest only according to his dexterity in throwing or evading a spear/’ it is inferable that such superior capacity for war as is displayed, generates of itself such temporary chieftainship as exists. Where, as among the Comanches, any one who distinguishes himself by taking many “ horses or scalps, may aspire to the honours of chieftaincy, and is gradually inducted by a tacit popular consent,” this natural genesis is clearly shown. Very commonly, however, there is deliberate choice ; as by the Flatheads, among whom, “ except by the war-chiefs no real authority is exercised.” Skill, strength, courage, and endurance are in some cases deliberately tested. The King of Tonga has to undergo a trial : three spears are thrown at him, which he must ward off. “ The ability to climb up a large pole, well-greased, is a necessary qualification of a fight- ing chief among the Sea Dyaks;” and St. John says that in some cases, “ it was a custom in order to settle who should be chief, for the rivals to go out in search of a head : the first in finding one being victor.” Moreover, the need for an efficient leader tends ever to re-establish chieftainship where it has become only nominal or feeble. Edward says of the Caribs that “ in war, experi- ence had taught them that subordination was as requisite as courage ; they therefore elected their captains in their general POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 337 assemblies with great solemnity and “ put their pretensions to the proof with circumstances of outrageous barbarity” Similarly, “ although the Abipones neither fear their cacique as a judge, nor honour him as a master, yet his fellow-soldiers follow him as a leader and governor of the war, whenever the enemy is to be attacked or repelled.” These and like facts, of which there are abundance, have three kindred implications. One is that continuity of war conduces to permanence of chieftainship. A second is that, with increase of his influence as successful military head, the chief gains influence as civil head. A third is that there is thus initiated a union, maintained through subsequent phases of social evolution, between military supremacy and political supremacy. Not only among the uncivilized Hottentots, Malagasy, and others, is the chief or king head of the army — not only among such semi-civilized peoples as the ancient Peruvians and Mexicans, do we find the monarch one with the commander-in-chief; but the histories of extinct and surviving nations all over the world exemplify the connexion. In Egypt “ in the early ages, the offices of king and general were inseparable.” Assyrian sculptures and inscriptions represent the despotic ruler as also the conquering soldier ; as do the records of the Hebrews. Civil and military headship were united among the Homeric Greeks ; and in primitive Rome “ the general was ordinarily the king himself.” That throughout European history it has been so, and partially continues so even now in the more militant societies, needs no showing. How command of a wider kind follows military command, we cannot readily see in societies which have no records : we can but infer that along with increased power of coercion which the successful head-warrior gains, naturally goes the exercise of a stronger rule in civil affairs. That this has been so among peoples who have known histories, there is proof. Of the primitive Germans Sohm remarks that the Roman invasions had one result: — 333 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. “ The kingship became united with the leadership (become permanent) of the army, and, as a consequence, raised itself to a power [institution] in the State. The military subordination under the king-leader fur- thered political subordination under the "king Kingship after the invasions is a kingship clothed with supreme rights — a king- ship in our sense.” In like manner it is observed by Eanke that during the wars with the English in the fifteenth century — “ The French monarchy, whilst struggling for its very existence, acquired at the same time, and as the result of the struggle, a firmer organization. The expedients adopted to carry on the contest grew, as in other important cases, to national institutions.” And modern instances of the relation between successful militancy and the strengthening of political control, are fur- nished by the career of Napoleon and the recent history of the German Empire. Headship of the society, then, commonly beginning with the influence gained by the warrior of greatest power, bold- ness, and capacity, becomes established where activity in war gives opportunity for his superiority to show itself and to generate subordination ; and thereafter the growth of civil governorship continues primarily related to the exercise of militant functions. § 474. Very erroneous, however, would be the idea formed if no further origin for political headship were named. There is a kind of influence, in some cases operating alone and in other cases cooperating with that above specified, which is all- important. I mean the influence possessed by the medicine- man. That this arises as early as the other, can scarcely be said ; since, until the ghost-theory takes shape, there is no origin for it. But when belief in the spirits of the dead becomes current, the medicine-man, professing ability to control them, and inspiring faith in his pretensions, is regarded with a fear which prompts obedience. When we read of the Thlinkeets that the “ supreme feat of a conjuror’s power is to POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 339 throw one of his liege spirits into the body of one who refuses to believe in his power, upon which the possessed is taken with swooning and fits,” we may imagine the dread he excites, and the sway he consequently gains. From some of the lowest races upwards we find illustrations. Fitzroy says of the “ doctor-wizard among the Fuegians ” that he is the most cunning aiid most deceitful of his tribe, and that he has great influence over his companions. “ Though the Tas- manians were free from the despotism of rulers, they were swayed by the counsels, governed by the arts, or terrified by the fears, of certain wise men or doctors. These could not only mitigate suffering, but inflict it.” A chief of the Haidalis “ seems to be the principal sorcerer, and indeed to possess little authority save from his connexion with the preter- human powers.” The Dakota medicine-men — “ Are the greatest rascals in the tribe, and possess immense influence over the minds of the young, who are brought up in the belief of their supernatural powers The war-chief, who leads the party to war, is always one of these medicine -men, and is believed to have the power to guide the party to success, or save it from defeat.” Among more advanced peoples in Africa, supposed abilities to control invisible beings similarly give influence — strengthen- ing authority otherwise gained. It is so wit h the Amazulu : a chief “ practises magic on another chief before fighting with him;” and his followers have great confidence in him if he has much repute as a magician. Hence the sway acquired by Langalibalele, who, as Bishop Colenzo says, “ knows well the composition of that intelezi [used for controlling the weather] ; and he knows well, too, the war- medicine, i.e ., its component parts, being himself a doctor.” Still better is seen the governmental influence thus acquired in the case of the king of Obbo, who in time of drought calls his subjects together and explains to them — “ how much he regrets that their conduct has compelled him to afflict them with unfavourable weather, but that it is their own fault. . . . He must have goats and corn. 4 No goats, no rain ; that’s our contract, my friends,’ says Katchiba. . . . Should his people complain of too 6 340 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. much rain, he threatens to pour storms and lightning upon them for ever, unless they bring him so many hundred baskets of corn, &c., &c. . . . His subjects have the most thorough confidence in his power.” And the king is similarly supposed to exercise control over the weather among the people of Loango. A like connexion is traceable in the records of various extinct peoples in both hemispheres. Of Huitzilopochtli, the founder of the Mexican power, we read that “ a great wizard lie had been, and a sorcerer and every Mexican king on ascending the throne had to swear “ to make the sun go his course, to make the clouds pour down rain, to make the rivers run, and all fruits to ripen.” Reproaching his subjects for want of obedience, a Chibcha ruler told them they knew “that it was in his power to afflict them with pestilence, small-pox, rheumatism, and fever, and to make to grow as much grass, vegetables, and plants as they wanted.” Ancient Egyptian records yield indications of a similar early belief. Thothmes III., after being deified, “ was considered as the luck-bringing god of the country, and a preserver against the evil influence of wicked spirits and magicians/’ And it was thus with the Jews : — “ Rabbinical writings are never weary of enlarging upon the magical power and knowledge of Solomon. He was represented as not only king of the whole earth, but also as reigning over devils and evil spirits, and having the power of expelling them from the bodies of men and animals and also of delivering people to them.” The traditions of European peoples furnish kindred evidence. As before shown (§ 198) stories in the Heims-kringla saga imply that the Scandinavian ruler, Odin, was a medicine- man ; as were also Niort and Frey, his successors. And after recalling the supernatural weajpons and supernatural achieve- ments of early heroic kings, we can scarcely doubt that with them were in some cases associated those ascribed magical characters whence have descended the supposed powers of kings to cure diseases by touching. We shall the less doubt this on finding that like powers were attributed to subordinate rulers of early origin. There existed certain Breton nobles POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 341 whose spittle and touch were said to have curative pro- perties. Thus one important factor in the genesis of political head- ship, originates with the ghost- theory, and the concomitant rise of a belief that some men, having acquired power over ghosts, can obtain their aid. Generally the chief and the medicine-man are separate persons; and there then exists between them some conflict : they have competing authorities. But where the ruler joins with his power naturally gained, this ascribed supernatural power, his authority is necessarily much increased. Becalcitrant members of his tribe who might dare to resist him if bodily prowess alone could decide the struggle, do not dare if they think he can send one of his posse comitatus of ghosts to torment them. That rulers desire to unite the two characters, we have, in one case, distinct proof. Canon Callaway tells us that among the Amazulu, a chief will endeavour to discover a medicine-man’s secrets and afterwards kill him. § 475. Still there recurs the question — How does per- manent political headship arise ? Such political headship as results from bodily power, or courage, or sagacity, even when strengthened by supposed supernatural aid, ends with the life of any savage who gains it. The principle of efficiency, physical or mental, while it tends to produce a temporary differentiation into ruler and ruled, does not suffice to produce a permanent differentiation. There has to cooperate another principle, to which we now pass. Already we have seen that even in the rudest groups, age gives some predominance. Among both Fuegians and Australians, not only old men, but also old women, exercise authority. And that this respect for age, apart from other distinction, is an important factor in establishing political subordination, is implied by the curious fact that, in sundry advanced societies characterized by extreme governmental coercion, the respect due to age takes precedence of all other 342 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. respect. Sliarpe remarks of ancient Egypt that “ here as in Persia and J udaea the king’s mother often held rank above his wife.” In China, notwithstanding the inferior position of women socially and domestically, there exists this supremacy of the female parent, second only to that of the male parent ; and the like holds in Japan. As supporting the inference that subjection to parents prepares the way for subjection to rulers, I may add a converse fact. Of the Coroados, whose groups are so incoherent, we read that — “ The paje, however, has as little influence over the will of the multi- tude as any other, for they live without any bond of social union, neither under a republican nor a patriarchial form of government. Even family ties are very loose among them .... there is no regular precedency between the old and the young, for age appears to enjoy no respect among them.” And, as re-inforcing this converse fact, I may call attention to § 317, where it was shown that the Mantras, the Caribs, the Mapuches, the Brazilian Indians, the Gallinomeros, the Shoshones, the Navajos, the Californians, the Comanches, who submit very little or not at all to chiefly rule, display a filial submission which is mostly small and ceases early. But now under what circumstances does respect for age take that pronounced form seen in societies distinguished by great political subordination ? It was shown in § 319 that when men, passing from the hunting stage into the pastoral stage, began to wander in search of food for their domesti- cated animals, they fell into conditions favouring the forma- tion of patriarchal groups. We saw that in the primitive pastoral horde, the man, released from those earlier tribal influences which interfere with paternal power, and prevent settled relations of the sexes, was so placed as to acquire headship of a coherent cluster : the father became by right of the strong hand, leader, owner, master, of wife, children, and all he carried with him. There w^ere enumerated the influences which tended to make the eldest male a patriarch ; and it was shown that not only the Semites, Aryans, and Turanian races of Asia have exemplified this relation between POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 343 pastoral habits and the patriarchal organization, but that it recurs in South African races. Be the causes what they may, however, we find abundant proof that this family-supremacy of the eldest male, common among pastoral peoples and peoples who have passed through the pastoral stage into the agricultural stage, develops into political supremacy. Of the Santals Hunter says — “ The village government is purely patriarchial. Each hamlet has an original founder (the Manjhi-Hanan), who is regarded as the father of the community. He receives divine honours in the sacred grove, and transmits his authority to his descendants . 55 Of the compound family among the Khonds we read in Mac- pherson that — “ There it [paternal authority] reigns nearly absolute. It is a Khond’s maxim that a man’s father is his god, disobedience to whom is the greatest crime ; and all the members of a family live united in strict subordination to its head until his death . 55 And the growth of simple groups into compound and doubly-compound groups, acknowledging the authority of one who unites family headship with political headship, has been made familiar by Sir Henry Maine and others as coiiimon to early Greeks, Romans, Teutons, and as still affecting social organization among Hindoos and Sclavs. Here, then, we have making its appearance, a factor which conduces to permanence of political headship. As was pointed out in a foregoing chapter, while succession by efficiency gives plasticity to social organization, succession by inherit- ance gives it stability. Ho settled arrangement can arise in a primitive community so long as the function of each unit is determined exclusively by his fitness ; since, at his death, the arrangement, in so far as he was a part of it, must be recommenced. Only when his place is forthwith filled by one whose claim is admitted, does there begin a differentia- tion which survives through successive generations. And evidently in the earlier stages of social evolution, while the coherence is small and the want of structure great, it is requi- site that the principle of inheritance should, especially in re- 344 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. spect of the political headship, predominate over the principle of efficiency. Contemplation of the facts will make this clear. §476. Two primary forms of hereditary succession have to be considered. The system of kinship through females, com- mon among rude peoples, results in descent of property and power to brothers or to the children of sisters ; while the system of kinship through males, general among advanced peoples, results in descent of property and power to sons oi daughters. We have first to note that succession through females is less conducive to stable political headships than is succession through males. From the fact named when treating of the domestic rela- tions, that the system of kinship through females arises where unions of the sexes are temporary or unsettled, it is to be inferred that this system characterizes societies which are unadvanced in all ways, political included. We saw in § 294, that irregular connexions involve paucity and feebleness of known relationships, and a type of family the successive links of which are not strengthened by so many collateral links. A common consequence is that along with descent through females there either goes no chieftainship, or such chieftainship as exists is established by merit, or, if here- ditary, is usually unstable. The Australians and Tasmanians supply typical instances. Among the Haidahs and other savage peoples of Columbia, “ rank is nominally hereditary, for the most part by the female line and actual chieftain- ship “ depends to a great extent on wealth and ability in war.” Of other North American tribes the Chippewas, Comanches, and Snakes, show us the system of kinship through females joined with either absence of established headship or very feeble development of it. Passing to South America, the Arawaks and the Waraus may be instanced as having female descent and almost nominal, though hereditary, chiefs ; and the same may be said of the Caribs. A group of facts having much significance may now be POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 345 named. In many societies where descent of property and frank in the female line is the rule, an exception is made in the case of the political head ; and societies exemplifying this exception are societies in which political headship is relatively stable. Though in Fiji there is kinship through females, yet, according to Seemann, the ruler, chosen from the members of the royal family, is “ generally the son ” of the late ruler. In Tahiti, where the two highest ranks follow the primitive system of descent, male succession to rulership is so pro- nounced that, on the birth of an eldest son the father becomes simply a regent on his behalf. And among the Malagasy, along with a prevailing kinship through females, the sovereign either nominates his successor, or, failing this, the nobles ap- point, and “ unless positive disqualification exists, the eldest son is usually chosen.” Africa furnishes evidence of varied kinds. Though the Congo people, the Coast Negroes, and the Inland Negroes have formed communities of some size and complexity, notwithstanding that kinship through females obtains in the succession to the throne, yet we read of the first that allegiance is “ vague and uncertain of the second that, save where free in form, the government is “ an insecure and short-lived monarchic despotism and of the third that, where the government is not of mixed type, it is “ a rigid but insecure despotism.” Meanwhile, in the two most advanced and powerful states, stability of political headship goes along with departure, incipient or entire, from succession through females. In Ashantee, claims to the crown stand in this order — “the brother, the sister’s son, the son and in Dahomey there is male primogeniture. Further instances of this transition are yielded by extinct American civilizations. The Aztec conquerors of Mexico brought with them the system of kinship through females, and consequent law of succession ; but this law of succession was partially, or com- pletely, changed to succession through males. In Tezcuco and Tlacopan (divisions of Mexico) the eldest son inherited the kingship ; and in Mexico the choice of a king was limited 346 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. to tlie sons and brothers of the preceding king, ancient Peru, Gomara says — “ nephews inherit, and not son except in the case of the Yncas:” this exception in th case of the Yncas, having the strange peculiarity that “ the first-born of this brother and sister [i.e., the Ynca and his principal wife] was the legitimate heir to the king- dom”: an arrangement which made the line of descent unusually narrow and definite. And here we are brought back to Africa by the parallelism between the case of Peru and that of Egypt. “ In Egypt it was maternal descent that gave the right to property and to the throne. The same prevailed in Ethiopia. If the monarch married out of the royal family the children did not enjoy a legiti- mate right to the crown.” When we add the statement that the monarch was “ supposed to be descended from the gods, in the male and female line and when we join with this the further statement that there were royal marriages between brother and sister ; we see that like causes worked like effects in Egypt and in Peru. For in Peru the Ynca was of sup- posed divine descent ; inherited his divinity on both sides ; and married his sister to keep the divine blood unmixed. And in Peru, as in Egypt, there resulted royal succession in the male line, where, otherwise, succession through females prevailed. Ancient Ceylon, where “ the form of government was at all times an unmitigated despotism,” appears to have furnished a parallel case ; for Sir J. E. Tennant tells us that “ the Singhelese kings frequently married their sisters.” With this process of transition from the one law of descent to the other, implied by these last facts, may be joined some processes which preceding facts imply. In New Caledonia a “chief nominates his successor, if possible, in a son or brother the one choice implying descent in the male line and the other being consistent with descent in either male or female line. And in Madagascar, where the system of female kinship prevailed, “ the sovereign nominated his successor — naturally choosing a son.” Further it is manifest that where, POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 347 E se cases, when no nomination has been made the loose among members of the royal family, and are ed in their choice by eligibility, there may be, and naturally is, a departure from descent in the female line ; and this system of descent once broken through is likely for several reasons to be abolished. We are also intro- duced to another transitional process. For some of these cases are among the many in which succession to rulership is fixed in respect of the family, but not fixed in respect of the member of the family — a stage implying a partial but incom- plete stability of the political headship. Several instances occur in Africa. “ The crown of Abyssinia is hereditary in one family, but elective in the person, 1 " says Bruce. “ Among the Timmanees and Bulloms, the crown remains in the same family, but the chiefs or head men of the country, upon whom the election of a king depends, are at liberty to nominate a very distant branch of that family/' And a Kaffir “ law requires the successor to the king should be chosen from amongst some of the youngest princes." In Java and Samoa, too, while succession to rulership is limited to the family, it is but partially settled with respect to the individual. And the like held in Spain (Aragon) before the 12th century; where “ a small number of powerful barons elected their sovereign on every vacancy, though, as usual in other countries, out of one family." . That stability of political headship is secured by establish- ment of descent in the male line, is, 'of course, not alleged. The allegation simply is that succession after this mode con- duces better than any other to its stability. Of probable reasons for this, one is that in the patriarchal group, as developed among those pastoral races from which the leading civilized peoples have descended, the sentiment of subordina- tion to the eldest male, fostered by circumstances in the family and in the gens, becomes instrumental to a wider subordination in the larger groups eventually formed. Another probable reason is, that with descent in the male line there is 348 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. more frequently a union of efficiency with supremacy. The^ son of a great warrior, or man otherwise capable as a ruler, is 1 more likely to possess kindred traits than is the son of his sister ; and if so, it will happen that in those earliest stages when personal superiority is requisite as well as legitimacy of claim, succession in the male line will conduce to main- tenance of power by making usurpation more difficult. There is, however, a more potent influence which aids in giving permanence to political headship, and which operates more in conjunction with descent through males than in con- junction with descent through females — an influence probably of greater importance than any other. § 477. When showing, in § 475, how respect for age gene- rates patriarchal authority where descent through males has arisen, I gave cases which incidentally showed a further result ; namely, that the dead patriarch, worshipped by his descend- ants, becomes a family deity. In sundry chapters of Vol. I. were set forth at length the proofs, past and present, furnished by many places and peoples, of this genesis of gods from ghosts. Here there remains to be pointed out the strengthen- ing of political headship which inevitably results. Descent from a ruler who impressed men by his superiority, and whose ghost, specially feared, is propitiated in so unusual a degree as to distinguish it from ancestral ghosts at large, exalts and supports the living ruler in two ways. He is assumed to inherit from his great progenitor more or less of the power, apt to be thought supernatural, which characterized him ; and, making sacrifices to this great progenitor, he is supposed to maintain such relations with him as insure divine aid. Passages in Canon Callaway’s account of the Amazulu, show the influence of this belief. It is said, “ the Itongo [ancestral ghost] dwells with the great man, and speaks with him ; ” and then it is also said (referring to a medicine-man), “ the chiefs of the house of Uzulu used not to allow a mere inferior to be even said to have power over the heaven; for POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 349 it was said that the heaven belonged only to the chief of that place.” These facts yield a definite interpretation of others, like the following, which show that the authority of the ter- restrial ruler is increased by his alleged relation to the celestial ruler ; be the celestial ruler the ghost of the remotest known ancestor who founded the society, or of a conquering invader, or of a superior stranger. Of the chiefs among the Kukis, who are descendants of Hindoo adventurers, we read : — “All these Kajahs are supposed to have sprung from the same stock, which it is believed originally had connection with the gods them- selves; their persons are therefore looked upon with the greatest respect and almost superstitious veneration, and their commands are in every case law.” Of the Tahitians Ellis says : — “ The god and the king were generally supposed to share the authority over the mass of mankind between them. The latter sometimes imper- sonated the former. . . . The kings, in some of the islands, were sup- posed to have descended from the gods. Their persons were always sacred.” According to Mariner, “ Toritonga and Veachi (hereditary divine chiefs in Tonga,) are both acknowledged descendants of chief gods who formerly visited the islands of Tonga.” And, in ancient Peru “ the Ynca gave them [his vassals] to understand that all he did with regard to them was by an order and revelation of his father, the Sun.” This re-inforcement of natural pow 7 er by supernatural power, becomes extreme where the ruler is at once a descend- ant of the gods and himself a god : a union which is familiar among peoples who do not distinguish the divine from the human as we do. It was thus in the case just instanced — that of the Peruvians. It was thus with the ancient Egyp- tians : the monarch “ was the representative of the Divinity on earth, and of the same substance.” Not only did he in many cases become a god after death, but he was worshipped as a god during life ; as witness this prayer to Eameses II. “ When they had come before the king . . . they fell down to the ground, and with their hands they prayed to the king. They praised this divine benefactor . . „ speaking thus : — ‘We are come before 350 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. tliee, the lord of heaven, lord of the earth, sun, life of the whole world, lord of time . . . lord of prosperity, creator of the harvest, fashioner and former of mortals, dispenser of breath to all men ; animater of the whole company of the gods . . . thou former of the great, creator of the small . . . thon our lord, onr snn, by whose words out of his mouth Turn lives . . . grant us life out of thy hands . . . and breath for our nostrils.’ ” This prayer introduces us to a remarkable parallel. Eameses, whose powers, demonstrated by his conquests, were regarded as so transcendant, is here described as ruling not only the lower world but also the upper world ; and a like royal power is alleged in two existing societies where absolutism is simi- larly unmitigated — China and J apan. As shown when treat- ing of Ceremonial Institutions (§ 347) both the Emperor of China and the Japanese Mikado, have such supremacy in heaven that they promote its inhabitants from rank to rank at will. That this strengthening of political headship, if not by ascribed godhood then by ascribed descent from a god (either the apotheosized ancestor of the tribe or one of the elder deities), was exemplified among the early Greeks, needs not be shown. It was exemplified, too, among the Northern Aryans. “ According to the old heathen faith, the pedigree of the Saxon, Anglian, Danish, Norwegian, and Swedish kings — probably also those of the German and Scandinavian kings generally — was traced to Odin, or to some of his immediate companions or heroic sons.” It is further to be noted that a god-descended ruler who is also chief priest of the gods (as he habitually is), obtains a more effective supernatural aid than does the ruler to whom magical powers alone are ascribed. For in the first place the invisible agents invoked by the magician are not conceived to be those of highest rank ; whereas the divinely-descended ruler is supposed to get the help of a supreme invisible agent. And in the second place, the one form of influence over these dreaded superhuman beings, tends much less than the other to become a permanent attribute of the ruler. Though among FOLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 351 the Chibchas, we find a case in which magical power was transferred to a successor — though “ the cazique of Sogamoso made known that he [Bochica] had left him heir of all his sanctity, and that he had the same power of making rain when he liked,” and giving health or sickness (an assertion believed by the people) ; yet this is an exceptional case. Speaking generally, the chief whose relations with the other world are those of a sorcerer does not transmit his relations ; and he does not therefore establish a supernatural dynasty, as does the chief of divine descent. § 478. And now, having considered the several factors which cooperate to establish political headship, let us consider the process of cooperation through its ascending stages. The truth to be noted is that the successive phenomena which occur in the simplest groups, habitually recur in the same order in compound groups, and again in doubly-compound groups. As, in the simple group, there is at first a state in which there is no headship ; so, when simple groups which have acquired political heads possessing slight authorities, are asso- ciated, there is at first no headship of the cluster. The Chinooks furnish an example. Describing them Lewis and Clarke say : — “ As these families gradually expand into bands, or tribes, or nations, the paternal authority is repre- sented by the chief of each association. This chieftain, how- ever, is not hereditary.” And then comes the further fact, which here specially concerns us, that “ the chiefs of the separate villages are independent of each other : ” there is no general chieftain. As headship in a simple group, at first temporary, ceases when the war which initiates it ends ; so in a cluster of groups which severally have recognized heads, a common headship at first results from a war, and lasts no longer than the war. Falkner says — “ In a general war, when many nations enter into an alliance against a common enemy,” the Patagonians 352 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. “ cliose an Apo, or Commander-in-chief, from among the oldest or most celebrated of the Caciques/' The Indians of the Upper Orinoco live “ in hordes of forty or fifty under a family government, and they recognize a common chief only in times of war/' So is it in Borneo. “ During war the chiefs of the Sarebas Dyaks give an uncertain allegiance to a head chief, or commander-in-chief.'' It has been the same in Europe. Seeley remarks that the Sabines “ seem to have had a central government only in war time." Again, “ Ger- many had anciently as many republics as it had tribes. Except in time of war, there was no chief common to all, or even to any given confederation." This recalls the fact, indicated when treating of Political Integration, that the cohesion within compound groups is less than that within simple groups, and that the cohesion within the doubly compound is less than that within the compound. What was there said of cohesion may here be said of the sub- ordination conducing to it ; for we find that when, by con- tinuous war, a permanent headship of a compound group has been generated, it is less stable than the headships of the simple groups are. Often it lasts only for the life of the man who achieves it ; as among the Karens and the Maganga, instanced in § 226, and as among the Dyaks, of whom Boyle says — “ It is an exceptional case if a Dyak chief is raised to an acknow- ledged supremacy over the other chiefs. If he is so raised he can lay no claim to his power except that of personal merit and the consent of his former equals ; and his death is instantly followed by the disruption of his dominions / 5 Even where there has arisen a headship of the compound group which lasts beyond the life of its founder, it remains for a long time not equal in stability to the headships of the component groups. Pallas, while describing the Mongol and Kalmuck chiefs as having unlimited power over their dependants, says that the khans had in general only an uncertain and weak authority over the subordinate chiefs. Concerning the Arau- canians, Thompson says “ the ulmenes are the lawful judges POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 353 of their vassals, and for this reason their authority is less pre- carious than that of the higher officers ” — the central rulers. Of the Kaffirs we read : — “ They are all vassals of the king, chiefs, as well as those under them; but the subjects are generally so blindly attached to their chiefs, that they will follow them against the king.” Europe has furnished kindred examples. Of the Homeric Greeks Mr. Gladstone writes : — • “ It is probable that the subordination of the sub-chief to his local sovereign was a closer tie than that of the local sovereign to the head of Greece.” And during the early feudal period in the West, allegiance to the minor but proximate ruler was stronger than that to the major but remote ruler. In the compound group, as in the simple group, the pro- gress towards stable headship is furthered by transition from succession by choice to succession by inheritance. During early stages of the independent tribe, chieftainship when not acquired by individual superiority tacitly yielded to, is ac- quired by election. In North America it is so with the Aleuts, the Comanches, and many more ; in Polynesia it is so with the Land Dyaks ; and, before the Mahommedan conquest, it was so in Java. Among the hill-peoples of India it is so with the Nagas and others. In sundry regions the change to heredi- tary succession is shown by different tribes of the same race. Of the Karens we read that “ in many districts the chieftain- ship is considered hereditary, but in more it is elective ” Some Chinook villages have chiefs who inherit their powers, though mostly they are chosen. Similarly, the com- pound group is at first ruled by an elected head. Several examples come to us from Africa. Bastian tells us that “ in many parts of the Congo region the king is chosen by the petty princes.” The crown of Yariba is not hereditary : “ the chiefs invariably electing, from the wisest and most sagacious of their own body.” And the king of Ibu, says Allen, seems to be “ elected by a council of sixty elders, or chiefs of large villages.” In Asia it is thus with the Kukis. “ One, among all the Bajahs of each class, is chosen to be the Prudham 354 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. or chief Rajah of that clan. The dignity is not hereditary, as is the case with the minor Rajahships, but is enjoyed by each Rajah of the clan in rotation.” So lias it been in Europe. Though by the early Greeks here- ditary right was in a considerable measure recognized, yet the case of Telemachus implies “ that a practice, either approach- ing to election, or in some way involving a voluntary action on the part of the subjects, or of a portion of them, had to be gone through.” The like is true of ancient Rome. That its monarchy was elective “ is proved by the existence in later times of an office of interrex , which implies that the kingly power did not devolve naturally upon a hereditary successor.” Later on it was thus with Western peoples. Up to the begin- ning of the tenth century “ the formality of election sub- sisted . . . in every European kingdom; and the imper- fect right of birth required a ratification by public assent ” And it was once thus with ourselves. Among the early English the Bretwaldsliip, or supreme headship over the minor kingdoms, was at first elective ; and the form of elec- tion continued long traceable in our history. Moreover, it is observable that the change to hereditary succession is by assent, as in France. “ The first six kings of this dynasty [the Capetian] procured the co-optation of their sons, by having them crowned during their own lives. And this was not done without the consent of the chief vassals.” The stability of the compound headship, made greater by efficient leadership in war and by establishment of hereditary succession, is further increased when there cooperates the additional factor — supposed supernatural origin or super- natural sanction. Everywhere, up from a New Zealand king, who is strictly tapu , or sacred, we may trace this in- fluence ; and occasionally, where divine descent or magical powers are not claimed, there is a claim to origin that is extraordinary. Asia yields an example in the Fodli dynasty, which reigned 150 years in South Arabia — a six-fingered dynasty, regarded with awe by the people because of its con- POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 355 tinuously-inlierited malformation. Europe of the Merovin- gian period yields an example. In pagan times the king’s race had an alleged divine origin; but in Christian times, says Waitz, when they could no longer mount back to the gods, a more than natural origin was alleged : “ a sea-monster ravished the wife of Chlogio as she sat by the sea-shore, and from this embrace Merovech sprang.” Later days show us the gradual acquisition of a sacred or semi-supernatural character, where it did not originally exist. Divine assent to their supremacy was asserted by the Carolingian kings. During the later feudal age, rare exceptions apart, kings “ were not far removed from believing themselves near rela- tives of the masters of heaven. Kings and gods were col- leagues.” In the 17th century this belief was endorsed by divines. “ Kings,” says Bossuet, “ are gods, and share in a manner the divine independence.” So that the headship of a compound group, arising tempo- rarily during war, then becoming, with frequent cooperation of the groups, settled for life by election, passing presently into the hereditary form, and gaining permanence as fast as the law of succession grows w T ell-defined and undisputed, acquires its greatest stability only when the king is regarded as a deputy god, or when, if he is not supposed to inherit a divine nature, he is supposed to have a divine commission. § 479. Ascribed divine nature, or divine descent, or divine commission, naturally gives to the political head unlimited sway. In theory, and often to a large extent in practice, he is owner of his subjects and of the territory they occupy. Where militancy is pronounced, and the claims of a con- queror unqualified, it is indeed to a considerable degree thus with those uncivilized peoples who do not ascribe super- natural characters to their rulers. Among the Zulu Kaffirs the chief “ exercises supreme power over the lives of his people the Bheel chiefs “ have a power over the lives and property of their own subjects and in Fiji the subject is 356 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. property. But it is still more thus where the ruler is con- sidered more than human. Astley tells us that in Loango the king is “ called samba and pongo , that is, god and, according to Proyart, the Loango people “ say their lives and goods belong to the king” In Wasoro (East Africa) “ the king has unlimited power of life and death ... in some tribes ... he is almost worshipped.” In Msam- bara the people say “ we are all slaves of the Zumbe (king), who is our Mulungu” [god]. “ By the state law of Dahomey, as at Benin, all men are slaves to the king, and most women are his wives and in Dahomey the king is called “ the spirit.” The Malagasy speak of their king as “ our god and he is lord of the soil, owner of all property, and master of his subjects. Their time and services are at his command.” In the Sandwich Islands the king, personating the god, utters oracular responses ; and his power “ extends over the pro- perty, liberty, and lives of his people.” Various Asiatic rulers, whose titles ascribe to them divine descent and nature, stand in like relations to their peoples. In Siam “the king is master not only of the persons but really of the property of his subjects : he disposes of their labour and directs their movements at will.” Of the Burmese we read — “ their goods likewise, and even their persons are reputed his [the king’s] property, and on this ground it is that he selects for his con- cubine any female that may chance to please his eye.” In China “ there is only one who possesses authority — the Emperor. ... A wang, or king, has no hereditary pos- sessions, and lives upon the salary vouchsafed by the Emperor. . . . He is the only possessor of the landed property.” And the like is alleged of the divinely-descended Japanese Mikado : “ his majesty, although often but a child a few years old, still dispensed ranks and dignities, and the ownership of the soil always in reality resided in him.” Of course, where the political head has unlimited power — where, as victorious invader, his subjects lie at his mercy, or where, as divinely descended, his will may not be questioned POLITICAL HEADS— CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC, 357 without impiety, or where he unites the characters of con- queror and god, he naturally absorbs every kind of authority. He is at once military head, legislative head, judicial head, ecclesiastical head. The fully developed king is the supreme centre of every social structure and director of every social function. § 480. In a small tribe it is practicable for the chief per- sonally to discharge all the duties of his office. Besides leading the other warriors in battle, he has time to settle disputes, he can sacrifice to the ancestral ghost, he can keep the village in order, he can inflict punishments, he can regu- late trading transactions ; for those governed by him are but few, and they live within a narrow space. When he acquires the headship of many united tribes, both the increased amount of business and the wider area covered by his sub- jects, put difficulties in the way of exclusively personal administration. It becomes necessary to employ others for the purposes of gaining information, conveying commands, seeing them executed ; and in course of time the assistants thus employed grow into established heads of departments with deputed authorities. While this development of governmental structures in- creases the ruler’s power, by enabling him to deal with more numerous affairs, it, in another way, decreases his power ; for his actions are more and more modified by the instrumentali- ties through which they are effected. Those who watch the ■working of administrations, no matter of what kind, have forced upon them the truth that a head regulative agency is at once helped and hampered by its subordinate agencies. In a philanthropic association, a scientific society, or a club, those who govern find that the organized officialism which they have created, often impedes, and not unfrequently defeats, their aims. Still more is it so with the immensely larger administrations of the State. Through deputies the ruler receives his information; by them his orders are 358 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. executed ; and as fast as his connexion with affairs becomes indirect, his control over affairs diminishes ; until, in extreme cases, he either dwindles into a puppet in the hands of his chief deputy or has his place usurped by him. Strange as it seems, the two causes which conspire to give permanence to political headship, also, at a later stage, con- spire to reduce the political head to an automaton, executing the wills of the agents he has created. In the first place, when hereditary succession is finally settled in some line of descent rigorously prescribed, the possession of supreme power becomes independent of capacity for exercising it. The heir to a vacant throne may be, and often is, too young for discharging its duties ; or he may be, and often is, too feeble in intellect, too deficient in energy, or too much occu- pied with the pleasures which his position offers in unlimited amounts. The result is that in the one case the regent, and in the other the chief minister, becomes the actual ruler. In the second place, that sacredness which supposed divine origin gives, makes him inaccessible to the ruled. All intercourse between him and them must be through the agents he surrounds himself with. Hence it becomes difficult or im- possible for him to learn more than they choose him to know ; and there follows inability to adapt his commands to the re- quirements, and inability to discover whether his commands have been fulfilled. His authority is consequently used to give effect to the purposes of his agents. Even in so relatively simple a society as that of Tonga, we find an example. There is an hereditary sacred chief who “ was originally the sole chief, possessing temporal as well as spiritual power, and regarded as of divine origin,” but who is now politically powerless. Abyssinia shows us something analogous. Holding no direct communication with his sub- jects, and having a sacredness such that even in council he sits unseen, the monarch is a mere dummy. In Gondar, one of the divisions of Abyssinia, the king must belong to the royal house of Solomon, but any one of the turbulent chiefs POLITICAL HEADS— CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 359 who has obtained ascendancy by force of arms, becomes a Eas — a prime minister or real monarch ; though he requires “ a titular emperor to perform the indispensable ceremony of nominating a Eas,” since the name, at least, of emperor “ is deemed essential to render valid the title of Eas.” The case of Thibet may be named as one in which the sacredness of the original political head is dissociated from the claim based on hereditary descent ; for the Grand Llama, considered as “ God the Father,” incarnate afresh in each new occupant of the throne, is discovered among the people at large by certain indications of his godhood. But with his divinity, involving disconnexion with temporal matters, there goes absence of political power. A like state of things exists in Bliotan. “ The Dhurma Baja is looked upon by the Bhotanese in the same light as the Grand Lama of Thibet is viewed by his subjects — namely as a perpetual incarnation of the Deity, or Bhudda himself in a corpo- real form. During the interval between his death and reappearance, or, more properly speaking, until he has reached an age sufficiently mature to ascend his spiritual throne, the office of Dhurma Baja is filled by proxy from amongst the priesthood . 35 And then along with this sacred ruler there co-exists a secular ruler. Bliotan “ has two nominal heads, known to us and to the neighbouring hill-tribes under the Hindoostanee names of the Dhurma and the Deb Bajas. . . . The former is the spiritual head, the latter the temporal one.” Though in this case the temporal head has not great influence (probably because the priest-regent, whose celibacy prevents him from founding a line, stands in the way of unchecked assumption of power by the temporal head), still the existence of a tem- poral head implies a partial lapsing of political functions out of the hands of the original political head. But the most remarkable, and at the same time most familiar, example, is that furnished by Japan. Here, the supplanting of inherited authority by deputed authority is exemplified, not in the central government alone, but in the local governments. “ Next to the prince and his family came the karos or c elders . 5 Their office became hereditary, and, like the princes, they in many instances 360 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. became effete. The business of what we may call the clan would thus fall into the hands of any clever man or set of men of the lower ranks, who, joining ability to daring and unscrupulousness, kept the princes and the karos out of sight, but surrounded with empty dignity, and, commanding the opinion of the bulk of the samarai or military class, wielded the real power themselves. They took care, however, to perform every act in the name of the faineants , their lords, and thus we hear of . . . daimios, just as in the case of the Emperors, accomplishing deeds ... of which they were perhaps wholly ignorant.” This lapsing of political power into the hands of ministers was, in the case of the central government, doubly illustrated. Successors as they were of a god-descended conqueror whose rule was real, the Japanese Emperors gradually became only nominal rulers ; partly because of the sacredness which sepa- rated them from the nation, and partly because of the early age at which the law of succession frequently enthroned them. Their deputies consequently gained predominance. The regency in the ninth century “ became hereditary in the Fujiwara [sprung from the imperial house], and these regents ultimately became all-powerful. They obtained the privilege of opening all petitions addressed to the sovereign, and of pre- senting or rejecting them at their pleasure.” And then, in course of time, this usurping agency had its own authority usurped in like manner. Again succession by fixed rule was rigorously adhered to; and again seclusion entailed loss of hold on affairs. “ High descent was the only qualification for office, and unfitness for functions was not regarded in the choice of officials.” Besides the Shogun’s four confidential officers, “ no one else could approach him. Whatever might be the crimes committed at Kama Koura, it was impossible, through the intrigues of these favourites, to complain of them to the Seogoun.” The result was that “ subsequently this family . . . gave way to military commanders, who,” however, often became the instruments of other chiefs. Though less definitely, this process w T as exemplified during early times in Europe. The Merovingian kings, to whom there clung a tradition of supernatural origin, and whose order of POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 361 succession was so far settled that minors reigned, fell under the control of those who had become chief ministers. Long before Childeric, the Merovingian family had ceased to govern. “ The treasures and the power of the kingdom had passed into the hands of the prefects of the palace, who were called ‘ mayors of the palace/ and to whom the supreme power really belonged. The prince was obliged to content himself with bearing the name of king, having flowing locks and a long beard, sitting on the chair of State, and repre- senting the image of the monarch.” § 481. From the Evolution-standpoint we are thus enabled to discern the relative beneficence of institutions which, con- sidered absolutely, are not beneficent; and are taught to approve as temporary that which, as permanent, we abhor. The evidence obliges us to admit that subjection to despots has been largely instrumental in advancing civilization. Induction and deduction alike prove this. If, on the one hand, we group together those wandering headless hordes which are found here and there over the Earth, they show us that, in the absence of political organiza- tion, little progress has taken place ; and if we contemplate those settled simple groups which have but nominal heads, we are shown that though there is some development of the industrial arts and some cooperation, the advance is but small. If, on the other hand, we glance at those ancient societies in which considerable heights of civilization were first reached, we see them under autocratic rule. In America, purely personal government, restricted only by settled customs, characterized the Mexican, Central American, and Chibclia states ; and in Peru, the absolutism of the divine king was unqualified. In Africa, ancient Egypt exhibited very con- spicuously this connexion between despotic control and social evolution. Throughout the distant past it was repeatedly displayed in Asia, from the Accadian civilization downwards ; and the still extant civilizations of Siam, Burmah, China, and Japan, re-illustrate it. Early European societies, too, where not characterized by centralized despotism, were still cha- 362 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. racterized by diffused patriarchal despotism. Only among modern peoples, whose ancestors passed through the discipline given under this social form, and who have inherited its effects, is civilization being dissociated from subjection to individual will. The necessity there has been for absolutism is best seen on observing that, during inter-tribal and inter-national conflicts, those have conquered who, other things equal, were the more obedient to their chiefs and kings. And since in early stages, military subordination and social subordination go together, it results that, for a long time, the conquering societies continued to be the despotically-governed societies. Such exceptions as histories appear to show us, really prove the rule. In the conflict between Persia and Greece, the Greeks, but for a mere accident, would have been ruined by that division of councils which results from absence of sub- jection to a single head. And their habit of appointing a dictator when in great danger from enemies, implies that the Romans had discovered that efficiency in war requires un- divided control. Thus, leaving open the question whether, in the absence of w r ar, wandering primitive groups could ever have developed into settled civilized communities, we conclude that, under such conditions as . there have been, those struggles for existence among societies which have gone on consolidating smaller into larger, until great nations have been produced, necessitated the development of a social type characterized by personal rule of a stringent kind. § 482. To make clear the genesis of this leading political institution, let us set down in brief the several influences which have conspired to effect it, and the several stages passed through. In the rudest groups, resistance to the assumption of supremacy by any individual, usually prevents the establish- ment of settled headship; though some influence is com- POLITICAL HEADS — CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 363 rnonly acquired by superiority of strength, or courage, or sagacity, or possessions, or the experience accompanying age. In such groups, and in tribes somewhat more advanced, two kinds of superiority conduce more than all others to predominance — that of the warrior and that of the medicine- man. Usually separate, but sometimes united in the same person, and then greatly strengthening him, both of these superiorities tending to initiate political headship, continue thereafter to be important factors in developing it. At first, however, the supremacy acquired by great natural power, or supposed supernatural powder, or both, is transitory — ceases with the life of one who has acquired it. So long as the principle of efficiency alone operates, political headship does not become settled. It becomes settled only when there cooperates the principle of inheritance. The custom of reckoning descent through females, which characterizes many rude societies and survives in others that have made considerable advances, is less favourable to esta- blishment of permanent political headship than is the custom of reckoning descent through males; and in sundry semi- civilized societies distinguished by permanent political head- ships, inheritance through males has been established in the ruling house while inheritance through females survives in the society at large. Beyond the fact that reckoning descent through males conduces to a more coherent family, to a greater culture of subordination, and to a more probable union of inherited position with inherited capacity, there is the more important fact that it fosters ancestor-worship, and the consequent re- inforcing of natural authority by supernatural authority. Development of the ghost-theory, leading as it does to special fear of the ghosts of powerful men, until, where many tribes have been welded together by a conqueror, his ghost acquires in tradition the pre-eminence of a god, produces two effects. In the first place his descendant, ruling after him, is supposed to partake of his divine nature ; and in the second place, by 7 364 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. propitiatory sacrifices to him, is supposed to obtain his aid. Rebellion hence comes to be regarded as alike wicked and hopeless. The processes by which political headships are established repeat themselves at successively higher stages. In simple groups chieftainship is at first temporary — ceases with the war which initiated it. When simple groups that have acquired permanent political heads, unite for military pur- poses, the general chieftainship is originally but temporary. As in simple groups chieftainship is at the outset habitually elective, and becomes hereditary at a later stage ; so chief- tainship of the compound group is habitually elective at the outset, and only later passes into the hereditary. Similarly in some cases where a doubly-compound society is formed. Further, this later-established power of a supreme ruler, at first given by election and presently gained by descent, is commonly less than that of the local rulers in their own localities ; and wdien it becomes greater, it is usually by the help of ascribed divine origin or ascribed divine commission. Where, in virtue of supposed supernatural genesis or authority, the king has become absolute, and, owning both subjects and territory, exercises all powers, he is obliged by the multiplicity of his affairs to depute his powers. There follows a reactive restraint due to the political machinery he creates ; and this machinery ever tends to become too strong for him. Especially where rigorous adhesion to the rule of inheritance brings incapables to the throne, or where ascribed divine nature causes inaccessibility save through agents, or where both causes conspire, power passes into the hands of deputies. The legitimate ruler becomes an automaton and his chief agent the real ruler ; and this agent, again, in some cases passing through parallel stages, himself becomes an auto- maton and his subordinates the rulers. Lastly, by colligation and comparison of the facts, we are led to recognize the indirectly-achieved benefits which have followed the directly-inflicted evils of personal government. POLITICAL HEADS— CHIEFS, KINGS, ETC. 365 Headship of the conquering chief has been a normal accom- paniment of that political integration without which any high degree of social evolution would probably have been impos- sible. Only by imperative need for combination in war were primitive men led into cooperation. Only by subjection to imperative command was such cooperation made efficient. And only by the cooperation thus initiated were made pos- sible those other forms of cooperation characterizing civilized life. CHAPTER VII. COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. § 483. In the preceding chapter we traced the development of the first element in that tri-une political structure which everywhere shows itself at the outset. We pass now to the development of the second element — the group of leading men among whom the chief is, at first, merely the most con- spicuous. Under what conditions this so evolves as to sub- ordinate the other two, what causes make it narrower, and what causes widen it until it passes into the third, we have here to observe. If the innate feelings and aptitudes of a race have large shares in determining the sizes and cohesions of the social groups it forms, still more must they have large shares in de- termining the relations which arise among the members of such groups. While the mode of life followed tends to gene- rate this or that political structure, its effects are always com- plicated by the effects of inherited character. Whether or not the primitive state in which governing power is equally distributed among all warriors or all elders, passes into the state in which governing power is monopolized by one, depends in part on the life of the group as predatory or peaceful, and in part on the natures of its members as prompting them to oppose dictation more or less doggedly. A few facts will make this clear. The Arafuras (Papuan Islanders) who “ live in peace and COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 367 brotherly love/' have no other “ authority among them than the decisions of their elders/’ Among the harmless Todas “ all disputes and questions of right and wrong are settled either by arbitration or by a Punchayet — i.e., a council of five.” Of the Bodo and the Dhimals, described as averse to military service, and “ totally free from arrogance, revenge, cruelty, and fierte ,” we read that though each of their small communities has a nominal head who pays the tribute on its behalf, yet he is without power, and “ disputes are settled among themselves by juries of elders/’ In these cases, besides absence of the causes which bring about chiefly supremacy, may be noted the presence of causes which directly hinder it. The Papuans generally, typified by the Arafuras above-named, while described by Modera, Ross, and Kolff, as “ good-natured,” “ of a mild disposition,” kind and peaceful to strangers, are said by Earl to be unfit for military action : “ their impatience of control . . . utterly precludes that organization which would enable” the Papuans “ to stand their ground against encroachments.” The Bodo and the Dhimals while “ they are void of all violence towards their own people or towards their neighbours” also “resist injunctions, injudiciously urged, with dogged obstinacy.” And of a kindred “very fascinating people,” the Lepchas, amiable, peaceful, kind, as travellers unite in describing them, and who refuse to take service as soldiers, we are told that they will “ undergo great privation rather than submit to oppression or injustice.” Where the repugnance to control is strong, an uncen- tralized political organization is maintained notwithstanding the warlike activities which tend to initiate chieftainship. The Nagas “ acknowledge no king among themselves, and deride the idea of such a personage among others their “ villages are continually at feud “ every man being his own master, his passions and inclinations are ruled by his share of brute force.” And then we further find that — M Petty disputes and disagreements about property are settled by a 368 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. council of elders, the litigants voluntarily submitting to their arbitra- tion. But correctly speaking, there is not the shadow of a constituted authority in the Naga community, and, wonderful as it may seem, this want of government does not lead to any marked degree of anarchy.” Similarly among the warlike tribes of North America. Speaking of these people at large, Schoolcraft says that “they all wish to govern, and not to be governed. Every Indian thinks he has a right to do as he pleases, and that no one is better than himself ; and he will fight before he will give up what he thinks right.” Of the Comanches, as an example, he remarks that “ the democratic principle is strongly implanted in them ;” and that for governmental purposes “ public councils are held at regular intervals during the year.” Fur- ther, we read that in districts of ancient Central America there existed somewhat more advanced societies which, though warlike, were impelled by a kindred jealousy to provide against monopoly of power. The government was carried on by an elective council of old men who appointed a war chief ; and this war chief, “if suspected of plotting against the safety of the commonwealth, or for the purpose of securing supreme power in his own hands, was rigorously put to death by the council.” Though the specialities of character which thus lead certain kinds of men in early stages to originate compound political heads, and to resist, even under stress of war, the rise of single political heads, are innate, we are not without clues to the circumstances which have made them innate ; and with a view to interpretations presently to be made, it will be useful to glance at these. The Comanches and kindred tribes, roaming about in small bands, active and skilful horsemen, have, through long past periods, been so con- ditioned as to make coercion of one man by another difficult. So, too, has it been, though in another way, with the Nagas. “ They inhabit a rough and intricate mountain range and their villages are perched “ on the crests of ridges.” Again, significant evidence is furnished by a remark of Captain Burton to the effect that in Africa, as in Asia, there are three COMPOUND POLiITCAL HEADS. 369 distinct forms of government — military despotisms, feudal monarchies, and rude republics: the rude republics being those formed by “ the Bedouin tribes, the hill people, and the jungle races.” Clearly, the names of these last show that they inhabit regions which, hindering by their physic al characters a centralized form of government, favour a more diffused form of government, and the less decided political subordination which is its concomitant. These facts are obviously related to certain others already named. We saw in § 17, and again in § 449, that it is rela- tively easy to form a large society if the country is one within which all parts are readily accessible, while it has barriers through which exit is difficult ; and that, conversely, forma- tion of a large society is prevented, or greatly delayed, by difficulties of communication within the occupied area, and by facilities of escape from it. Here we see, further, that not only is political integration under its primary aspect of in- creasing mass, hindered by these last-named physical condi- tions, but that there is hindrance to the development of a more integrated form of government. The ^circumstances which impede social consolidation also impede the concentration of political power. The truth here chiefly concerning us, however, is that the continued presence of the one or the other set of conditions, fosters a character to which either the centralized political organization or the diffused political organization is appro- priate. Existence, generation after generation, in a region where despotic control has arisen, produces an adapted type of nature ; partly by daily habit and partly by survival of those most fit for living under such control. Contrariwise, in a region favouring preservation of their independence by small groups, there is a strengthening, through successive ages, of sentiments averse to restraint ; since, not only are these sentiments exercised in all members of a group by resisting the efforts from time to time made to sub- ordinate it, but, on the average, those who most per- 370 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. tinaciously resist are those who, remaining unsubdued, and transmitting their mental traits to posterity, determine the character of the race. Having thus glanced at the effects of the factors, external and internal, as displayed in simple tribes, we shall under- stand how they cooperate when, by migration or otherwise, such tribes fall into circumstances favouring the growth of large societies. § 484. The case of an uncivilized people of the nature de- scribed, who have in recent times shown what occurs when union of small groups into great ones is prompted, will best initiate the interpretation. The Iroquois nations, each made up of many tribes pre- viously hostile, had to defend themselves against European invaders. Combination for this purpose among these five (and finally six) nations, necessitated a recognition of equality among them ; since agreement to join would not have been arrived at had it been required that some divisions should be subject to others. The groups had to cooperate on the under- standing that their “ rights, privileges and obligations” should be the same. Though the numbers of permanent and here- ditary sachems appointed by the respective nations to form the Great Council, differed, yet the voices of the several nations were equal. Omitting details of the organization, we have to note, first, that for many generations, notwithstanding the wars which this league carried on, its constitution re- mained stable — no supreme individual arose; and, second, that this equality among the powers of the groups co-existed with inequality within each group : the people had no share in its government. A clue is thus furnished to the genesis of those compound heads with which ancient history familiarizes us. We are enabled to see how there came to co-exist in the same socie- ties, some institutions of a despotic kind, with other institu- tions of a kind appearing to be based on the principle of COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 371 equality, and often confounded witli free institutions. Let us recall the antecedents of those early European peoples who developed governments of this form. During the wandering pastoral life, subordination to a single head was made habitual. A recalcitrant member of any group had either to submit to the authority under which he had grown up, or, rebelling, had to leave the group and face those risks which unprotected life in the wilderness threatened. The establishment of this subordination was furthered by the more frequent survival of groups in which it was greatest ; since, in the conflicts between groups, those of which the members were insubordinate, ordinarily being both smaller and less able to cooperate effectually, w 7 ere the more likely to disappear. But now to the fact that in such families and clans, obedience to the father and to the patriarch was fostered by circumstances, has to be added the fact above emphasized, that circumstances also fostered the sentiment of liberty in the relations between clans. The exercise of power by one of them over another, was made difficult by wide scattering and by great mobility; and with successful oppo- sition to external coercion, or evasion of it, carried on through numberless generations, the tendency to resent and resist all strange authority was likely to become strong. Whether, when groups thus disciplined aggregate, they assume this or that form of political organization, depends partly, as already implied, on the conditions into which they fall. Even could we omit those differences between Mongols, Semites, and Aryans, established in prehistoric times by causes unknown to us, or even had complete likeness of nature been produced among them by long-continued pastoral life ; yet large societies formed by combinations of their small hordes, could be similar in type only under similar circumstances. In unfavourableness of circumstances is to be found the reason why Mongols and Semites, where they have settled and multiplied, have failed to maintain the autonomies of their hordes after combination of them, and to 372 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. evolve the resulting institutions. Even the Aryans, among whom chiefly the less concentrated forms of political rule have arisen, show us that almost everything depends on favourable or unfavourable conditions fallen into. Originally inheriting in common the mental traits generated during their life in the Hindu Koosh and its neighbourhood, the different divisions of the race have developed different insti- tutions and accompanying characters. Those of them who spread into the plains of India, where great fertility made possible a large population, to the control of which there were small physical impediments, lost their independence of nature, and did not evolve political systems like those which grew up among their Western kindred, under circumstances furthering maintenance of the original character. The implication is, then, that where groups of the patri- archal type fall into regions permitting considerable growth of population, but having physical structures which impede the centralization of power, compound political heads will arise, and for a time sustain themselves, through cooperation of the two factors — independence of local groups and need for union in war. Let us consider some examples. § 485. The island of Crete has numerous high mountain valleys containing good pasturage, and provides many seats for strongholds — seats which ruins prove that the ancient inhabitants utilized. Similarly with the mainland of Greece. A complicated mountain system cuts off its parts from one another and renders each difficult of access. Especially is this so in the Peloponnesus ; and, above all, in the part occu- pied by the Spartans. It has been remarked that the State which possesses both sides of Taygetus, has it in its power to be master of the peninsula : “ it is the Acropolis of the Pelo- ponnese, as that country is of the rest of Greece.” When, over the earlier inhabitants, there came successive waves of Hellenic conquerors, these brought with them the type of nature and organization common to the Aryans, dis- COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 373 playing tlie united traits above described. Such a people taking possession of such a land, inevitably fell in course of time “ into as many independent clans as the country itself was divided by its mountain chains into valleys and dis- tricts.” From separation resulted alienation ; so that those remote from one another, becoming strangers, became ene- mies. In early Greek times the clans, occupying mountain villages, were so liable to incursions from one another that the planting of fruit trees was a waste of labour. There existed a state like that seen at present among such Indian- hill tribes as the Nagas. Though preserving the tradition of a common descent, and owning allegiance to the oldest male representative of the patriarch, a people spreading over a region which thus cut off from one another even adjacent small groups, and still more those remoter clusters of groups arising in course of genera- tions, would inevitably become disunited in government: subjection to a general head would be more and more difficult to maintain, and subjection to local heads would alone con- tinue practicable. At the same time there would arise, under such conditions, increasing causes of insubordination. When the various branches of a common family are so separated as to prevent intercourse, their respective histories, and the lines of descent of their respective heads, must become unknown, or but partially known, to one another ; and claims to supre- macy made now by this local head and now by that, are cer- tain to be disputed. If we remember how, even in settled societies having records, there have been perpetual conflicts about rights of succession, and how, down to our own day, there are frequent law-suits to decide on heirships to titles and properties, we cannot but infer that in a state like that of the early Greeks, the difficulty of establishing the legiti- macy of general headships, conspiring with the desire to assert independence and the ability to maintain it, inevitably entailed lapse into numerous local headships. Of course, under conditions varying in each locality, splittings-up of 374 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. wider governments into narrower went to different extents ; and naturally, too, re-establishments of wider governments or extensions of narrower ones in some cases took place. But, generally, the tendency under such conditions was to form small independent groups, severally having the patriarchal type of organization. Hence, then, the decay of such king- ships as are implied in the Iliad* As Grote writes — “ When we approach historical Greece, we find that (with the exception of Sparta) the primitive, hereditary, unresponsible monarch, uniting in himself all the functions of government, has ceased to reign.”* Let us now ask what will happen when a cluster of clans of common descent, which have become independent and hostile, are simultaneously endangered by enemies to whom they are not at all akin, or but remotely akin ? Habitually they will sink their differences and cooperate for defence. But on what terms will they cooperate ? Even among friendly groups, joint action would be hindered if some claimed supre- macy ; and among groups having out-standing feuds there could be no joint action save on a footing of equality. The common defence would, therefore, be directed by a body * While I am writing, the just-issued third volume of Mr. Skene’s Celtic Scotland , supplies me with an illustration of the process above indicated. It appears that the original Celtic tribes which formed the earldoms of Moray, Buchan, Athol, Angus, Menteith, became broken up into clans ; and how influential was the physical character of the country in producing this result, we are shown by the fact that this change took place in the parts of them which fell within the highland country. Describing the smaller groups which resulted, Mr. Skene says : — “ While the clan, viewed as a single com* munity, thus consisted of the chief, with his kinsmen to a certain limited degree of relationship ; the commonalty who were of the same blood, who all bore the same name, and his dependents, consisting of subordinate septs of native men, who did not claim to be of the blood of the chief, but were either probably descended from the more ancient occupiers of the soil, or were broken men from other clans, who had taken protection with him. . . . Those kinsmen of the chief who acquired the property of their land founded families. . . . The most influential of these was that of the oldest cadet in the family which had been longest separated from the main stem, and usually presented the appearance of a rival house little less powerful than that of tho chief.’ 1 COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 375 formed of the heads of the cooperating small societies ; and if the cooperation for defence was prolonged, or became changed into cooperation for offence, this temporary control- ling body would naturally grow into a permanent one, holding the small societies together. The special characters of this compound head would, of course, vary with the circum- stances. Where the traditions of the united clans agreed in identifying some one chief as the lineal representative of the original patriarch or hero, from whom all descended, prece- dence and some extra authority would be permitted to him. Where claims derived from descent were disputed, personal superiority or election would determine which member of the compound head should take the lead. If within each of the component groups chiefly power was unqualified, there would result from union of chiefs a close oligarchy ; while the close- ness of the oligarchy would become less in proportion as recognition of the authority of each chief diminished. And in cases where there came to be incorporated numerous aliens, owing allegiance to the heads of none of the compo- nent groups, there would arise influences tending still more to widen the oligarchy. Such, we may conclude, were the origins of those com- pound headships of the Greek states which existed at the beginning of the historic period. In Crete, where there sur- vived the tradition of primitive kingship, but where disper- sion and subdivision of clans had brought about a condition in which f< different towns carried on open feuds, 5 ’ there were “ patrician houses, deriving their rights from the early ages of royal government , 55 who continued “ to retain possession of the administration . 55 In Corinth the line of Herakleid kings “ subsides gradually, through a series of empty names, into the oligarchy denominated Bacchiadce. . . . The persons so named were all accounted descendants of Herakles, and formed the governing caste in the city . 55 So was it with Megara. According to tradition, this arose by combination of several villages inhabited by kindred tribes, which, originally in 376 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. antagonism with Corinth, had, probably in the course of this antagonism, become consolidated into an independent state. At the opening of the historic period the like had happened in Sikyon and other places. Sparta, too, “ always maintained, down to the times of the despot Nabis, its primitive aspect of a group of adjacent hill- villages rather than a regular city.” Though in Sparta kingship had survived under an anomalous form, yet the joint representatives of the primitive king, still reverenced because the tradition of their divine descent was preserved, had become little more than members of the governing oligarchy, retaining certain prerogatives. And though it is true that in its earliest historically-known stage, the Spartan oligarchy did not present the form which would spontaneously arise from the union of chiefs of clans for co- operation in war — though it had become elective within a limited class of persons ; yet the fact that an age of not less than sixty was a qualification, harmonizes with the belief that it at first consisted of the heads of the respective groups, who were always the eldest sons of the eldest ; and that these groups with their heads, described as having been in pre- Lykurgean times, “the most lawless of all the Greeks,” became united by that continuous militant life which dis- tinguished them.* # As bearing on historical interpretations at large, and especially on inter- pretations to be made in this work, let me point out further reasons than those given by Grote and others for rejecting the tradition that the Spartan constitution was the work of Lykurgus. The universal tendency to ascribe an effect to the most conspicuous proximate cause, is especially strong where the effect is one of which the causation is involved. Our own time has fur- nished an illustration in the ascription of Corn-law Repeal to Sir Robert Peel, and after him to Messrs. Cobden and R right : leaving Colonel Thomp- son un-named. In the next generation tbe man who for a time carried on the fight single-handed, and forged sundry of the weapons used by the vic- tors, will be unheard of in connexion with it. It is not enough, however, to suspect that Lykurgus was simply the finisher of other men’s work. Wo may reasonably suspect that the work was that of no man, but simply that of the needs and the conditions. This may be seen in the institution of the public mess. If we ask what will happen with a small people who, for gene- rations spreading as conquerors, have a contempt for all industry, and who, COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 377 The Eomans exemplify the rise of a compound headship under conditions which, though partially different from those the Greeks were subject to, were allied fundamentally. In its earliest-known state, Latium was occupied by village- communities, which were united into cantons ; while these cantons formed a league headed by Alba — a canton regarded as the oldest and most eminent. This combination was for joint defence ; as is shown by the fact that each group of clan-villages composing a canton, had an elevated stronghold in common, and also by the fact that the league of cantons had for its centre and place of refuge, Alba, the most strongly placed as well as the oldest. The component cantons of the league were so far independent that there were wars between them ; whence we may infer that when they cooperated for joint defence it was on substantially equal terms. Thus before Kome existed, the people who formed it had been habituated to a kind of life such that, with great subordina- tion in each family and clan, and partial subordination within each canton (which was governed by a prince, council of elders, and assembly of warriors), there went a union of heads of cantons, who were in no degree subordinate one to another. When the inhabitants of three of these cantons, the Eamnians, Titles, and Luceres, began to occupy the tract on which Eome stands, they brought with them their political organization. when not' at war, pass their time in exercises fitting them for war, it becomes manifest that at first the daily assembling to carry on these exercises will entail the daily bringing of provisions by each. As happens in those pic-nics in which all who join contribute to the common repast, a certain obligation respecting quantities and qualities will naturally arise — an obligation which, repeated daily, will pass from custom into law : ending in a specification of the kinds and amounts of food. Further, it is to be expected that as the law thus arises in an age when food is coarse and unvaried, the simplicity of the diet, originally unavoidable, will eventually be considered as intended — as an ascetic regimen deliberately devised. [When writing this I was not aware that, as pointed out by Prof. Paley in Fraser's Magazine , for February, 1881, among the Greeks of later times, it was common to have dinners to which each guest brought his share of provisions, and that those who con- tributed little and consumed much were objects of satire. This fact increases the probability that the Spartan mess originated as suggested.] 378 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. The oldest Roman patricians bore the names of rural clans belonging to these cantons. Whether, when seating them- selves on the Palatine hills and on the Quirinal, they pre- served their cantonal divisions, is not clear ; though it seems probable a priori. But, however this may be, there is proof that they fortified themselves against one another, as well as against outer enemies. The “ mount-men ” of the Palatine and the “ hill-men ” of the Quirinal were habitually at feud ; and even among the minor divisions of those who occupied the Palatine, there were dissensions. As Mommsen says, primitive Rome was “ rather an aggregate of urban settle- ments than a single city,” And that the clans who formed these settlements brought with them their enmities, is to be inferred from the fact that not only did they fortify the hills on which they fixed themselves, but even “ the houses of the old and powerful families were constructed somewhat after the manner of fortresses.” So that again, in the case of Rome, we see a cluster of small independent communities, allied in blood but partially antagonistic, which had to cooperate against enemies on such terms as all would agree to. In early Greece the means of defence were, as Grote remarks, greater than the means of attack ; and it was the same in early Rome. Hence, while coercive rule within the family and the group of related families w 7 as easy, there was difficulty in extending coercion over many such groups : fortified as they were against one another. Moreover, the stringency of government within each of the communities constituting the primitive city, was diminished by facility of escape from one and admission into another. As we have seen among simple tribes, desertions take place when the rule is harsh ; and we may infer that, in primitive Rome there was a check on exercise of force by the more powerful families in each settlement over the less powerful, caused by the fear that migration might w r eaken the settlement and strengthen an adjacent one. Thus the cir- cumstances were such that wffien, for defence of the city, co- COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 379 operation became needful, the heads of the clans included in its several divisions came to have substantially equal powers. The original senate was the collective body of clan-elders; and “ this assembly of elders was the ultimate holder of the ruling power it was “ an assembly of kings.” At the same time, the heads of families in each clan, forming the body of burgesses, stood, for like reasons, on equal footing. Primarily for command in war, there was an elected head, who was also chief magistrate. Though not having the authority given by alleged divine descent, he had the autho- rity given by supposed divine approval ; and, himself bearing the insignia of a god, he retained till death the absoluteness appropriate to one. But besides the fact that the choice, originally made by the senate, had to be again practically made by it in case of sudden vacancy ; and besides the fact that each king, nominated by his predecessor, had to be ap- proved by the assembled burgesses ; there is the fact that the king's power was executive only. The assembly of burgesses “ was in law superior to, rather than co-ordinate with, the king.” Further, in the last resort was exercised the supreme power of the senate ; which was the guardian of the law and could veto the joint decision of king and burgesses. Thus the constitution was in essence an oligarchy of heads of clans, included in an oligarchy of heads of houses — a compound oligarchy which became unqualified when kingship was sup- pressed. And here should be emphasized the truth, sufficiently obvious and yet continually ignored, that the Eoman Ptepublic which remained when the regal power ended, differed utterly in nature from those popular governments with which it has been commonly classed. The heads of clans, of whom the narrower governing body was formed, as well as the heads of families who formed the wider governing- body, were, indeed, jealous of one another's powers ; and in so far simulated the citizens of a free state who individually maintain their equal rights. But these heads severally exercised unlimited powers over the members of their house- 380 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. holds and over their clusters of dependents. A community of which the component groups severally retained their in- ternal autonomies, with the result that the rule within each remained absolute, was nothing but an aggregate of small despotisms. Institutions under which the head of each group, besides owning slaves, had such supremacy that his wife and children, including even married sons, had no more legal rights than cattle, and were at his mercy in life and limb, or could be sold into slavery, can be called free institu- tions only by those who confound similarity of external out- line with similarity of internal structure.* § 48G. The formation of compound political heads in later times, repeats this process in essentials if not in details. In one way or other, the result arises when a common need for defence compels cooperation, while there exists no means of securing cooperation save voluntary agreement. Beginning with the example of Venice, we notice first that the region occupied by the ancient Veneti, included the exten- sive marshy tract formed of the deposits brought down by several rivers to the Adriatic — a tract which, in Strabo’s day, was “ intersected in every quarter by rivers, streams, and morasses so that ie Aquileia and Ravenna were then cities in the marshes.” Having for their stronghold this region full of spots accessible only to inhabitants who knew the intri- cate ways to them, the Veneti maintained their independence, spite of the efforts of the Romans to subdue them, until the time of Csesar. In later days, kindred results were more markedly displayed in that part of this region specially characterized by inaccessibility. From early ages the islets, or rather mud-banks, on which Venice stands, were inhabited # I should have thought it needless to insist on so obvious a truth had it not been that even still there continues this identification of things so utterly different. Within these few years has been published a magazine-article by a distinguished historian, describing the corruptions of the Roman Republic during its latter days, with the appended moral that such were, and are, likely to be the results of democratic government ! COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 381 by a maritime people. Each islet, secure in the midst of its tortuous lagunes, had a popular government of annually- elected tribunes. And these original governments, existing at the time when there came several thousands of fugitives, driven from the mainland by the invading Huns, survived under the form of a rude confederation. As we have seen happens generally, the union into which these inde- pendent little communities were forced for purposes of de- fence, was disturbed by feuds ; and it was only under the stress of opposition to aggressing Lombards on the one side and Sclavonic pirates on the other, that a general assembly of nobles, clergy, and citizens, appointed a duke or doge to direct the combined forces and to restrain internal factions : being superior to the tribunes of the united islets and subject only to this body which appointed him. What changes subsequently took place — how, beyond the restraints imposed by the general assembly, the doge was presently put under the check of two elected councillors, and on important occa- sions had to summon the principal citizens — how there came afterwards a representative council, which underwent from time to time modifications — does not now concern us. Here we have simply to note that, as in preceding cases, the com- ponent groups being favourably circumstanced for severally maintaining their independence of one another, the impera- tive need for union against enemies initiated a rude compound headship, which, notwithstanding the centralizing effects of war, long maintained itself in one or other form. On finding allied results among men of a different race but occupying a similar region, doubts respecting the process of causation must be dissipated. Over the area, half land, half water, formed of the sediment brought down by the Rhine and adjacent rivers, there early existed scattered families. Living on isolated sand-hills, or in huts raised on piles, they were so secure amid their creeks and mud-banks and marshes, that they remained unsubdued by the Romans. Subsisting at first by fishing, with here and there such small agriculture as was 382 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. possible, and eventually becoming maritime and commercial, these people, in course of time, rendered their land more habitable by damming out the sea; and they long enjoyed a partial if not complete independence. In the third century, “the low countries contained the only free people of the German race.” Especially the Frisians, more remote than the rest from invaders, “ associated themselves with the tribes settled on the limits of the German Ocean, and formed with them a connexion celebrated under the title of the ‘ Saxon League/ ” Though at a later time, the inhabitants of the low countries fell under Frankish invaders ; yet the nature of their habited continued to give them such advantages in resisting foreign control, that they organized themselves after their own fashion notwithstanding interdicts. “ From the time of Charlemagne, the people of the ancient Menapia, now become a prosperous commonwealth, formed political associa- tions to raise a barrier against the despotic violence of the Franks,” Meanwhile the Frisians, who, after centuries of resistance to the Franks, were obliged to yield and render small tributary services, retained their internal autonomy. They formed “a confederation of rude but self-governed maritime provinces:” each of these seven provinces being divided into districts severally governed by elective heads with their councils, and the whole being under a general elective head and a general council. Of illustrations which modern times have furnished, must be named those which again show us the effects of a moun- tainous region. The most notable is, of course, that of Switzerland. Surrounded by forests, “among marshes, and rocks, and glaciers, tribes of scattered shepherds had, from the early times of the Roman conquest, found a land of refuge from the successive invaders of the rest of Helvetia.” In the labyrinths of the Alps, accessible to those only who knew the ways to them, their cattle fed unseen ; and against straggling- bands of marauders who might discover their retreats, they had great facilities for defence. These districts—which COMrOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 383 eventually became the cantons of Schweitz, Uri, and Unter- walden, originally having but one centre of meeting, but eventually, as population increased, getting three, and forming separate political organizations — long preserved complete in- dependence. With the spread of feudal subordination throughout Europe, they became nominally subject to the Emperor ; but, refusing obedience to the superiors set over them, they entered into a solemn alliance, renewed from time to time, to resist outer enemies. Details of their history need not detain us. The fact of moment is that in these three cantons, which physically favoured in so great a degree the maintenance of independence by individuals and by groups, the people, while framing for themselves free governments, united on equal terms for joint defence. And it was these typical “ Swiss,” as they were the first to be called, whose union formed the nucleus of the larger unions which, through varied fortunes, eventually grew r up. Severally independent as were the cantons composing these larger unions, there at first existed feuds among them, which were suspended during times of joint defence. Only gradually did the league pass from temporary and unsettled forms to a permanent and settled form. Two facts of significance should be added. One is that, at a later date, a like process of resist- ance, federation, and emancipation from feudal tyranny, among separate communities occupying small mountain valleys, took place in the Grisons and in the Yalais: regions which, though mountainous, were more accessible than those of the Oberland and its vicinity. The other is that the more level cantons neither so early nor so completely gained their independence; and, further, that their internal constitutions were less free in form. A marked contrast existed between the aristocratic republics of Berne, Lucerne, Eribourg, and Soleure, and the pure democracies of the forest cantons and the Grisons; in the last of which “ every little hamlet resting in an Alpine valley, or perched on mountain crag, was an independent community, of which all the members 384 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. were absolutely equal — entitled to vote in every assembly, and qualified for every public function.” “ Each hamlet had its own laws, jurisdiction, and privileges ; ” while the hamlets were federated into communes, the communes into districts, and the districts into a league. Lastly, with the case of Switzerland may be associated that of San Marino — a little republic which, seated in the Apen- nines, and having its centre on a cliff a thousand feet high, has retained its independence for fifteen centuries. Here 8,000 people are governed by a senate of 60 and by captains elected every half-year : assemblies of the whole people being called on important occasions. There is a standing army of 18 ; “ taxation is reduced to a mere nothing ; ” and officials are paid by the honour of serving. One noteworthy difference between the compound heads arising under physical conditions of the kinds exemplified, must not be overlooked — the difference between the oligarchic form and the popular form. As shown at the outset of this section, if each of the groups united by militant cooperation is despotically ruled — if the groups are severally framed on the patriarchal type, or are severally governed by men of supposed divine descent ; then the compound head becomes one in which the people at large have no share. But if, as in these modern cases, patriarchal authority has decayed ; or if belief in divine descent of rulers has been undermined by a creed at variance with it ; or if peaceful habits have weakened that coercive authority which war ever strengthens ; then the compound head is no longer an assembly of petty despots. With the progress of these changes it becomes more and more a head formed of those who exercise power not by right of position but by right of appointment. § 487. There are other conditions which favour the rise of compound heads, temporary if not permanent — those, namely, which occur at the dissolutions of preceding organizations. Among peoples habituated for ages to personal rule, having COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 385 sentiments appropriate to it, and no conception of anything else, the fall of one despot is at once followed by the rise of another ; or, if a large personally-governed empire collapses, its parts severally generate governments for themselves of like kind. But among less servile peoples, the breaking up of political systems having single heads, is apt to be followed by the establishment of others having compound heads; especially where there is a simultaneous separation into parts which have not local governments of stable kinds. Under such circumstances there is a return to the primitive state. The pre-existing regulative system having fallen, the members of the community are left without any controlling power save the aggregate will ; and political organization having to com- mence afresh, the form first assumed is akin to that which we see in the assembly of the savage horde, or in the modern public meeting. Whence there presently results the rule of a select few subject to the approval of the many. In illustration may first be taken the rise of the Italian republics. When, during the ninth and tenth centuries, the German Emperors, who had long been losing their power to restrain local antagonisms in Italy and the outrages of wandering robber bands, failed more than ever to protect their subject communities, and, as a simultaneous result, exercised diminished control over them ; it became at once necessary and practicable for the Italian towns to develop political organizations of their own. Though in these towns there were remnants of the old Roman organization, this had obviously become effete • for, in time of danger, there was an assembling of “ citizens at the sound of a great bell, to concert together the means for their common defence.” Doubtless on such occasions were marked out the rudiments of those republican constitutions which afterwards arose. Though it is alleged that the German Emperors allowed the towns to form these constitutions, yet we may reasonably conclude, rather, that having no care further than to get their tribute, they made no efforts to prevent the towns from 386 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. forming them. And though Sismondi says of the towns- people — “ ils chercherent h se constituer sur le modele de la republique romaine yet we may question whether, in those dark days, the people knew enough of Roman institutions to be influenced by their knowledge. With more probability may we infer that “this meeting of all the men of the state capable of bearing arms ... in the great square/’ originally called to take measures for repelling aggressors — a meeting which must, at the very outset, have been swayed by a group of dominant citizens and must have chosen leaders, was itself the republican government in its incipient state. Meetings of this kind, first held on occasions of emergency, would gradually come into use for deciding all important public questions. Repetition would bring greater regularity in the modes of procedure, and greater definiteness in the divisions formed ; ending in compound political heads, presided over by elected chiefs. And that this was the case in those early stages of which there remain but vague accounts, is shown by the fact that a similar, though some- what more definite, process afterwards occurred at Florence, w T hen the usurping nobles were overthrown. Records tell us that in 1250 “ the citizens assembled at the same moment in the square of Santa Croce ; they divided themselves into fifty groups, of which each group chose a captain, and thus formed companies of militia : a council of these officers was the first-born authority of this newly revived republic.’’ Clearly, that sovereignty of the people which, for a time, characterized these small governments, would inevitably arise if the political form grew out of the original public meeting ; while it would be unlikely to have arisen had the political form been artificially devised by a limited class. That this interpretation harmonizes with the facts which modern times have furnished, scarcely needs pointing out. On an immensely larger scale and in ways variously modified, here by the slow collapse of an old regime and there by com- bination for war, the rise of the first French Republic and of COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 387 the American Republic have similarly shown us this tendency towards resumption of the primitive form of political organi- zation, when a decayed or otherwise incapable government collapses. Obscured by complicating circumstances and special incidents as these transformations were, we may recognize in them the play of the same general causes. § 488. In the last chapter we saw that, as conditions deter- mine, the first element of the tri-une political structure may be differentiated from the second in various degrees : begin- ning with the warrior-chief, slightly predominant over other warriors, and ending with the divine and absolute king widely distinguished from the select few next to him. By the foregoing examples we are shown that the second element is, as conditions determine, variously differentiated from the third: being at the one extreme qualitatively distinguished in a high degree and divided from it by an impassable barrier, and at the other extreme almost merged into it. Here we are introduced to the truth next to be dealt with ; that not only do conditions determine the various forms which compound heads assume, but that conditions determine the various changes they undergo. There are two leading kinds of such changes — those through which the compound head passes towards a less popular form, and those through which it passes towards a more popular form. We will glance at them in this order. Progressive narrowing of the compound head is one of the concomitants of continued military activity. Setting out with the case of Sparta, the constitution of which in its early form differed but little from that which the Iliad shows us existed among the Homeric Greeks, we first see the tendency towards concentration of power, in the regula- tion, made a century after Lykurgus, that “ in case the people decided crookedly, the senate with the kings should reverse their decisions and then we see that later, in consequence of the gravitation of property into fewer hands, “ the number 8 388 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of qualified citizens went on continually diminishing : 99 the implication being not only a relatively-increased power of the oligarchy, but, probably, a growing supremacy of the wealthier members within the oligarchy itself. Turning to the case of Rome, ever militant, we find that in course of time inequali- ties increased to the extent that the senate became "an order of lords, filling up its ranks by hereditary succession, and exercising collegiate misrule.” Moreover, “ out of the evil of oligarchy there emerged the still worse evil of usurpation of power by particular families.” In the Italian Republics, again, perpetually at war one with another, there resulted a kindred narrowing of the governing body. The nobility, deserting their castles, began to direct “ the municipal govern- ment of the cities, which consequently, during this period of the Republics, fell chiefly into the hands of the superior fami- lies.” Then at a later stage, when industrial progress had generated wealthy commercial classes, these, competing with the nobles for power, and finally displacing them, repeated within their respective bodies this same process. The richer gilds deprived the poorer of their shares in the choice of the ruling agencies; the privileged class was continually dimi- nished by disqualifying regulations ; and newly risen families were excluded by those of long standing. So that, as Sis- mondi points out, those of the numerous Italian Republics which remained nominally such at the close of the fifteenth century, were, like “ Sienna and Lucca, each governed by a single caste of citizens : . . . had no longer popular govern- ments.” A kindred result occurred among the Dutch. During the wars of the Flemish cities with the nobles and with one another, the relatively popular governments of the towns were narrowed. The greater gilds excluded the lesser from the ruling body ; and their members, “ clothed in the municipal purple . . . ruled with the power of an aristo- cracy . . . the local government was often an oligarchy, while the spirit of the burghers was peculiarly democratic.” And with these illustrations may be joined that furnished by COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 389 those Swiss cantons which, physically characterized in ways less favourable than the others to personal independence, were at the same time given to wars, offensive as well as defensive. Berne, Lucerne, Fribourg, Soleure, acquired politi- cal constitutions in large measure oligarchic ; and in “ Berne, where the nobles had always been in the ascendant, the entire administration had fallen into the hands of a few families, with whom it had become hereditary.” We have next to note as a cause of progressive modification in compound heads, that, like simple heads, they are apt to be subordinated by their administrative agents. The earliest case to be named is one in which this effect is exemplified along with the last — the case of Sparta. Originally appointed by the kings to perform prescribed duties, the ephors first made the kings subordinate, and eventually subordinated the senate ; so that they became substantially the rulers. From this we may pass to the instance supplied by Venice, where power, once exercised by the people, gradually lapsed into the hands of an executive body, the members of which, habitually re-elected, and at death replaced by their children, became an aristocracy, whence there eventually grew the council of ten, who were, like the Spartan ephors, “ charged to guard the security of the state with a power higher than the law;” and who thus, “ restrained by no rule,” constituted the actual government. Through its many revolutions and changes of constitution, Florence exhibited like tendencies. The appointed administrators, now signoria, now priors, became able, during their terms of office, to effect their private ends even to the extent of suspending the constitu- tion : getting the forced assent of the assembled people, who were surrounded by armed men. And then, eventually, the head executive agent, nominally re-elected from time to time but practically permanent, became, in the person of Cosmo de’ Medici, the founder of an inherited headship. But the liability of the compound political head to become subject to its civil agents, is far less than its liability to 390 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. become subject to its military agents. From the earliest times this liability has been exemplified and commented upon ; and, familiar though it is, I must here illustrate and emphasize it, because it directly bears on one of the cardinal truths of political theory. Setting out with the Greeks, we observe that the tyrants, by whom oligarchies were so often overthrown, had armed forces at their disposal. Either the tyrant was “ the executive magistrate, upon whom the oligarchy themselves had devolved important administrative powers or he was a demagogue, who pleaded the alleged interests of the community, “ in order to surround ” himself “ with armed defenders : ” soldiers being in either case the agents of his usurpation. And then, in Rome, we see the like done by the successful general. As Macchiavelli remarks — “ For the further abroad they [the generals] carried their arms, the more necessary such prolongations [of their commissions] appeared, and the more common they became ; hence it arose, in the first place, that but a few of their Citizens could be employed in the command of armies, and consequently few were capable of acquiring any considerable degree of experience or reputation ; and in the next, that when a Commander in chief was continued for a long time in that post, he had an oppor- tunity of corrupting his army to such a degree that the Soldiers entirely threw off their obedience to the Senate, and acknowledged no authority but his. To this it was owing that Sylla and Marius found means to debauch their armies and make them fight against their country ; and that Julius Csesar was enabled to make himself absolute in Rome.” The Italian Republics, again, furnish many illustrations. By the beginning of the fourteenth century, those of Lombardy “ all submitted themselves to the military power of some nobles to whom they had entrusted the command of their militias, and thus all lost their liberty.” Later times and nearer regions yield instances. At home, Cromwell showed how the successful general tends to become autocrat. In the Netherlands the same thing was exemplified by the Van Arteveldes, father and son, and again by Maurice of Nassau ; and, but for form's sake, it would be needless to name the case of Napoleon. It should be added that not only by command of armed forces is the military chief enabled to seize on COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 391 supreme power; but acquired popularity, especially in a militant nation, places him in a position which makes it relatively easy to do this. Neither their own experience nor the experiences of other nations throughout the past, pre- vented the French from lately making Marshal Macmahon executive head ; and even the Americans, in more than once choosing General Grant for President, proved that, predomi- nantly industrial though their society is, militant activity promptly caused an incipient change towards the militant type, of which an essential trait is the union of civil headship with military headship. From the influences which narrow compound political headships, or change them into single ones, let us pass to the influences which widen them. The case of Athens is, of course, the first to be considered. To understand this we must remember that up to the time of Solon, democratic government did not exist in Greece. The only actual forms were the oligarchic and the despotic ; and in those early days, before political speculation began, it is unlikely that there was recognized in theory, a social form entirely unknown in practice. We have, therefore, to exclude the notion that popular government arose in Athens under the guidance of any preconceived idea. As having the same implication should be added the fact that (Athens being governed by an oligarchy at the time) the Solonian legislation served but to qualify and broaden the oligarchy and remove crying in- justices. In seeking the causes of change which worked through Solon, and also made practicable the re-orga- nization he initiated, we shall find them to lie in the direct and indirect influences of trade. Grote comments on “ the anxiety, both of Solon and of Drako, to enforce among their fellow- citizens industrious and self-maintaining habits : ” a proof that, even before Solon’s time, there was in Attica little or no reprobation of “ sedentary industry, which in most other parts of Greece was regarded as comparatively dishonourable.” Moreover, Solon was himself in early life a trader ; and his 392 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. legislation “ provided for traders and artizans a new home at Athens, giving the first encouragement to that numerous town-population, both in the city and in the Peiraeus, which we find actually residing there in the succeeding century ” The immigrants who flocked into Attica because of its greater security, Solon was anxious to turn rather to manufacturing industry than to cultivation of a soil naturally poor ; and one result was “ a departure from the primitive temper of Atti- cism, which tended both to cantonal residence and rural occu- pation ; ” while another result was to increase the number of people who stood outside those gentile and phratric divisions, which were concomitants of the patriarchal type and of per- sonal rule. And then the constitutional changes made by Solon were in leading respects towards industrial organiza- tion. The introduction of a property-qualification for classes, instead of a birth-qualification, diminished the rigidity of the political form ; since aquirement of wealth by industry, or otherwise, made possible an admission into the oligarchy, or among others of the privileged. By forbidding self-enslave- ment of the debtor, and by emancipating those who had been self-enslaved, his laws added largely to the enfranchised class as distinguished from the slave-class. Otherwise regarded, this change, leaving equitable contracts untouched, prevented those inequitable contracts under which, by a lien on himself, a man gave more than an equivalent for the sum he borrowed. And with a decreasing number of cases in which there existed the relation of master and slave, went an increasing number of cases in which benefits were exchanged under agreement. The odium attaching to that lending at interest which ended in slavery of the debtor, having disappeared, legitimate lending became general and unopposed ; the rate of interest was free ; and accumulated capital was made available. Then, as co- operating cause, and as ever-increasing consequence, came the growth of a population favourably circumstanced for acting in concert Urban people who, daily in contact, gather one another’s ideas and feelings, and who, by quickly-diffused COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 393 intelligence are rapidly assembled, can cooperate far more readily than people scattered through rural districts. With all which direct and indirect results of industrial develop- ment, must be joined the ultimate result on character, pro- duced by daily fulfilling and enforcing contracts — a discipline which, while requiring each man to recognize the claims of others, also requires him to maintain his own. In Solon himself this attitude which joins assertion of personal rights with respect for the rights of others, was well exemplified ; since, when his influence was great he refused to become a despot, though pressed to do so, and in his latter days he resisted at the risk of death the establishment of a despo- tism. In various w^ays, then, increasing industrial activity tended to widen the original oligarchic structure. And though these effects of industrialism, joined with subse- quently-accumulated effects, were for a long time held in check by the usurping Peisistratidse, yet, being ready to show themselves when, some time after the expulsion of these tyrants, there came the Kleisthenian revolution, they were doubtless instrumental in then initiating the popular form of government. Though not in so great a degree, yet in some degree, the same causes operated in liberalizing the Eoman oligarchy. Eome “ was indebted for the commencement of its import- ance to international commerce;” and, as Mommsen points out, “ the distinction between Eome and the mass of the other Latin towns, must certainly be traced back to its com- mercial position, and to the type of character produced by that position . . . Eome was the emporium of the Latin districts.” Moreover, as in Athens, though doubtless to a smaller extent, trade brought an increasing settlement of strangers, to whom rights were given, and who, joined with emancipated slaves and with clients, formed an industrial population, the eventual inclusion of which in the burgess- body caused that widening of the constitution effected by Servius Tullius. 39 4 POLITICAL INSTITUTION’S. The Italian Republics of later days again show us, in nume- rous cases, this connexion between trading activities and a freer form of rule. The towns were industrial centres. “The merchants of Genoa, Pisa, Florence, and Venice supplied Europe with the products of the Mediterranean and of the East : the bankers of Lombardy instructed the world in the mysteries of finance, and foreign exchanges : Italian artificers taught the workmen of other countries the highest skill in the manufactures of steel, iron, bronze, silk, glass, porcelain, and jewelry. Italian shops, with their dazzling array of luxuries, excited the admiration and envy of foreigners from less favoured lands.” Then, on looking into their histories, we find that industrial gilds were the bases of their political organizations ; that the upper mercantile classes became the rulers, in some cases excluding the nobles ; and that while external wars and in- ternal feuds tended continually to revive narrower, or more personal, forms of rule, rebellions of the industrial citizens occasionally happening, tended to re-establish popular rule. When we join with these the like general connexions that arose in the Netherlands and in the Hanse towns — when we remember the liberalization of our own political institutions which has gone along with growing industrialism — when we observe that the towns more than the country, and the great industrial centres more than the small ones, have given the impulses to these changes; it becomes unquestionable that while by increase of militant activities compound headships are narrowed, they are widened in proportion as industrial activities become predominant. § 489. In common with the results reached in preceding chapters, the results above reached show that types of poli- tical organization are not matters of deliberate choice. It is common to speak of a society as though it had, once upon a time, decided on the form of government which thereafter existed in it. Even Mr. Grote, in his comparison between the institutions of ancient Greece and those of mediaeval Europe (vol. iii. pp. 10 — 12), tacitly implies that conceptions of the COMPOUND POLITICAL HEADS. 395 advantages or disadvantages of this or that arrangement, fur- nished motives for establishing or maintaining it. But, as gathered together in the foregoing sections, the facts show that as with the genesis of simple political heads, so with the genesis of compound political heads, conditions and not intentions determine. Recognizing the truth that independence of character is a factor, but ascribing this independence of character to the continued existence of a race in a habitat which facilitates evasion of control, we saw that with such a nature so con- ditioned, cooperation in war causes the union on equal terms of groups whose heads are joined to form a directive council. And according as the component groups are governed more or less autocratically, the directive council is more or less oligarchic. We have seen that in localities differing so widely as do mountain regions, marshes or mud islands, and jungles, men of different races have developed political heads of this compound kind. And on observing that the localities, otherwise so unlike, are alike in being severally made up of parts difficult of access, we cannot question that to this is mainly due the governmental form under which their in- habitants unite. Besides the compound heads which are thus indigenous in places favouring them, there are other compound heads which arise after the break-up of preceding political organizations. Especially apt are they so to arise where the people, not scattered through a wide district but concentrated in a town, can easily assemble bodily. Control of every kind having disappeared, it happens in such cases that the aggregate will has free play, and there establishes itself for a time that relatively-popular form with which all government begins ; but, regularly or irregularly, a superior few become differen- tiated from the many ; and of predominant men some one is made, directly or indirectly, most predominant. Compound heads habitually become, in course of time, either narrower or wider. They are narrowed by militancy, 396 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. which tends ever to concentrate directive power in fewer hands, and, if continued, almost certainly changes them into simple heads. Conversely, they are widened by industrialism. This, by gathering together aliens detached from the restraints imposed by patriarchal, feudal, or other such organizations ; by increasing the number of those to be coerced in compa- rison with the number of those who have to coerce them ; by placing this larger number in conditions favouring concerted action ; by substituting for daily-enforced obedience, the daily fulfilment of voluntary obligations and daily maintenance of claims ; tends ever towards equalization of citizenship. CHAPTER VIII. CONSULTATIVE BODIES. § 490. Two parts of the primitive tri-une political struc- ture have, in the last two chapters, been dealt with sepa- rately ; or, to speak strictly, the first has been considered as independent of the second, and again, the second as inde- pendent of the first : incidentally noting its relations to the third. Here we have to treat of the two in combination. Instead of observing how from the chief, little above the rest, there is, under certain conditions, evolved the absolute ruler, entirely subordinating the select few and the many; and instead of observing how, under other conditions, the select few become an oligarchy tolerating no supreme man, and keeping the multitude in subjection ; we have now to observe the cases in which there is established a cooperation between the first and the second. After chieftainship has become settled, the chief continues to have sundry reasons for acting in concert with his head men. It is needful to conciliate them ; it is needful to get their advice and willing assistance ; and, in serious matters, it is desirable to divide responsibility with them. Hence the prevalence of consultative assemblies. In Samoa, “ the chief of the village and the heads of families formed, and still form, the legislative body of the place” Among the Fulahs, “ before undertaking anything important or declaring w 7 ar, the king [of Babbali] is obliged to summon a council of 398 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Mallams and the principal people.” Of the Mandingo states we read that “ in all affairs of importance, the king calls an assembly of the principal men, or elders, by whose counsels he is directed.” And such cases might be multiplied inde- finitely. That we may understand the essential nature of this in- stitution, and that we may see why, as it evolves, it assumes the characters it does, we must once more go back to the beginning. § 491. Evidence coming from many peoples in all times, shows that the consultative body is, at the outset, nothing more than a council of war. It is in the open-air meeting of armed men, that the cluster of leaders is first seen performing that deliberative function in respect of military measures, which is subsequently extended toother measures. Long after its deliberations have become more general in their scope, there survive traces of this origin. In Rome, where the king was above all things the general, and where the senators, as the heads of clans, were, at the outset, war-chiefs, the burgesses were habitually, when called together, addressed as “ spear-men : ” there survived the title which was naturally given to them when they were present as listeners at war-councils. So during later days in Italy, when the small republics grew up. Describing the assem- bling of “ citizens at the sound of a great bell, to concert together the means of their common defence,” Sismondi says — “ this meeting of all the men of the State capable of bearing arms, was called a Parliament.” Concerning the gatherings of the Poles in early times we read : — “ Such assemblies, before the establishment of a senate, and while the kings were limited in power, were of frequent occurrence, and . . . were attended by all who bore arms;” and at a later stage “ the comitici paludata , which assembled during an interregnum, consisted of the whole body of nobles, who attended in the open plain, aimed and equipped as if for battle ” In Hungary, CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 399 too, up to the beginning of the sixteenth century, “les eisgneurs, a cheval et armes de pied en cap comme pour alter en guerre, se reunissaient dans le champ de courses de Rakos, pres de Pesth, et la discutaient en plain air les affaires pub- liques .” Again, “ the supreme political council is the nation in arms,” says Stubbs of the primitive Germans ; and though, during the Merovingian period, the popular power declined, yet “ under Chlodovech and his immediate successors, the People assembled in arms had a real participation in the resolutions of the king.” Even now the custom of going weapon in hand, is maintained where the primitive political form remains. “ To the present day,” writes M. de Laveleye, “ the inhabitants of the outer Rhodes of Appenzell come to the general assembly, one year at Hundwyl and the other at Trogen, each carrying in his hand an old sword or ancient rapier of the middle ages.” Mr. Freeman, too, was witness to a like annual gathering in Uri, where those who joined to elect their chief magistrate, and to deliberate, came armed. It may, indeed, be alleged that in early unsettled times, the carrying of weapons by each freeman was needful for personal safety ; especially when a place of meeting far from his home had to be reached. But there is evidence that though this continued to be a cause for going prepared for fight, it was not by itself a sufficient cause. While we read of the ancient Scandinavians that “all freemen capable of bearing arms were admitted” to the national assembly, and that after his election from “ among the descendants of the sacred stock,” “ the new sovereign was elevated amidst the clash of arms and the shouts of the multitude we also read that “ nobody, not even the king or his champions, were allowed to come armed to the assizes.” Even apart from such evidence, there is ample reason to infer that the council of war originated the consultative body, and gave outlines to its structure. Defence against enemies was everywhere the need which first prompted joint deli- beration. For other purposes individual action, or action in 400 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. small parties, might suffice; but for insuring the general safety, combined action of the whole horde or tribe was ne- cessary ; and to secure this combined action must have been the primary motive for a political gathering. Moreover, certain constitutional traits of early assemblies among the civilized, point to councils of war as having initiated them. If we ask what must happen when the predominant men of a tribe debate military measures in presence of the rest, the reply is that in the absence of a developed political organiza- tion, the assent of the rest to any decision must be obtained before it can be acted upon ; and the like must at first happen when many tribes are united. As Gibbon says of the diet of the Tartars, formed of chiefs of tribes and their martial trains, “ the monarch wdio reviews the strength, must consult the inclination, of an armed people.” Even if, under such conditions, the ruling few could impose their will on the many, armed like themselves, it would be impolitic to do so ; since success in war would be endangered by dissension. Hence would arise the usage of putting to the surrounding warriors, the question whether they agreed to the course which the council of chiefs had decided upon. There would grow up a form such as that which had become established for governmental purposes at large among the early Eomans, whose king or general, asked the assembled burgesses or “ spear-men,” whether they approved of the proposal made ; or like that ascribed by Tacitus to the primitive Germans, who, now with murmurs and now with brandishing of spears, rejected or accepted the suggestions of their leaders. More- over, there would naturally come just that restricted expres- sion of popular opinion which we are told of. The Boman burgesses were allowed to answer only “yes” or “no” to any question put to them ; and this is exactly the simple answer which the chief and head warriors would require from the rest of the warriors when war or peace were the alternatives. A kindred restriction existed among the Spartans. In addi- tion to the senate and co-ordinate kings, there was “an CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 401 Ekklesia or public assembly of citizens, convened for the purpose of approving or rejecting propositions submitted to them, with little or no liberty of discussion’" — a usage quite explicable if we assume that in the Homeric agora, from which the Spartan constitution descended, the assembled chiefs had to gain the assent of their followers before im- portant actions could be undertaken. Concluding, then, that war originates political deliberation, and that the select body which especially carries on this deli- beration first takes shape on occasions when the public safety has to be provided for, we shall be prepared the better to understand the traits which characterize the consultative body in later stages of its development. § 492. Already we have seen that at the outset the militant class was of necessity the land-owning class. In the savage tribe there are no owners of the tract occupied, save the warriors who use it in common for hunting. During pastoral life good regions for cattle-feeding are jointly held against intru- ders by force of arms. And where the agricultural stage has been reached, communal possession, family possession, and individual possession, have from time to time to be defended by the sword. Hence, as w r as shown, the fact that in early stages the bearing of arms and the holding of land habitually go together. While, as among hunting peoples, land continues to be held in common, the contrasts which arise between the few and the many, are such only as result from actual or supposed personal superiority of one kind or other. It is true that, as pointed out, differences of wealth, in the shape of chattels, boats, slaves, &c., cause some class-differentiations ; and that thus, even before private land-owning begins, quantity of possessions aids in distinguishing the governing from the governed. When the pastoral state is arrived at and the patriarchal type established, such ownership as there is vests in the eldest son of the eldest ; or if, as Sir Henry Maine 402 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. says, he is to be considered as trustee for the group, still his trusteeship joins with his military headship in giving him supremacy. At a later stage, when lands come to be occupied by settled families and communities, and land-ownership gains definiteness, this union of traits in each head of a group becomes more marked ; and, as was shown when treating of the differentiation of nobles from freemen, several influences conspire to give the eldest son of the eldest, superiority in extent of landed possessions, as well as in degree of power. Nor is this fundamental relation changed when a nobility of service replaces a nobility of birth, and when, as presently happens, the adherents of a conquering invader are rewarded by portions of the subjugated territory. Throughout, the tendency continues to be for the class of military superiors to be identical with the class of large landowners. It follows, then, that beginning with the assemblage of armed freemen, all of them holding land individually or in groups, whose council of leaders, deliberating in presence of the rest, are distinguished only as being the most capable warriors, there will, through frequent wars and progressing consolidations, be produced a state in which this council of leaders becomes further distinguished by the greater estates, and consequent greater powers, of its members. Becom- ing more and more contrasted with the armed freemen at large, the consultative body will tend gradually to subor- dinate it, and, eventually separating itself, will acquire inde- pendence. The growth of this temporary council of war in which the king, acting as general, summons to give their advice the leaders of his forces, into the permanent consultative body in which the king, in his capacity of ruler, presides over the deliberations of the same men on public affairs at large, is exemplified in various parts of the world. The consultative body is everywhere composed of minor chiefs, or heads of clans, or feudal lords, in whom the military and civil rule of local groups is habitually joined with wide possessions ; and CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 403 the examples frequently exhibit this composition on both a small and a large scale — both locally and generally. A rude and early form of the arrangement is shown in Africa. "We read of the Kaffirs that “ every chief chooses from among his most wealthy subjects five or six, who act as counsellors to him. . . the great council of the king is composed of the chiefs of particular kraals.” A Eechuana tribe “ gene- rally includes a number of towns or villages, each having its distinct head, under whom there are a number of subordinate chiefs,” who “ all acknowledge the supremacy of the principal one. His power, though very great and in some instances despotic, is nevertheless controlled by the minor chiefs, who in their piclios or pitshos , their parliament, or public meetings, use the greatest plainness of speech in exposing what they consider culpable or lax in his government.” Of the Wan- yamwezi, Burton says that the Sultan is “ surrounded by a council varying from two to a score of chiefs and elders. . . His authority is circumscribed by a rude balance of power ; the chiefs around him can probably bring as many warriors into the field as he can.” Similarly in Ashantee. “ The caboceers and captains . . . claim to be heard on all ques- tions relating to war and foreign politics. Such matters are considered in a general assembly ; and the king sometimes finds it prudent to yield to the views and urgent representa- tions of the majority.” From the ancient American states, too, instances may be cited. In Mexico “general assemblies were presided over by the king every eighty days. They came to these meetings from all parts of the country ; ” and then we read, further, that the highest rank of nobility, the Teuctli, “took precedence of all others in the senate, both in the order of sitting and voting : ” showing what was the composition of the senate. It was so, too, with the Central Americans of Yera Paz. “ Though the supreme rule was exercised by a king, there were inferior lords as his coadjutors, who mostly were titled lords and vassals ; they formed the royal council . . . and joined the king in his 404 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. palace as often as they were called upon.” Turning to Europe, mention may first be made of ancient Poland. Originally formed of independent tribes, “ each governed by its own hniaz , or judge, whom age or reputed wisdom had raised to that dignity,” and each led in war by a temporary voivod or captain, these tribes had, in the course of that com- pounding and re-compounding which wars produced, differen- tiated into classes of nobles and serfs, over whom w~as an elected king. Of the organization which existed before the king lost his power, we are told that — “ Though each of these palatines, bishops, and barons, could thus advise his sovereign, the formation of a regular senate was slow, and com- pleted only when experience had proved its utility. At first, the only subjects on which the monarch deliberated with his barons related to war : what he originally granted through courtesy, or through diffidence in himself, or with a view to lessen his responsibility in case of failure, they eventually claimed as a right.” So, too, during internal wars and wars against Pome, the primitive Germanic tribes, once semi-nomadic and but slightly organized, passing through the stage in which armed chiefs and freemen periodically assembled for deliberations on war and other matters, evolved a kindred structure. In Carolin- gian days the great political gathering of the year was simultaneous with the great military levy ; and the military element entered into the foreground. Armed service being the essential thing, and questions of peace and war being habitually dominant, it resulted that all freemen, while under obligation to attend, had also a right to be present at the assembly and to listen to the deliberations. And then con- cerning a later period, as Hallam writes — " In all the German principalities a form of limited monarchy pre- vailed, reflecting, on a reduced scale, the general constitution of the Empire. As the Emperors shared their legislative sovereignty with the diet, so all the princes who belonged to that assembly had their own provincial states, composed of their feudal vassals and of their mediate towns within their territory.” In France, too, provincial estates existed for local rule; and there were consultative assemblies of general scope. Thus CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 405 an " ordinance of 1228, respecting the heretics of Languedoc, is rendered with the advice of our great men and prud- hommes ; ” and one “ of 1246, concerning levies and re- demptions in Anjou and Maine,” says that “ having called around us, at Orleans, the barons and great men of the said counties, and having held attentive counsel with them,” &c. To meet the probable criticism that no notice has been taken of the ecclesiastics usually included in the consultative body, it is needful to point out that due recognition of them does not involve any essential change in the account above given. Though modern usages lead us to think of the priest- class as distinct from the warrior-class, yet it was not origi- nally distinct. With the truth that habitually in militant societies, the king is at once commander-in-chief and high priest, carrying out in both capacities the dictates of his deity, we may join the truth that the subordinate priest is usually a direct or indirect aider of the wars thus supposed to be divinely prompted. In illustration of the one truth may be cited the fact that before going to war, Eadama, king of Madagascar, “ acting as priest as well as general, sacrificed a cock and a heifer, and offered a prayer at the tomb of Andria- Masina, his most renowned ancestor.” And in illustration of the other truth may be cited the fact that among the Hebrews, whose priests accompanied the army to battle, we read of Samuel, a priest from childhood upwards, as conveying to Saul God’s command to “ smite Amalek,” and as having himself hewed Agag in pieces. More or less active partici- pation in war by priests we everywhere find in savage and semi-civilized societies ; as among the Dakotas, Mundrucus, Abipones, Khonds, whose priests decide on the time for war, or give the signal for attack ; as among the Tahitians, whose priests “ bore arms, and marched with the warriors to battle ; ” as among the Mexicans, whose priests, the habitual instiga- tors of wars, accompanied their idols in front of the army, and “ sacrificed the first taken prisoners at once ; ” as among the ancient Egyptians, of whom we read that “ the priest of a 406 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. god was often a military or naval commander;’ And the naturalness of the connexion thus common in rude and in ancient societies, is shown by its revival in later societies, notwithstanding an adverse creed. After Christianity had passed out of its early non-political stage into the stage in which it became a State-religion, its priests, during actively militant periods, re-acquired the primitive militant character. “ By the middle of the eighth century [in France], regular military service on the part of the clergy was already fully developed.” In the early feudal period, bishops, abbots, and priors, became feudal lords, with all the powers and responsi- bilities attaching to their positions. They had bodies of troops in their pay, took towns and fortresses, sustained sieges, led or sent troops in aid of kings. And Orderic, in 1094, describes the priests as leading their parishioners to battle, and the abbots their vassals. Though in recent times Church dignitaries do not actively participate in war, yet their advisatory function respecting it — often prompting rather than restraining — has not even now ceased ; as among our- selves was lately shown in the vote of the bishops, w T ho, with one exception, approved the invasion of Afghanistan. That the consultative body habitually includes ecclesiastics, does not, therefore, conflict with the statement that, beginning as a war-council, it grows into a permanent assembly of minor military heads. § 493. Under a different form, there is here partially repeated what was set forth when treating of oligarchies : the difference arising from inclusion of the king as a co-operative factor. Moreover, much that was before said respecting the influence of war in narrowing oligarchies, applies to that narrowing of the primitive consultative assembly by which there is produced from it a body of land-owning military nobles. But the consolidation of small societies into large ones effected by war, brings other influences which join in working this result. CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 407 In early assemblies of men similarly armed, it must happen that though the inferior many will recognize that authority of the superior few which is due to their leaderships as warriors, to their clan-headships, or to their supposed super- natural descent ; yet the superior few, conscious that they are no match for the inferior many in a physical contest, will be obliged to treat their opinions with some deference — will not be able completely to monopolize power. But as fast as there progresses that class-differentiation before described, and as fast as the superior few acquire better weapons than the inferior many, or, as among various ancient peoples, have war- chariots, or, as in mediaeval Europe, wear coats of mail or plate armour and are mounted on horses, they, feeling their advantage, will pay less respect to the opinions of the many. And the habit of ignoring their opinions will be followed by the habit of regarding any expression of their opinions as an impertinence. This usurpation will be furthered by the growth of those bodies of armed dependents with which the superior few surround themselves — mercenaries and others, who, while unconnected with the common freemen, are bound by fealty to their employers. These, too, with better weapons and defensive appliances than the mass, will be led to regard them with contempt and to aid in subordinating them. Not only on the occasions of general assemblies, but from day to day in their respective localities, the increasing powers of the nobles thus caused, will tend to reduce the freemen more and more to the rank of dependents ; and especially so where the military service of such nobles to their king is dispensed with or allowed to lapse, as happened in Denmark about the thirteenth century. “ The free peasantry, who were originally independent proprietors of the soil, and had an equal suffrage with the highest nobles in the land, were thus compelled to seek the protection of these powerful lords, and to come under vassalage to some neighbouring Herremand, or bishop, or convent. The provincial diets, or Lands-Ting, were gradually super- seded by the general national parliament of the Dannehnf Adel Ting, or Herredag ; the latter being exclusively composed of the princes, pre- 408 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. lates, and other great men of the kingdom. ... As the influence of the peasantry had declined, whilst the burghers did not yet enjoy any share of political power, the constitution, although disjointed and fluctuating, was rapidly approaching the form it ultimately assumed ; that of a feudal and sacerdotal oligarchy.” Another influence conducing to loss of power by the armed freemen, and gain of power by the armed chiefs who form the consultative body, follows that widening of the occupied area which goes along with the compounding and re-com- pounding of societies. As Eichter remarks of the Mero- vingian period, “ under Chlodovecli and his immediate successors, the people assembled in arms had a real participa- tion in the resolutions of the king. But, with the increasing size of the kingdom, the meeting of the entire people became impossible : ” only those who lived near the appointed places could attend. Two facts, one already given under another head, may be named as illustrating this effect. “The greatest national council in Madagascar is an assembly of the people of the capital, and the heads of the provinces, districts, towns, villages,” &c. ; and, speaking of the English Witenage- mot, Mr. Freeman says — “ sometimes we find direct mention of the presence of large and popular classes of men, as the citizens of London or Winchester : ” the implication in both cases being that all freemen had a right to attend, but that only those on the spot could avail themselves of the right. This cause for restriction, which is commented upon by Mr. Freeman, operates in several ways. When a kingdom has become large, the actual cost of a journey to the place fixed for the meeting, is too great to be borne by a man who owns but a few acres. Further, there is the indirect cost entailed by loss of time, which, to one who personally labours or superintends labour, is serious. Again, there is the danger, which in turbulent times is considerable, save to those who go with bodies of armed retainers. And, obviously, these deter- rent causes must tell where, for the above reasons, the incen- tives to attend have become small. Yet one more cause co-operates. An assembly of all the CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 409 armed freemen included in a large society, could they be gathered, would be prevented from taking active part in the proceedings, both by its size and by its lack of organization. A multitude consisting of those who have come from scattered points over a wide country, mostly unknown to one another, unable to hold previous communication and therefore without plans, as well as without leaders, cannot cope with the rela- tively small but well-organized body of those having common ideas and acting in concert. Nor should there be omitted the fact that when the causes above named have conspired to decrease the attendance of men in arms who live afar off, and when there grows up the usage of summoning the more important among them, it naturally happens that in course of time the receipt of a summons becomes the authority for attendance, and the absence of a summons becomes equivalent to the absence of a right to attend. Here, then, are several influences, all directly or indirectly consequent upon war, which join in differentiating the con- sultative body from the mass of armed freemen out of which it arises. § 494. Given the ruler, and given the consultative body thus arising, there remains to ask — What are the causes of change in their relative powers ? Always between these two authorities there must be a struggle — each trying to subordi- nate the other. Under what conditions, then, is the king enabled to over-ride the consultative body ? and under what conditions is the consultative body enabled to over-ride the king ? A belief in the superhuman nature of the king gives him an immense advantage in the contest for supremacy. If he is god-descended, open opposition to his will by his advisers is out of the question ; and members of his council, singly or in combination, dare do no more than tender humble advice. Moreover, if the line of succession is so settled that there 410 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. rarely or never occur occasions on which the king has to be elected by the chief men, so that they have no opportunity of choosing one who will conform to their wishes, they are further debarred from maintaining any authority. Hence, habitually, we do not find consultative bodies having an inde- pendent status in the despotically-governed countries of the East, ancient or modern. Though we read of the Egyptian king that “ he appears to have been attended in war by the council of the thirty, composed apparently of privy councillors, scribes, and high officers of state,” the implication is that the members of this council were functionaries, having such powers only as the king deputed to them. Similarly in Babylonia and Assyria, attendants and others who performed the duties of ministers and advisers to the god-descended rulers, did not form established assemblies for deliberative purposes. In ancient Persia, too, there was a like condition. The hereditary king, almost sacred and bearing extravagant titles, though subject to some check from princes and nobles of royal blood who were leaders of the army, and who ten- dered advice, was not under the restraint of a constituted body of them. Throughout the history of Japan down to our own time, a kindred state of things existed. The Daimios were required to reside in the capital during prescribed inter- vals, as a precaution against insubordination ; but they were never, while there, called together to take any share in the government. So too is it in China. We are told that, “ although there is nominally no deliberative or advisatory body in the Chinese government, and nothing really analo- gous to a congress, parliament, or tiers etat, still necessity compels the emperor to consult and advise with some of his officers.” Nor does Europe fail to yield us evidence of like meaning. I do not refer only to the case of Russia, but more especially to the case of France during the time when monarchy had assumed an absolute form. In the age when divines like Bossuet taught that “ the king is account- able to no one . . . the whole state is in him, and the will CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 411 of the whole people is contained in his in the age when the king (Louis XIV.), “ imbued with the idea of his omnipo- tence and divine mission/' “ was regarded by his subjects with adoration/' he “ had extinguished and absorbed even the minutest trace, idea, and recollection of all other authority except that which emanated from himself alone/' Along with establishment of hereditary succession and acquirement of semi-divine character, such power of the other estates as existed in early days had disappeared. Conversely, there are cases showing that where the king has never had, or does not preserve, the prestige of supposed descent from a god, and v T here he continues to be elective, the powder of the consultative body is apt to over-ride the royal power, and eventually to suppress it. The first to be named is that of Borne. Originally “ the king convoked the senate wdien he pleased, and laid before it his questions ; no senator might declare his opinion unasked ; still less might the senate meet without being summoned." But here, where the king, though regarded as having divine approval tvas not held to be of divine descent, and where, though usually nominated by a predecessor he was sometimes practically elected by the senate, and always submitted to the form of popular assent, the consultative body presently became supreme. “ The senate had in course of time been converted from a corporation intended merely to advise the magistrates, into a board com- manding the magistrates and self-governing." Afterwards “ the right of nominating and cancelling senators originally belonging to the magistrates was withdrawn from them /' and finally, “ the irremovable character and life-tenure of the members of the ruling order who obtained seat and vote, was definitely consolidated:" the oligarchic constitution became pronounced. The history of Poland yields another example. After unions of simply-governed tribes had produced small states, and generated a nobility ; and after these small states had been united ; there arose a kingship. At first elective, as kingships habitually are, this continued so — never became 412 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. hereditary. On the occasion of each election out of the royal clan, there was an opportunity of choosing for king one whose character the turbulent nobles thought fittest for their own purposes ; and hence it resulted that the power of the king- ship decayed. Eventually — “ Of the three orders into which the state was divided, the king, though his authority had been anciently despotic, was the least important. His dignity was unaccompanied with power ; he was merely the president of the senate, and the chief judge of the republic.” And then there is the instance furnished by Scandinavia, already named in another relation. Danish, Norwegian, and Swedish kings were originally elective ; and though, on sundry occasions, hereditary succession became for a time the usage, there were repeated lapses into the elective form, with the result that predominance was gained by the feudal chieftains and prelates forming the consultative body. § 495. The second element in the tri-une political struc- ture is thus, like the first, developed by militancy. By this the ruler is eventually separated from all below him ; and by this the superior few are gradually integrated into a delibera- tive body, separated from the inferior many. That the council of war, formed of leading warriors who debate in presence of their followers, is the germ out of which the consultative body arises, is implied by the survival of usages which show that a political gathering is originally a gathering of armed men. In harmony with this implication are such facts as that after a comparatively settled state has been reached, the power of the assembled people is limited to accepting or rejecting the proposals made, and that the mem- bers of the consultative body, summoned by the ruler, who is also the general, give their opinions only wdien invited by him to do so. Nor do we lack clues to the process by which the primitive war-council grows, consolidates, and separates itself. Within the >varrior class, which is also the land-owning class, war CONSULTATIVE BODIES. 413 produces increasing differences of wealth as well as increas- ing differences of status ; so that, along with the com- pounding and re-compounding of groups, brought about by war, the military leaders come to be distinguished as large land-owners and local rulers. Hence members of the consultative body become contrasted with the freemen at large, not only as leading warriors are contrasted with their followers, but still more as men of wealth and authority. This increasing contrast between the second and third elements of the tri-une political structure, ends in separation when, in course of time, war consolidates large territories. Armed freemen scattered over a wide area are deterred from attending the periodic assemblies by cost of travel, by cost of time, by danger, and also by the experience that multitudes of men unprepared and unorganized, are helpless in presence of an organized few, better armed and mounted, and with bands of retainers. So that passing through a time during which only the armed freemen living near the place of meet- ing attend, there comes a time when even these, not being summoned, are considered as having no right to attend ; and thus the consultative body becomes completely differentiated. Changes in the relative powers of the ruler and the con- sultative body are determined by obvious causes. If the king retains or acquires the repute of supernatural descent or authority, and the law of hereditary succession is so settled as to exclude election, those who might else have formed a consultative body having co-ordinate power, become simply appointed advisers. But if the king has not the prestige of supposed sacred origin or commission, the consultative body retains power ; and if the king continues to be elective, it is liable to become an oligarchy. Of course it is not alleged that all consultative bodies have been generated in the way described, or are constituted in like manner. Societies broken up by wars or dissolved by revolutions, may preserve so little of their primitive organiza- tions that there remain no classes of the kinds out of which 414 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. such consultative bodies as those described arise. Or, as we see in our own colonies, societies may have been formed in ways which have not fostered classes of land-owning militant chiefs, and therefore do not furnish the elements out of which consultative bodies, in their primitive shapes, are composed. Under conditions of these kinds the assemblies answering to them, so far as may be, in position and function, arise under the influence of tradition or example ; and in default of men of the original kind are formed of others — generally, how- ever, of those who by position, seniority, or previous official experience, are more eminent than those forming popular assemblies. It is only to what may be called normal consulta- tive bodies which grow up during that compounding and re- compounding of small societies into larger ones which war effects, that the foregoing account applies ; and the senates, or superior chambers, which come into existence under later and more complex conditions, may be considered as homolo- gous to them in function and composition so far only as the new conditions permit. CHAPTER IX. REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. § 496. Amid the varieties and complexities of political organization, it has proved not impossible to discern the ways in which simple political heads and compound political heads are evolved; and how, under certain conditions, the two become united as ruler and consultative body. But to see how a representative body arises, proves to be more difficult ; for both process and product are more variable. Less specific results must content us. As hitherto, so again, we must go back to the beginning to take up the clue. Out of that earliest stage of the savage horde in which there is no supremacy beyond that of the man whose strength, or courage, or cunning, gives him pre- dominance, the first step is to the practice of election — - deliberate choice of a leader in war. About the conducting of elections in rude tribes, travellers say little : probably the methods used are various. But we have accounts of elections as they were made by European peoples during early times. In ancient Scandinavia, the chief of a province chosen by the assembled people, was thereupon “ elevated amidst the clash of arms and the shouts of the multitude ; ” and among the ancient Germans he was raised on a shield, as also was the popularly-approved Merovingian king. Recalling, as this ceremony does, the chairing of a newly-elected member of parliament up to recent times ; and reminding us that origi- nally an election was by show of hands ; we are taught that the choice of a representative was once identical with the 416 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. choice of a chief. Our House of Commons had its roots in local gatherings like those in which uncivilized tribes select head warriors. Besides conscious selection there occurs among rude peoples selection by lot. The Samoans, for instance, by spinning a cocoa-nut, which, on coming to rest, points to one of the sur- rounding persons, thereby single him out. Early historic races supply illustrations ; as the Hebrews in the affair of Saul and Jonathan, and as the Homeric Greeks when fixing on a champion to fight with Hector. In both these last cases there was belief in supernatural interference: the lot was supposed to be divinely determined. And probably at the outset, choice by lot for political purposes among the Athe- nians, and for military purposes among the Bomans, as also in later times the use of the lot for choosing deputies in some of the Italian republics, and in Spain (as in Leon during the twelfth century) was influenced by a kindred belief ; though doubtless the desire to give equal chances to rich and poor, or else to assign without dispute a mission which was onerous or dangerous, entered into the motive or was even predominant. Here, however, the fact to be noted is that this mode of choice which plays a part in representation, may also be traced back to the usages of primitive peoples. So, too, we find foreshadowed the process of delegation. Groups of men who open negociations, or who make their submission, or who send tribute, habitually appoint certain of their number to act for them. The method is, indeed, necessitated ; since a tribe cannot well perform such actions bodily. Whence, too, it appears that the sending of repre- sentatives is, at the first stage, originated by causes like those which re-originate it at a later stage. Eor as the will of the tribe, readily displayed in its assemblies to its own members, cannot be thus displayed to other tribes, but must, in respect of inter-tribal matters be communicated by deputy ; so in a large nation, the people of each locality, able to govern them- selves locally, but unable to join the peoples of remote REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 417 localities in deliberations which concern them all, have to send one or more persons to express their will. Distance in both cases changes direct utterance of the popular voice into indirect utterance. Before observing the conditions under which this singling out of individuals in one or other way for specified duties, comes to be used in the formation of a representative body, we must exclude classes of cases not relevant to our present inquiry. Though representation as ordinarily conceived, and as here to be dealt with, is associated with a popular form of government, yet the connexion between them is not a neces- sary one. In some places and times representation has co- existed with entire exclusion of the masses from power. In Poland, both before and after the so-called republican form was assumed, the central diet, in addition to senators nominated by the king, was composed of nobles elected in provincial assemblies of nobles : the people at large being powerless and mostly serfs. In Hungary, too, up to recent times, the privileged class which, even after it had been greatly enlarged readied only “ one-twentieth of the adult males,” alone formed the basis of representation. “ A Hun- garian county before the reforms of 1848 might be called a direct aristocratical republic : ” all members of the noble class having a right to attend the local assembly and vote in appointing a representative noble to the general diet; but members of the inferior classes having no shares in the government. Other representative bodies than those of an exclusively aristocratic kind, must be named as not falling within the scope of this chapter. As Duruy remarks — “ Antiquity was not as ignorant as is supposed of the representative sys- tem. . . . Each Eoman province had its general assem- blies. . . . Thus the Lycians possessed a true legislative body formed by the deputies of their twenty-three towns. ,, “This assembly had even executive functions.” And Gaul, Spain, all the eastern provinces, and Greece, had like assem- 418 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. blies. But, little as is known of them, the inference is tolerably safe that these were but distantly allied in genesis and position to the bodies we now distinguish as representa- tive. Nor are we concerned with those senates and councils elected by different divisions of a town-population (such as were variously formed in the Italian republics) which served simply as agents whose doings were subject to the directly- expressed approval or disapproval of the assembled citizens. Here we must limit ourselves to that kind of representative body which arises in communities occupying areas so large that their members are obliged to exercise by deputy such powers as they possess ; and, further, we have to deal exclu- sively with cases in which the assembled deputies do not replace pre-existing political agencies but cooperate witli them. It will be well to set out by observing, more distinctly than we have hitherto done, what part of the primitive political structure it is from which the representative body, as thus conceived, originates. § 497. Broadly, this question is tacitly answered by the contents of preceding chapters. For if, on occasions of public deliberation, the primitive horde spontaneously divides into the inferior many and the superior few, among whom some one is most influential ; and if, in the course of that compounding and re-compounding of groups which war brings about, the recognized war-chief develops into the king, while the superior few become the consultative body formed of minor military leaders ; it follows that any third co-ordinate political power must be either the mass of the inferior itself, or else some agency acting on its behalf. Truism though this may be called, it is needful here to set it down ; since, before inquiring under what circumstances the growth of a repre- sentative system follows the growth of popular power, we have to recognize the relation between the two. The undistinguished mass, retaining a latent supremacy in REPKESENTATIVE BODIES. 419 simple societies not yet politically organized, though it is brought under restraint as fast as war establishes obedience, and conquests produce class-differentiations, tends, when occasion permits, to re-assert itself. The sentiments and beliefs, organized and transmitted, which, during certain stages of social evolution, lead the many to submit to the few, come, under some circumstances, to be traversed by other sentiments and beliefs. Passing references have been in several places made to these. Here we must consider them seriatim and more at length. One factor in the development of the patriarchal group during the pastoral stage, was shown to be the fostering of subordination to its head by war ; since, continually, there survived the groups in which subordination was greatest. But if so, the implication is that, conversely, cessation of war tends to diminish subordination. Members of the com- pound family, originally living together and fighting together, become less strongly bound in proportion as they have less frequently to cooperate for joint defence under their head. Hence, the more peaceful the state the more independent become the multiplying divisions forming the gens, the phratry, and the tribe. With progress of industrial life arises greater freedom of action — especially among the distantly- related members of the group. So must it be, too, in a feudally-governed assemblage. While standing quarrels with neighbours are ever leading to local battles — while bodies of men-at-arms are kept ready, and vassals are from time to time summoned to fight — while, as a concomitant of military service, acts of homage are insisted upon; there is maintained a regimental sub- jection running through the group. But as fast as aggres- sions and counter-aggressions become less frequent, the carrying of arms becomes less needful; there is less occa- sion for periodic expressions of fealty; and there is an increase of daily actions performed without direction of a superior, whence a fostering of individuality of character. 420 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. These changes are furthered by the decline of superstitious beliefs concerning the natures of head men, general and local. As before shown, the ascription of superhuman origin, or supernatural power, to the king, greatly strengthens his hands ; and where the chiefs of component groups have a sacredness due to nearness in blood to the semi-divine ancestor worshipped by all, or are members of an invading, god-descended race, their authority over dependents is largely enforced. By implication then, whatever undermines ancestor- worship, and the system of beliefs accompanying it, favours the growth of popular power. Doubtless the spread of Christianity over Europe, by diminishing the prestige of governors, major and minor, prepared the way for greater independence of the governed. These causes have relatively small effects where the people are scattered. In rural districts the authority of political superiors is weakened with comparative slowness. Even after peace has become habitual, and local heads have lost their semi-sacred characters, there cling to them awe-inspiring traditions : they are not of ordinary flesh and blood. Wealth which, through long ages, distinguishes the nobleman exclu- sively, gives him both actual power and the power arising from display. Fixed literally or practically, as the several grades of his inferiors are during days when locomotion is difficult, he long remains for them the solitary sample of a great man. Others are only known by hearsay ; he is known by experience. Inspection is easily maintained by him over dependent and sub-dependent people ; and the disrespectful or rebellious, if they cannot be punished overtly, can be deprived of occupation, or otherwise so hindered in their lives that they must submit or migrate. Down to our own day, the behaviour of peasants and farmers to the squire, is suggestive of the strong restraints which kept rural popula- tions in semi-servile states after primitive controlling influences had died away. Converse effects may be expected under converse condi- REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 421 /r tions; namely, where large numbers become closely aggre- gated. Even if such large numbers are formed of groups severally subordinate to heads of clans, or to feudal lords, sundry influences combine to diminish subordination. When there are present in the same place many superiors to whom respectively their dependents owe obedience, these superiors tend to dwarf one another. The power of no one is so im- posing if there are daily seen others who make like displays. Further, when groups of dependents are mingled, supervision cannot be so well maintained by their heads. And this which hinders the exercise of control, facilitates combination among those to be controlled : conspiracy is made easier and detec- tion of it more difficult. Again, jealous of one another, as these heads of clustered groups are likely in such circum- stances to be, they are prompted severally to strengthen themselves; and to this end, competing for popularity, are tempted to relax the restraints over their inferiors and to give protection to inferiors ill-used by other heads. Still more are their powers undermined when the assemblage includes many aliens. As before implied, this above all causes favours the growth of popular power. In proportion as immigrants, detached from the gentile or feudal divisions they severally belong to, become numerous, they weaken the structures of the divisions among which they live. Such organization as these strangers fall into is certain to be a looser one; and their influence acts as a dissolvent to the surrounding organizations. And here we are brought back to the truth which cannot be too much insisted upon, that growth of popular power is in all ways associated with trading activities. For only by trading activities can many people be brought to live in close contact. Physical necessities maintain the wide dispersion of a rural population ; while physical necessities impel the gathering together of those who are commercially occupied. Evidence from various countries and times shows that periodic gatherings for religious rites, or other public purposes, furnish 422 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. opportunities for buying and selling, which are habitually utilized ; and this connexion between the assembling of many people and the exchanging of commodities, which first shows itself at intervals, becomes a permanent connexion where many people become permanently assembled — where a town grows up in the neighbourhood of a temple, or around a stronghold, or in a place favoured by local circumstances for some manufacture. Industrial development further aids popular emancipation by generating an order of men whose power, derived from their wealth, competes with, and begins in some cases to exceed, the power of those who previously were alone wealthy — the men of rank. While this initiates a conflict which diminishes the influence previously exercised by patriarchal or feudal heads only, it also initiates a milder form of sub- ordination. Eising, as the rich trader habitually does in early times, from the non-privileged class, the relation between him and those under him is one from which there is excluded the idea of personal subjection. In proportion as the indus- trial activities grow predominant, they make familiar a con- nexion between employer and employed which differs from the relation between master and slave, or lord and vassal, by not including allegiance. Under earlier conditions there does not exist the idea of detached individual life — life which neither receives protection from a clan-head or feudal supe- rior, nor is carried on in obedience to him. But in town populations, made up largely of refugees, who either become small traders or are employed by great ones, the experience of a relatively-independent life becomes common, and the conception of it clear. And the form of cooperation distinctive of the industrial state thus arising, fosters the feelings and thoughts appro- priate to popular power. In daily usage there is a balancing of claims ; and the idea of equity is, generation after genera- tion, made more definite. The relations between employer and employed, and between buyer and seller, can be main- REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 423 tained only on condition that the obligations on either side are fulfilled. Where they are not fulfilled the relation lapses, and leaves outstanding those relations in which they are ful- filled. Commercial success and growth have thus, as their inevitable concomitants, the maintenance of the respective rights of those concerned, and a strengthening consciousness of them. In brief, then, dissolving in various ways the old relation of status , and substituting the new relation of contract (to use Sir Henry Maine’s antithesis), progressing industrialism brings together masses of people who by their circumstances are enabled, and by their discipline prompted, to modify the political organization which militancy has bequeathed. § 498. It is common to speak of free forms of government as having been initiated by happy accidents. Antagonisms between different powers in the State, or different factions, have caused one or other of them to bid for popular support, with the result of increasing popular power. The king’s jealousy of the aristocracy has induced him to enlist the sympathies of the people (sometimes serfs but more fre- quently citizens) and therefore to favour them ; or, otherwise, the people have profited by alliance with the aristocracy in resisting royal tyrannies and exactions. Doubtless, the facts admit of being thus presented. With conflict there habitually goes the desire for allies ; and throughout mediaeval Europe while the struggles between monarchs and barons were chronic, the support of the towns was important. Germany, France, Spain, Hungary, furnish illustrations. But it is an error to regard occurrences of these kinds as causes of popular powder. They are to be regarded rather as the conditions under which the causes take effect. These incidental weakenings of pre-existing institutions, do but furnish opportunities for the action of the pent-up force which is ready to work political changes. Three factors in this force may be distinguished : — the relative mass of those com- 424 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. posing the industrial communities as distinguished from those embodied in the older forms of organization ; the permanent sentiments and ideas produced in them by their mode of life ; and the temporary emotions roused by special acts of oppression or by distress. Let us observe the cooperation of these. Two instances, occurring first in order of time, are fur- nished by the Athenian democracy. The condition which preceded the Solonian legislation, was one of violent dis- sension among political factions ; and there was also “ a general mutiny of the poorer population against the rich, re- sulting from misery combined with oppression.” The more extensive diffusion of power effected by the revolution which Kleisthenes brought about, occurred under kindred circum- stances. The relatively-detached population of immigrant traders, had so greatly increased between the time of Solon and that of Kleisthenes, that the four original tribes forming the population of Attica had to be replaced by ten. And then this augmented mass, largely composed of men not under clan-discipline, and therefore less easily restrained by the ruling classes, forced itself into predominance at a time when the ruling classes were divided. Though it is said that Kleisthenes “ being vanquished in a party contest with his rival, took the people into partnership” — though the change is represented as being one thus personally initiated ; yet in the absence of that voluminous popular will which had long been growing,, the political re-organization could not have been made, or, if made, could not have been maintained. The remark which Grote quotes from Aristotle, “ that sedi- tions are generated by great causes but out of small incidents,” if altered slightly by writing “political changes” instead of “seditions,” fully applies. Tor clearly, once having been enabled to assert itself, this popular power could not be forth- with excluded. Kleisthenes could not under such circum- stances have imposed on so large a mass of men arrangements at variance with their wishes. Practically, therefore, it was the REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 425 growing industrial power which then produced, and thereafter preserved, the democratic organization. Turning to Italy, we first note that the establishment of the small republics, referred to in a preceding chapter as having been simultaneous with the decay of imperial power, may here be again referred to more specifically as having been simul- taneous with that conflict of authorities which caused this decay. Says Sismondi, “ the war of investitures gave wing to this universal spirit of liberty and patriotism in all the municipalities of Lombardy, of Piedmont, Venetia, Romagna, and Tuscany.” In other words, while the struggle between Emperor and Pope absorbed the strength of both, it became possible for the people to assert themselves. And at a later time, Florence furnished an instance similar in nature if somewhat different in form. “ At the moment when ‘ Florence expelled the Medici, that republic was bandied between three different parties/ Savonarola took advan- tage of this state of affairs to urge that the people should reserve their power to themselves, and exercise it by a council. His proposition was agreed to, and this ‘ council was declared sovereign/ ” In the case of Spain, again, popular power increased during the troubles accompanying the minority of Fernando IY. ; and of the periodic assemblies subsequently formed by deputies from certain towns (which met without authority of the Government) we read that — “ The desire of the Government to frustrate the aspiring schemes of the Infantes de la Cerda, and their numerous adherents, made the attachment of these assemblies indispensable. The disputes during the minority of Alfonso XI. more than ever favoured the pretensions of the third estate. Each of the candidates for the regency paid assiduous court to the municipal authorities, in the hope of obtaining the neces- sary suffrages / 5 And how all this was consequent on industrial development, appears in the facts that many, if not most, of these associated towns, had arisen during a preceding age by the re-coloniza- tion of regions desolated during the prolonged contests of Moors and Christians ; and that these “ poblaciones,” or com- munities of colonists, which, scattered over these vast tracts 426 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. grew into prosperous towns, had been formed of serfs and artizans to whom various privileges, including those of self- government, were given by royal charter. With which examples must be joined the example familiar to all. For in England it was during the struggle between king and barons, when the factions were nearly balanced, and when the town-populations had been by trade so far increased that their aid was important, that they came to play a noticeable part, first as allies in war and afterwards as sharers in govern- ment. It cannot be doubted that when summoning to the parliament of 1265, not only knights of the shire but also deputies from cities and boroughs, Simon of Montfort w T as prompted by the desire to strengthen himself against the royal party supported by the Pope. And whether he sought thus to increase his adherents, or to obtain larger pecuniary means, or both, the implication equally is that the urban populations had become a relatively-important part of the nation. This interpretation harmonizes with subsequent events. For though the representation of towns afterwards lapsed, yet it shortly revived, and in 1295 became established. As Hume remarks, such an institution could not “have attained to so vigorous a growth and have flourished in the midst of such tempests and convulsions,” unless it had been one, “ for which the general state of things had already pre- pared the nation the truth here to be added being that this “ general state of things” was the augmented mass, and hence augmented influence, of the free industrial communities. Confirmation is supplied by cases showing that power gained by the people during times when the regal and aris- tocratic powers are diminished by dissension, is lost again if, while the old organization recovers its stability and activity, industrial growth does not make proportionate progress. Spain, or more strictly Castile, yields an example. Such share in government as was acquired by those industrial communities which grew up during the colonization of the waste lands, became, in the space of a few reigns characterized KEPBE SENT ATIYE BODIES. 427 by successful wars and resulting consolidations, scarcely more than nominal. § 499. It is instructive to note how that primary incentive to cooperation which initiates social union at large, continues afterwards to initiate special unions within the general union. For just as external militancy sets up and carries on the organization of the whole, so does internal militancy set up and carry on the organization of the parts ; even when those parts, industrial in their activities, are intrinsically non- militant. On looking into their histories we find that the increasing clusters of people who, forming towns, lead lives essentially distinguished by continuous exchange of services under agreement, develop their governmental structures during their chronic antagonisms with the surrounding mili- tant clusters. We see, first, that these settlements of traders, growing important and obtaining royal charters, were by doing this placed in quasi-militant positions — became in modified ways holders of fiefs from their king, and had the associated re- sponsibilities. Habitually they paid dues of sundry kinds equivalent in general nature to those paid by feudal tenants ; and, like them, they were liable to military service. In Spanish chartered towns “ this was absolutely due from every inhabitant and “ every man of a certain property was bound to serve on horseback or pay a fixed sum.” In France “ in the charters of incorporation which towns received, the number of troops required was usually expressed.” And in the chartered royal burghs of Scotland “ every burgess was a direct vassal of the crown.” Next observe that industrial towns (usually formed by coalescence of pre-existing rural divisions rendered populous because local circumstances favoured some form of trade, and presently becoming places of hiding for fugitives, and of security for escaped serfs) began to stand toward the small feudally-governed groups around them, in relations like those 428 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. in which these stood to one another : competing with them for adherents, and often fortifying themselves. Sometimes, too, as in France in the 13th century, towns became suze- rains, while communes had the right of war in numerous cases; and in England in early days the maritime towns carried on wars with one another. Again there is the fact that these cities and boroughs, which by royal charter or otherwise had acquired powers of administering their own affairs, habitually formed within themselves combinations for protective purposes. In England, in Spain, in France, in Germany (sometimes with assent of the king, sometimes notwithstanding his reluctance as in England, sometimes in defiance of him, as in ancient Holland) there rose up gilds, which, having their roots in the natural unions among related persons, presently gave origin to frith- gilds and merchant-gilds ; and these, defensive in their rela- tions to one another, formed the bases of that municipal organization which carried on the general defence against aggressing nobles. Once more, in countries where the antagonisms between these industrial communities and the surrounding militant communities were violent and chronic, the industrial com- munities combined to defend themselves. In Spain the “ poblaciones,” which when they flourished and grew into large places were invaded and robbed by adjacent feudal lords, formed leagues for mutual protection ; and at a later date there arose, under like needs, more extensive confedera- tions of cities and towns, which, under severe penalties for non-fulfilment of the obligations, bound themselves to aid one another in resisting aggressions, whether by king or nobles. In Germany, too, we have the perpetual alliance entered into by sixty towns on the Ehine in 1255, when, during the troubles that followed the deposition of the Emperor Frederic II., the tyranny of the nobles had become insupportable. And we have the kindred unions formed under like incentives in Holland and in France. So that, REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 429 both in small and in large ways, the industrial groups here and there growing up within a nation, are, in many cases, forced by local antagonisms partially to assume activities and structures like those which the nation as a whole is forced to assume in its antagonisms with nations around. Here the implication chiefly concerning us is that if indus- trialism is thus checked by a return to militancy, the growth of popular power is arrested. Especially where, as happened in the Italian republics, defensive war passes into offensive war, and there grows up an ambition to conquer other terri- tories and towns, the free form of government proper to industrial life, becomes qualified by, if it does not revert to, the coercive form accompanying militant life. Or where, as happened in Spain, the feuds between towns and nobles con- tinue through long periods, the rise of free institutions is arrested; since, under such conditions, there can be neither that commercial prosperity which produces large urban popu- lations, nor a cultivation of the associated mental nature. Whence it may be inferred that the growth of popular power accompanying industrial growth in England, was largely due to the comparatively small amount of this warfare between the industrial groups and the feudal groups around them. The effects of the trading life were less interfered with ; and the local governing centres, urban and rural, were not pre- vented from uniting to restrain the general centre. § 500. And now let us consider more specifically how the governmental influence of the people is acquired. By the histories of organizations of whatever kind, we are shown that the purpose originally subserved by some arrangement is not always the purpose eventually subserved. It is so here. Assent to obligations rather than assertion of rights has ordi- narily initiated the increase of popular power. Even the transformation effected by the revolution of Kleisthenes at Athens, took the form of a re-distribution of tribes and demes for purposes of taxation and military service. In Eome, too, 430 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. that enlargement of the oligarchy which occurred under Servius Tullius, had for its ostensible motive the imposing on plebeians of obligations which up to that time had been borne exclusively by patricians. But we shall best under- stand this primitive relation between duty and power, in which the duty is original and the power derived, by going back once more to the beginning. For when we remember that the primitive political assembly is essentially a war-council, formed of leaders who debate in presence of their followers ; and when we remember that in early stages all free adult males, being warriors, are called on to join in defensive or offensive actions ; we see that, originally, the attendance of the armed freemen is in pursuance of the military service to which they are bound, and that such power as, when thus assembled, they exercise, is incidental. Later stages yield clear proofs that this is the normal order ; for it recurs where, after a political dissolution, political organiza- tion begins de novo. Instance the Italian cities, in which, as we have seen, the original “ parliaments,” summoned for defence by the tocsin, included all the men capable of bearing arms : the obligation to fight coming first, and the right to vote coming second. And, naturally, this duty of attendance survives when the primitive assemblage assumes other functions than those of a militant kind ; as witness the before- named fact that among the Scandinavians it was “ disrepu- table for freemen not to attend ” the annual assembly ; and the further facts that in France the obligation to be present at the hundred-court in the Merovingian period, rested upon all full freemen ; that in the Carolingian period “ non-attendance is punished by fines” ; that in England the lower freemen, as well as others, were “ bound to attend the shire-moot and hundred-moot ” under penalty of “ large fines for neglect of duty and that in the thirteenth century in Holland, when the burghers were assembled for public purposes, “ anyone ringing the town bell, except by general consent, and anyone not appearing when it tolls, are liable to a fine.” REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 431 After recognizing this primitive relation between popular duty and popular power, we shall more clearly understand the relation as it re-appears when popular power begins to revive along with the growth of industrialism. For here, again, the fact meets us that the obligation is primary and the power secondary. It is mainly as furnishing aid to the ruler, generally for war purposes, that the deputies from towns begin to share in public affairs. There recurs under a com- plex form, that which at an early stage we see in a simple form. Let us pause a moment to observe the transition. As was shown when treating of Ceremonial Institutions, the revenues of rulers are derived, at first wholly and after- wards partially, from presents. The occasions on which assemblies are called together to discuss public affairs (mainly military operations for which supplies are needed) naturally become the occasions on which the expected gifts are offered 'and received. When by successful wars the militant king consolidates small societies into a large one — when there comes an “ increase of royal power in intension as the king- dom increases in extension ” (to quote the luminous expres- sion of Prof. Stubbs) ; and when, as a consequence, the quasi- voluntary gifts become more and more compulsory, though still retaining such names as donum and auxilium ; it generally happens that these exactions, passing a bearable limit, lead to resistance : at first passive and in extreme cases active. If by consequent disturbances the royal power is much weakened, the restoration of order, if it takes place, is likely to take place on the understanding that, with such modifications as may be needful, the primitive system of voluntary gifts shall be re-established. Thus, when in Spain the death of Sancho I. was followed by political dissensions, the deputies from thirty- two places, who assembled at Valladolid, decided that demands made by the king beyond the customary dues should be answered by death of the messenger ; and the need for gaining the adhesion of the towns during the conflict with a pre- tender, led to an apparent toleration of this attitude. Simi- 432 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. larly in the next century, during disputes as to the regency while Alphonse XI. was a minor, the cortes at Burgos demanded that the towns should “contribute nothing beyond what was prescribed in” their charters. Kindred causes wrought kindred results in France ; as when, by an insur- rectionary league, Louis Hutin was obliged to grant charters to the nobles and burgesses of Picardy and of Normandy, renouncing the right of imposing undue exactions; and as when, on sundry occasions, the States-general were assembled for the purpose of reconciling the nation to imposts levied to carry on wars. Nor must its familiarity cause us to omit the instance furnished by our own history, when, after pre- liminary steps towards that end at St. Alban's and St. Edmund’s, nobles and people at Eunnymede effectually restrained the king from various tyrannies, and, among others, from that of imposing taxes, without the consent of his sub- jects. And now what followed from arrangements which, with modifications due to local conditions, were arrived at in several countries under similar circumstances ? Evidently when the king, hindered from enforcing unauthorized demands, had to obtain supplies by asking his subjects, or the more powerful of them, his motive for summoning them, or their representa- tives, became primarily that of getting these supplies. The predominance of this motive for calling together national assemblies, may be inferred from its predominance previously shown in connexion with local assemblies ; as instance a writ of Henry I. concerning shire-moots, in which, professing to restore ancient custom, he says — “ I will cause those courts to be summoned when I will for my own sovereign necessity, at my pleasure.” To vote money is therefpre the primary purpose for which chief men and representatives are as- sembled. § 501. From the ability to prescribe conditions under which money will be voted, grows the ability, and finally the right, REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 433 to join in legislation. This connexion is vaguely typified in early stages of social evolution. Making gifts and getting redress go together from the beginning. As was said of Gulab Singh, when treating of presents— “ even in a crowd one could catch his eye by holding up a rupee and crying out, ‘Maharajah, a petition/ He would pounce down like a hawk on the money, and, having appropriated it, would patiently hear out the petitioner.”* I have in the same place given further examples of this relation between yielding support to the governing agency, and demanding protection from it ; and the examples there given may be enforced by such others as that, among ourselves in early days, “ the king's court itself, though the supreme judicature of the kingdom, was open to none that brought not presents to the king/’ and that, as shown by the exchequer rolls, every remedy for a grievance or security against aggression had to be paid for by a bribe : a state of things which, as Hume remarks, was paralleled on the Continent. Such being the original connexion between support of the political head and protection by the political head, the inter- pretation of the actions of parliamentary bodies, when they arise, becomes clear. Just as in rude assemblies of king, military chiefs, and armed freemen, preserving in large measure the primitive form, as those in France during the Merovingian period, the presentation of gifts went along with the transaction of public business, judicial as well as military — just as in our own ancient shire-moot, local government, in- cluding the administration of justice, was accompanied by the furnishing of ships and the payment of “ a composition for the feorm-fultum, or sustentation of the king so when, after successful resistance to excess of royal power, there came * Reference to the passage since made shows not only this initial relation, but still more instructively shows that at the very beginning there arises the question whether protection shall come first and payment afterwards, or pay- ment first and protection afterwards. For the passage continues : — “ Once a man after this fashion making a complaint, when the Maharajah was taking the rupee, closed his hand on it, and said, ‘ No, first hear what I have to say.’ ” 434 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. assemblies of nobles and representatives summoned by the king, there re-appeared, on a higher platform, these simulta- neous demands for money on the one side and for justice on the other. We may assume it as certain that with an average humanity, the conflicting egoisms of those concerned will be the main factors ; and that on each side the aim will be to give as little, and get as much, as circumstances allow. F ranee, Spain, and England, yield examples which unite in showing this. When Charles Y. of France, in 1357, dismissing the States- general for alleged encroachments on his rights, raised money by further debasing the coinage, and caused a sedition in Paris which endangered his life, there was, three months later, a re-convocation of the States, in which the petitions of the former assembly were acceded to, while a subsidy for war purposes was voted. And of an assembled States-general in 1366, Hallam writes : — “ The necessity of restoring the coinage is strongly represented as the grand condition upon which they consented to tax the people, who had been long defrauded by the base money of Philip the Fair and his successors.” Again, in Spain, the incorporated towns, made liable by their charters only for certain payments and services, had continually to resist unauthorized demands ; while the kings, continually promising not to take more than their legal and customary dues, were continually breaking their promises. In 1328 Alfonso XI. “ bound himself not to exact from his people, or cause them to pay, any tax, either partial or general, not hitherto established by law, without the previous grant of all the deputies convened by the Cortes.” And how little such pledges were kept is shown by the fact that, in 1393, the Cortes w T ho made a grant to Henry III., joined the condition that — “ He should swear before one of the archbishops not to take or demand any money, service, or loan, or anything else of the cities and towns, nor of individuals belonging to them, on any pretence of necessity, until the three estates of the kingdom should first be duly summoned and assembled in Cortes according to ancient usage.” Similarly in England during the time when parliamentary REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 435 power was being established. While, with national consoli- dation, the royal authority had been approaching to absolute- ness, there had been, by reaction, arising that resistance which, resulting in the Great Charter, subsequently initiated the prolonged struggle between the king, trying to break through its restraints, and his subjects trying to maintain and to strengthen them. The twelfth article of the Charter having promised that no scutage or aid save those which were esta- blished should be imposed without consent of the national council, there perpetually recurred, both before and after the expansion of Parliament, endeavours on the king’s part to get supplies without redressing grievances, and endeavours on the part of Parliament to make the voting of supplies con- tingent on fulfilment of promises to redress grievances. On the issue of this struggle depended the establishment of popular power ; as we are shown by comparing the histories of the French and Spanish Parliaments with that of the English Parliament. Quotations above given prove that the Cortes originally established, and for a time maintained, the right to comply with or to refuse the king’s requests for money, and to impose their conditions ; but they eventually failed to get their conditions fulfilled. “ In the struggling condition of Spanish liberty under Charles I., the crown began to neglect answering the petitions of Cortes, or to use un- satisfactory generalities of expression. This gave rise to many remon- strances. The deputies insisted, in 1523, on having answers before they granted money. They repeated the same contention in 1525, and obtained a general law, inserted in the Recopilacion, enacting that the king should answer all their petitions before he dissolved the assembly. This, however, was disregarded as before.” And thereafter rapidly went on the decay of parliamentary power. Different in form but the same in nature, was the change which occurred in France. Having at one time, as shown above, made the granting of money conditional on the obtainment of justice, the States-general was induced to surrender its restraining powers. Charles VII. — “ obtained from the States of the royal domains which met in 1439 that 10 436 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. they [the tailles] should be declared permanent, and from 1444 he levied them as such, i.e . uninterruptedly and without previous vote. . . . The permanence of the tailles was extended to the provinces annexed to the crown, but these preserved the right of voting them by their pro- vincial estates. ... In the hands of Charles VII., and Louis XI., the royal impost tended to be freed from all control. . . . Its amount increased more and more.” Whence, as related by Dareste, it resulted that “ when the tailles and aides . . . had been made permanent, the convocation of the States -general ceased to be necessary. They were little more than show assemblies.” But in our own case, during the century succeeding the final establish- ment of Parliament, frequent struggles necessitated by royal evasions, trickeries, and falsehoods, brought increasing power to withhold supplies until petitions had been attended to. Admitting that this issue was furthered by the conflicts of political factions, which diminished the coercive power of the king, the truth to be emphasized is that the increase of a free industrial population was its fundamental cause. The calling together knights of the shire, representing the class of small landowners, which preceded on several occasions the calling together deputies from towns, implied the growing im- portance of this class as one from which money was to be raised ; and when deputies from towns were summoned to the Parliament of 1295, the form of summons shows that the motive was to get pecuniary aid from portions of the popula- tion which had become relatively considerable and rich. Already the king had on more than one occasion sent special agents to shires and boroughs to raise subsidies from them for his wars. Already he had assembled provincial councils formed of representatives from cities, boroughs, and market- towns, that he might ask them for votes of money. And when the great Parliament was called together, the reason set forth in the writs was that wars with Wales, Scotland, and France, were endangering the realm : the implication being that the necessity for obtaining supplies led to this recogni- tion of the towns as well as the counties. REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 437 So too was it in Scotland. The first known occasion on which representatives from burghs entered into political action, was when there was urgent need for pecuniary help from all sources; namely, “at Cambuskenneth on the 15th day of July, 1326, when Bruce claimed from his people a revenue to meet the expenses of his glorious war and the necessities of the State, which was granted to the monarch by the earls, barons, burgesses, and free tenants, in full parliament assembled.” In which cases, while we are again shown that the obliga- tion is original and the power derived, we are also shown that it is the increasing mass of those who carry on life by volun- tary cooperation instead of compulsory cooperation — partly the rural class of small freeholders and still more the urban class of traders — which initiates popular representation. § 502. Still there remains the question — How does the representative body become separate from the consultative body ? Betaining the primitive character of councils of war, national assemblies w T ere in the beginning mixed. The dif- ferent “ arms,” as the estates were called in Spain, originally formed a single body. Knights of the shire when first sum- moned, acting on behalf of numerous smaller tenants of the king owing military service, sat and voted with the greater tenants. Standing, as towns did at the outset, very much in the position of fiefs, those who represented them were not unallied in legal status to feudal chiefs ; and, at first assembling with these, in some cases remained united with them, as appears to have been habitually the case in France and Spain. Under what circumstances, then, do the consultative and representa- tive bodies differentiate ? The question is one to which there seems no very satisfactory answer. Quite early we may see foreshadowed a tendency to part, determined by unlikeness of functions. During the Carolin- gian period in France, there were two annual gatherings : a larger which all the armed freemen had a right to attend, and 438 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. a smaller formed of the greater personages deliberating on more special affairs. “ If the weather was fine, all this passed in the open air ; if not, in distinct buildings. . . . When the lay and ecclesiastical lords were . . . separated from the multitude, it remained in their option to sit together, or separately, according to the affairs of which they had to treat.” And that unlikeness of functions is a cause of separation we find evidence in other places and times. Describing the armed national assemblies of the Hungarians, originally mixed, Levy writes : — “ La derniere reunion de ce genre eut lieu quelque temps avant la bataille de Mohacs ; mais bientot apres, la diete se divisa en deux chambres: la table des magnats et la table des deputes.” In Scotland, again, in 1367 — 8, the three estates having met, and wishing, for reasons of economy and convenience, to be excused from their functions as soon as possible, “ elected certain persons to hold Parliament, who were divided into two bodies, one for the general affairs of the king and kingdom, and another, a smaller division, for acting as judges upon appeals.” In the case of England we find that though, in the writs calling together Simon of Montfort’s Parliament, no distinction was made between magnates and deputies, yet when, a generation after, Parliament became established, the writs made a dis- tinction : “ counsel is deliberately mentioned in the invitation to the magnates, action and consent in the invitation to representatives.” Indeed it is clear that since the earlier- formed body of magnates w T as habitually summoned for consultative purposes, especially military, while the represen- tatives afterwards added were summoned only to grant money, there existed from the outset a cause for separation. Sundry influences conspired to produce it. Difference of language, still to a considerable extent persisting and imped- ing joint debate, furnished a reason. Then there was the effect of class-feeling, of which we have definite proof. Though they were in the same assembly, the deputies from boroughs “ sat apart both from the barons and knights, who REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 439 disdained to mix with such mean personages ; ” and probably the deputies themselves, little at ease in presence of imposing superiors, preferred sitting separately. Moreover, it was customary for the several estates to submit to taxes in dif- ferent proportions ; and this tended to entail consultation among the members of each by themselves. Finally, we read that “ after they [the deputies] had given their consent to the taxes required of them, their business being then finished, they separated, even though the Parliament still continued to sit, and to canvass the national business.” In which last fact we are clearly shown that though aided by other causes, unlikeness of duties was the essential cause which at length produced a permanent separation between the representative body and the consultative body. Thus at first of little account, and growing in power only because the free portion of the community occupied in pro- duction and distribution grew in mass and importance, so that its petitions, treated with increasing respect and more fre- quently yielded to, began to originate legislation, the repre- sentative body came to be that part of the governing agency which more and more expresses the sentiments and ideas of industrialism. While the monarch and upper house are the products of that ancient regime of compulsory cooperation the spirit of which they still manifest, though in decreasing degrees, the lower house is the product of that modern regime of voluntary cooperation which is replacing it ; and in an increasing degree, this low r er house carries out the wishes of people habituated to a daily life regulated by contract instead of by status. § 503. To prevent misconception it must be remarked, before summing up, that an account of representative bodies which have been in modern days all at once created, is not here called for. Colonial legislatures, consciously framed in conformity with traditions brought from the mother-country, illustrate the genesis of senatorial and representative bodies 440 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. in but a restricted sense: showing, as they do, how the structures of parent societies reproduce themselves in derived societies, so far as materials and circumstances allow; but not showing how these structures were originated. Still less need we notice those cases in which, after revolutions, peoples who have lived under despotisms are led by imitation sud- denly to establish representative bodies. Here we are con- cerned only with the gradual evolution of such bodies. Originally supreme, though passive, the third element in the tri-une political structure, subjected more and more as militant activity develops an appropriate organization, begins to re-acquire power when war ceases to be chronic. Subordi- nation relaxes as fast as it becomes less imperative. Awe of the ruler, local or general, and accompanying manifestations of fealty, decrease ; and especially so where the prestige of supernatural origin dies out. Where the life is rural the old relations long survive in qualified forms ; but clans or feudal groups clustered together in towns, mingled with numbers of unattached immigrants, become in various ways less con- trollable ; while by their habits their members are educated to increasing independence. The small industrial groups thus growing up within a nation consolidated and organized by militancy, can but gradually diverge in nature from the rest. For a long time they remain partially militant in their structures and in their relations to other parts of the com- munity. At first chartered towns stand substantially on the footing of fiefs, paying feudal dues and owing military service. They develop, within themselves, unions, more or less coercive in character, for mutual protection. They often carry on wars with adjacent nobles and with one another. They not uncommonly form leagues for joint defence. And where the semi-militancy of towns is maintained, industrial development and accompanying increase of popular power are arrested. But where circumstances have favoured manufacturing and commercial activities, and growth of the population devoted REPRESENTATIVE BODIES. 441 to them, this, as it becomes a large component of the society, makes its influence felt. The primary obligation to render money and service to the head of the State, often reluctantly complied with, is resisted when the exactions are great ; and resistance causes conciliatory measures. There comes asking assent rather than resort to compulsion. If absence of violent local antagonisms permits, then on occasions when the political head, rousing anger by injustice, is also weakened by defections, there comes cooperation with other classes of oppressed ' subjects. Men originally delegated simply that they may authorize imposed burdens, are enabled as the power behind them increases, more and more firmly to insist on conditions ; and the growing practice of yielding to their petitions as a means to obtaining their aid, initiates the practice of letting them share in legislation. Finally, in virtue of the general law of organization that difference of functions entails differentiation and division of the parts performing them, there comes a separation. At first summoned to the national assembly for purposes par- tially like and partially unlike those of its other members, the elected members show a segregating tendency, which, where the industrial portion of the community continues to gain power, ends in the formation of a representative body distinct from the original consultative body. CHAPTER X. MINISTKIES. § 504. Men chosen by the ruler to help him, we meet with in early stages of social evolution — men whose positions and duties are then vague and variable. At the outset there is nothing to determine the selection of helpers save considera- tions of safety, or convenience, or liking. Hence we find ministers of quite different origins. Relationship leads to the choice in some places and times; as with the Bachassins, among whom the chief’s brother conveys his orders and sees them executed; as of old in Japan, where the Emperor’s son was prime minister and the daimios had cadets of their families as counsellors; as in ancient Egypt where “ the principal officers of the Court or administration appear to have been at the earliest period the relatives” of the king. Though in some cases family -jealousy excludes kinsmen from these places of authority, in other cases family-feeling and trust, and the belief that the desire for family-predominance will ensure loyalty, lead to the employment of brothers, cousins, nephews, &e. More general appears to be the unobtrusive growth of per- sonal attendants, or household servants, into servants of State. Those who are constantly in contact with the ruler have opportunities of aiding or hindering intercourse with him, of biassing him by their statements, and of helping or impeding the execution of his commands; and they thus gain power, and tend to become advising and executive MINISTRIES. 443 agents. From the earliest times onwards we meet with illustrations. In ancient Egypt — “ The office of fan-bearer to the king was a highly honourable post, which none but the royal princes, or the sons of the first nobility, were permitted to hold. These constituted a principal part of his staff ; and in the field they either attended on the monarch to receive his orders, or were despatched to have the command of a division.” In Assyria the attendants who thus rose to power were not relatives, but were habitually eunuchs; and the like hap- pened in Persia. “ In the later times, the eunuchs acquired a vast political authority, and appear to have then filled all the chief offices of state. They were the king’s advisers in the palace, and his generals in the field.” Kindred illustra- tions are furnished by the West. Shown among the primitive Germans, the tendency for officers of the king’s household to become political officers, was conspicuous in the Merovingian period : the seneschal, the marshal, the chamberlain, grew into public functionaries. Dowm to the later feudal period in France, the public and household administrations of .the king were still undistinguished. So was it in old English times. According to Kemble, the four great officers of the Court and Household were the Hraege Thegn (servant of the wardrobe) ; the Steallere and Horsthegn (first, Master of the Horse, then General of the Household Troops, then Constable or Grand Marshal) ; the Discthegn (or thane of the table — afterwards Seneschal) ; the Butler (perhaps Byrele or Scenca). The like held under the conquering Normans ; and it holds in a measure down to the present time. Besides relatives and servants, friends are naturally in some cases fixed on by the ruler to get him information, give him advice, and carry out his orders. Among ancient examples the Hebrews furnish one. Remarking that in the small kingdoms around Israel in earlier times, it was customary for the ruler to have a single friend to aid him, Ewald points out that under David, with a larger State and a more complex ad- ministration, “ the different departments are necessarily more subdivided, and new offices of ‘ friends ’ or ministers of the 444 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. king assume a sort of independent importance.” Like needs produced kindred effects in the first days of the Eoman empire. Duruy writes : — “ Augustus, who called himself a plain Eoman citizen, could not, like a king, have ministers, but only friends who aided him with their experi- ence. . . . The multitude of questions . . . induced him afterwards to distribute the chief affairs regularly among his friends. . . . This council was gradually organized.” And then in later days and other regions, we see that out of the group known as “ friends of the king ” there are often some, or there is one, in whom confidence is reposed and to whom power is deputed. In Eussia the relation of Lefort to Peter the Great, in Spain that of Albuquerque to Don Pedro, and among ourselves that of Gaveston to Edward II., sufficiently illustrate the genesis of ministerial power out of the power gained by personal friendship and consequent trust. And then with instances of this kind are to be joined instances showing how attachment between the sexes comes into play. Such facts as that after xilbuquerque fell, all offices about the court were filled by relations of the king's mistress ; that in France under Louis XV. “ the only visible government was that by women” from Mme. de Prie to Mme. du Barry ; and that in Eussia during the reign of Catherine II., her successive lovers acquired political power, and became some of them prime ministers and practically autocrats ; will serve adequately to recall a ten- dency habitually displayed. Eegarded as able to help the ruler supernaturally as well as naturally, the priest is apt to become his chosen ally and agent. The Tahitians may be named as having a prime minister who is also chief priest. In Africa, among the Eggarahs (Inland Negroes), a priest “officiates as minister of war.” How political power of priests results from their sup- posed influence with the gods, is well shown by the case of Mizteca (part of Mexico). “The high-priests were highly respected by the caziques, who did nothing without their advice ; they commanded armies, and ruled the MINISTRIES. 445 state, reproved vice, and when there was no amendment, threatened famine, plague, war, and the anger of the gods.” Other places in ancient America — Guatemala, Yera Paz, &c., furnish kindred facts ; as do historic peoples from the earliest times downwards. In ancient Egypt the king’s advisers mostly belonged to the priestly caste. Under the Roman emperors ecclesiastics became ministers and secret counsellors. In mediaeval days Dominican and Franciscan monks held the highest political offices. And in later times the connexion was shown by the ministerial power of cardinals, or, as in Russia, of patriarchs. This acquisition of leading political functions by functionaries of the church, has in some cases special causes in addition to the general cause. A royal chaplain (uniting the character of personal attendant with that of priest) stands in a relation to the king which almost necessitates acquisition of great influence. Moreover, being fitted by culture for secretarial work, he falls naturally into certain State-duties; as he did into those of chancellor among ourselves in early days. Recognizing the fact that at the outset, these adminis- trative agents, whatever further characters they have, are usually also soldiers, and are included in the primitive consul- tative body, of which they become specialized parts, w'e may say of them generally, that they are relatives, friends, attend- ants, priests, brought into close relations with the ruler, out of whom he is obliged by stress of business to choose assist- ants ; and that at first vague and irregular, their appointments and functions gradually acquire definiteness. § 505. Amid much that is too indefinite for generalization, a few tolerably constant traits of ministers, and traits of ministries, may be briefly indicated. That a trusted agent commonly acquires power over his principal, is a fact everywhere observable. Even in a gen- tleman’s household a head servant of long standing not unfrequently gains such influence, that his master is in 446 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. various matters guided by him — almost controlled by him. With chief officers of State it has often been the same ; and especially where hereditary succession is well established. A ruler who, young, or idle, or pleasure-seeking, performs his duties by proxy, or who, through personal liking or entire trust, is led to transfer his authority, presently becomes so ill informed concerning affairs, or so unused to modes of pro- cedure, as to be almost poAverless in the hands of his agent. Where hereditary succession pervades the society and fixes its organization, there is sometimes shown a tendency to inheritance, not of the rulership only, but also of these offices which grow into deputy-rulerships. Under the Nor- man dukes before the Conquest, the places of seneschal, cup-bearer, constable, and chamberlain, were “ hereditary grand serjeanties.” In England in Henry II.’s time, succes- sion to the posts of high-steward, constable, chamberlain, and butler, followed from father to son in the houses of Leicester, Miles, Yere, and Albini. So was it with the Scotch in King David’s reign : “ the offices of great steward and high constable had become hereditary in the families of Stewart and De Morevil.” And then in Japan the principle of inheritance of ministerial position had so established itself as to insure ministerial supremacy. In these cases there come into play influences and methods like those which conduce to hereditary kingship. When, as during the later feudal period in France, we see efforts made to fix in certain lines of descent, the chief offices of State (efforts which, in that case, sometimes succeeded and sometimes failed), we are shown that ministers use the facilities which their places give them, to establish succession to these places in their own families, in the same way that early kings do. Just as, during the stage of elective kingship, the king is apt to use the advan- tages derived from his position to secure the throne for his son, by getting him chosen during his own life, and thus to initiate hereditary succession ; so the minister who has been allowed to acquire great power, is prompted to employ it for MINISTRIES. 447 the purpose of establishing a monopoly of his office among his own descendants. Generally his desire is effectually antagonized by that of the ruler; but where, as in Japan, seclusion of the ruler impedes his hold on affairs, this desire of the minister takes effect. Since there ever tend to arise these struggles between a king and one or more of those who serve him — since his efforts to maintain his authority are sometimes so far defeated that lie is obliged to accept assistants who are hereditary ; there results a jealousy of those whose interests are at variance with his own, and an endeavour to protect himself by ex- cluding them from office. There comes a motive for choosing as ministers men who, having no children, cannot found houses which, growing powerful, may compete for supremacy ; and hence in certain times the preference for celibate priests. Or, from allied motives, men neither clerical nor military are selected; as in France, where in the 15th and 17th centuries, members of the bourgeois class came to be preferred. A policy like that shown in the befriending of towns as a set-off against feudal chiefs, prompted the official employment of citizens instead of nobles. Under other conditions, again, there is a jealousy of ecclesiastics and an exclusion of them from power. For generations before the time of Peter the Great, the head of the church in Eussia was “ considered the second person in the empire ; he was consulted on all State-affairs, until at length, their [his] spiritual pride outrunning all decorum, venturing upon, and even attempting to control the sovereign power, it was resolved by Peter the Great to abolish the patriarchate altogether.” Between Louis XIY. and the Pope, there was a conflict for supremacy over the French church ; and on more occasions than one, certain of the clergy encouraged “the absolutist pretensions of the Eoman Pontiffs the result being that such prelates as held office were those v/ho subordinated clerical to political aims, and that by Louis XIY., after 1661, “no churchman was allowed to touch the great engine of State-go vernment,” Among ourselves may 448 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. be traced, if less clearly, the working of kindred tendencies. During the 15th century, “ clergymen were secretaries of government, the privy seals, cabinet councillors, treasurers of the crown, ambassadors, commissioners to open parlia- ment, and to Scotland; presidents of the king’s council, supervisors of the royal works, chancellors, keepers of the records, the masters of the rolls, &c. but with antagonism to the Church came partial, and in later days complete, disappear- ance of the clerical element from the administration. Under Henry VIII. the King’s secretary, and afterwards the chan- cellor, ceased to be ecclesiastics ; while of the council of six- teen executors appointed to govern during the minority of his son, three only were in holy orders. And though, during a subsequent temporary revival of papal influence, there was a re-acquirement of ministerial position by priests, they after- wards again ceased to be chosen. Whether a ruler is able to prevent high offices of State from being held by men whose ambitions and interests he fears, depends, however, upon his acquirement of adequate predominance. A class which, being powerful, is excluded as therefore dangerous, being still more powerful, cannot be excluded; and is apt either to monopolize administrative functions or practically to dictate the choice of ministers. In ancient Egypt, where the priesthood was pre-eminent in influence, the administration was chiefly officered by its members, with the result that at one time there was usurpa- tion of the kingship by priests ; and the days during which the Catholic church was most powerful throughout Europe, were the days during which high political posts were very generally held by prelates. In other cases supremacy of the military class is shown ; as in Japan, where soldiers have habitually been the ministers and practically usurpers ; as in feudal England, when Henry III. was obliged by the barons to accept Hugh Le Despenser as chief justiciary, and other nominees as officers of his household ; or as when, in the East, down to our own time, changes of ministry are insisted MINISTRIES. 449 on by the soldiery. Naturally in respect of these administra- tive offices, as in respect of all other places of power, there arises a conflict between the chiefs of the warrior class, who are the agents of the terrestrial ruler, and the chiefs of the clerical class, who profess to be agents of the celestial ruler ; and the predominance of the one or the other class, is in many cases implied by the extent to which it fills the chief offices of State. Such facts show us that where there has not yet been established any regular process for making the chief advisers and agents of the ruler into authorized exponents of public opinion, there nevertheless occurs an irregular process by which some congruity is maintained between the actions of these deputy rulers and the will of the community ; or, at any rate, the will of that part which can express its will. § 506. Were elaboration desirable, and collection of the needful data less difficult, a good deal might here be added respecting the development of ministries. Of course it could, in multitudinous cases, be shown how, beginning as simple, they become compound — the soli- tary assistant to the chief, helping him in all ways, develop- ing into the numerous great officers of the king, dividing among them duties which have become extensive and in- volved. Along with this differentiation of a ministry might also be traced the integration of it that takes place under certain conditions : the observable change being from a state in which the departmental officers separately take from the ruler their instructions, to a state in which they form an incorporated body. There might be pursued an inquiry respecting the conditions under which this incorporated body gains power and accompanying responsibility ; with the pro- bable result of showing that development of an active executive council, and accompanying reduction of the original executive head to an automatic state, characterizes that re- presentative form of government proper to the industrial 450 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. type. But while results neither definite nor important are likely to he reached, the reaching of such as are promised would necessitate investigation at once tedious and unsatis- factory. For such ends as are here in view, it suffices to recognize the general facts above set forth. As the political head is at first but a slightly-distinguished member of the group — now a chief whose private life and resources are like those of any other warrior, now a patriarch or a feudal lord who, becoming predominant over other patriarchs or other feudal lords, at first lives like them on revenues derived from private possessions — so the assistants of the political head take their rise from the personal connexions, friends, servants, around him : they are those who stand to him in private relations of blood, or liking, or service. With the extension of territory, the in- crease of affairs, and the growth of classes having special interests, there come into play influences which differentiate some of those wdio surround the ruler into public functionaries, distinguished from members of his family and his household. And these influences, joined with special circumstances, de- termine the kinds of public men who come into power. Where the absoluteness of the political head is little or not at all restrained, he makes arbitrary choice irrespective of rank, occupation, or origin. If, being predominant, there are nevertheless classes of whom he is jealous, exclusion of these becomes his policy ; while if his predominance is inadequate, representatives of such classes are forced into office. And this foreshadows the system under which, along with decline of monarchical power, there grows up an incorporated body of ministers having for its recognized function to execute the public will. CHAPTEE XI. LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. § 507. This title is needed because the classes of facts to be here dealt with, cover a wider area than those comprehended under the title “ Local Governments.” We have to deal with two kinds of appliances for control, originally one but gradually becoming distinguished. Alike among peoples characterized by the reckoning of kinship through females, and among peoples characterized by descent of property and power through males, the regulative system based on blood-relationship is liable to be involved with, and subordinated by, a regulative system originating from military leadership. Authority established by triumph in war, not unfrequently comes into conflict with authority derived from the law of succession, when this has become partially settled, and initiates a differentiation of political headship from family headship. We have seen that, from primitive stages upwards, the principle of efficiency and the principle of inheritance are both at work in determining men’s social positions; and where, as happens in many cases, a war-chief is appointed when the occasion arises, notwithstanding the existence of a chief of acknowledged legitimacy, there is a tendency for transmitted power to be over-ridden by power derived from capacity. From the beginning, then, there is apt to grow up a species of government distinct from family-government ; and the apti- tude takes effect where many family-groups, becoming united. 452 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. carry on militant activities. The growth of the family into the gens, of the gens into the phratry, of the phratry into the tribe, implies the multiplication of groups more and more remotely akin, and less and less easily subordinated by the head of some nominally-leading group ; and when local aggre- gation brings interfusion of tribes which, though of the same stock, have lost their common genealogy, the rise of some headship other than the headships of family-groups becomes imminent. Though such political headship, passing through the elective stage, often becomes itself inheritable after the same manner as the original family-headships, yet it consti- tutes a new kind of headship. Of the local governing agencies to which family-headships and political headships give origin, as groups become com- pounded and re-compounded, we will consider first the poli- tical, as being most directly related to the central governing agencies hitherto dealt with. o § 508. According to the relative powers of conqueror and conquered, war establishes various degrees of subordination. Here the payment of tribute and occasional expression of homage, interfere but little with political independence ; and there political independence is almost or quite lost. Generally, however, at the outset the victor either finds it necessary to respect the substantial autonomies of the vanquished societies, or finds it his best policy to do this. Hence, before inte- gration has proceeded far, local governments are usually nothing more than those governments of the parts which existed before they were united into a whole. We find instances of undecided subordination everywhere. In Tahiti “ the actual influence of the king over the haughty and despotic district chieftains, was neither powerful nor permanent. ,, Of our own political organization in old English times Kemble writes : — “ the whole executive government may be considered as a great aristocratic association, of which the ealdormen were the constituent earls, and the king little LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 453 more than president” Similarly during early feudal times ; as, for example, in France. “ Under the first Capetians, we find scarcely any general act of legislation. . . . Everything was local, and all the possessors of fiefs first, and afterwards all the great suzerains, possessed the legislative power within their domains.” This is the kind of relation habitually seen during the initial stages of those clustered groups in which one group has acquired power over the rest. In cases where the successful invader, external to the cluster instead of internal, is powerful enough completely to subju- gate all the groups, it still happens that the pre-existing local organizations commonly survive. Ancient American states yield examples. “ When the kings of Mexico, Tezcuco, and Tacuba conquered a province, they used to maintain in their authority all the natural chiefs, the highest as well as the lower ones.” Concerning certain rulers of Chibcha com- munities, who became subject to Bogota, we read that the Zipa subdued them, but left them their jurisdiction and left the succession to the caziqueship in their families. And as was pointed out under another head, the victorious Yncas left outstanding the political headships and administrations of the many small societies they consolidated. Such is, in fact, the most convenient policy. As is remarked by Sir Henry Maine, “ certain institutions of a primitive people, their cor- porations and village-communities, will always be preserved by a suzerain-state governing them, on account of the facilities which they afford to civil and fiscal administration and the like may be said of the larger regulative structures. Indeed the difficulty of suddenly replacing an old local organization by an entirely new one, is so great that almost of necessity the old one is in large measure retained. The autonomies of local governments, thus sometimes scarcely at all interfered with and in other cases but partially suppressed, manifest themselves in various ways. The original independence of groups continues to be shown by the right of private war between them. They retain their 454 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. local gods, their ecclesiastical organizations, their religious festivals. And in time of general war the contingents they severally furnish remain separate. Egyptian nomes, Greek cities, feudal lordships, yield illustrations. § 509. The gradual disappearance of local autonomies is a usual outcome of the struggle between the governments of the parts, which try to retain their powers, and the central government, which tries to diminish their powers. In proportion as his hands are strengthened, chiefly by successful wars, the major political head increases his restraints over the minor political heads ; first by stopping private wars among them, then by interfering as arbitrator, then by acquiring an appellate jurisdiction. Where the local rulers have been impoverished by their struggles with one another, or by futile attempts to recover their independence, or by drafts made on their resources for external wars — where, also, followers of the central ruler have grown into a new order of nobles, with gifts of conquered or usurped lands as rewards for services ; the way is prepared for administrative agencies centrally appointed. Thus in France, when the monarch became dominant, the seigneurs were gradually deprived of legislative authority. Eoyal confirmation became requisite to make signorial acts valid ; and the crown acquired the exclusive right of granting charters, the exclusive right of ennobling, the exclusive right of coining. Then with decline in the power of the original local rulers came deputies of the king overlooking them : provincial governors holding office at the king’s pleasure were nominated. In subsequent periods grew up the administration of intendants and their sub-dele- gates, acting as agents of the crown ; and whatever small local powers remained were exercised under central supervision. English history at various stages yields kindred illustrations. When Mercia was formed out of petty kingdoms, the local kings became ealdormen; and a like change took place afterwards on a larger scale. “ From the time of Ecgberht LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 455 onwards there is a marked distinction between the King and the Ealdorman. The King is a sovereign, the Ealdorman is only a magistrate/’ Just noting that under Cnut, eal- dormen became subordinated by the appointment of earls, and again that under William I. earldoms were filled up afresh, we observe that after the Wars of the Eoses had weak- ened them, the hereditary nobles had their local powers inter- fered with by those of centrally-appointed lords-lieutenant. Not only provincial governing agencies of a personal kind come to be thus subordinated as the integration furthered by war progresses, but also those of a popular kind. The old English Scirgerefa, who presided over the Sciregemot, was at first elective, but was afterwards nominated by the king. Under a later regime there occurred a kindred change: “ 9 Edward II. abolished the popular right to election” to the office of sheriff. And similarly, “from the beginning of Edward III/s reign, the appointment of conservators ” of the peace, who were originally elected, “ was vested in the crown,” “ and their title changed to that of justices.” With sufficient distinctness such facts show us that, rapidly where a cluster of small societies is subjugated by an invader, and slowly where one among them acquires an established supremacy, the local rulers lose their directive powers and become executive agents only ; discharging what- ever duties they retain as the servants of newer local agents. In the course of political integration, the original governing centres of the component parts become relatively automatic in their functions. § 510. A further truth to be noted is that there habitually exists a kinship in structure between the general government and the local governments. Several causes conspire to pro- duce this kinship. Where one of a cluster of groups has acquired power over the rest, either directly by the victories of its ruler over them, or indirectly by his successful leadership of 456 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the confederation in war, this kinship becomes a matter of course. For under such conditions the general government is but a development of that which was previously one of the local governments. We have a familiar illustration furnished by old English times in the likeness between the hundred-moot (a small local governing assembly), the shire-moot (constituted in an analogous way, but having military, judicial, and fiscal duties of a wider kind, and headed by a chief originally elected), and the national witanagemot (containing originally the same class-elements, though in different proportions, headed by a king, also at first elected, and discharging like functions on a larger scale). This similarity recurs under another phase. Sir Henry Maine says : — “ It has often, indeed, been noticed that a Feudal Monarchy was an exact counterpart of a Feudal Manor, but the reason of the correspon- dence is only now beginning to dawn upon us, which is, that both of them were in their origin bodies of assumed kinsmen settled on land and undergoing the same transmutation of ideas through the fact of settlement.” Of France in the early feudal period, Maury says, “the court of every great feudatory, was the image, of course slightly reduced, of that of the king and the facts he names curiously show that locally, as generally, there was a develop- ment of servants into ministerial officers. Kindred evidence comes from other parts of the world — Japan, several African States, sundry Polynesian islands, ancient Mexico, Mediaeval India, &c. ; where forms of society essentially similar to those of the feudal system exist or have existed. Where the local autonomy has been almost or quite destroyed, as by a powerful invading race bringing with it another type of organization, we still see the same thing; for its tendency is to modify the institutions locally as it modifies them generally. From early times eastern king- doms have shown us this ; as instance the provincial rulers, or satraps, of the Persians. “ While . . . they remained in office they were despotic — they represented the Great King, LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 457 and were clothed with a portion of his majesty, . . . They wielded the power of life and death.” And down to the present day this union of central chief- despot with local sub- despots survives ; as is implied by Eawlinson’s remark that these ancient satraps had “ that full and complete authority which is possessed by Turkish pashas and modem Persian khans or beys — an authority practically uncontrolled.” Other ancient societies of quite other types displayed this tendency to assimilate the structures of the incorporated parts to that of the incorporating whole. Grecian history shows us that oligarchic Sparta sought to propagate oligarchy as a form of government in dependent territories, while democratic Athens propagated the democratic form. And, similarly, where Pome conquered and colonized, there followed the Eoman municipal system. This last instance reminds us that as the character of the general government changes, the character of the local government changes too. In the Eoman empire that progress towards a more concentrated form of rule which con- tinued militancy brought, spread from centre to periphery. “ Under the Kepublic every town had, like Eome, a popular assembly which was sovereign for making the law and ‘ creat- ing’ magistrates; ” but with the change towards oligarchic and personal rule in Eome, popular power in the provinces decreased : “ the municipal organization, from being demo- cratic, became aristocratic.” In France, as monarchical power approached absoluteness, similar changes were effected in another way. The government seized on municipal offices, “ erecting them into hereditary offices, and . . . selling them at the highest price : . . . a permanent mayor and assessors were imposed upon all the municipalities of the kingdom, which ceased to be elective ; ” and then these magistrates began to assume royal airs — spoke of the sanctity of their magistracy, the veneration of the people, &c. Our own history interest- ingly shows simultaneous movements now towards freer, and now towards less free, forms, locally and generally. When, 458 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. under King John, the central government was liberalized, towns acquired the power to elect their own magistrates. Conversely when, at the Eestoration, monarchical power increased, there was a framing of the “ municipalities on a more oligarchical model.” And then comes the familiar case of the kindred liberalizations of the central government and the local governments which have occurred in our own time. § 511. From those local governing agencies which have acquired a political character, we turn now to those which have retained the primitive family character. Though with the massing of groups, political organization and rule become separate from, and predominant over, family-organization and rule, locally as well as generally, yet family- organization and rule do not disappear ; but in some cases retaining their orginal nature, in some cases give origin to other local organizations of a governmental kind. Let us first note how wide-spread is the presence of the family-cluster, considered as a component of the political society. Among the uncivilized Bedouins we see it existing sepa- rately : “ every large family with its relations constituting a small tribe by itself.” But, says Palgrave, “ though the clan and the family form the basis and are the ultimate expression of the civilized Arab society, they do not, as is the case among the Bedouins, sum it up altogether.” That is, political union has left outstanding the family-organization, but has added something to it. And it was thus with Semitic societies of early days, as those of the Hebrews. Everywhere it has been thus with the Ayrans. 1 The [Irish] Sept is a body of kinsmen whose progenitor is no longer living, but whose descent from him is a reality. . . . An association of this sort is well known to the law of India as the Joint Undivided Family. . . . The family thus formed by the continuance of several generations in union, is identical in outline with a group very familiar to the students of the older Eoman law — the Agnatic Kindred.” Hot only where descent in the male line has been established, LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 459 but also where the system of descent through females con- tinues, this development of the family into gens, pliratry, and tribe, is found. It was so with such ancient American peoples, as those of Yucatan, where, within each town, tribal divisions were maintained ; and, according to Mr. Morgan and Major Powell, it is still so with such American tribes as the Iroquois and the Wyandottes. After its inclusion in a political aggregate, as before its in- clusion, the family-group evolves a government jwasi-political in nature. According to the type of race and the system of descent, this family-government may be, as among ancient Semites and Ayrans, an unqualified patriarchal despotism ; or it may be, as among the Hindoos at present, a personal rule arising by selection of a head from the leading family of the group (a selection usually falling on the eldest) ; or it may be, as in American tribes like those mentioned, the govern- ment of an elected council of the gens, which elects its chief. That is to say, the triune structure which tends to arise in any incorporated assembly, is traceable in the compound family-group, as in the political group : the respective com- ponents of it being variously developed according to the nature of the people and the conditions. The government of each aggregate of kinsmen repeats, on a small scale, functions like those of the government of the political aggregate. As the entire society revenges itself on other such societies for injury to its members, so does the family-cluster revenge itself on other family-clusters included in the same society. This fact is too familiar to need illus- tration ; but it may be pointed out that even now, in parts of Europe where the family-organization survives, the family vendettas persist. “ L’Albanais vous dira froidement . . . Akeni-Dgiak? avez-vous du sang a venger dans votre famille and then, asking the name of your tribe, he puts his hand on his pistol. With this obligation to take vengeance goes, of course, reciprocal responsibility. The family in all its branches is liable as a whole, and in each part, for the 460 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. injuries done by its members to members of other families ; just as the entire society is held liable by other entire societies. This responsibility holds not alone for lives taken by members of the family-group, but also for damages they do to property, and for pecuniary claims, “ Dans les districts Albanais libres, les dettes sont contractces a terme. En cas de non-paiement, on a recours aux chefs de la tribu du debiteur, et si cenx-ci refusent de faire droit, on arrete le premier venu qui appartient a cette tribn, et on Faccable de manvais traitements jusqu’a ce qu’il s’entende avec le veritable debiteur, ou qu J il paie lui- meme ses dettes, risque a se pouvoir ensuite devant les anciens de sa tribu ou de poursuivre par les armes celui qui lui a valu ce dommage,” And of the old English msegth we read that “ if any one was imprisoned for theft, witchcraft, &c., his kindred must pay the fine . . . and must become surety for his good conduct on his release/’ While, within the political aggregate, each compound family-group thus stood towards other such included groups in quasi-political relations, its government exercised internal control. In the gens as constituted among the American peoples above named, there is administration of affairs by its council. The gentile divisions among historic peoples were ruled by their patriarchs ; as are still those of the Hindoos by their chosen elders. And then besides this judicial organi- zation within the assemblage of kindred, there is the religious organization, arising from worship of a common ancestor, which entails periodic joint observances. Thus the evidence shows us that while the massing together of groups by war, has, for its concomitant, develop- ment of a political organization which dominates over the organizations of communities of kindred, yet these com- munities of kindred long survive, and partially retain their autonomies and their constitutions. § 512. Social progress,* however, transforms them in sundry ways — differentiating them into groups which gradually lose their family-characters. One cause is change from the wander- LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 461 ing life to tlie settled life, with the implied establishment of definite relations to the land, and the resulting multipli- cation and interfusion. To show that this process and its consequences are general, I may name the calpulli of the ancient Mexicans, which “ means a district inhabited by a family ... of ancient origin ; ” whose members hold estates which “ belong not to each inhabitant, but to the calpulli ; ” who have chiefs chosen out of the tribe ; and who “ meet for dealing with the com- mon interests, and regulating the apportionment of taxes, and also what concerns the festivals.” And then I may name as being remote in place, time, and race, the still-existing Russian mir, or village-commune ; which is constituted by descendants of the same family-group of nomads who became settled ; which is “ a judicial corporation . . . proprietor of the soil, of which individual members have but the usufruct or temporary enjoyment;” which is governed by “ the heads of families, assembled in council under the presidency of the s tarosta or mayor, whom they have elected.” Just noting these allied examples, we may deal more especially with the Teu- tonic mark, which was “ formed by a primitive settlement of a family or kindred,” when, as said by Caesar of the Suevi, the land was divided among “ gentes et cognationes homi- num.” In the words of Kemble, marks were — “ Great family-unions, comprising households of various degrees of wealth, rank, and authority ; some in direct descent from the common ancestors, or from the hero of the particular tribe ; others, more dis- tantly connected . . . ; some, admitted into communion by marriage, others by adoption, others by emancipation ; but all recognizing a brotherhood, a kinsmanship or sibsceaft ; all standing together as one unit in respect of other similar communities ; all governed by the same judges and led by the same captains ; all sharing in the same religious rites ; and all known to themselves and to their neighbours by one general name.” To which add that, in common with family-groups as already described, the cluster of kindred constituting the mark had, like both smaller and larger clusters, a joint obligation to 462 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. defend and avenge its members, and a joint responsibility for their actions. And now we are prepared for observing sundry influences which conspire to change the grouping of kindred into poli- tical grouping, locally as well as generally. In the first place, there is that admission of strangers into the family, gens, or tribe, which we have before recognized as a normal process, from savage life upwards. Livingstone, remarking of the Bakwains that “ the government is patriarchal/’ describes each chief man as having his hut encircled by the huts of his wives, relatives, and dependents, forming a kotla : “ a poor man attaches himself to the kotla of a rich one and is con- sidered a child of the latter.” Here we see being done informally, that which was formally done in the Roman household and the Teutonic mark. In proportion as the adopted strangers increase, and in proportion also as the cluster becomes diluted by incorporating with Itself emanci- pated dependents, the links among its members become weakened and its character altered. In the second place, when, by concentration and multiplication, different clusters of kindred placed side by side, become interspersed, and there ceases to be a direct connexion between locality and kinship, the family or gentile bonds are further weakened. And then there eventually results, both for military and fiscal pur- poses, the need for a grouping based on locality instead of on relationship. An early illustration is furnished by the Kleisthenian revolution in Attica, which made a division of the territory into demes, replacing for public purposes tribal divisions by topographical divisions, the inhabitants of each of which had local administrative powers and public respon- sibilities. We are here brought to the vexed question about the origin of tythings and hundreds. It was pointed out that the ancient Peruvians had civil as well as military divisions into tens and hundreds, with their respective officers. In China, where there is pushed to an extreme the principle of LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 463 making groups responsible for their members, the clan-divi- sions are not acknowledged by the government, but only the tytliings and hundreds : the implication being that these last were results of political organization as distinguished from family-organization. In parts of Japan, too, “ there is a sort of subordinate system of wards, and heads of tens and hundreds, in the Otonos of towns and villages, severally and collectively responsible for each other’s good conduct.” We have seen that in Eome, the groupings into hundreds and tens, civil as well as military, became political substitutes for the gentile groupings. Under the Frankish law, “ the tything- man is Decanus , the hundred-man Centenarius ; ” and what- ever may have been their indigenous names, divisions into tens and hundreds appear to have had (judging from the state- ments of Tacitus) an independent origin among the Germanic races. And now remembering that these hundreds and tytliings, formed within the marks or other large divisions, still answered in considerable degrees to groups based on kinship (since the heads of families of which they were constituted as local groups, were ordinarily closer akin to one another than to the heads of families similarly grouped in other parts of the mark), we go on to observe that there survived in them, or were re-developed in them, the family-organization, rights, and obligations. I do not mean merely that by their hundred-moots, &c., they had their internal administra- tions ; but I mean chiefly that they became groups which had towards other groups the same joint claims and duties which family-groups had. Responsibility for its members, previously attaching exclusively to the cluster of kindred irrespective of locality, was in a large measure transferred to the local cluster formed but partially of kindred. For this transfer of responsibility an obvious cause arose as the gentes and tribes spread and became mingled. While the family-community was small and closely aggregated, an offence committed by one of its members against another such com- 464 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. munity could usually be brought home to it bodily, if not to the sinning member; and as a whole it had to take the consequences. But when the family-community, multi- plying, began to occupy a wide area, and also became inter- fused with other family-communities, the transgressor, while often traceable to some one locality within the area, was often not identifiable as of this or that kindred; and the con- sequences of his act, when they could not be visited on his family, which was not known, were apt to be visited on the inhabitants of the locality, who were known. Hence the genesis of a system of suretyship which is so ancient and so widespread. Here are illustrations : — “This then is my will, that every man be in surety, both within the towns and without the towns.” — Eadg. ii. Supp. § 3. “ And we will that every freeman be brought into a hundred and into a tithing, who desires to be entitled to lad or wer , in case any one should slay him after he have reached the age of xii years : or let him not other- wise be entitled to any free rights, be he householder, be he follower.” — Cnut, ii. § xx. “ ... in all the vills throughout the kingdom, all men are bound to be in a guarantee by tens, so that if one of the ten men offend, the other nine may hold him to right.” — Edw. Conf., xx. Speaking generally of this system of mutual guarantee, as exhibited among the Russians, as well as among the Franks, Koutorga says — “ Tout membre de la societe devait entrer dans une decanie, laquelle avait pour mission la defence et la garantie de tous en general et de chacun en particular ; c’est-ei-dire que la decanie devait venger le citoyen qui lui appartenait et exiger le w^ehrgeld, s’il avait ete tue ; mais en meme temps elle se portait caution pour tous les seins.” In brief, then, this form of local governing agency, developing out of, and partially replacing, the primitive family-form, was a natural concomitant of the multiplication and mixture resulting from a settled life. § 513. There remains to be dealt with an allied kind of local governing agency — a kind which, appearing to have been once identical with the last, eventually diverged from it. LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 465 Kemble concludes that the word “ gegyldan ” means " those who mutually pay for one another . . . the associates of the tithing and the hundred;” and how the two were originally connected, we are shown by the statement that as late as the 10th century in London, the citizens were united into frithgylds, “ or associations for the maintenance of the peace, each consisting of ten men ; while ten such gylds were gathered into a hundred.” Prof. Stubbs writes : — "The collective responsibility for producing an offender, which had lain originally on the msegth or kindred of the accused, was gradually devolved on the voluntary association of the guild ; and the guild super- seded by the local responsibility of the tithing.” Here we have to ask whether there are not grounds for con- cluding that this transfer of responsibility originally took place through development of the family-cluster into the gild, in consequence of the gradual loss of the family-cha- racter by incorporation of unrelated members. That we do not get evidence of this in written records, is probably due to the fact that the earlier stages of the change took place before records were common. But we shall see reasons fox believing in such earlier stages if we take into account facts furnished by extinct societies and societies less developed than those of Europe. Of the skilled arts among the Peruvians, Prescott re- marks : — “ these occupations, like every other calling and office in Peru, always descended from father to son ; ” and Clavigero says of the Mexicans “ that they perpetuated the arts in families to the advantage of the State : ” the reason Gomara gives why “ the poor taught their sons their own trades,” being that “ they could do so without expense ” — a reason of general application. Heeren’s researches into ancient Egyptian usages, have led him to accept the state- ment of early historians, that “ the son was bound to carry on the trade of his father and that alone ; ” and he cites a papyrus referring to an institution naturally connected with this usage — “ the guild or company of curriers or leather- 466 POLITICAL INSTITUTION'S. dressers.” Then of the Greeks, Hermann tell us that various arts and professions were — “ peculiar to certain families, whose claims to an exclusive exercise of them generally ascended to a fabulous origin. We moreover find ‘ pupil and son 5 for many successive generations designated by the same term ; and closely connected with the exclusiveness and monopoly of many professions, is the little respect in which they were, in some instances, held by the rest of the people : a circumstance which Greek authors themselves compare with the prejudice of caste prevalent among other nations.” China, as at present existing, yields evidence : — “The popular associations in cities and towns are chiefly based upon a community of interests, resulting either from a similarity of occupation, when the leading persons of the same calling form themselves into guilds, or from the municipal regulations requiring the householders living in the same street to unite to maintain a police, and keep the peace of their division. Each guild has an assembly-hall, where its members meet to hold the festival of their patron saint.” And, as I learn from the J apanese minister, a kindred state of things once existed in J apan. Children habitually followed the occupations of their parents; in course of generations there resulted clusters of relatives engaged in the same trade ; and these clusters developed regulative arrangements within themselves. Whether the fact that in Japan, as in the East generally, the clustering of traders of one kind in the same street, arises from the original clustering of the similarly- occupied kindred, I find no evidence; but since, in early times, mutual protection of the members of a trading kindred, as of other kindred, was needful, this seems probable. Fur- ther evidence of like meaning may be disentangled from the involved phenomena of caste in India. In No. CXLII of the Calcutta Review , in an interesting essay by Jogendra Chandra Ghosh, caste is regarded as “ a natural development of the Indian village-communities ; ” as “ distinguished not only by the autonomy of each guild,” “ but by the mutual relations between these autonomous guilds ; ” and as being so internally organized “ that caste government does not recognize the finding or the verdict of any court other than LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 467 what forms part of itself/’ In answer to my inquiries, the writer of this essay has given me a mass of detailed informa- tion, from which I extract the following : — “ A Hindoo joint family signifies (1) that the members all mess together ; (2) and live in the same house ; (3) that the male members and un- married girls are descended from a common ancestor ; and (4) that the male members put their incomes together. . . . The integral character of the family is destroyed when the joint mess and common purse cease to exist. However, the branches thus disunited continue to observe certain close relations as gnatis up to some seven or fourteen generations from the common ancestor. Beyond that limit they are said to be merely of the same gotra Passing over the detailed constitution of a caste as consist- ing of many such gotras , and of the groups produced by their intermarriages under restrictions of exogamy of the gotras and endogamy of the caste — passing over the feasts, sacrificial and other, held among members of the joint family when their groups have separated ; I turn to the facts of chief significance. Though, under English rule, inheritance of occupation is no longer so rigorous, yet — “ the principle is universally recognized that every caste is bound to follow a particular occupation and no other. . . . The partition of the land, or the house as well, is governed by the law of equal succession ; and as fresh branches set up new houses, they are found all clustered together, with the smallest space between them for roadway. . . . But when, as in bazaars , men take up houses for commercial purposes, the clustering is governed either by family and caste -relations, or by common avocations [which imply some caste-kinship] and facility of finding customers.” In which facts we may see pretty clearly that were there none of the complications consequent on the intermarriage regulations, there would simply result groups united by occupation as well as by ancestry, clustering together, and having their internal governments. Returning from consideration of these facts supplied by other societies, let us now observe how numerous are the reasons for concluding that the gild, familiar to us as a union of similarly-occupied workers, was originally a union of kindred. In the primitive compound family there was 468 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. worship of the common ancestor ; and the periodic sacrificial feasts were occasions on which all the descendants assembled. Describing the origin of gilds, Thierry writes “Dans Fancienne Scandinavie, ceux qni se reunissaient aux epoques solennelles pour sacrifier ensemble terminaient la ceremonie par un festin religieux. Assis autour du feu et de la chaudiere du sacrifice, ils buvaient a la ronde et vidaient successivement trois cornes remplies de biere, Tune pour les dieux, Fautre pour les braves du vieux temps, et la troisieme pour les parents et les amis dont les tombes, marquees par des monticules de gazon, se voyaient §a et la dans la plaine ; on appelait celle-ci la coupe de Famitie. Le nom d’amiti6 (minne) se donnait aussi quelquefois a la reunion de ceux qui offraient en commun le sacrifice, et, d’ordinaire, cette reunion etait appelee ghilde .” And Brentano, giving a similar account, says — “ f Gild ’ meant originally the sacrificial meal made up of the common contri- butions ; then a sacrificial banquet in general ; and lastly a society/' Here we find a parallelism with the observances of the Hindoo joint-family, consisting of clusters of relatives carrying on the same occupation, who meet at feasts which were primarily sacrificial to ancestors; and we find a parallelism with the religious observances of such clusters of similarly-occupied relatives as the Asklepiadse among the Greeks; and we find a parallelism with the gild- feasts of the ancestor- worshipping Chinese, held in honour of the patron saint : all suggesting the origin of those religious services and feasts habitual in early gilds of our own society. To state briefly the further likenesses of nature : — We have, in the primitive compound family, the obligation of blood-revenge for slain relatives ; and in early gilds, as in ancient Sleswig, there was blood-revenge for members of the gild. We have, in the compound family, responsibility for transgressions of its members ; and gilds were similarly responsible : the wergylds falling in part on them, after murders were compounded for by money. We have, in the compound family, joint claims to sustenance derived from the common property and labour ; and in the gild we have the duty of maintaining incapable members. Within the family there was control of private conduct, either LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 469 by a despotic head or by a council, as there is now within the local clusters of the Hindoo castes ; and in like manner the ordinances of gilds extended to the regulation of personal habits. Lastly, this family or caste government, as still shown us in India, includes in its punishments excommuni- cation ; and so, too, was there outlawry from the gild.* It is inferable, then, that the gild was evolved from the family. Continuance of a business, art, or profession, among descendants, is, in early stages, almost inevitable. Acquisi- tion of skill in it by early practice is easy ; the cost of teaching is inappreciable ; and retention of the “ craft ” or “ mystery ” within the family is desirable : there being also the reason that while family-groups are in antagonism, the teaching of one another’s members cannot usually be practicable. But in course of time there come into play influences by which the character of the gild as an assemblage of kindred is obscured. Adoption, which, as repeatedly pointed out, is practised by groups of all kinds, needs but to become common to cause this constitutional change. We have seen that among the Greeks, “pupil” and “son” had the same name. At the present time in J apan, an apprentice, standing in the position of son to his master, calls him “ father and in our own craft-gilds “the apprentice became a member of the family of his master, who instructed him in his trade, and who, like a father, had to watch over his morals, as well as his work.” The eventual admission of the apprentice into the gild, when he was a stranger in blood to its mem- bers, qualified, in so far, its original nature; and where, through successive generations, the trade was a prosperous * A friend who has read this chapter in proof, points out to me passages in which Brentano draws from these parallelisms a like inference. Re- ferring to the traits of certain fully-developed gilds, he says : — “ If we con- nect them with what historians relate about the family in those days, we may still recognize in them the germ from which, in later times, at a certain stage of civilization, the Gild had necessarily to develop itself , . . the family appears as the pattern and original type, after which all the later Gilds were formed,” 470 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. one, tempting masters to get more help than their own sons could furnish, this process would slowly bring about predomi- nance of the unrelated members, and an ultimate loss of the family-character. After which it would naturally happen that the growing up of new settlements and towns, bringing together immigrants who followed the same calling but were not of the same blood, would lead to the deliberate forma- tion of gilds after the pattern of those existing in older places : an appearance of artificial origin being the result ; just as now, in our colonies, there is an apparently artificial origin of political institutions which yet, a3 being fashioned like those of the mother-country, where they were slowly evolved, are traceable to a natural origin. Any one who doubts the transformation indicated, may be reminded of a much greater transformation of allied- kind. The gilds of London, — goldsmiths’, fishmongers’, and the rest, — were originally composed of men carrying on the trades implied by their names ; but in each of these com- panies the inclusion of persons of other trades, or of no trade, has gone to the extent that few if any of the members carry on the trades which their memberships imply. If, then, the process of adoption in this later form, has so changed the gild that, while retaining its identity, it has lost its distinctive trade-character, we are warranted in concluding that still more readily might the earlier process of adop- tion into the simple family or the compound family practis- ing any craft, eventually change the gild from a cluster of kindred to a cluster formed chiefly of unrelated persons. § 514. Involved and obscure as the process has been, the evolution of local governing agencies is thus fairly compre- hensible. We divide them into two kinds, which, starting from a common root, have diverged as fast as small societies have been integrated into large ones. Through successive stages of consolidation, the political heads of the once-separate parts pass from independence to LOCAL GOVERNING AGENCIES. 471 dependence, and end in being provincial agents — first partially- conquered chiefs paying tribute ; then fully-conquered chiefs governing under command ; then local governors who are appointed by the central governor and hold power under approval : becoming eventually executive officers. There is habitually a kinship in character between the controlling systems of the parts and the controlling system of the whole (assuming unity of race), consequent on the fact that both are ultimately products of the same individual nature. With a central despotism there goes local despotic rule ; with a freer form of the major government there goes a freer form of the minor governments ; and a change either way in the one is followed by a kindred change in the other. While, with the compounding of small societies into large ones, the political ruling agencies which develop locally as well as generally, become separate from, and predominant over, the ruling agencies of family-origin, these last do not disappear ; but, surviving in their first forms, also give origin to differentiated forms. The assemblage of kindred long continues to have a qualified semi* political autonomy, with internal government and external obligations and claims. And while family-clusters, losing their definiteness by inter- fusion, slowly lose their traits as separate independent societies, there descend from them clusters which, in some cases united chiefly by locality and in others chiefly by occupation, inherit their traits, and constitute governing agencies supplementing the purely political ones. It may be added that these supplementary governing agencies, proper to the militant type of society, dissolve as the industrial type begins to predominate. Defending their members, held responsible for the transgressions of their members, and exercising coercion over their members, they are made needful by, and bear the traits of, a regime of chronic antagonisms ; and as these die away their raison d'etre disappears. Moreover, artificially restricting, as they 472 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. do, tlie actions of each member, and also making him re- sponsible for other deeds than his own, they are at variance with that increasing assertion of individuality which accom- panies developing industrialism. CHAPTER XII. MILITARY SYSTEMS. § 515. Indirectly, much has already been said concerning the subject now to be dealt with. Originally identical as is the political organization with the military organization, it has been impossible to treat of the first without touching on the second. After exhibiting the facts under one aspect we have here to exhibit another aspect of them ; and at the same time to bring into view classes of related facts thus far unob- served. But, first, let us dwell a moment on the alleged original identity. In rude societies all adult males are warriors ; and, conse- quently, the army is the mobilized community, and the com- munity is the army at rest, as was remarked in § 259. With this general truth we may join the general truth that the primitive military gathering is also the primitive poli- tical gathering. Alike in savage tribes and in communities like those of our rude ancestors, the assemblies which are summoned for purposes of defence and offence, are the assemblies in which public questions at large are decided. Next stands the fact, so often named, that in the normal course of social evolution, the military head grows into the political head. This double character of leading warrior and civil ruler, early arising, ordinarily continues through long stages; and where, as not unfrequently happens, military headship becomes in a measure separated from political 474 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. headship, continued warfare is apt to cause a re-identifi- cation of them. As societies become compounded and re-compounded, coin- cidence of military authority with political authority is shown in detail as well as in general — in the parts as in the whole. The minor war-chiefs are also minor civil rulers in their several localities; and the commanding of their respective groups of soldiers in the field, is of like nature with the governing of their respective groups of dependents at home. Once more, there is the general fact that the economic organizations of primitive communities, coincide with their military organizations. In savage tribes war and hunting are carried on by the same men ; while their wives (and their slaves where they have any) do the drudgery of domestic life. And, similarly, in rude societies that have become settled, the military unit and the economic unit are the same. The soldier is also the landowner. Such, then, being the primitive identity of the political organization with military organization, we have in this chapter to note the ways in which the two differentiate. • § 516. We may most conveniently initiate the inquiry by observing the change which, during social evolution, takes place in the incidence of military obligations ; and by recog- nizing the accompanying separation of the fighting body from the rest of the community. Though there are some tribes in which military service (for aggressive war at any rate) is not compulsory, as the Comanches, Dakotas, Chippewas, whose war-chiefs go about enlisting volunteers for their expeditions ; yet habitually where political subordination is established, every man not privately possessed as a chattel is bound to fight when called on. There have been, and are, some societies of considerably-advanced structures in which this state of things continues. In ancient Peru the common men were all either actually in the army or formed a reserve occupied in labour ; and in modern Siam MILITARY SYSTEMS. 475 the people “ are all soldiers, and owe six months’ service yearly to their prince” But, usually, social progress is accom- panied by a narrowed incidence of military obligation. When the enslavement of captives is followed by the rear- ing of their children as slaves, as well as by the consigning of criminals and debtors to slavery — when, as in some cases, there is joined with the slave-class a serf-class composed of subjugated people not detached from their homes ; the com- munity becomes divided into two parts, on one of which only does military duty fall. Whereas, in previous stages, the division of the whole society had been into men as fighters and women as workers, the division of workers now begins to include men ; and these continue to form an increasing part of the total male population. Though we are told that in Aslrantee (where everyone is in fact owned by the king) the slave-population “ principally constitutes ihe military force,” and that in Rabbah (among the Fulahs) the army is com- posed of slaves liberated “ on consideration of their taking up arms yet, generally, those in bondage are not liable to mili- tary service : the causes being partly distrust of them (as was shown among the Spartans when forced to employ the helots) partly contempt for them as defeated men or the offspring of defeated men, and partly a-desire to devolve on others, labours at once necessary and repugnant. Causes aside, however, the evidence proves that the army at this early stage usually coincides with the body of freemen ; who are also the body of landowners. This, as before shown in § 458, was the case in Egypt, Greece, Rome, and Germany. How natural is this incidence of military obligation, we see in the facts that in ancient Japan and mediaeval India, there were systems of military tenure like that of the middle ages in Europe ; and that a kindred connexion had arisen even in societies like those of Tahiti and Samoa. Extent of estate being a measure of its owner’s ability to bear burdens, there grows up a connexion between the amount of land held and the amount of military aid 4:76 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. to be rendered. Thus in Greece under Solon, those whose properties yielded less than a certain revenue were exempt from duty as soldiers, save in emergencies. In Eome, with a view to better adjustment of the relation between means and requirements, there was a periodic “ revision of the register of landed property, which was at the same time the levy-roll.” Throughout the middle ages this principle was acted upon by proportioning the numbers of warriors demanded to the sizes of the fiefs ; and again, afterwards, by requiring from parishes their respective contingents. A dissociation of military duty from land-ownership begins when land ceases to be the only source of wealth. The growth of a class of free workers, accumulating pro- perty by trade, is followed by the imposing on them, also, of obligations to fight or to provide fighters. Though, as appa- rently in the cases of Greece and Eome, the possessions in virtue of which citizens of this order at first become liable, are lands in which they have invested ; yet, at later stages, they become liable as possessors of other property. Such, at least, is the interpretation we may give to the practice of making industrial populations furnish their specified numbers of warriors ; whether, as during the Eoman conquests, it took the shape of requiring “ rich and populous ” towns to maintain cohorts of infantry or divisions of cavalry, or whether, as with chartered towns in mediaeval days, there was a contract with the king as suzerain, to supply him with stated numbers of men duly armed. Later on, the same cause initiates a further change. As fast as industry increases the relative quantity of trans- ferable property, it becomes more easy to compound for service in war ; either by providing a deputy or by paying to the ruler a sum which enables him to provide one. Origi- nally the penalty for non-fulfilment of military obligation was loss of lands ; then a heavy fine, which, once accepted, it became more frequently the custom to bear; then an habitual compounding for the special services demanded ; MILITARY SYSTEMS. 477 then a levying of dues, such as those called scutages, in place of special compositions. Evidently, industrial growth made this change possible ; both by increasing the population from which the required numbers of substitutes could be obtained, and by producing the needful floating capital. So that whereas in savage and semi-civilized communities of warlike kinds, the incidence of military obligation is such that each free man has to serve personally, and also to pro- vide his own arms and provisions ; the progress from this state in which industry does but occupy the intervals between wars, to a state in which war does but occasionally break the habitual industry, brings an increasing dissociation of mili- tary obligation from free citizenship : military obligation at the same time tending to become a pecuniary burden levied in proportion to property of whatever land. Though where there is a conscription, personal service is theoretically due from each on whom the lot falls, yet the ability to buy a sub- stitute brings the obligation back to a pecuniary one. And though we have an instance in our own day of universal military obligation not thus to be compounded for, we see that it is part of a reversion to the condition of predominant militancy. § 517. An aspect of this change not yet noted, is the simultaneous decrease in the ratio which the fighting part of the community bears to the rest. With the transition from nomadic habits to settled habits, there begins an economic resistance to militant action, which increases as industrial life develops, and diminishes the relative size of the military body. Though in tribes of hunters the men are as ready for war at one time as at another, yet in agricultural societies there obviously exists an impediment to unceasing warfare. In the exceptional case of the Spartans, the carrying on of rural industry was not allowed to prevent daily occupation of all freemen in warlike exercises ; but, speaking generally, the sowing and reaping of crops hinder the gathering together 478 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of freemen for offensive or defensive purposes. Hence in course of time come decreased calls on them. The ancient Suevi divided themselves so as alternately to share war- duties and farm-work : each season the active warriors re- turned to till the land, while their places were “ supplied by the husbandmen of the previous year.” Alfred established in England a kindred alternation between military service and cultivation of the soil. In feudal times, again, the same tendency was shown by restrictions on the duration and amount of the armed aid which a feudal tenant and his re- tainers had to give — now for sixty, for forty, for twenty days, down even to four ; now alone, and again with specified num- bers of followers ; here without limit of distance, and there within the bounds of a county. Doubtless, insubordination often caused resistances to service, and consequent limitations of this kind. But manifestly, absorption of the energies in industry, directly and indirectly antagonized militant action ; with the result that separation of the fighting body from the general body of citizens was accompanied by a decrease in its relative mass. There are two cooperating causes for this decrease of its relative mass, which are of much significance. One is the increasing costliness of the soldier, and of war appliances, which goes along with that social progress made possible by industrial growth. In the savage state each warrior provides his own weapons ; and, on war-excursions, depends on himself for sustenance. At a higher stage this ceases to be the case. When chariots of war, and armour, and siege-implements come to be used, there are presupposed sundry specialized and skilled artizan-classes ; implying a higher ratio of the industrial part of the community to the militant part. And when, later on, there are introduced fire-arms, artillery, ironclads, torpedoes, and the like, we see that there must co-exist a large and highly-organized body of producers and dis- tributors ; alike to furnish the required powers and bear the entailed cost. That is to say, tlie f war-machinery, both living MILITARY SYSTEMS. 479 and dead, cannot be raised in efficiency without lowering the ratio it bears to those sustaining structures which give it efficiency. The other cooperating cause which simultaneously comes into play, is directly due to the compounding and re-compound- ing of societies. The larger nations become, and the greater the distances over which their military actions range, the more expensive do those actions grow. It is with an army as with a limb, the effort put forth is costly in proportion to the remoteness of the acting parts from the base of operations. Though it is true that a body of victorious invaders may raise some, or the whole, of its supplies from the conquered society, yet before it has effected conquest it cannot do this, but is dependent for maintenance on its own society, of which it then forms an integral part: where it ceases to form an integral part and wanders far away, living on spoils, like Tatar hordes in past ages, we are no longer dealing with social organization and its laws, but with social destruction. Limiting ourselves to societies which, permanently localized, preserve their individualities, it is clear that the larger the integrations formed, the greater is the social strain conse- quent on the distances at which fighting has to be done ; and the greater the amount of industrial population required to bear the strain. Doubtless, improved means of communica- tion may all at once alter the ratio ; but this does not conflict with the proposition when qualified by saying — other things equal. In three ways, therefore, does settled life, and the develop- ment of civilization, so increase the economic resistance to militant action, as to cause decrease of the ratio borne by the militant part to the non-militant part. § 518. With those changes in the incidence of military obligation which tend to separate the body of soldiers from the body of workers, and with those other changes which tend to diminish its relative size, there go changes 4S0 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. which tend to differentiate it in a further way. The first of these to be noted is the parting of military headship from political headship. We have seen that the commencement of social organization is the growth of the leading warrior into the civil governor. To illustrative facts before named may be added the fact that an old English ruler, as instance Hengist, was originally called “ Here-toga ” — literally army-leader ; and the office developed into that of king only after settlement in Britain. But with establishment of hereditary succession to political headship, there comes into play an influence which tends to make the chief of the State distinct from the chief of the army. That antagonism between the principle of inheritance and the principle of efficiency, everywhere at work, has from the beginning been conspicuous in this relation, because of the imperative need for efficient generalship. Often, as shown in § 473, there is an endeavour to unite the two qualifications ; as, for example, in ancient Mexico, where the king, before being crowned, had to fill successfully the position of commander- in-chief. But from quite early stages we find that where hereditary succession has been established, and there does not happen to be inheritance of military capacity along with political supremacy, it is common for headship of the warriors to become a separate post filled by election. Says Waitz, “ among the Guaranis the chieftainship generally goes from father to first-born son. The leader in war is, however, elected.” In Ancient Nicaragua “ the war-chief was elected by the warriors to lead them, on account of his ability and bravery in battle ; but the civil or hereditary chief often accompanies the army.” Of the New Zealanders we read that “ hereditary chiefs were generally the leaders,” but not always : others being chosen on account of bravery. And among the Sakarran Dyaks there is a war chief, in addition to the ordinary chief. In the case of the Bedouins the original motive has been defeated in a curious way. “ During a campaign in actual warfare, the authority of the sheikh MILITARY SYSTEMS. 481 of the tribe is completely set aside, and the soldiers are wholly under the command of the agyd. . . . The office of agyd is hereditary in a certain family, from father to son ; and the Arabs submit to the com- mands of an agyd, whom they know to be deficient both in bravery and judgment, rather than yield to the orders of their sheikh during the actual expedition ; for they say that expeditions headed by the sheikh, are always unsuccessful.” It should be added that in some cases we see coming into play further motives. Forster tells ns that in Tahiti the king sometimes resigns the post of commander-in-chief of the fighting force, to one of his chiefs : conscious either of his own unfitness or desirous of avoiding danger. And then in some cases the anxiety of subjects to escape the evils follow- ing loss of the political head, leads to this separation ; as when, among the Hebrews, “ the men of David sware unto him, saying, Thou shalt go no more out with us to battle, that thou quench not the light of Israel ; ” or as when, in France in 923, the king was besought by the ecclesiastics and nobles who surrounded him, to take no part in the im- pending fight. At the same time the ruler, conscious that military com- mand gives great power to its holder, frequently appoints as army-leader his son or other near relative : thus trying to prevent the usurpation so apt to occur (as, to add another instance, it occurred among the Hebrews, whose throne was several times seized by captains of the host). The Iliad shows that it was usual for a Greek king to delegate to his heir the duty of commanding his troops. In Merovingian times kings’ sons frequently led their fathers’ armies ; and of the Carolingians we read that while the king commanded the main levy, “ over other armies his sons were placed, and to them the business of commanding was afterwards increas- ingly transferred.” It was thus in ancient Japan. When the emperor did not himself command his troops, “ this charge was only committed to members of the Imperial house,” and “ the power thus remained with the sovereign.” In ancient Peru there was a like alternative. “ The army was 482 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. put under tlie direction of some experienced chief of the royal blood, or, more frequently, headed by the Ynca in person.” The widening civil functions of the political head, obviously prompt this delegation of military functions. But while the discharge of both becomes increasingly difficult as the nation enlarges ; and while the attempt to discharge both is danger- ous ; there is also danger in doing either by deputy. At the same time that there is risk in giving supreme command of a distant army to a general, there is also risk in going with the army and leaving the government in the hands of a vice- gerent ; and the catastrophes from the one or the other cause, which, spite of precautions, have taken place, show us alike that there is, during social evolution, an inevitable ten- dency to the differentiation of the military headship from the political headship, but that this differentiation can become permanent only under certain conditions. The general fact would appear to be that while militant activity is great, and the whole society has the organiza- tion appropriate to it, the state of equilibrium is one in which the political head continues to be also the militant head ; that in proportion as there grows up, along with industrial life, a civil administration distinguishable from the military administration, the political head tends to become increas- ingly civil in his functions, and to delegate, now occasionally, now generally, his militant functions ; that if there is a return to great militant activity, with consequent reversion to militant structure, there is liable to occur a re-establishment of the primitive type of headship, by usurpation on the part of the successful general — either practical usurpation, where the king is too sacred to be displaced, or complete usurpation where he is not too sacred; but that where, along with decreasing militancy, there goes increasing civil life and ad- ministration, headship of the army becomes permanently differentiated from political headship, and subordinated to it. § 519. While, in the course of social evolution, there has MILITARY SYSTEMS. 483 been going on this separation of the fighting body from the community at large, this diminution in its relative mass, and this establishment of a distinct headship to it, there has been going on an internal organization of it. The fighting body is at first wholly without structure. Among savages a battle is a number of single combats : the chief, if there is one, being but the warrior of most mark, who fights like the rest. Through long stages this disunited action continues. The Iliad tells of little more than the personal en- counters of heroes, which were doubtless multiplied in detail by their unmentioned followers ; and after the decay of that higher military organization which accompanied Greek and Roman civilization, this chaotic kind of fighting recurred throughout mediaeval Europe. During the early feudal period everything turned on the prowess of individuals. War, says Gautier, consisted of “ bloody duels ;” and even much later the idea of personal action dominated over that of com- bined action. But along with political progress, the subjec- tion of individuals to their chief is increasingly shown by fulfilling his commands in battle. Action in the field becomes in a higher degree concerted, by the absorption of their wills in his will. A like change presently shows itself on a larger scale. While the members of each component group have their actions more and more combined, the groups themselves, of which an army is composed, pass from disunited action to united action. When small societies are compounded into a larger one, their joint body of warriors at first consists of the tribal clusters and family-clusters assembled together, but retaining their respective individualities. The head of each Hottentot kraal, “ has the command, under the chief of his nation, of the troops furnished out by his kraal.” Similarly, the Malagasy “ kept their own respective clans, and every clan had its own leader.” Among the Chibchas, “ each cazique and tribe came with different signs on their tents, fitted out with the mantles by which they distinguished themselves from each other.” A 12 484 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. kindred arrangement existed in early Eoman times : the city- army was “ distributed into tribes, curiae, and families.” It was so, too, with the Germanic peoples, who, in the field, “ arranged themselves, when not otherwise tied, in families and affinities or, as is said by Kemble of our ancestors in old English times, “ each kindred was drawn up under an officer of its own lineage and appointment, and the several members of the family served together/' This organization, or lack of organization, continued throughout the feudal period. In France, in the 14th century, the army was a “ horde of independent chiefs, each with his own following, each doing his own will and, according to Froissart, the different groups “ were so ill-informed ” that they did not always know of a discomfiture of the main body. Besides that increased subordination of local heads to the general head which accompanies political integration, and which must of course precede a more centralized and com- bined mode of military action, two special causes may be recognized as preparing the way for it. One of these is unlikeness of kinds in the arms used. Sometimes the cooperating tribes, having habituated them- selves to different weapons, come to battle already marked off from one another. In such cases the divisions by weapons correspond with the tribal divisions ; as seems to have been to some extent the case with the Hebrews, among whom the men of Benjamin, of Gad, and of Judah, were partially thus distinguished. But, usually, the unlikenesses of arms consequent on unlikenesses of rank, initiate these milit- ary divisions which tend to traverse the divisions arising from tribal organization. The army of the ancient Egyptians included bodies of charioteers, of cavalry, and of foot ; and the respective accoutrements of the men forming these bodies, differing in their costliness, implied differences of social posi- tion. The like may be said of the Assyrians. Similarly, the Iliad shows us among the early Greeks a state in which the MILITARY SYSTEMS. 485 contrasts in weapons due to contrasts in wealth, had not yet resulted in differently-armed bodies, such as are formed at later stages with decreasing regard for tribal or local divi- sions. And it was so in Western Europe during times when each feudal superior led his own knights, and his followers of inferior grades and weapons. Though within each group there were men differing alike in their rank and in their arms, yet what we may call the vertical divisions between groups were not traversed by those horizontal divisions throughout the whole army, which unite all who are similarly armed. This wider segregation it is, however, which we observe taking place with the advance of military organization. The supre- macy acquired by the Spartans was largely due to the fact that Lykurgus “ established military divisions quite distinct from the civil divisions, whereas in the other states of Greece, until a period much later . . . the two were confounded — the hoplites or horsemen of the same tribe or ward being marshalled together on the field of battle.” With the pro- gress of the Roman arms there occurred kindred changes. The divisions came to be related less to rank as dependent on tribal organization, and more to social position as deter- mined by property ; so that the kinds of arms to be borne and the services to be rendered, were regulated by the sizes of estates, with the result of “ merging all distinctions of a gentile and local nature in the one common levy of the com- munity.” In the field, divisions so established stood thus : — 4< The four first ranks of each phalanx were formed of the full-armed hoplites of the first class, the holders of an entire hide [?] ; in the fifth and sixth were placed the less completely equipped farmers of the second and third class ; the two last classes were annexed as rear ranks to the phalanx. And though political distinctions of clan-origin were not thus directly disregarded in the cavalry, yet they were in- directly interfered with by the addition of a larger troop of non-burgess cavalry. That a system of divisions which tends to obliterate those of rank and locality, has been reproduced 486 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. during the re-development of military organization in modern times, is a familiar fact. A concomitant cause of this change has all along been that interfusion of the gentile and tribal groups entailed by aggregation of large numbers. As before pointed out, the Kleisthenian re-organization in Attica, and the Servian re- organization in Rome, were largely determined by the im- practicability of maintaining the correspondence between tribal divisions and military obligations ; and a redistribution of military obligations naturally proceeded on a numerical basis. By various peoples, we find this step in organization taken for civil purposes or military purposes, or both. To cases named in § 512, may be added that of the Hebrews, who were grouped into tens, fifties, hundreds and thousands. Even the barbarous Araucanians divided themselves into regiments of a thousand, sub-divided into companies of a hundred. Evidently numerical grouping conspires with classing by arms to obliterate the primitive divisions. This transition from the state of incoherent clusters, each having its own rude organization, to the state of a coherent w T hole, held together by an elaborate organization running throughout it, of course implies a concomitant progress in the centralization of command. As the primitive horde becomes more efficient for war in proportion as its members grow obedient to the orders of its chief ; so, the army formed of aggregated hordes becomes more efficient in proportion as the chiefs of the hordes fall under the power of one supreme chief. And the above-described transition from aggregated tribal and local groups to an army formed of regular divisions and sub-divisions, goes along with the development of grades of commanders, successively subordinated one to another. A controlling system of this kind is developed by the uncivilized, where considerable military efficiency has been reached ; as at present among the Araucanians, the Zulus, the Uganda people, who have severally three grades of officers ; as in the past among the ancient Peruvians and MILITARY SYSTEMS. 487 ancient Mexicans, who had respectively several grades ; and as also among the ancient Hebrews. § 520. One further general change has to be noticed — the change from a state in which the army now assembles and now disperses, as required, to a state in which it becomes permanently established. While, as among savages, the male adults are all warriors, the fighting body, existing in its combined form only during war, becomes during peace a dispersed body carrying on in parties or separately, hunting and other occupations; and similarly, as we have seen, during early stages of settled life the armed freemen, owning land jointly or separately, all having to serve as soldiers when called on, return to their farming when war is over : there is no standing army. But though after the compounding of small societies into larger ones by war, and the rise of a central power, a kindred system long continues, there come the beginnings of another system. Of course, irrespective of form of goverment, frequent wars generate permanent military forces; as they did in early times among the Spartans ; as later among the Athenians ; and as among the Romans, when extension of territory brought frequent needs for repressing rebellions. Recognizing these cases, we may pass to the more usual cases, in which a permanent military force originates from the body of armed attendants surrounding the ruler. Early stages show us this nucleus. In Tahiti the king or chief had warriors among his attendants ; and the king of Ashantee has a body- guard clad in skins of wild beasts — leopards, panthers, &c. As was pointed out when tracing the process of political differentiation, there tend everywhere to gather round a pre- dominant chieftain, refugees and others who exchange armed service for support and protection ; and so enable the pre- dominant chieftain to become more predominant. Hence the comites attached to the princeps in the early German com- munity, the huscarlas or housecarls surrounding old English 488 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. kings, and the antrustions of the Merovingian rulers. These armed followers displayed in little, the characters of a stand- ing army ; not simply as being permanently united, but also as being severally bound to their prince or lord by relations of personal fealty, and as being subject to internal govern- ment under a code of martial law, apart from the govern- ment of the freemen ; as was especially shown in the large assemblage of them, amounting to 6,000, which was formed by Cnut. In this last case we see how small body-guards, growing as the conquering chief or king draws to his standard adven- turers, fugitive criminals, men who have fled from injustice, &c., pass unobtrusively into troops of soldiers who fight for pay. The employment of mercenaries goes back to the earliest times — being traceable in the records of the Egyptains at all periods ; and it continues to re-appear under certain conditions : a primary condition being that the ruler shall have acquired a considerable revenue. Whether of home origin or foreign origin, these large bodies of professional soldiers can be maintained only by large pecuniary means ; and, ordinarily, possession of these means goes along with such power as enables the king to exact dues and fines. In early stages the members of the fighting body, when sum- moned for service, have severally to provide themselves not only with their appropriate arms, but also with the needful supplies of all kinds : there being, while political organiza- tion is little developed, neither the resources nor the adminis- trative machinery required for another system. But the economic resistance to militant action, which, as we have seen, increases as agricultural life spreads, leading to occa- sional non-attendance, to confiscations, to heavy fines in place of confiscations, then to fixed money-payments in place of personal services, results in the growth of a revenue which serves to pay professional soldiers in place of the vassals who have compounded. And it then becomes possible, instead of hiring many such substitutes for short times, to hire a smaller MILITARY SYSTEMS. 489 number continuously — so adding to the original nucleus of a permanent armed force. Every further increase of royal power, increasing the ability to raise money, furthers this differentiation. As Ranke remarks of France, “ standing armies, imposts, and loans, all originated together.” Of course the primitive military obligation falling on all freemen, long continues to be shown in modified ways. Among ourselves, for instance, there were the various laws under which men were bound, according to their incomes, to have in readiness specified supplies of horses, weapons, and accoutrements, for themselves and others when demanded. Afterwards came the militia-laws, under which there fell on men in proportion to their means, the obligations to provide duly armed horse-soldiers or foot-soldiers, per- sonally or by substitute, to be called out for exercise at specified intervals for specified numbers of days, and to be provided with subsistence. There may be instanced, again, such laws as those under which in France, in the 15th cen- tury, a corps of horsemen was formed by requiring all the parishes to furnish one each. And there are the various more modern forms of conscription, used, now to raise temporary forces, and now to maintain a permanent army. Everywhere, indeed, freemen remain potential soldiers when not actual soldiers. § 521. Setting out with that undifferentiated state of the body politic in which the army is co-extensive with the adult male population, we thus observe several ways in which there goes on the evolution which makes it a specialized part. There is the restriction in relative mass, which, first seen in the growth of a slave-population, engaged in work instead of war, becomes more decided as a settled agricultural life occupies freemen, and increases the obstacles to military service. There is, again, the restriction caused by that growing costliness of the individual soldier accompanying 490 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the development of arms, accoutrements, and ancillary ap- pliances of warfare. And there is the yet additional restric- tion caused by the intenser strain which military action puts on the resources of a nation, in proportion as it is carried on at a greater distance. With separation of the fighting body from the body-politic at large, there very generally goes acquirement of a sepa- rate head. Active militancy ever tends to maintain union of civil rule with military rule, and often causes re-union of them where they have become separate; but with the primary differentiation of civil from military structures, is commonly associated a tendency to the rise of distinct con- trolling centres for them. This tendency, often defeated by usurpation where wars are frequent, takes effect under oppo- site conditions ; and then produces a military head subordi- nate to the civil head. While the whole society is being developed by differen- tiation of the army from the rest, there goes on a develop- ment within the army itself. As in the primitive horde the progress is from the uncombined fighting of individuals to combined fighting under direction of a chief ; so, on a larger scale, when small societies are united into great ones, the progress is from the independent fighting of tribal and local groups, to fighting under direction of a general commander. And to effect a centralized control, there arises a graduated system of officers, replacing the set of primitive heads of groups, and a system of divisions which, traversing the original divisions of groups, establish regularly-organized masses having different functions. With developed structure of the fighting body comes per- manence of it. While, as in early times, men are gathered together for small wars and then again dispersed, efficient organization of them is impracticable. It becomes practicable only among men who are constantly kept together by wars or preparations for wars ; and bodies of such men growing up, replace the temporarily-summoned bodies. MILITARY SYSTEMS. 491 Lastly, we must not omit to note that while the army becomes otherwise distinguished, it becomes distinguished by retaining and elaborating the system of status ; though in the rest of the community, as it advances, the system of contract is spreading and growing definite. Compulsory cooperation continues to be the principle of the military part, however widely the principle of voluntary cooperation comes into play throughout the civil part. CHAPTER XIII. JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. § 522. That we may be prepared for recognizing the primitive identity of military institutions with institutions for administering justice, let us observe how close is the kin- ship between the modes of dealing with external aggression and internal aggression, respectively. We have the facts, already more than once emphasized, that at first the responsibilities of communities to one another are paralleled by the responsibilities to one another of family- groups within each community ; and that the kindred claims are enforced in kindred ways. Various savage tribes show us that, originally, external war has to effect an equalization of injuries, either directly in kind or indirectly by compen- sations. Among the Chinooks, “ has the one party a larger number of dead than the other, indemnification must be made by the latter, or the war is continued and among the Arabs “ when peace is to be made, both parties count up their dead, and the usual blood-money is paid for excess on either side.” By which instances we are shown that in the wars between tribes, as in the family-feuds of early times, a death must be balanced by a death, or else must be com- pounded for ; as it once was in Germany and in England, by specified numbers of sheep and cattle, or by money. Not only are the wars which societies carry on to effect the righting of alleged wrongs, thus paralleled by family-feuds in the respect that for retaliation in kind there may be substi- JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 493 tuted a penalty adjudged by usage or authority; but they are paralleled by feuds between individuals in the like respect. From the first stage in which each man avenges himself by force on a transgressing neighbour, as the whole community does on a transgressing community, the transition is to a stage in which he has the alternative of demanding justice at the hands of the ruler. We see this beginning in such places as the Sandwich Islands, where an injured person who is too weak to retaliate, appeals to the king or principal chief ; and in quite advanced stages, option between the two methods of obtaining redress survives. The feeling shown down to the 13th century by Italian nobles, who “ regarded it as dis- graceful to submit to laws rather than do themselves justice by force of arms,” is traceable throughout the history of Europe in the slow yielding of private rectification of wrongs to public arbitration. “A capitulary of Charles the Bald bids them [the freemen] go to court armed as for war, for they might have to fight for their jurisdiction and our own history furnishes an interesting example in the early form of an action for recovering land : the “ grand assize ” which tried the cause, originally consisted of knights armed with swords. Again we have evidence in such facts as that in the 12 th century in France, legal decisions were so little regarded that trials often issued in duels. Further proof is yielded by such facts as that judicial duels (which were the authorized substitutes for private wars between families) continued in France down to the close of the 14th century; that in England, in 17G8, a legislative proposal to abolish trial by battle, was so strongly opposed that the measure was dropped ; and that the option of such trial was not disallowed till 1819. We may observe, also, that this self-protection gradually gives place to protection by the State, only under stress of public needs — especially need fqr military efficiency. Edicts of Charlemagne and of Charles the Bald, seeking to stop the disorders consequent on private wars, by insisting on appeals to the ordained authorities, and threatening punishment of 494 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. those who disobeyed, sufficiently imply the motive ; and this motive was definitely shown in the feudal period in France, by an ordinance of 1296, which “ prohibits private wars and judicial duels so long as the king is engaged in war.” Once more the militant nature of legal protection is seen in the fact that, as at first, so now, it is a replacing of indi- vidual armed force by the armed force of the State — always in reserve if not exercised. “ The sword of justice” is a phrase sufficiently indicating the truth that action against the public enemy and action against the private enemy are in the last resort the same. Thus recognizing the original identity of the functions, we shall be prepared for recognizing the original identity of the structures by which they are carried on. § 523. For that primitive gathering of armed men which, as we have seen, is at once the council of war and the political assembly, is at the same time the judicial body. Of existing savages the Hottentots show this. The court of justice “consists of the captain and all the men of the kraal. . . . J Tis held in the open fields, the men squatting in a circle. . . . All matters are determined by a majority.” . . . If the prisoner is “ convicted, and the court adjudges him worthy of death, sentence is executed upon the spot.” The captain is chief executioner, striking the first blow ; and is followed up by the others. The records of various historic peoples yield evidence of kindred meaning. Taking first the Greeks in Homeric days, we read that “ sometimes the king separately, sometimes the kings or chiefs or Gerontes, in the plural number, are named as deciding disputes and awarding satisfaction to complainants; always however in public, in the midst of the assembled agora,” in which the popular sympathies were expressed: the meeting thus described, being the same with that in which questions of war and peace were debated. That in its early form the Eoman gathering of “ spearmen,” asked by the king to JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 495 say “ yes ” or “ no ” to a proposed military expedition or to some State-measure, also expressed its opinion concerning criminal charges publicly judged, is implied by the fact that “ the king could not grant a pardon, for that privilege was vested in the community alone.” Describing the gatherings of the primitive Germans, Tacitus says : — “ The multitude sits armed in such order as it thinks good ... It is lawful also in the Assembly to bring matters for trial and to bring charges of capital crimes ... In the same assembly chiefs are chosen to administer justice throughout the districts and villages. Each chief in so doing has a hundred companions of the commons assigned to him, to strengthen at once his judg- ment and his dignity.” A kindred arrangement is ascribed by Lelevel to the Poles in early times, and to the Slavs at large. Among the Danes, too, “ in all secular affairs, justice was administered by the popular tribunal of the Lands- Ting for each province, and by the Herreds-Ting for the smaller dis- tricts or sub-divisions.” Concerning the Irish in past times. Prof. Leslie quotes Spenser to the effect that it was their usage “ to make great assemblies together upon a rath or hill, there to v parley about matters and wrongs between township and township, or one private person and another.” And then there comes the illustration furnished by old English times. The local moots of various kinds had judicial functions; and the witenagemot sometimes acted as a high court of justice. Interesting evidence that the original military assembly was at the same time the original judicial assembly, is sup- plied by the early practice of punishing freemen for non- attendance. Discharge of military obligation being imperative, the fining of those who did not come to the armed gathering naturally followed; and fining for absence having become the usage, survived when, as for judicial purposes, the need for the presence of all was not imperative. Thence the interpretation of the fact that non-attendance at the hundred- court was thus punishable. In this connexion it may be added that, in some cases 496 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. where the primitive form continued, there was manifested an incipient differentiation between the military assembly and the judicial assembly. In the Carolingian period, judicial assemblies began to be held under cover ; and freemen were forbidden to bring their arms. As was pointed out in § 491, among the Scandinavians no one was allowed to come armed when the meeting was for judicial purposes. And since we also read that in Iceland it was disreputable (not punishable) for a freeman to be absent from the annual gathering, the implication is that the imperativeness of attendance dimi- nished with the growing predominance of civil functions. § 524, The judicial body being at first identical with the politico-military body, has necessarily the same triune structure ; and we have now to observe the different forms it assumes according to the respective developments of its three components. We may expect to find kinship between these forms and the concomitant political forms. Where, with development of militant organization, the power of the king has become greatly predominant over that of the chiefs and over that of the people, his supremacy is shown by his judicial absoluteness, as well as by his absolute- ness in political and military affairs. Such shares as the elders and the multitude originally had in trying causes, almost or quite disappear. But though in these cases the authority of the king as judge, is unqualified by that of his head men and his other subjects, there habitually survive traces of the primitive arrangement. For habitually his decisions are given in public and in the open air. Petitioners for justice bring their cases before him when he makes his appearance out of doors, surrounded by his attendants and by a crowd of spectators ; as we have seen in § 372 that they do down to the present day in Kashmere. By the Hebrew rulers, judicial sittings were held “in the gates” — the usual meeting-places of Eastern peoples. Among the earty Romans the king administered justice “in the place of JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 497 public assembly, sitting on a ‘ chariot-seat/ ” Mr. Gomme’s Primitive Folk-Moots contains sundry illustrations showing that among the Germans in old times, the Konigs-stuhl, or king’s judgment-seat, was on the green sward ; that in other cases the stone steps at the town-gates constituted the seat before which causes were heard by him ; and that again, in early French usage, trials often took place under trees. According to Joinville this practice long continued in France. “ Many a time did it happen that, in summer, he [Lewis IX] would go and sit in the forest of Vincennes after mass, and would rest against an oak, and make us sit round him ... he asked them with his own mouth, ‘ Is there any one who has a suit V . . . I have seen him some- times in summer come to hear his people's suits in the garden of Paris.” And something similar occurred in Scotland under David I. All which customs among various peoples, imply survival of the primitive judicial assembly, changed only by concentra- tion in its head of power originally shared by the leading men and the undistinguished mass. Where the second component of the triune political structure becomes supreme, this in its turn monopolizes judicial functions. Among the Spartans the oligarchic senate, and in a measure the smaller and chance-selected oligarchy constituted by the ephors, joined judicial functions with their political functions. Similarly in Athens under the aristocratic rule of the Eupatridse, we find the Areopagus formed of its members, discharging, either itself or through its nine chosen Archons, the duties of deciding causes and executing decisions. In later days, again, we have the case of the Venetian council of ten. And then, certain incidents of the middle ages instructively show us one of the processes by which judicial power, as well as political power, passes from the hands of the freemen at large into the hands of a smaller and wealthier class. In the Carolingian period, besides the bi-annual meetings of the hundred- court, it was — “ convoked at the Grafs will and pleasure, to try particular cases . . . in the one case, as in the other, non-attendance was punished ... it was found that the Grafs used their right to summon these extraordinary 498 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Courts in excess, with a view, by repeated fines and amercements, to ruin the small freeholders, and thus to get their abodes into their own hands. Charlemagne introduced a radical law-reform . . . the great body of the freemen were released from attendance at the Gebotene Dinge , at which, from thenceforth, justice was to be administered under the presidency, ex officio , of the Centenar , by . . . permanent jurymen . . . chosen de melioribus — i.e. y from the more well-to-do freemen.” But iii other cases, and especially where concentration in a town renders performance of judicial functions less burdensome, we see that along with retention or acquire- ment of predominant power by the third element in the triune political structure, there goes exercise of judicial func- tions by it. The case of Athens, after the replacing of oli- garchic rule by democratic rule, is, of course, the most familiar example of this. The Kleisthenian revolution made the annually-appointed magistrates personally responsible to the people j udicially assembled ; and when, under Perildes, there were established the dikasteries, or courts of paid jurors chosen by lot, the administration of justice was transferred almost wholly to the body of freemen, divided for convenience into committees. Among the Frieslanders, who in early times were enabled by the nature of their habitat to maintain a free form of political organization, there continued the popu- lar judicial assembly: — “ When the commons were summoned for any particular purpose, the assembly took the name of the Bodthing. The bodthing was called for the purpose of passing judgment in cases of urgent necessity / 7 And M. de Laveleye, describing the Teutonic mark as still existing in Holland, “ especially in Drenthe / 7 a tract “ surrounded on all sides by a marsh and bog 77 (again illustrating the physical conditions favourable to maintenance of primitive free institutions), goes on to say of the inhabitants as periodically assembled : — “ They appeared in arms ; and no one could absent himself, under pain of a fine. This assembly directed all the details as to the enjoyment of the common property ; appointed the works to be executed ; imposed pecuniary penalties for the violation of rules, and nominated the officers charged with the executive power.” The likeness between the judicial form and the political JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 499 form is further shown where the government is neither despotic nor oligarchic, nor democratic, but mixed. For in our own case we see a system of administering justice which, like the political system, unites authority that is in a considerable degree irresponsible, with popular authority. In old English times a certain power of making and enforcing local or “ bye- laws ” was possessed by the township ; and in more important and definite ways the hundred-moot and the shire-moot dis- charged judicial and executive functions: their respective officers being at the same time elected. But the subsequent growth of feudal institutions, followed by the development of royal power, was accompanied by diminution of the popular share in judicial business, and an increasing assignment of it to members of the ruling classes and to agents of the crown. And at present we see that the system, as including the power of juries (which arose by selection of representative men, though not in the interest of the people), is in part popular ; that in the summary jurisdiction of unpaid magis- trates who, though centrally appointed, mostly belong to the wealthy classes, and especially the landowners, it is in part aristocratic; that in the regal commissioning of judges it continues monarchic ; and that yet, as the selection of magis- trates and judges is practically in the hands of a ministry executing, on the average, the public will, royal power and class-power in the administration of justice are exercised under popular control. § 525. A truth above implied and now to be definitely observed, is that along with the consolidation of small societies into large ones effected by war, there necessarily goes an increasing discharge of judicial functions by deputy. As the primitive king is very generally himself both commander-in-chief and high priest, it is not unnatural that his delegated judicial functions should be fulfilled both by priests and soldiers. Moreover, since the consultative body, where it becomes established and separated from the multi- 500 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. tude, habitually includes members of both these classes, such judicial powers as it exercises cannot at the outset be mono- polized by members of either. And this participation is further seen to arise naturally on remembering how, as before shown, priests have in so many societies united military functions with clerical functions ; and how, in other cases, becoming local rulers, having the same tenures and obliga- tions with purely military local rulers, they acquire, in com- mon with them, local powers of judgment and execution ; as did mediaeval prelates. Whether the ecclesiastical class or the class of warrior-chiefs acquires judicial predominance, probably depends mainly on the proportion between men’s fealty to the successful soldier, and their awe of the priest as a recipient of divine communications. Among the Zulus, who, with an undeveloped mythology, have no great deities and resulting organized priesthood, the king “ shares his power with two soldiers of his choice. These two form the supreme judges of the country.” Similarly with the Eggarahs (Inland Negroes), whose fetisli-men do not form an influential order, the first and second judges are “also commanders of the forces in time of war.” Passing to historic peoples, we have in Attica, in Solon’s time, the nine archons, who, while possessing a certain sacredness as belonging to the Eupatridae, united judicial with military functions — more especially the polemarch. In ancient Rome, that kindred union of the two functions in the consuls, who called themselves indiscriminately, prwtores or judices, naturally resulted from their inheritance of both functions from the king they replaced ; but beyond this there is the fact that though the pontiffs had previously been judges in secular matters as well as in sacred matters, yet, after the esta- blishment of the republic, the several orders of magistrates were selected from the non-clerical patricians, — the original soldier- class. And then throughout the middle ages in Europe, we have the local military chiefs, whether holding positions like those of old English thanes or like those of feudal barons, acting JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 501 as judges in tlieir respective localities. Perhaps the clearest illustration is that furnished by Japan, where a long-con- tinued and highly-developed military regime , has been throughout associated with the monopoly of judicial func- tions by the military class : the apparent reason being that in presence of the god-descended Mikado, supreme in heaven as on earth, the indigenous Shinto religion never developed a divine ruler whose priests acquired, as his agents, an autho- rity competing with terrestrial authority. But mostly there is extensive delegation of judicial powers to the sacerdotal class, in early stages. We find it among existing uncivilized peoples, as the Kalmucks, whose priests, besides playing a predominant part in the greatest judicial council, exercise local jurisdiction ; in the court of each sub- ordinate chief, one of the high priests is head judge. Of extinct uncivilized or semi-civilized peoples, may be named the Indians of Yucatan, by whom priests were appointed as judges in certain cases — judges who took part in the execu- tion of their own sentences. Originally, if not afterwards, the giving of legal decisions was a priestly function in ancient Egypt ; and that the priests were supreme judges among the Hebrews is a familiar fact : the Deuteronomic law con- demning to death any one who disregarded their verdicts. In that general assembly of the ancient Germans which, as we have seen, exercised judicial powers, the priests were prominent ; and, according to Tacitus, in war “ none but the priests are permitted to judge offenders, to inflict bonds or stripes; so that chastisement appears not as an act of military discipline, but as the instigation of the god whom they sup- pose present with warriors.” In ancient Britain, too, accord- ing to Caesar, the druids alone had authority to decide in both civil and criminal cases, and executed their own sentences : the penalty for disobedience to them being excommunication. Grimm tells us that the like held among the Scandinavians. “ In their judicial character the priests seem to have exercised a good deal of control over the people ... In Iceland, even 502 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. under Christianity, the judges retained the name and several of the functions of heathen goftar ” And then we have the illustration furnished by that rise of ecclesiastics to the posi- tions of judges throughout mediaeval Europe, which accom- panied belief in their divine authority. When, as during the Merovingian period and after, “ the fear of hell, the desire of winning heaven,” and other motives, prompted donations and bequests to the Church, till a large part of the landed pro- perty fell into its hands — when there came increasing numbers of clerical aud semi-clerical dependents of the Church, over whom bishops exercised judgment and disci- pline — when ecclesiastical influence so extended itself that, wdiile priests became exempt from the control of laymen, lay authorities became subject to priests ; there was established a judicial power of this divinely-commissioned class to which even kings succumbed. So was it in England too. Before the Conquest, bishops had become the assessors of ealdormen in the scire-gemot, and gave judgments on various civil matters. With that recrudescence of military organization which fol- lowed the Conquest, came a limitation of their jurisdiction to spiritual offences and causes concerning clerics. But in subsequent periods ecclesiastical tribunals, bringing under canon law numerous ordinary transgressions, usurped more and more the duties of secular judges: their excommuni- cations being enforced by the temporal magistrates. More- over, since prelates as feudal nobles were judges in their respective domains ; and since many major and minor judicial offices in the central government were filled by prelates; it resulted that the administration of justice was largely, if not mainly, in the hands of priests. This sharing of delegated judicial functions between the military class and the priestly class, with predominance here of the one and there of the other, naturally continued while there was no other class having wealth and influence. But with the increase of towns and the multiplication of traders, who accumulated riches and acquired education, previously JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 503 possessed only by ecclesiastics, judicial functions fell more and more into their hands. Sundry causes conspired to pro- duce this transfer. One was lack of culture among the nobles, and their decreasing ability to administer laws, ever increasing in number and in complexity. Another was the political unfitness of ecclesiastics, who grew distasteful to rulers in proportion as they pushed further the powers and privileges which their supposed divine commission gave them. Details need not detain us. The only general fact needing to be emphasized, is that this transfer ended in a differen- tiation of structures. For whereas in earlier stages, judicial functions were discharged by men who were at the same time either soldiers or priests, they came now to be discharged by men exclusively devoted to them. § 526. Simultaneously, the evolution of judicial systems is displayed in several other ways. One of them is the ad- dition of judicial agents who are locomotive to the pre-exist- ing stationary judicial agents. During the early stages in which the ruler administers justice in person, he does this now in one place and now in another ; according as affairs, military or judicial, carry him to this or that place in his kingdom. Societies of various types in various times yield evidence. Historians of ancient Peru tell us that “ the Ynca gave sentence according to the crime, for he alone was judge wheresoever he resided, and all persons wronged had recourse to him. ,, Of the German emperor in the 12th century we read that “ not only did he receive appeals, but his presence in any duchy or county suspended the functions of the local judges.” France in the 15th century supplies an instance. King Charles “ spent two or three years in travelling up and down the kingdom . . . maintaining justice to the satisfaction of his subjects/’ In Scotland something similar was done by David I., who “ settled marches, forest rights, and rights of pasture : ” himself making the marks which recorded his 504 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. decisions, or seeing them made. In England, “ Edgar and Canute had themselves made judicial circuits and there is good evidence of such judicial travels in England up to the time of the Great Charter. Sir Henry Maine has quoted documents showing that King John, in common with earlier kings, moved about the country with great activity, and held his court wherever he might happen to be. Of course with the progress of political integration and consequent growing power of the central ruler, there come more numerous cases in which appeal is made to him to rectify the wrongs committed by local rulers ; and as State-business at large augments and complicates, his inability to do this personally leads to doing it by deputy. In France, in Char- lemagne’s time, there were the “ Missi Regii, who held assizes from place to place f and then, not forgetting that during a subsequent period the chief heralds in royal state, as the king’s representatives, made circuits to judge and punish transgressing nobles, we may pass to the fact that in the later feudal period, when the business of the king’s court became too great, commissioners were sent into the provinces to judge particular cases in the king’s name : a method which does not appear to have been there developed further. But in England, in Henry II.’s time, kindred causes prompted kindred steps which initiated a permanent system. Instead of listening to the increasing number of appeals made to his court, personally or through his lieutenant the justiciar, the king commissioned his constable, chancellor, and co-justiciar to hear pleas in the different counties. Later, there came a larger number of these members of the central judicial court who made these judicial journeys : part of them being clerical and part military. And hence eventually arose the esta- blished circuits of judges who, like their prototypes, had to represent the king and exercise supreme authority. It should be added that here again we meet with proofs that in the evolution of arrangements conducing to the main- tenance of individual rights, the obligations are primary and JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 505 the claims derived. For the business of these travelling judges, like the business of the king’s court by which they were commissioned, was primarily fiscal and secondarily judicial. They were members of a central body that was at once Exchequer and Curia Regis , in which financial functions at first predominated ; and they were sent into the provinces largely, if not primarily, for purposes of assessment : as in- stance the statement that in 1168, “ the four Exchequer officers who assessed the aid pur fille marier , acted not only as taxers but as judges.” In which facts we see harmony with those before given, showing that support of the ruling agency precedes obtainment of protection from it. § 527. With that development of a central government which accompanies consolidation of small societies into a large one, and with the consequent increase of its business, entailing delegation of functions, there goes, in the judicial organiza- tion as in the other organizations, a progressive differen- tiation. The evidence of this is extremely involved; both for the reason that in most cases indigenous judicial agencies have been subordinated but not destroyed by those which conquest has originated, and for the reason that kinds of power, as well as degrees of power, have become distinguished. A few leading traits only of the process can here be indicated. The most marked differentiation, already partially implied, is that between the lay, the ecclesiastical, and the military tribunals. From those early stages in which the popular assembly, with its elders and chief, condemned military de- faulters, decided on ecclesiastical questions, and gave judg- ments about offences, there has gone on a divergence which, accompanied by disputes and struggles concerning jurisdiction, has parted ecclesiastical courts and courts martial from the courts administering justice in ordinary civil and criminal cases. Just recognizing these cardinal specializations, we may limit our attention to the further specializations which have taken place within the last of the three structures. 506 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Originally the ruler, with or without the assent of the assembled people, not only decides : he executes his deci- sions, or sees them executed. For example, in Dahomey the king stands by, and if the deputed officer does not please him, takes the sword out of his hand and shows him how to cut off a head. An account of death-punishment among the Bedouins ends with the words— “ the executioner being the sheikh himself.” Our own early history affords traces of personal executive action by the king ; for there came a time when he was interdicted from arresting any one himself, and had thereafter to do it in all cases by deputy. And this interprets for us the familiar truth that, through his deputies the sheriffs, who are bound to act personally if they cannot themselves find deputies, the monarch continues to be theoretically the agent who carries the law into execution : a truth further implied by the fact that execution in criminal cases, nominally authorized by him though actually by his minister, is arrested if his assent is withheld by his minister. And these facts imply that a final power of judgment remains with the monarch, not- withstanding delegation of his judicial functions. How this happens we shall see on tracing the differentiation. Naturally, when a ruler employs assistants to hear com- plaints and redress grievances, he does not give them abso- lute authority ; but reserves the power of revising their decisions. We see this even in such rude societies as that of the Sandwich Islands, where one who is dissatisfied with the decision of his chief may appeal to the governor, and from the governor to the king; or as in ancient Mexico, where “none of the judges were allowed to condemn to death without communicating with the king, who had to pass the sentence.” And the principle holds where the political head- ship is compound instead of simple. “ When the hegemony of Athens became, in fact, more and more a dominion, the civic body of Attica claimed supreme judicial authority over all the allies. The federal towns only retained their lower JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 507 courts.” Obviously by such changes are produced unlikenesses of degree and differences of kind in the capacities of judicial agencies. As political subordination spreads, the local assemblies which originally judged and executed in cases of all kinds, lose part of their functions; now by restriction in range of jurisdiction, now by subjection of their decisions to supervision, now by denial of executive power. To trace up the process from early stages, as for instance from the stage in which the old English tything-moot discharged administrative, judicial, and executive functions, or from the stage in which the courts of feudal nobles did the like, is here alike impracticable and unnecessary. Reference to such remnants of power as vestries and manorial courts possess, will sufficiently indicate the character of the change. But along with degradation of the small and local judicial agencies, goes development of the great and central ones; and about this something must be said. Returning to the time when the king with his servants and chief men, surrounded by the people, administers justice in the open air, and passing to the time when his court, held more frequently under cover and consequently with less of the popular element, still consists of king as president and his household officers with other appointed magnates as coun- sellors (who in fact constitute a small and permanent part of that general consultative body occasionally summoned) ; we have to note two causes which cooperate to produce a division of these remaining parts of the original triune body — one cause being the needs of subjects, and the other the desire of the king. So long as the king’s court is held wherever he happens to be, there is an extreme hindrance to the hearing of suits, and much entailed loss of money and time to suitors. To remedy this evil came, in our own case, the provision included in the Great Charter that the common pleas should no longer follow the king’s court, but be held in some certain place. This place was fixed in the palace of Westminster. And then as Blackstone points out — 13 508 POLITICAL INSTITUTION'S. “This precedent was soon after copied by King Philip the Fair in France, who about the year 1302, fixed the parliament of Paris to abide constantly in that metropolis ; which before used to follow the person of the king wherever he went . . . And thus also, in 1495, the Emperor Maximilian I. fixed the imperial chamber, which before always travelled with the court and household, to be constantly at Worms.” As a sequence of these changes it of course happens that suits of a certain kind come habitually to be decided with- out the king’s presence : there results a permanent transfer of part of his judicial power. Again, press of business or love of ease prompts the king himself to hand over such legal matters as are of little interest to him. Thus in France, while we read that Charles V., when regent, sat in his council to administer justice twice a week, and Charles YI. once, we also read that in 1370 the king declared he would no longer try the smaller causes personally. Once initiated and growing into a usage, this judging by commission, be- coming more frequent as affairs multiply, is presently other- wise furthered : there arises the doctrine that the king ought not, at any rate in certain cases, to join in judgment. Thus “at the trial of the duke of Brittany in 1378, the peers of France protested against the presence of the king.” Again <£ at the trial of the Marquis of Saluces, under Francis I., that monarch was made to see that he could not sit.” When Lewis XIII. wished to be judge in the case of the Duke de la Yalette, he was resisted by the judges, who said that it was without precedent. And in our own country there came a time when “James I. was informed by the judges that he had the right to preside in the court, but not to express his opinion:” a step towards that exclusion finally reached. While the judicial business of the political head thus lapses into the hands of appointed agencies, these agencies them- selves, severally parting with certain of their functions one to another, become specialized. Among ourselves, even before there took place the above-named separation of the per- manently-localized court of common pleas, from the king’s court which moved about with him, there had arisen within JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 509 the king’s court an incipient differentiation. Causes concern- ing revenue were dealt with in sittings distinguished from the general sittings of the king’s court, by being held in another room ; and establishment of this custom produced a division. Adaptation of its parts to unlike ends led to divergence of them; until, out of the original Curia Regis, had come the court of exchequer and the court of common pleas ; leaving behind the court of king’s bench as a remnant of the original body. When the office of justiciar (who, represent- ing the king in his absence, presided over these courts) was abolished, the parting of them became decided ; and though, for a length of time, competition for fees led to trenching on one another’s functions, yet, eventually, their functions became definitely marked off*. A further important development, different but allied, took place. We have seen that when appointing others to judge for him, the king reserves the power of deciding in cases which the law has not previously provided for, and also the power of supervising the decisions made by his deputies. Naturally this power comes to be especially used to over-ride deci- sions which, technically according to law, are practically unjust: the king acquires an equity jurisdiction. At first exercised personally, this jurisdiction is liable to be deputed ; and in our own case was so. The chancellor, one of the king’s servants, who “ as a baron of the exchequer and as a leading member of the curia” had long possessed judicial func- tions, and who was the officer to present to the king petitions concerning these “ matters of grace and favour,” became presently himself the authority who gave decisions in equity qualifying the decisions of law ; and thus in time resulted the court of chancery. Minor courts with minor functions also budded out from the original Curia Regis. This body included the chief officers of the king’s household, each of whom had a jurisdiction in matters . pertaining to liis special business ; and hence resulted the court of the chamberlain, the court of the steward, the court of the earl marshal (now 510 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. at Herald’s College), the court of the constable (no longer extant), the court of the admiral, &c. In brief, then, we find proofs that, little trace as its struc- ture now shows of such an origin, our complex judicial system, alike in its supreme central parts and in its various small local parts, has evolved by successive changes out of the primitive gathering of people, head men, and chief. § 528. Were further detail desirable, there might here be given an account of police-systems ; showing their evolution from the same primitive triune body whence originate the several organizations delineated in this and preceding chapters. As using force to subdue internal aggressors, police are like soldiers, who use force to subdue external aggressors ; and the two functions, originally one, are not even now quite sepa- rated either in their natures or their agents. For besides being so armed that they are in some countries scarcely dis- tinguishable from soldiers, and besides being subject to mili- tary discipline, the police are, in case of need, seconded by soldiers in the discharging of their duties. To indicate the primitive identity it will suffice to name two facts. During the Merovingian period in France, armed bands of serfs, attached to the king’s household and to the households of dukes, were employed both as police and for garrison pur- poses ; and in feudal England, tlie posse comitcttus , consisting of all freemen between fifteen and sixty, under command of the sheriff, was the agent for preserving internal peace at the same time that it was available for repelling invasions, though not for foreign service — an incipient differentiation between the internal and external defenders which became in course of time more marked. Letting this brief indication suffice, it remains only to sum up the conclusions above reached. Evidences of sundry kinds unite in showing that judicial action and military action, ordinarily having for their common end the rectification of real or alleged wrongs, are closely JUDICIAL AND EXECUTIVE SYSTEMS. 511 allied at the outset. The sword is the ultimate resort in either case : use of it being in the one case preceded by a w T ar of words carried on before some authority whose aid is invoked, while in the other case it is not so preceded. As is said by Sir Henry Maine, “the fact seems to be that contention in Court takes the place of contention in arms, but only gradually takes its place.” Thus near akin as the judicial and military actions origi- nally are, they are naturally at first discharged by the same agency — the primitive triune body formed of chief, head men, and people. This which decides on affairs of war and settles questions of public policy, also gives judgments concerning alleged wrongs of individuals and enforces its decisions. According as the social activities develop one or other element of the primitive triune body, there results one or other form of agency for the administration of law. If continued militancy makes the ruling man all-powerful, he becomes absolute judicially as in other ways : the people lose all share in giving decisions, and the judgments of the chief men who surround him are overridden by his. If con- ditions favour the growth of the chief men into an oligarchy, the body they form becomes the agent forjudging and punish- ing offences as for other purposes : its acts being little or not at all qualified by the opinion of the mass. While if the sur- rounding circumstances and mode of life are such as to prevent supremacy of one man, or of the leading men, its primitive judicial power is preserved by the aggregate of freemen — or is regained by it where it re-acquires predomi- nance. And where the powers of these three elements are mingled in the political organization, they are also mingled in the judicial organization. In those cases, forming the great majority, in which habitual militancy entails subjection of the people, partial or complete, and in which, consequently, political power and judicial power come to be exercised exclusively by the several orders of chief men, the judicial organization which arises as 512 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the society enlarges and complicates, is officered by the sacerdotal class, or the military class, or partly the one and partly the other: their respective shares being apparently dependent on the ratio between the degree of conscious subordination to the human ruler and the degree of conscious subordination to the divine ruler, whose will the priests are supposed to communicate. But with the progress of indus- trialism and the rise of a class which, acquiring property and knowledge, gains consequent influence, the judicial system comes to be largely, and at length chiefly, officered by men derived from this class ; and these men become distinguished from their predecessors not only as being of other origin, but also as being exclusively devoted to judicial functions. While there go on changes of this kind, there go on changes by which the origin ally-simple and comparatively- uniform judicial system, is rendered increasingly complex. Where, as in ordinary cases, there has gone along with achievement of supremacy by the king, a monopolizing of judicial authority by him, press of business presently obliges him to appoint others to try causes and give judg- ments : subject of course to his approval. Already his court, originally formed of himself, his chief men, and the sur- rounding people, has become supreme over courts constituted in analogous ways of local magnates and their inferiors — so initiating a differentiation ; and now by delegating certain of his servants or assessors, at first with temporary commissions to hear appeals locally, and then as permanent itinerant judges, a further differentiation is produced. And to this are added yet further differentiations, kindred in nature, by which other assessors of his court are changed into the heads of specialized courts, which divide its business among them. Though this particular course has been taken in but a single case, yet it serves to exemplify the general principle under which, in one way or other, there arises out of the primitive simple judicial body, a centralized and heterogeneous judicial organization. CHAPTER XIV. LAWS. § 529. If, going back once more to tlie primitive horde, we ask what happens when increase of numbers necessitates migration — if we ask what it is which causes the migrating part to fall into social arrangements like those of the parent part, and to behave in the same way ; the obvious reply is that the inherited natures of its members, regulated by the ideas transmitted from the past, cause these results. That \ guidance by custom which we everywhere find among rude 1 peoples, is the sole conceivable guidance at the outset. To recall vividly the truth set forth in § 467, that the rudest men conform their lives to ancestral usages, I may name such further illustrations as that the Sandwich Islanders had “ a kind of traditionary code . . . followed by general con- sent ; ” and that by the Bechuanas, government is carried on according to “ long-acknowledged customs/' A more specific statement is that made by Mason concerning the Karens, among whom “ the elders are the depositaries of the laws, both moral and political, both civil and criminal, and they give them as they receive them, and as they have been brought down from past generations” orally. Here, however, we have chiefly to note that this government by custom, persists through long stages of progress, and even still largely in- fluences judicial administration. Instance the fact that as late as the 14th century in France, an ordinance declared that “ the whole kingdom is regulated by ‘ custom,' and it is as 514 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ‘ custom’ that some of our subjects make use of the written law." Instance the fact that our own Common Law is mainly an embodiment of the “ customs of the realm/’ which have gradually become established : its older part, nowhere existing in the shape of enactment, is to be learnt only from text- books ; and even parts, such as mercantile law, elaborated in modern times, are known only through reported judgments, given in conformity with usages proved to have been pre- viously followed. Instance again the fact, no less signi- ficant, that at the present time custom perpetually re-appears as a living supplementary factor ; for it is only after judges’ decisions have established precedents which pleaders after- wards quote, and subsequent judges follow, that the applica- tion of an act of parliament becomes settled. So that while in the course of civilization written law tends to replace traditional usage, the replacement never becomes complete. | And here we are again reminded that law, whether written or unwritten, formulates the rule of the dead over the living. In addition to that power which past generations exercise over present generations by transmitting their natures, bodily and mental ; and in addition to the power they exercise over them by bequeathed private habits and modes of life ; there is this power they exercise through these regulations for public conduct handed down orally or in writing. Among savages and in barbarous societies, the authority of laws thus derived is unqualified ; and even in advanced stages of civili- zation, characterized by much modifying of old laws and making of new ones, conduct is controlled in a far greater degree by the body of inherited laws than by those laws which the living make. I emphasize these obvious truths for the purpose of point- ing out that they imply a tacit ancestor-worship. I wish to make it clear that when asking in any case — What is the Law? we are asking — What was the dictate of our fore- fathers ? And my object in doing this is to prepare the way for showing that unconscious conformity to the dictates of the LAWS. 515 dead, thus shown, is, in early stages, joined with conscious conformity to their dictates. § 530. For along with development of the ghost-theory, there arises the practice of appealing to ghosts, and to the gods evolved from ghosts, for directions in special cases, in addi- tion to the general directions embodied in customs. There come methods by which the will of the ancestor, or the dead chief, or the derived deity, is sought ; and the reply given, usually referring to a particular occasion, originates in some cases a precedent, from which there results a law added to the body of laws the dead have transmitted. The seeking of information and advice from ghosts, takes here a supplicatory and there a coercive form. The Yeddahs, who ask the spirits of their ancestors for aid, believe that in dreams they tell them where to hunt ; and then we read of the Scandinavian diviners, that they “ dragged the ghosts of the departed from their tombs and forced the dead to tell them what would happen cases which remind us that among the Hebrews, too, there were supernatural directions given in dreams as well as information derived from invoked spirits. This tendency to accept special guidance from the dead, in addition to the general guidance of an inherited code, is traceable in a transfigured shape even among ourselves ; for besides conforming to the orally-declared wish of a deceased parent, children are often greatly influenced in their conduct by considering what the deceased parent would have desired or advised: his imagined injunction practically becomes a supplementary law. Here, however, we are chiefly concerned with that more developed form of such guidance which results where the spirits of distinguished men, regarded with special fear and trust, become deities. Ancient Egyptian hieroglyphics reveal two stages of it. The “ Instructions ” recorded by King Easlfotephet are given by his father in a dream. “ Son of the Sun Amenemhat — deceased : — He says in a dream — unto his 516 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. son the Lord intact, — he says rising up like a god : — Listen to what I speak unto thee/” And then another tablet narrates how Thothmes IV, travelling when a prince, and taking his siesta in the shade of the Sphinx, was spoken to in a dream by that god, who said — “ Look at me ! . . . Answer me that you will do me what is in my heart ” &c. ; and when he ascended the throne, Thothmes fulfilled the injunction. Analogous stages were well exemplified among the ancient Peruvians. There is a tradition that Huayna Ccapac, wish- ing to marry his second sister, applied for assent to the dead body of his father; “but the dead body gave no answer, while fearful signs appeared in the heavens, portending blood.” Moreover, as before pointed out in § 477, “ the Ynca gave them (the vassals) to understand that all he did with regard to them was by an order and revelation of his father, the Sun.” Turning to extant races, we see that in the Poly- nesian Islands, where the genesis of a pantheon by ancestor worship is variously exemplified, divine direction is habitually sought through priests. Among the Tahitians, one “ mode by which the god intimated his will,” was to enter the priest, who then “ spoke as entirely under supernatural influence.” Mariner tells us that in Tonga, too, when the natives wished to consult the gods, there was a ceremony of invocation; and the inspired priest then uttered the divine command. Similar beliefs and usages are described by Turner as existing in Samoa. Passing to another region, we find among the Todas of the Indian hills, an appeal for supernatural guidance in judicial matters. “ When any dispute arises respecting their wives or their buffaloes, it has to be decided by the priest, who affects to become possessed by the Bell-god, and . . . pronounces the deity’s decision upon the point in dispute.” These instances serve to introduce and interpret for us those which the records of historic peoples yield. Taking first the Hebrews, we have the familiar fact that the laws for general guidance were supposed to be divinely communi- cated ; and we have the further fact that special directions LAWS. 517 were often sought. Through the priest who accompanied the army, the commander “ inquired of the Lord ” about any military movement of importance, and sometimes received very definite orders ; as when, before a battle with the Philistines, David is told to “ fetch a compass behind them, and come upon them over against the mulberry trees.” Sundry Ayran peoples furnish evidence. In common with other Indian codes, the code of Manu, “ according to Hindoo mythology, is an emanation from the supreme God.” So, too, was it with the Greeks. Hot forgetting the tradition that by an ancient Cretan king, a body of laws was brought down from the mountain where Jupiter was said to be buried, we may pass to the genesis of laws from special divine com- mands, as implied in the Homeric poems. Speaking of these Grote says : — “ The appropriate Greek word for human laws never occurs : amidst a very wavering phraseology, we can detect a gradual transition from the primitive idea of a personal goddess, Themis, attached to Zeus, first to his sentences or orders called Themistes, and next by a still farther remove to various established customs which those sentences were believed to sanctify — the authority of religion and that of custom coalescing into one indivisible obligation.” Congruous in nature was the belief that “ Lycurgus ob- tained not only his own consecration to the office of legis- lator, but his laws themselves from the mouth of the Delphic God.” To which add that we have throughout later Greek times, the obtainment of special information and direc- tion through oracles. Evidence that among the Eomans there had occurred a kindred process, is supplied by the story that the ancient laws were received by Numa from the goddess Egeria ; and that Huma appointed augurs by whose inter- pretation of signs the will of the gods was to be ascertained. Even in the 9th century, under the Carolingians, there were brought before the nobles “ articles of law named capitula , which the king himself had drawn up by the inspiration of God.” Without following out the influence of like beliefs in later 518 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. times, as seen in trial by ordeal and trial by judicial combat, in both of which God was supposed indirectly to give judgment, the above evidence makes it amply manifest that, in addition to those injunctions definitely expressed, or embodied in usages tacitly accepted from seniors and through them from remote ancestors, there are further in- junctions more consciously attributed to supernatural beings — either the ghosts of parents and chiefs who were personally known, or the ghosts of more ancient traditionally-known chiefs which have been magnified into gods. Whence it follows that originally, under both of its forms, law embodies the dictates of the dead to the living. § 531. And here we are at once shown how it happens that throughout early stages of social evolution, no distinction is made between sacred law and secular law. Obedience to established injunctions of whatever kind, originating in reverence for supposed supernatural beings of one or other order, it results that at first all these injunctions have the same species of authority. The Egyptian wall-sculptures, inscriptions, and papyri, everywhere expressing subordination of the present to the past, show us the universality of the religious sanction for rules of conduct. Of the Assyrians Layard says : — “ The intimate connection between the public and private life of the Assyrians and their religion, is abundantly proved by the sculptures. ... As among most ancient Eastern nations, not only all public and social duties, but even the commonest forms and customs, appear to have been more or less influenced by religion. . . . All his [the king’s] acts, whether in war or peace, appear to have been connected with the national religion, and were believed to be under the special protection and superintendence of the deity.” That among the Hebrews there existed a like connexion, is conspicuously shown us in the Pentateuch ; where, besides the commandments specially so-called, and besides religious ordinances regulating feasts and sacrifices, the doings of the priests, the purification by scapegoat, &e., there are numerous LAWS. 519 directions for daily conduct — directions concerning kinds of food and modes of cooking ; directions for proper farming in respect of periodic fallows, not sowing mingled grain, &c. ; directions for the management of those in bondage, male and female, and the payment of hired labourers ; directions about trade-transactions and the sales of lands and houses ; along with sumptuary laws extending to the quality and fringes of garments and the shaping of beards: instances sufficiently showing that the rules of living, down even to small details, had a divine origin equally with the supreme laws of con- duct. The like was true of the Ayrans in early stages. The code of Manu was a kindred mixture of sacred and secular regulations — of moral dictates and rules for carrying on ordinary affairs. Says Tiele of the Greeks after the Doric migration “ No new political institutions, no fresh culture, no additional games, were established without the sanction of the Pythian oracle.” And again we read — " Chez les Grecs et cliez les Eomains, comme chez les Hindous, la loi fut d’abord une partie de la religion. Les anciens codes des cites etaient un ensemble de rites de prescriptions liturgiques de prieres, en meme temps que de dispositions legislatives. Les regies du droit de propriety et du droit de succession y etaient eparses au milieu des regies des sacrifices, de la sepulture et du culte des morts.” Originating in this manner, law acquires stability. Possess- ing a supposed supernatural sanction, its rules have a rigidity enabling them to restrain men’s actions in greater degrees than could any rules having an origin recognized as natural. They tend thus to produce settled social arrangements ; both directly, by their high authority, and indirectly by limiting the actions of the living ruler. As was pointed out in § 468, early governing agents, not daring to transgress inherited usages and regulations, are practically limited to interpreting and enforcing them : their legislative power being exercised only in respect of matters not already prescribed for. Thus of the ancient Egyptians we read : — “ It was not on his [the king’s] own will that his occupations depended, but on those rules of duty and propriety which the wisdom of his 520 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ancestors had framed, with a just regard for the welfare of the king and of his people.” And how persistent is this authority of the sanctified past over the not-yet-sanctified present, we see among ourselves, in the fact that every legis- lator has to bind himself by oath to maintain certain political arrangements which our ancestors thought good for us. While the unchangeableness of law, due to its supposed sacred origin, greatly conduces to social order during those early stages in w T hich strong restraints are most needed, there of course results an unadaptiveness w’hich impedes progress when there arise new conditions to be met. Hence come into use those “ legal fictions,” by the aid of which nominal obedience is reconciled with actual disobedience. Alike in Roman law and in English law, as pointed out by Sir Henry Maine, legal fictions have been the means of modifying statutes which were transmitted as immutable ; and so fitting them to new requirements : thus uniting stability with that plasticity which allows of gradual transformation. § 532. Such being the origin and nature of laws, it becomes manifest that the cardinal injunction must be obedience. Conformity to each particular direction pre-supposes allegiance to the authority giving it ; and therefore the imperativeness of subordination to this authority is primary. That direct acts of insubordination, shown in treason and rebellion, stand first in degree of criminality, evidently fol- lows. This truth is seen at the present time in South Africa. “ According to a horrible law of the Zulu despots, when a chief is put to death they exterminate also his sub- jects.” It was illustrated by the ancient Peruvians, among whom “ a rebellious city or province was laid waste, and its inhabitants exterminated ; ” and again by the ancient Mexi- cans, by whom one guilty of treachery to the king “ was put to death, with all his relations to the fourth degree.” A like extension of punishment occurred in past times in Japan, where, when “ the offence is committed against the state, LAWS. 521 punishment is inflicted upon the whole race of the offender ” Of efforts thus wholly to extinguish families guilty of dis- loyalty, the Merovingians yielded an instance : king Gunt- chram swore that the children of a certain rebel should be destroyed up to the ninth generation. And these examples naturally recall those furnished by Hebrew traditions. When Abraham, treating Jahveh as a terrestrial superior (just as existing Bedouins regard as god the most powerful living ruler known to them) entered into a covenant under which, for territory given, he, Abraham, became a vassal, circumcision was the prescribed badge of subordination ; and the sole capital offence named was neglect of circumcision, implying insubordination : J ahveh elsewhere announcing himself as “ a jealous god,” and threatening punishment “ upon the children unto the third and fourth generation of them that hate me.” And the truth thus variously illustrated, that during stages in which maintenance of authority is most imperative, direct dis- loyalty is considered the blackest of crimes, we trace down through later stages in such facts as that, in feudal days, so long as the fealty of a vassal was duly manifested, crimes, often grave and numerous, were overlooked. Less extreme in its flagitiousness than the direct dis- obedience implied by treason and rebellion, is, of course, the indirect disobedience implied by breach of commands. This, however, where strong rule has been established, is regarded as a serious offence, quite apart from, and much exceeding, that which the forbidden act intrinsically involves. Its greater gravity was distinctly enunciated by the Peruvians, among whom, says Garcilasso, “ the most common punishment was death, for they said that a culprit was not punished for the delinquencies he had committed, but for having broken the commandment of the Ynca, who was respected as God.” The like conception meets us in another country where the ab- solute ruler is regarded as divine. Sir E. Alcock quotes Thunberg to the effect that in Japan, “ most crimes are punished with death, a sentence which is inflicted with less 522 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. regard to the magnitude of the crime than to the audacity of the attempt to transgress the hallowed laws of the empire.” And then, beyond the criminality which disobeying the ruler involves, there is the criminality involved by damaging the ruler’s property, where his subjects and their services belong wholly or partly to him. In the same way that maltreating a slave, and thereby making him less valuable, comes to be considered as an aggression on his owner — in the same way that even now among ourselves a father’s ground for proceed- ing against a seducer is loss of his daughter’s services ; so, where the relation of people to monarch is servile, there arises the view that injury done by one person to another, is injury done to the monarch’s property. An extreme form of this view is alleged of Japan, where cutting and maiming of the king’s dependents “ becomes wounding the king, or regicide.” And hence the general principle, traceable in European juris- prudence from early days, that a transgression of man against man is punishable mainly, or in large measure, as a trans- gression against the State. It was thus in ancient Eome : “ every one convicted of having broken the public peace, expiated his offence with his life.” An early embodiment of the principle occurs in the Salic law, under which “ to the wehrgeld is added, in a great number of cases, . . . the frecl , a sum paid to the king or magistrate, in reparation for the violation of public peace ; ” and in later days, the fine paid to the State absorbed the wehrgeld. Our own history simi- larly shows us that, as authority extends and strengthens, the guilt of disregarding it takes precedence of intrinsic guilt. “ ‘ The king’s peace 5 was a privilege which attached to the sovereign’s court and castle, but which he could confer on other places and persons, and which at once raised greatly the penalty of misdeeds committed in regard to them.” Along with the growing check on the right of private revenge for wrongs — along with the increasing subordination of minor and local jurisdictions — along with that strengthening of a central authority which these changes imply, “ offences against LAWS. 523 the law become offences against the king, and the crime of disobedience a crime of contempt to be expiated by a special sort of fine.” And we may easily see how, where a ruler gains absolute power, and especially where lie has the prestige of divine origin, the guilt of contempt comes to exceed the intrinsic guilt of the forbidden act. A significant truth may be added. On remembering that Peru, and Japan till lately, above named as countries in which the crime of disobedience to the ruler was considered so great as practically to equalize the flagitiousness of all forbidden acts, had societies in which militant organization, carried to its extreme, assimilated the social government at large to the government of an army ; we are reminded that even in societies like our own, there is maintained in the army the doctrine that insubordination is the cardinal offence. Disobedience to orders is penal irrespective of the nature of the orders or the motive for the disobedience ; and an act which, considered in itself, is quite innocent, may be visited with death if done in opposition to commands. While, then, in that enforced conformity to inherited customs which plays the part of law in the earliest stages, we see insisted upon the duty of obedience to ancestors at large, irrespective of the injunctions to be obeyed, which are often trivial or absurd — while in the enforced conformity to special directions given in oracular utterances by priests, or in “ themistes,” &c., which form a supplementary source of law, we see insisted upon the duty of obedience, in small tilings as in great, to certain recognized spirits of the dead, or deities derived from them ; we also see that obedience to the edicts of the terrestrial ruler, whatever they may be, becomes, as his power grows, a primary duty. § 533. What has been said in the foregoing sections brings out with clearness the truth that rules for the regulation of conduct have four sources. Even in early stages we see that beyond the inherited usages which have a quasi-religious sane- 524 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. tion ; and beyond the special injunctions of deceased leaders, which have a more distinct religious sanction ; there is some, though a slight, amount of regulation derived from the will of the predominant man ; and there is also the effect, vague but influential, of the aggregate opinion. Not dwelling on the first of these, which is slowly modified by accretions derived from the others, it is observable that in the second we have the germ of the law afterwards distinguished as divine ; that in the third we have the germ of the law which gets its sanc- tion from allegiance to the living governor ; and that in the fourth we have the germ of the law which eventually becomes recognized as expressing the public will. Already I have sufficiently illustrated those kinds of laws which originate personally, as commands of a feared invisible ruler and a feared visible ruler. But before going further, it will be well to indicate more distinctly the kind of law which originates impersonally, from the prevailing sentiments and ideas, and which we find clearly shown in rude stages before the other two have become dominant. A -few extracts will exhibit it. Schoolcraft says of the Chippewayans — u Thus, though they have no regular government, as every man is lord in his own family, they are influenced more or less by certain principles which conduce to their general benefit.” Of the unorganized Shoshones Bancroft writes — “ Every man does as he likes. Private revenge, of course, occasionally overtakes the murderer, or, if the sympathies of the tribe be with the murdered man, he may possibly be publicly executed, but there are no fixed laws for such cases.” In like manner the same writer tells us of the Haidahs that — - “ Crimes have no punishment by law ; murder is settled for with rela- tives of the victim, by death or by the payment of a large sum ; and sometimes general or notorious offenders, especially medicine -men, are put to death by an agreement among leading men.” Even where government is considerably developed, public opinion continues to be an independent source of law. Ellis says that — “ In cases of theft in the Sandwich Islands, those who had been robbed retaliated upon the guilty party, by seizing whatever they could find ; LAWS. 525 and this mode of obtaining redress was so supported by public opinion, that the latter, though it might be the stronger party, dare not offer resistance.” By which facts we are reminded that where central authority and administrative machinery are feeble, the laws thus inform- ally established by aggregate feeling are enforced by making revenge for wrongs a socially-imposed duty ; while failure to revenge is made a disgrace, and a consequent danger. In ancient Scandinavia, “ a man’s relations and friends who had not revenged his death, would instantly have lost that repu- tation which constituted their principal security.” So that, obscured as this source of law becomes when the popular ele- ment in the triune political structure is entirely subordinated, yet it was originally conspicuous, and never ceases to exist. And now having noted the presence of this, along with the other mingled sources of law, let us observe how the several sources, along with their derived laws, gradually become distinguished. Recalling the proofs above given that where there has been established a definite political authority, inherited from apotheosized chiefs and made strong by divine sanction, laws of all kinds have a religious character ; we have first to note that a differentiation takes place between those regarded as sacred and those recognized as secular. An illustration of this advance is furnished us by the Greeks. Describing the state of things exhibited in the Homeric poems, Grote re- marks that “ there is no sense of obligation then existing, between man and man as such — and very little between each man and the entire community of which he is a member;” while, at the same time, “ the tie which binds a man to his father, his kinsman, his guest, or any special promisee towards wkom he has taken the engagement of an oath, is conceived in conjunction with the idea of Zeus, as witness and guarantee allegiance to a divinity is the source of obligation. But in historical Athens, “ the great impersonal authority called ‘ The Laws ’ stood out separately, both as 526 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. guide and sanction, distinct from religious duty or private sympathies.” And at the same time there arose the distinc- tion between breach of the sacred law and breach of the secular law : “ the murderer came to be considered, first as having sinned against the gods, next as having deeply injured the society, and thus at once as requiring absolution and deserving punishment.” A kindred differentiation early occurred in Rome. Though, during the primitive period, the head of the State, at once king and high priest, and in his latter capacity dressed as a god, was thus the mouth-piece of both sacred law and secular law ; yet, after- wards, with the separation of the ecclesiastical and political authorities, came a distinction between breaches of divine ordinances and breaches of human ordinances. In the words of Sir Henry Maine, there were “laws punishing sins. There were also laws punishing torts. The con- ception of offence against God produced the first class of ordinances ; the conception of offence against one’s neighbour produced the second ; but the idea of offence against the State or aggregate community did not at first produce a true criminal jurisprudence.” In explanation of the last statement it should, however, be added that since, during the regal period, according to Mommsen, “judicial procedure took the form of a public or a private process, according as the king interposed of his own motion, or only when appealed to by the injured party;” and since “the former course was taken only in cases which involved a breach of the public peace it must be inferred that wdien kingship ceased, there survived the distinction between transgression against the individual and transgression against the State, though the mode of dealing with this last had not, for a time, a definite form. Again, even among the Hebrews, more per- sistently theocratic as their social system was, we see a con- siderable amount of this change, at the same time that we are shown one of its causes. The Mishna contains many detailed civil laws ; and these manifestly resulted from the LAWS. 527 growing complication of affairs. The instance is one showing ns that primitive sacred commands, originating as they do in a comparatively undeveloped state of society, fail to cover the cases which arise as institutions become involved. In respect of these there consequently grow up rules having a known human authority only. By accumulation of such rules, is produced a body of human laws distinct from the divine laws ; and the offence of disobeying the one becomes unlike the offence of disobeying the other. Though in Christianized Europe, throughout which the indigenous religions were superseded by an introduced religion, the differentiating process was interfered with; yet, on setting out from the stage at which this introduced religion had acquired that supreme authority proper to indigenous re- ligions, we see that the subsequent changes were of like nature with those above described. Along with that mingling of structures shown in the ecclesiasticism of kings and the secularity of prelates, there went a mingling of political and religious legislation. Gaining supreme power, the Church interpreted sundry civil offences as offences against God; and even those which w^ere left to be dealt with by the magistrate were considered as thus left by divine ordi- nance. But subsequent evolution brought about stages in which various transgressions, held to be committed against both sacred and secular law, were simultaneously expiated by religious penance and civil punishment ; and there followed a separation which, leaving but a small remnant of ecclesiastical offences, brought the rest into the category of offences against the State and against individuals. And this brings us to the differentiation of equal, if not greater, significance, between those laws which derive their obligation from the will of the governing agency, and those laws which derive their obligation from the consensus of individual interests — between those laws which, having as their direct end the maintenance of authority, only indirectly thereby conduce to social welfare, and those which, directly and irrespective 528 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of authority, conduce to social welfare : of which last, law, in its modern form, is substantially an elaboration. Already I have pointed out that the kind of law initiated by the consensus of individual interests, precedes the kind of law initiated by political authority. Already I have said that though, as political authority develops, laws acquire the shape of commands, even to the extent that those original prin- ciples of social order tacitly recognized at the outset, come to be regarded as obligatory only because personally enacted, yet that the obligation derived from the consensus of indi- vidual interests survives, if obscured. And here it remains to show that as the power of the political head declines — as industrialism fosters an increasingly free population — as the third element in the triune political structure, long sub- ordinated, grows again predominant ; there again grows pre- dominant this primitive source of law — the consensus of individual interests. We have further to note that in its re-developed form, as in its original form, the kind of law hence arising has a character radically distinguishing it from the kinds of law thus far considered. Both the divine laws and the human laws which originate from personal authority, have inequality as their common essential principle ; while the laws which originate impersonally, in the consensus of individual interests, have equality as their essential principle. Evidence is furnished at the very outset. For w r hat is this lex talionis which, in the rudest hordes of men, is not only recognized but enforced by general opinion ? Obviously, as enjoining an equalization of injuries or losses, it tacitly assumes equality of claims among the individuals concerned. The principle of requiring “ an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth,” embodies the primitive idea of justice everywhere: the endeavour to effect an exact balance being sometimes quite curious. Thus we read in Arbousset and Daumas : — “ A Basuto whose son had been wounded on the head with a staff, came to entreat me to deliver up the offender, — 4 with the same staff and on the same spot where my son was beaten, will I give a blow on the head of the man who did it.’ ” LAWS. 529 A kindred effort to equalize in this literal way, the nffence and the expiation, occurs in Abyssinia ; where, when the murderer is given over to his victim’s family, “the nearest of kin puts him to death with the same kind of weapon as that with which he had slain their relative.” As the last case shows, this primitive procedure, when it does not assume the form of inflicting injury for injury between individuals, assumes the form of inflicting injury for injury between families or tribes, by taking life for life. With the instances given in § 522 may be joined one from Sumatra. “ When in an affray [between families], there happen to be several persons killed on both sides, the business of justice is only to state the reciprocal losses, in the form of an account current, and order the balance to be discharged if the numbers be unequal.” And then, from this rude justice which insists on a balancing of losses between families or tribes, it results that so long as their mutual injuries are equalized, it matters not whether the blameable persons are or are not those who suffer ; and hence the system of vicarious punishment — hence the fact that vengeance is wreaked on any member of the transgressing family or tribe. Moreover, ramifying in these various ways, the principle applies where not life but property is con- cerned. Schoolcraft tells us that among the Dakotas, “injury to property is sometimes privately revenged by destroying other property in place thereof and among the Araueanians, families pillage one another for the purpose of making their losses alike. The idea survives, though changed in form, when crimes come to be compounded for by gifts or payments. Very early we see arising the alternative between submitting to vengeance or making compensation. Kane says of certain North American races, that “ horses or other Indian valuables ” were accepted in compensation for murder. With the Dakotas “ a present of white wampum,” if accepted, condones the offence. Among the Araueanians, homicides “ can screen themselves from punishment by a composition with the relations of the murdered.” Recalling, as these few instances do, the kindred alternatives recognized throughout 530 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. primitive Europe, they also make us aware of a significant difference. For with the rise of class-distinctions in primitive Europe, the rates of compensation, equal among members of each class, had ceased to be equal between members of dif- ferent classes. Along with the growth of personally- derived law, there had been a departure from the impersonally- derived law as it originally existed. But now the truth to be noted is that, with the relative weakening of kingly or aristocratic authority and relative strengthening of popular authority, there revives the partially- suppressed kind of law derived from the consensus of indi- vidual interests ; and the kind of law thus originating tends continually to replace all other law. For the chief business of courts of justice at present, is to enforce, without respect of persons, the principle, recognized before governments arose, that all members of the community, however otherwise dis- tinguished, shall be similarly dealt with when they aggress one upon another. Though the equalization of injuries by retaliation is no longer permitted ; and though the Govern- ment, reserving to itself the punishment of transgressors, does little to enforce restitution or compensation ; yet, in pur- suance of the doctrine that all men are equal before the law, it has the same punishment for transgressors of every class. And then in respect of unfulfilled contracts or disputed debts, from the important ones tried at Assizes to the trivial ones settled in County Courts, its aim is to maintain the rights and obligations of citizens without regard for wealth or rank. Of course in our transition state the change is incomplete. But the sympathy with individual claims, and the consensus of individual interests accompanying it, lead to an increasing predominance of that kind of law which provides directly for social or’der; as distinguished from that kind of lav/ which indirectly provides for social order by insisting on obedience to authority, divine or human. With decline of the regime of status and growth of the regime of contract, personally-derived law more and more gives place to impel- LAWS. 531 sonally-derived law ; and this of necessity, since a formulated inequality is implied by the compulsory cooperation of the one, while, by the voluntary cooperation of the other, there is implied a formulated equality. So that, having first differentiated from the laws of sup- posed divine origin, the laws of recognized human origin subsequently re-differentiate into those which ostensibly have the will of the ruling agency as their predominant sanction, and those which ostensibly have the aggregate of private interests as their predominant sanction ; of which two the last tends, in the course of social evolution, more and more to absorb the first. Necessarily, however, while militancy con- tinues, the absorption remains incomplete ; since obedience to a ruling will continues to be in some cases necessary. § 534. A right understanding of this matter is so important, that I must be excused for briefly presenting two further aspects of the changes described : one concerning the accom- panying sentiments, and the other concerning the accompany- ing theories. As laws originate partly in the customs inherited from the undistinguished dead, partly in the special injunctions of the distinguished dead, partly in the average will of the undis- tinguished living, and partly in the will of the distinguished living, the feelings responding to them, allied though differ- ent, are mingled in proportions that vary under diverse cir- cumstances. A ccording to the nature of the society, one or other sanction predominates ; and the sentiment appropriate to it obscures the sentiments appropriate to the others, without, however, obliterating them. Thus in a theocratic society, the crime of murder is punished primarily as a sin against God ; but not without there being some consciousness of its criminality as a disobedience to the human ruler who enforces the divine command, as well as an injury to a family, and, by implication, to the community. Where, as among the Bedouins or in 14 532 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Sumatra, there is no such supematurally-derived injunction, and no consequent reprobation of disobedience to it, the loss entailed on the family of the victim is the injury recognized ; and, consequently, murder is not distinguished from man- slaughter. Again, in Japan and in Peru, unqualified abso- luteness of the living ruler is, or was, accompanied by the belief that the criminality of murder consisted primarily in transgression of his commands ; though doubtless the establish- ment of such commands implied, both in ruler and people, some recognition of evil, individual or general, caused by breach of them. In ancient Eome, the consciousness of injury done to the community by murder was decided ; and the feeling enlisted on behalf of public order was that which mainly enforced the punishment. And then among ourselves when a murder is committed, the listener to an account of it shudders not mainly because the alleged command of God has been broken, nor mainly because there has been a breach of “ the Queen’s peace but his strongest feeling of repro- bation is that excited by the thought of a life taken away, with which is joined a secondary feeling due to the diminution of social safety which every such act implies. In these different emotions which give to these several sanctions their respective powers, we see the normal concomitants of the social states to which such sanctions are appropriate. More especially we see how that weakening of the sentiments offended by breaches of authority, divine or human, which accompanies growth of the sentiments offended by injuries to individuals and the community, is naturally joined with revival of that kind of law which originates in the consensus of individual interests — the law which was dominant before personal authority grew up, and which again becomes domi- nant as personal authority declines. At the same time there goes on a parallel change of theory. Along with a rule predominantly theocratic, there is current a tacit or avowed doctrine, that the acts prescribed or for- bidden are made right or wrong solely by divine command ; LAWS# 533 and though this doctrine survives through subsequent stages (as it does still in our own religious world), yet belief in it becomes nominal rather than real. Where there has been established an absolute human authority, embodied in a single individual, or, as occasionally, in a few, there comes the theory that law has no other source than the will of this authority : acts are conceived as proper or improper accord- ing as they do or do not conform to its dictates. With progress towards a popular form of government, this theory becomes modified to the extent that though the obligation to do this and refrain from that is held to arise from State- enactment ; yet the authority which gives this enactment its force is the public desire. Still it is observable that along with a tacit implication that the consensus of individual interests affords the warrant for law, there goes the overt assertion that this warrant is derived from the formulated will of the majority : no question being raised whether this formulated will is or is not congruous with the consensus of individual interests. In this current theory there obviously survives the old idea that there is no other sanction for law than the command of embodied authority ; though the autho- rity is now a widely different one. But this theory, much in favour witli “ philosophical politicians,” is a transitional theory. The ultimate theory, which it foreshadows, is that the source of legal obligation is the consensus of individual interests itself, and not the will of a majority determined by their opinion concerning it ; which may or may not be right. Already, even in legal theory, especially as expounded by French jurists, natural law or law of nature, is recognized as a source of formulated law : the admission being thereby made that, primarily certain in- dividual claims, and secondarily the social welfare furthered by enforcing such claims, furnish a warrant for law, ante- ceding political authority and its enactments. Already in the qualification of Common Law by Equity, which avowedly proceeds upon the law of “ honesty and reason and of nations ” 534 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. there is involved the pre-supposition that, as similarly-con- stituted beings, men have certain rights in common, main- tenance of which, while directly advantageous to them in- dividually, indirectly benefits the community ; and that thus the decisions of equity have a sanction independent alike of customary law and parliamentary votes. Already in respect of religious opinions there is practically conceded the right of the individual to disobey the law, even though it expresses the will of a majority. Whatever disapproval there may be of him as a law-breaker, is over-ridden by sympathy with his assertion of freedom of judgment. There is a tacit recog- nition of a warrant higher than that of State-enactments, whether regal or popular in origin. These ideas and feelings are all significant of progress towards the view, proper to the developed industrial state, that the justification for a law is that it enforces one or other of the conditions to harmonious social cooperation ; and that it is unjustified (enacted by no matter how high an authority or how general an opinion) if it traverses these conditions. And this is tantamount to saying that the impersonally- derived law which revives as personally-derived law declines, and which gives expression to the consensus of individual interests, becomes, in its final form, simply an applied system of ethics — or rather, of that part of ethics which concerns men’s just relations with one another and with the community. § 535. Returning from this somewhat parenthetical dis- cussion, we might here enter on the development of laws, not generally but specially ; exhibiting them as accumulating in mass, as dividing and sub-dividing in their kinds, as becom- ing increasingly definite, as growing into coherent and com- plex systems, as undergoing adaptations to new conditions. But besides occupying too much space, such an exposition would fall outside the lines of our subject. Present require- ments are satisfied by the results above set forth, which may be summarized as follows. LAWS. 535 Setting out with the truth, illustrated even in the very rudest tribes, that the ideas conveyed, sentiments inculcated, and usages taught, to children by parents who themselves were similarly taught, eventuate in a rigid set of customs ; we recognize the fact that at first, as to the last, law is mainly an embodiment of ancestral injunctions. To the injunctions of the undistinguished dead, which, qualified by the public opinion of the living in cases not prescribed for, constitute the code of conduct before any political organization has arisen, there come to be added the injunctions of the distinguished dead, when there have arisen chiefs who, in some measure feared and obeyed during life, after death give origin to ghosts still more feared and obeyed. And when, during that compounding of societies effected by war, such chiefs develop into kings, their remembered commands and the commands supposed to be given by their ghosts, become a sacred code of conduct, partly embodying and partly adding to the code pre-established by custom. The living ruler, able to legislate only in respect of matters unprovided for, is bound by these transmitted commands of the unknown and the known who have passed away ; save only in cases where the living ruler is himself regarded as divine, in which cases his injunctions become laws having a like sacredness. Hence the trait common to societies in early stages, that the prescribed rules of conduct of whatever kind have a religious sanction. Sacrificial observances, public duties, moral injunctions, social ceremonies, habits of life, industrial regulations, and even modes of dressing, stand on the same footing. Maintenance of the unchangeable rules of conduct thus originating, which is requisite for social stability during those stages in which the type of nature is yet but little fitted for harmonious social cooperation, pre-supposes implicit obedience; and hence disobedience becomes the blackest crime. Treason and rebellion, whether against the divine or the human ruler bring penalties exceeding all others in severity. The breaking 536 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of a law is punished not because of the intrinsic criminality of the act committed, but because of the implied insubordina- tion. And the disregard of governmental authority continues, through subsequent stages, to constitute, in legal theory, the primary element in a transgression. In societies that become large and complex, there arise forms of activity and intercourse not provided for in the sacred code ; and in respect of these the ruler is free to make regulations. As such regulations accumulate there comes into exist- ence a body of laws of known human origin ; and though this acquires an authority due to reverence for the men who made it and the generations wdiich approved it, yet it has not the sacredness of the god-descended body of laws : human law differentiates from divine law. But in societies which remain predominantly militant, these two bodies of laws continue similar in the respect that they have a personally- derived authority. The avowed reason for obeying them is that they express the will of a divine ruler, or the will of a human ruler, or, occasionally, the will of an irresponsible oligarchy. But with the progress of industrialism and growth of a free population wdiich gradually acquires political power, the humanly-derived law begins to sub-divide; and that part which originates in the consensus of individual interests, begins to dominate over the part which originates in the authority of the ruler. So long as the social type is one organized on the principle of compulsory cooperation, law, having to maintain this compulsory cooperation, must be primarily concerned in regulating status , maintaining in- equality, enforcing authority ; and can but secondarily con- sider the individual interests of those forming the mass. But in proportion as the principle of voluntary cooperation more and more characterizes the social type, fulfilment of contracts and implied assertion of equality in men's rights, become the fundamental requirements, and the consensus of individual interests the chief source of law r : such authority LAWS. 537 as law otherwise derived continues to have, being recognized as secondary, and insisted upon only because maintenance of law for its own sake indirectly furthers the general welfare. Finally, we see that the systems of laws belonging to these successive stages, are severally accompanied by the senti- ments and theories appropriate to them ; and that the theories at present current, adapted to the existing compromise between militancy and industrialism, are steps towards the ultimate theory, in conformity with which law will have no other justification than that gained by it as maintainer of the conditions to complete life in the associated state. CHAPTER XV. PROPERTY. § 536. The fact referred to in § 292, that even intelligent animals display a sense of proprietorship, negatives the belief propounded by some, that individual property was not recog- nized by primitive men. When we see the claim to exclusive possession understood by a dog, so that he fights in defence of his masters clothes if left in charge of them, it becomes impossible to suppose that even in their lowest state men were devoid of those ideas and emotions which initiate private ownership. All that may be fairly assumed is that these ideas and sentiments were at first less developed than they have since become. It is true that in some extremely rude hordes, rights of pro- perty are but little respected. Lichtenstein tells us that among the Bushmen, “ the weaker, if he would preserve his own life, is obliged to resign to the stronger, his weapons, his wife, and even his children and there are some degraded North American tribes in which there is no check on the more powerful who choose to take from the less powerful : their acts are held to be legitimized by success. But absence of the idea of property, and the accompanying sentiment, is no more implied by these forcible appropriations than it is implied by the forcible appropriation which a bigger schoolboy makes of the toy belonging to a less. It is also true that even where force is not used, individual PROPERTY. 539 claims are in considerable degrees over-ridden or imperfectly maintained. We read of the Chippewayans that “ Indian law requires the successful hunter to share the spoils of the chase with all present and Hillliouse says of the Arawaks that though individual property is “ distinctly marked amongst them/’ “yet they are perpetually borrowing and lending, without the least care about payment.” But such instances merely imply that private ownership is at first ill- defined, as we might expect, a priori , that it would be. Evidently the thoughts and feelings which accompany the act of taking possession, as when an animal clutches its prey, and which at a higher stage of intelligence go along with the grasping of any article indirectly conducing to gratification, are the thoughts and feelings to which the theory of property does but give a precise shape. Evidently the use in legal documents of such expressions as “ to have and to hold,” and to be “seized” of a thing, as well as the survival up to comparatively late times of ceremonies in which a portion (rock or soil) of an estate bought, representing the whole, actually passed from hand to hand, point back to this primitive physical basis of ownership. Evidently the de- veloped doctrine of property, accompanying a social state in which men’s acts have to be mutually restrained, is a doctrine which on the one hand asserts the freedom to take and to keep within specified limits, and denies it beyond those limits — gives positiveness to the claim while restricting it. And evidently the increasing definiteness thus given to rights of individual possession, may be expected to show itself first where definition is relatively easy and afterwards where it is less easy. This we shall find that it does. § 537. While in early stages it is difficult, not to say impos- sible, to establish and mark off individual claims to parts of the area wandered over in search of food, it is not difficult to mark off the claims to movable things and to habitations ; and these claims we find habitually recognized. The follow- 540 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ing passage from Bancroft concerning certain North American savages, well illustrates the distinction : — “Captain Cook found among the Alits very * strict notions of their having a right to the exclusive property of everything that their country produces/ so that they claimed pay for even wood, water, and grass. The limits of tribal property are very clearly defined, but indi- viduals rarely claim any property in land. Houses belong to the. men who combine to build them. Private wealth consists of boats and implements for obtaining food, domestic utensils, slaves, and blankets.” A like condition is shown us by the Comanches : — “ They recognize no distinct rights of meum and tuum, except to per- sonal property ; holding the territory they occupy, and the game that depastures upon it, as common to all the tribe : the latter is appro- priated only by capture.” And the fact that among these Comanches, as among other peoples, “ prisoners of war belong to the captors, and may be sold or released at their will,” further shows that the right of property is asserted where it is easily defined. Of the Brazilian Indians, again, Yon Martius tells us that, — “ Huts and utensils are considered as private property ; but even with regard to them certain ideas of common possession prevail. The same hut is often occupied by more families than one ; and many utensils are the joint property of all the occupants. Scarcely anything is considered strictly as the property of an individual except his arms, accoutrements, pipe, and hammock.” Dr. Bink’s account of the Esquimaux shows that among them, too, while there is joint ownership of houses made jointly by the families inhabiting them, there is separate ownership of weapons, fishing boats, tools, etc. Thus it is made manifest that private right, completely recognized where recognition of it is easy, is partially recognized where partial recognition only is possible — where the private rights of companions are entangled with it. Instances of other kinds equally prove that among savages claims to possession are habitually marked off when practicable : if not fully, yet partially. Of the Chippewayans “who have no regular government ” to make laws or arbitrate, we yet read that, — “ In the former instance [when game is taken in inclosures by a hunt- ing party], the game is divided among those who have been engaged in PROPERTY. 54:1 the pursuit of it. In the latter [when taken in private traps] it is con- sidered as private property; nevertheless, any unsuccessful hunter passing by, may take a deer so caught, leaving the head, skin, and saddle, for the owner.” In cases, still more unlike, but similar in the respect that there exists an obvious connexion between labour expended and benefit achieved, rude peoples re-illustrate this same individualization of property. Burckhardt tells us of the Bedouins that wells are exclusive property, either of a whole tribe, or of individuals whose ancestors dug the wells.” Taken together such facts make it indisputable that in early stages, private appropriation, carried to a considerable extent, is not carried further because circumstances render extension of it impracticable. § 538. Recognition of this truth at once opens the way to explanation of primitive land-ownership ; and elucidates the genesis of those communal and family tenures which have prevailed so widely. While subsistence on wild food continues, the wandering horde inhabiting a given area, must continue to make joint use of the area; both because no claim can be shown by any member to any portion, and because the marking out of small divisions, if sharing were agreed upon, would be impracticable. Where pastoral life has arisen, ability to drive herds hither and thither within the occupied region is necessary. In the absence of cultivation, cattle and their owners could not survive were each owner restricted to one spot: there is nothing feasible but united possession of a wide tract. And when there comes a transition to the agricultural stage, either directly from the hunting stage or indirectly through the pastoral stage, several causes conspire to prevent, or to check, the growth of private land-ownership. There is first the traditional usage. Joint ownership con- tinues after circumstances no longer render it imperative,, because departure from the sacred example of forefathers is^ resisted. Sometimes the resistance is insuperable ; as with 542 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the Kechabites and the people of Petra, who by their vow “were not allowed to possess either vineyards or corn- fields or houses ” but were bound “ to continue the nomadic life.” And obviously, where the transition to a settled state is effected, the survival of habits and sentiments esta- blished during the nomadic state, must long prevent posses- sion of land by individuals. Moreover, apart from opposing ideas and customs, there are physical difficulties in the way. Even did any member of a pastoral horde which had become partially settled, establish a claim to exclusive possession of one part of the occupied area, little advantage could be gained before there existed the means of keeping out the animals belonging to others. Common use of the greater part of the surface must long continue from mere inability to set up effectual divisions. Only small portions can at first be fenced off. Yet a further reason why land-owning by individuals, and land-owning by families, establish them- selves very slowly, is that at first each particular plot has but a temporary value. The soil is soon exhausted; t and in the absence of advanced arts of culture becomes useless. Such tribes as those of the Indian hills show us that primitive cultivators uniformly follow the practice of clearing a tract of ground, raising from it two or three crops, and then abandon- ing it : the implication being that whatever private claim had arisen, lapses, and the surface, again becoming wild, reverts to the community. Thus throughout long stages of incipient civilization, the impediments in the way of private land-ownership are great and the incentives to it small. Besides the fact that primitive men, respecting the connexion between effort expended and benefit gained, and therefore respecting the right of property in things made by labour, recognize no claim thus estab- lished by an individual to a portion of land ; and besides the fact that in the adhesion to inherited usage and the inability effectually to make bounds, there are both moral and physical obstacles to the establishment of any such individual PROPERTY. 543 monopoly ; there is the fact that throughout early stages of settled life, no motive to maintain permanent private possession of land comes into play. Manifestly, therefore, it is not from conscious assertion of any theory, or in pur- suance of any deliberate policy, that tribal and communal proprietorship of the areas occupied originate; but simply from the necessities of the case. Hence the prevalence among unrelated peoples of this public ownership of land, here and there partially qualified by temporary private ownership. Some hunting tribes of North America show us a stage in which even the com- munal possession is still vague. Concerning the Dakotas Schoolcraft says — “ Each village has a certain district of country they hunt in, but do not object to families of other villages hunting with them. Among the Dacotas, I never knew an instance of blood being shed in any disputes or difficulties on the hunting grounds.” Similarly of the Comanches, he remarks that “ no dispute ever arises between tribes with regard to their hunting grounds, the whole being held in common.” Of the semi- settled and more advanced Iroquois, Morgan tells us that — “No individual could obtain the absolute title to land, as that was vested by the laws of the Iroquois in all the people ; but he could reduce unoccupied lands to cultivation to any extent he pleased ; and so long as he continued to use them, his right to their enjoyment was pro- tected and secured.” Sundry pastoral peoples of South Africa show us the sur- vival of such arrangements under different conditions. “ The land which they [the Bechuanas] inhabit is the common pro- perty of the whole tribe, as a pasture for their herds.” “ Being entirely a pastoral people, the Damaras have no notion of permanent habitations. The whole country is considered public pro- perty. . . . There is an understanding that he who arrives first at any given locality, is the master of it as long as he chooses to remain there.” Kaffir custom “does not recognize private property in the soil beyond that of actual possession.” “No one possesses landed property ” [among the Koosas] ; “he sows his corn wherever he can find a convenient spot.” And various of the uncivilized, who are mainly or wholly POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. 541 agricultural, exhibit but slight modifications of this usage. Though by the New Zealanders some extra claim of the chief is recognized, yet “ all free persons, male and female, consti- tuting the nation, were proprietors of the soil: ,, there is a qualified proprietorship of land, obtained by cultivation, which does not destroy the proprietorship of the nation or tribe. In Sumatra, cultivation gives temporary ownership but nothing more. We read that the ground “on which a man plants or builds, with the consent of his neighbours, becomes a species of nominal property ” ; but when the trees which he has planted disappear in the course of nature, “ the land reverts to the public.” From a distant region may be cited an instance where the usages, though different in form, involve the same principle. Among the modern Indians of Mexico — “ Only a house-place and a garden are hereditary ; the fields belong to the village, and are cultivated every year without anything being paid for rent. A portion of the land is cultivated in common, and the pro- ceeds are devoted to the communal expenses.” This joint ownership of land, qualified by individual owner- ship only so far as circumstances and habits make it easy to mark off individual claims, leads to different modes of using the products of the soil, according as convenience dictates. Anderson tells us that in “Damara-land, the carcases of all animals — whether wild or domesticated — are considered public property.” Among the Todas — “ Whilst the land is in each case the property of the village itself, . . . the cattle which graze on it are the private property of individuals, being males. . . . The milk of the entire herd is lodged in the paltlichi, village dairy, from which each person, male and female, receives for his or her daily consumj)tion ; the unconsumed balance being divided, as personal and saleable property, amongst the male members of all ages, in proportion to the number of cattle which each possesses in the herd.” And then in some cases joint cultivation leads to a kindred system of division. “ When harvest is over,” the Congo people “ put all the kidney -beans into one heap, the Indian wheat into another, and so of other grain : then giving the Macolonte [chief] enough for his maintenance, and laying aside what they design for sowing, the rest is divided at so much to PROPERTY. 545 every cottage, according to the number of people each contains. Then all the women together till and sow the land for a new harvest.” In Europe an allied arrangement is exhibited by the southern Slavs. “ The fruits of agricultural labour are consumed in common, or divided equally among the married couples ; but the produce of each man's industrial labour belongs to him individually." Further, some of the Swiss allmends show us a partial survival of this system ; for besides lands which have become in large measure private, there are “ communal vineyards cultivated in common," and “there are also cornlands cultivated in the same manner," and “the fruit of their joint labour forms the basis of the banquets, at which all the members of the commune take part." Thus we see that communal ownership and family owner- ship at first arose and long continued because, in respect of land, no other could well be established. Eecords of the civilized show that w r ith them in the far past, as at present with the uncivilized, private possession, beginning with movables, extends itself to immovables only under certain conditions. We have evidence of this in the fact named by Mayer, that “ the Hebrew language has no expression for ‘ landed pro- perty ; ’ " and again in the fact alleged by Mommsen of the Eomans, that “ the idea of property was primarily associated not with immovable estate, but with ‘ estate in slaves and cattle.' " And if, recalling the circumstances of pastoral life, as carried on alike by Semites and Ayrans, we remember that, as before shown, the patriarchal group is a result of it ; we may understand how, in passing into the settled state, there would be produced such forms of land-tenure by the clan and the family as, with minor variations, characterized primitive European societies. It becomes comprehensible why among the Eomans “ in the earliest times, the arable land was cul- tivated in common, probably by the several clans ; each of these tilled its own land, and thereafter distributed the pro- duce among the several households belonging to it." We are shown that there naturally arose such arrangements as those 546 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of the ancient Teutonic mark — a territory held “ by a primi- tive settlement of a family or kindred,” each free male member of which had “ a right to the enjoyment of the woods, the pastures, the meadow, and the arable land of the mark but whose right was “ of the nature of usufruct or possession only,” and whose allotted private division became each season common grazing land after the crop had been taken off, while his more permanent holding was limited to his homestead and its immediate surroundings. And we may perceive how the community’s ownership might readily, as circumstances and sentiments determined, result here in an annual use of apportioned tracts, here in a periodic re-par- titioning, and here in tenures of more permanent kinds, — still subject to the supreme right of the whole public. § 539. Induction and deduction uniting to show, as they do, that at first land is common property, there presents itself the question— How did possession of it become individualized ? There can be little doubt as to the general nature of the answer. Force, in one form or other, is the sole cause adequate to make the members of a society yield up their joint claim to the area they inhabit. Such force may be that of an external aggressor or that of an internal aggressor ; but in either case it implies militant activity. The first evidence of this which meets us is that the primi- tive system of land-ownership has lingered longest where circumstances have been such as either to exclude war or to minimize it. Already I have referred to a still-extant Teutonic mark existing in Drenthe, “ surrounded on all sides by marsh and bog,” forming “ a kind of island of sand and heath and this example, before named as showing the sur- vival of free judicial institutions where free institutions at large survive, simultaneously shows the communal land- ownership which continues while men are unsubordinated. After this typical case may be named one not far distant, and somewhat akin — that, namely, which occurs “in the PROPERTY. 547 sandy district of the Campine and beyond the Meuse, in the Ardennes region,” where there is great “ want of commu- nication the implied difficulty of access and the poverty of surface making relatively small the temptation to invade. So that while, says Laveleye, “ except in the Ardennes, the lord had succeeded in usurping the eminent domain, without however destroying the inhabitants’ rights of user,” in the Ardennes itself, the primitive communal possession survived. Other cases show that the mountainous character of a locality, rendering subjugation by external or internal force impracticable, furthers maintenance of this primitive institution, as of other primitive institutions. In Switzerland, and especially in its Alpine parts, the allmends above men- tioned, which are of the same essential nature as the Teutonic marks, have continued down to the present day. Sundry kindred regions present kindred facts. Ownership of land by family-communities is still to be found “ in the hill-districts of Lombardy.” In the poverty-stricken and mountainous por- tion of Auvergne, as also in the hilly and infertile depart- ment of Nievre, there are still, or recently have been, these original joint-ownerships of land. And the general remark concerning the physical circumstances in which they occur, is that Ci it is to the wildest and most remote spots that we must go in search of them” — a truth again illustrated “ in the small islands of Hcedic and Honat, situated not far from Belle Isle ” on the French coast, and also in our own islands of Orkney and Shetland. Contrariwise, we find that directly by invasion, and in- directly by the chronic resistance to invasion which gene- rates those class-inequalities distinguishing the militant type, there is produced individualization of land-ownership, in one or other form. All the world over, conquest gives a posses- sion that is unlimited because there is no power to dispute it. Along with other spoils of war, the land becomes a spoil ; and, according to the nature of the conquering society, is owned wholly by the despotic conqueror, or, partially and in 548 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. dependent ways, by his followers. Of the first result there are many instances. “ The kings of Abyssinia are above all laws . . . the land and persons of their subjects are equally their property.” “ In Kongo the king hath the sole property of goods and lands, which he can grant away at pleasure.” And § 479 contains sundry other examples of militant socie- ties in which the monarch, otherwise absolute, is absolute possessor of the soil. Of the second result instances were given in § 458 ; and I may here add some others. Ancient Mexico supplies one. “ Montezuma possessed in most of the villages . . . and especially in those he had conquered, fiefs which he distributed among those called 6 the gallant fellows of Mexico.’ These were men who had distinguished themselves in war.” Under a more primitive form the like was done in Iceland by the invading Norsemen. “ When a chieftain had taken possession of a district, he allotted to each of the freemen who accompanied him a certain portion of land, erected a temple (hof), and became, as he had been in Norway, the chief, the pontiff, and the judge of the herad.” But, as was shown when treating of political differentia- tion, it is not only by external aggressors that the joint pos- session by all freemen of the area they inhabit is over-ridden. It is over-ridden, also, by those internal aggressors whose power becomes great in proportion as the militancy of the society becomes chronic. With the personal subordination generated by warfare, there goes such subordination of owner- ship, that lands previously held absolutely by the community, come to be held subject to the claims of the local magnate ; until, in course of time, the greater part of the occupied area falls into his exclusive possession, and only a small part con- tinues to be common property. To complete the statement it must be added that occasion- ally, though rarely, the passing of land into private hands takes place neither by forcible appropriation, nor by the gra- dual encroachment of a superior, but by general agreement. Where there exists that form of communal ownership under PROPERTY. 549 which joint cultivation is replaced by separate cultivation of parts portioned out — where there results from this a system of periodic redistribution, as of old in certain Greek states, as among the ancient Suevi, and as even down to our own times in some of the Swiss allmends ; ownership of land by indi- viduals may and does arise from cessation of the redistribu- tion. Says M. de Laveleye concerning the Swiss allmends — “in the work of M. Rowalewsky, we see how the communal lands became private property by the periodic partitioning becoming more and more rare, and finally falling into desuetude.’* When not otherwise destroyed, land-owning by the commune tends naturally to end in this way. For besides the inconveniences attendant on re-localization of the mem- bers of the commune, positive losses must be entailed by it on many. Out of the whole number, the less skilful and less diligent will have reduced their plots to lower degrees of fertility ; and the rest will have a motive for opposing a re- distribution which, depriving them of the benefits of past labours, makes over these or parts of them to the relatively unworthy. Evidently this motive is likely, in course of time, to cause refusal to re-divide; and permanent private possession will result. § 540. An important factor not yet noticed has cooperated in individualizing property, both movable and fixed ; namely, the establishment of measures of quantity and value. Only the rudest balancing of claims can be made before there come into use appliances for estimating amounts. At the outset, ownership exists only in respect of things actually made or obtained by the labour of the owner; and is therefore nar- rowly limited in range. But when exchange arises and spreads, first under the indefinite form of barter and then under the definite form of sale and purchase by means of a circulating medium, it becomes easy for ownership to extend itself to other things. Observe how clearly this extension depends on the implied progress of industrialism. 550 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. It was pointed out in § 319 that during the pastoral stage, it is impracticable to assign to each member of the family- community, or to each of its dependents, such part of the pro- duce or other property as is proportionate to the value of his labour. Though in the case of J acob and Laban the bargain made for services was one into which some idea of equiva- lence entered, yet it was an extremely rude idea ; and by no such bargains could numerous transactions, or transactions of smaller kinds, be effected. On asking what must happen when the patriarchal group, becoming settled, assumes one or other enlarged form, we see that reverence for traditional usages, and the necessity of union for mutual defence, con- spire to maintain the system of joint production and joint consumption : individualization of property is still hindered. Though under such conditions each person establishes private ownership in respect of things on which he has expended separate labour, or things received in exchange for such products of his separate labour ; yet only a small amount of property thus distinguished as private, can be acquired. The greater part of his labour, mixed with that of others, brings returns inseparable from the returns of their labours ; and the united returns must therefore be enjoyed in common. But as fast as it becomes safer to dispense with the protection of the family-group ; and as fast as increasing commercial inter- course opens careers for those who leave their groups ; and as fast as the use of money and measures gives definiteness to exchanges ; there come opportunities for accumulating indi- vidual possessions, as distinguished from joint possessions. And since among those who labour together and live together, there will inevitably be some who feel restive under the imposed restraints, and also some (usually the same) who feel dissatisfied with the equal sharing among those whose labours are not of equal values ; it is inferable that these opportunities will be seized : private ownership will spread at the expense of public ownership. Some illustrations may be given. Speaking of the family-communities of the PKOPERTY. 551 Southern Slavs, mostly in course of dissolution, M. de Laveleye says — “ The family-group was far more capable of defending itself against the severity of Turkish rule than were isolated individuals. Accordingly, it is in this part of the southern Slav district that family-communities are best preserved, and still form the basis of social order.” The influence of commercial activity as conducing to dis- integration, is shown by the fact that these family-commu- nities ordinarily hold together only in rural districts. “ In the neighbourhood of the towns the more varied life has weakened the ancient family-sentiment. Many communities have been dissolved, their property divided and sold, and their members have degenerated into mere tenants and proletarians.” And then the effect of a desire, alike for personal independ- ence and for the exclusive enjoyment of benefits consequent on superiority, is recognized in the remark that these family- communities— u cannot easily withstand the conditions of a society in which men are striving to improve their own lot, as well as the political and social organization under which they live. . . . Once the desire of self -aggran- disement awakened, man can no longer support the yoke of the zadruga. ... To live according to his own will, to work for himself alone, to drink from his own cup, is now the end preeminently sought.” That this cause of disintegration is general, is implied by passages concerning similar communities still existing in the hill-districts of Lombardy — that is, away from the centres of mercantile activity. Growing averse to the control of the house-fathers, the members of these communities say — “ ‘ Why should we and all our belongings remain in subjection to a master ? It were far the best for each to work and think for himself. As the profits derived from any handicraft form a sort of private peculium , the associates are tempted to enlarge this at the expense of the common revenue.” And then “ the craving to live independently carries him away, and he quits the community.” All which evidence shows that the progress of industrialism is the general cause of this growing individualization of pro- perty ; for such progress is pre-supposed alike by the greater security which makes it safe to live separately, by the in- 552 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. creased opportunity for those sales which further the accu- mulation of a peculium , and by the use of measures of quantity and value : these being implied primarily by such sales, and secondarily by the sale and division of all that has been held in common. Spread of private ownership, which thus goes along with decay of the system of status and growth of the system of contract, naturally passes on from movable property to fixed property. For when the multiplication of trading transactions has made it possible for each member of a family-community to accumulate a peculium ; and when the strengthening desire for individual domestic life has im- pelled the majority of the community to sell the land which they have jointly inherited ; the several portions of it, whether sold to separate members of the body or to strangers, are thus reduced by definite agreement to the form of indi- vidual properties; and private ownership of land thereby acquires a character apparently like that of other private ownership. In other ways, too, this result is furthered by developing industrialism. If, omitting as not relevant the cases in which the absolute ruler allows no rights of pro- perty, landed or other, to his subjects, we pass to the cases in which a conqueror recognizes a partial ownership of land by those to whom he has parcelled it out on condition of render- ing services and paying dues, we see that the private land- ownership established by militancy is an incomplete one. It has various incompletenesses. The ownership by the suzerain is qualified by the rights he has made over to his vassals ; the rights of the vassals are qualified by the conditions of their tenure ; and they are further qualified by the claims of serfs and other dependents, who, while bound to specified services, have specified shares of produce. But with the decline of militancy and concomitant disappearance of vassal- age, the obligations of the tenure diminish and finally almost lapse out of recognition ; while, simultaneously, abolition of serfdom destroys or obscures the other claims which qualified PROPERTY. 553 private land-ownership.* As both changes are accompani- ments of a developing industrialism, it follows that in these ways also, the individualization of property in land is furthered by it. At first sight it seems fairly inferable that the absolute ownership of land by private persons, must be the ultimate state which industrialism brings about. But though indus- trialism has thus far tended to individualize possession of land, while individualizing all other possession, it may be doubted whether the final stage is at present reached. Ownership established by force does not stand on the same footing as ownership established by contract ; and though multiplied sales and purchases, treating the two ownerships in the same way, have tacitly assimilated them, the assimi- lation may eventually be denied. The analogy furnished by assumed rights of possession over human beings, helps us to recognize this possibility. For while prisoners of war, taken by force and held as property in a vague way (being at first much on a footing with other members of a household), -were reduced more definitely to the form of property when the buying and selling of slaves became general ; and while it might, centuries ago, have been thence inferred that the ownership of man by man was an ownership in course of being permanently established ; yet we see that a later stage of civilization, reversing this process, has destroyed owner- ship of man by man. Similarly, at a stage still more advanced it may be that private ownership of land will disappear. As that primitive freedom of the individual which existed before war established coercive institutions and personal slavery, comes to be re-established as militancy declines ; so it seems possible that the primitive ownership of land by the com- munity, which, with the development of coercive institutions, lapsed in large measure or wholly into private ownership, will * In our own case the definite ending of these tenures took place in 1660 ; when, for feudal obligations (a burden on landowners) was substituted a beer-excise (a burden on the community). 554 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. be revived as industrialism further develops. The regime of contract, at present so far extended that the right of property in movables is recognized only as having arisen by exchange of services or products under agreements, or by gift from those who had acquired it under such agreements, may be further extended so far that the products of the soil will be recog- nized as property only by virtue of agreements between indi- viduals as tenants and the community as landowner. Even now, among ourselves, private ownership of land is not abso- lute. In legal theory landowners are directly or indirectly tenants of the Crown (which in our day is equivalent to the State, or, in other words, the Community); and the Community from time to time resumes possession after making due com- pensation. Perhaps the right of the Community to the land, thus tacitly asserted, will in time to come be overtly asserted ; and acted upon after making full allowance for the accumulated value artificially given. § 541. The rise and development of arrangements which fix and regulate private possession, thus admit of tolerably clear delineation. The desire to appropriate, and to keep that which has been appropriated, lies deep, not in human nature only, but in animal nature : being, indeed, a condition to survival. The consciousness that conflict, and consequent injury, may pro- bably result from the endeavour to take that which is held by another, ever tends to establish and strengthen the custom of leaving each in possession of whatever he has obtained by labour ; and this custom takes among primitive men the shape of an overtly-admitted claim. This claim to private ownership, fully recognized in respect of movables made by the possessor, and fully or partially recognized in respect of game killed on the territory over which members of the community wander, is not recognized in respect of this territory itself, or tracts of it. Property is individualized as far as circumstances allow individual claims PROPERTY. 555 to be marked off with some definiteness ; but it is not indi- vidualized in respect of land, because, under the conditions, no individual claims can be shown, or could be effectually marked off were they shown. With the passage from a nomadic to a settled state, owner- ship of land by the community becomes qualified by indi- vidual ownership; but only to the extent that those who clear and cultivate portions of the surface have undisturbed enjoyment of its produce. Habitually the public claim sur- vives ; and either when, after a few crops, the cleared tract is abandoned, or when, after transmission to descendants, it has ceased to be used by them, it reverts to the community. And this system of temporary ownership, congruous with the sentiments and usages inherited from ancestral nomads, is associated also with an undeveloped agriculture : land becoming exhausted after a few years. Where the patriarchal form of organization has been carried from the pastoral state into the settled state, and, sanctified by tradition, is also maintained for purposes of mutual protection, possession of land partly by the clan and partly by the family, long continues ; at the same time that there is separate possession of things produced by separate labour. And while in some cases the communal land- ownership, or family land-ownership, survives, it in other cases yields in various modes and degrees to qualified forms of private ownership, mostly temporary, and subject to supreme ownership by the public. But war, both by producing class-differentiations within each society, and by effecting the subjugation of one society by another, undermines or destroys communal proprietorship of land ; and partly or wholly substitutes for it, either the unqualified proprietorship of an absolute conqueror, or pro- prietorship by a conqueror qualified by the claims of vassals holding it under certain conditions, while their claims are in turn qualified by those of dependents attached to the soil. That is to say, the system of status which militancy develops, 15 556 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. involves a graduated ownership of land as it does a graduated ownership of persons. Complete individualization of ownership is an accompani- ment of industrial progress. From the beginning, things identified as products of a man's own labour are recognized as his ; and throughout the course of civilization, communal possession and joint household living, have not excluded the recognition of a peculium obtained by individual effort. Accu- mulation of movables privately possessed, arising in this way, increases as militancy is restrained by growing industrialism ; because this pre-supposes greater facility for disposing of industrial products ; because there come along with it measures of quantity and value, furthering exchange ; and because the more pacific relations implied, render it safer for men to detach themselves from the groups in which they previously kept together for mutual protection. The indi- vidualization of ownership, extended and made more definite by trading transactions under contract, eventually affects the ownership of land. Bought and sold by measure and for money, land is assimilated in this respect to the personal property produced by labour ; and thus becomes, in the general apprehension, confounded with it. But there is reason to suspect that while private possession of things pro- duced by labour, will grow even more definite and sacred than at present ; the inhabited area, which cannot be produced by labour, will eventually be distinguished as something which may not be privately possessed. As the individual, primitively owner of himself, partially or wholly loses ownership of him- self during the militant regime , but gradually resumes it as the industrial regime develops ; so, possibly, the communal proprietorship of land, partially or wholly merged in the ownership of dominant men during evolution of the militant type, will be resumed as the industrial type becomes fully- evolved. CHAPTER XVI. EEYENUE. § 542. P>roadly dividing the products of men’s labours into the part which remains with them for private purposes and the part taken from them for public purposes ; and recog- nizing the truism that the revenue constituted by this last part must increase with the development of the public organi- zation supported by it ; we may be prepared for the fact that in early stages of social evolution, nothing answering to revenue exists. The political head being at first distinguished from other members of the community merely by some personal supe- riority, his power, often recognized only during war, is, if recognized at other times, so slight as to bring him no mate- rial advantage. Habitually in rude tribes he provides for himself as a private man. Sometimes, indeed, instead of gaining by his distinction he loses by it. Among the Dako- tas “ the civil-chiefs and war-chiefs are distinguished from the rest by their poverty. They generally are poorer clad than any of the rest.” A statement concerning the Abipones shows us why this occasionally happens. “ The cacique has nothing, either in his arms or his clothes, to distin- guish him from a common man, except the peculiar oldness and shabbi- ness of them ; for if he appears in the streets with new and handsome apparel, . . . the first person he meets will boldly cry, Give me that dress . . . and unless he immediately parts with it, he becomes the scoff and the scorn of all, and hears himself called covetous.” Among the Patagonians the burdens entailed by relieving and protecting inferiors, lead to abdication. Many “bora 558 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Caciques refuse to have any vassals ; as they cost them dear, and yield but little profit.” Generally, however, and always where war increases his predominance, the leading warrior begins to be distinguished by wealth accruing to him in sundry ways. The superiority which gains him supremacy, implying as it mostly does greater skill and energy, conduces to accumulation : not uncommonly, as we have seen, (§ 472) the primitive chief is also the rich man. And this possession of much private property grows into a conspicuous attribute when, in the settled state, land held by the community begins to be appro- priated by its more powerful members. Eulers habitually become large landowners. In ancient Egypt there were royal lands. Of the primitive Greek king we read that “ an ample domain is assigned to him [? taken by him] as an appur- tenance of his lofty position.” And among other peoples in later times, we find the monarch owning great estates. The income hence derived, continues to the last to represent that revenue which the political head originally had, when he began to be marked off from the rest only by some personal merit. Such larger amount of private means as thus usually dis- tinguishes the head man at the outset, augments as successful war, increasing his predominance, brings him an increasing portion of the spoils of conquered peoples. In early stages it is the custom for each warrior to keep whatever he personally takes in battle; while that which is taken jointly is in some cases equally divided. But of course the chief is apt to get an extra share ; either by actual capture, or by the willing award of his comrades, or, it may be, by forcible appropriation. And as his power grows, this forcible appropriation is yielded to, sometimes tacitly, sometimes under protest; as we are shown by the central incident in the Iliad . Through later stages his portion of plunder, reserved before division of the remainder among followers, continues to be a source of revenue. And where he becomes absolute, the property taken REVENUE. 559 from tlie vanquished, lessened only by such portions as he gives in reward for services, augments his means of sup- porting his dependents and maintaining his supremacy. To these sources of income which may be classed as inci- dental, is simultaneously added a source which is constant. When predominance of the chief has become so decided that he is feared, he begins to receive propitiatory presents; at first occasionally and afterwards periodically. Already in §§ 369-71, when treating of presents under their .ceremo- nial aspects, I have given illustrations ; and many more may be added. Describing the king among the Homeric Greeks, Grote writes — “ Moreover he receives frequent pre- sents, to avert his enmity, to conciliate his favour, or to buy olf his exactions.” So, too, of the primitive Germans, we are told by Tacitus that “ it is the custom of the states to bestow by voluntary and individual contribution on the chiefs, a present of cattle or of grain, which, while accepted as a compliment, supplies their wants.” And gifts to the ruler voluntarily made to obtain good will, or prevent ill will, continue to be a source of revenue until quite late stages. Among ourselves “ during the reign of Elizabeth, the custom of presenting Hew Year's gifts to the sovereign was carried to an extravagant height ;” and even “ in the reign of James I. the money gifts seem to have been con- tinued for some time.” Along with offerings of money and goods there go offerings of labour. Hot unfrequently in primitive communities, it is the custom for all to join in building a new house or clearing a plot of ground for one of their number : such benefits being recipro- cated. Of course the growing predominance of a political head, results in a more extensive yielding of gratuitous labour for his benefit, in these and other ways. The same motives which prompt gifts to the ruler prompt offers of help to him more than to other persons ; and thus the custom of working for him grows into a usage. We read of the village chief among the Guaranis that “his subjects cultivated for him 560 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. his plantation, and he enjoyed certain privileges on divi- sion of the spoils of the chase. Otherwise he possessed no marks of distinction/ 7 And the like practice was followed by some historic races during early stages. In ancient Rome it was “ the privilege of the king to have his fields tilled by taskwork of the burgesses/' § 543. Growth of the regular and definite out of the irre- gular and indefinite, variously exemplified in the loregoing chapters, is here again exemplified very clearly, Tor, as already said, it is from propitiatory presents and services, at first spontaneous and incidental, that there eventually come taxes specified in their amounts and times of payment. It needs but to observe how such a custom as that of making wedding-presents has acquired a partially coercive character, to understand how, when once there begins the practice of seeking the good will of the headman by a gift, this practice is apt to be established. One having gained by it, another follows his example. The more generally the example is followed the greater becomes the disadvantage to those w T ho do not follow it. Until at length all give because none dare stand conspicuous as exceptions. Of course if some repeat the presents upon such occasions as first prompted them, others have to do the like ; and at length the periodic obligation becomes so peremptory, that the gift is demanded when it is not offered. In Loango, where presents are expected from all free subjects, “ if the king thinks they do not give enough, he sends slaves to their places to take what they have/ 7 Among the Tongans, who from time to time give their king or chief “ yams, mats, gnatoo, dried fish, live birds, &c.,” the quantity is determined “ generally by the will of each individual, who will always take care to send as much as he can well afford, lest the superior chief should be offended with him, and deprive him of all that he has.” At the present time in Cashmere, at the spring festival, “ it is the custom ... for the Maharajah's servants to bring him a REVENUE. 561 nazar, a present. . . . This has now become so regulated that every one is on these days [festivals] obliged to give from a 10th to a 12th of his monthly pay. . . . The name of each is read from a list, and the amount of his nazar is marked down : those that are absent will have the sum deducted from their pay.” Traces of a like transition are seen in the fact that in ancient times crowns of gold, beginning as gifts made by dependent states to Eastern rulers, and by Boman provinces to generals or pro-consuls, became sums of money demanded as of right ; and again in the fact that in our own early history, we read of “exactions called benevo- lences.” Similarly with the labour which, at first voluntarily given to the chief, comes, as his power grows, to be compulsory. Here are some illustrations showing stages in the transition. A Kafir chief “ summons the people to cultivate his gardens, reap his crops, and make his fences ; but in this, as in other respects, he has to consult the popular will, and hence the manual labour required by the chiefs has always been of very limited duration.” In the Sandwich Islands, “ when a chief wants a house, he requires the labour of all who hold lands under him. . . . Each division of the people has a part of the house allotted by the chief in proportion to its number.” In ancient Mexico “ the personal and common service which fur- nished the water and wood required every day in the houses of the chiefs, was distributed from day to day among the villages and quar- ters.” It was the same in Yucatan : “ the whole community did the sowing for the lord, looked after the seed, and harvested what was required for him and his house.” So in the adjacent regions of Guatemala and San Salvador, “ the tribute was paid by means of the cultivation of estates.” And in Madagascar “ the whole population is liable to be employed on government work, without remuneration, and for any length of time.” Occurring among peoples unallied in blood and unlike in their stages of civilization, these facts show the natural growing up of a forced labour system such as that which existed during feudal times throughout Europe, when labour 562 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. was exacted from dependents by local rulers, and became also a form of tribute to the central ruler ; as instance the specified numbers of days’ work which, before the Revolution, had to be given by French peasants to the State under the name of corvfo. After presents freely given have passed into presents expected and finally demanded, and volunteered help has passed into exacted service, the way is open for a further step. Change from the voluntary to the compulsory, accom- panied as it necessarily is by specification of the amounts of commodities and work required, is apt to be followed eventually by substitution of money payments. Daring stages in which there has not arisen a circulating medium, the ruler, local or general, is paid his revenue in kind. In Fiji a chiefs house is supplied with daily food by his depen- dents ; and tribute is paid by the chiefs to the king “in yams, taro, pigs, fowls, native cloth, &c In Tahiti, where besides supplies derived from “ the hereditary districts of the reigning family,” there were “ requisitions made upon the people;” the food was generally brought cooked. In early European societies, too, the expected donations to the ruler continued to be made partly in goods, animals, clothes, and valuables of all kinds, long after money was in use. But the convenience both of giver and receiver prompts commutation, when the values of the presents looked for have become settled. And from kindred causes there also comes, as we have seen in a previous chapter, commutation of military services and com- mutation of labour services. No matter what its nature, that which was at first spontaneously offered, eventually becomes a definite sum taken, if need be, by force — a tax. § 544. At the same time his growing power enables the political head to enforce demands of many other kinds. European histories furnish ample proofs. Besides more settled sources of revenue, there had, in the early feudal period, been established such others as are typi- REVENUE. 563 cally illustrated by a statement concerning the Dukes of Normandy in the 12th century. They profited by escheats (lands reverting to the monarch in default of posterity of the first baron) ; by guardianships and reliefs ; by seizure of the property of deceased prelates, usurers, excommunicated per- sons, suicides, and certain criminals; and by treasure-trove. They were paid for conceded privileges ; and for confirmations of previous concessions. They received bribes when desired to do justice ; and were paid fines by those who wished to be maintained in possession of property, or to get liberty to exercise certain rights. In England, under the Norman kings, there were such other sources of revenue as composi- tions paid by heirs before taking possession ; sales of ward- ships ; sales to male heirs of rights to choose their wives ; sales of charters to towns, and subsequent re-sales of such charters ; sales of permissions to trade ; and there was also what was called “ moneyage ” — a shilling paid every three years by each hearth to induce the king not to debase the coinage. Advantage was taken of every favourable oppor- tunity for making and enforcing a demand ; as we see in such facts as that it was customary to mulct a discharged official, and that Eichard I. “ compelled his father’s servants to re- purchase their offices.” Showing us, as such illustrations do, that these arbitrary seizures and exactions are numerous and heavy in proportion as the power of the ruler is little restrained, the implication is that they reach their extreme where the social organization is typically militant. Evidence that this is so, was given in § 443 ; and in the next chapter, under another head, we shall meet with more of it. § 545. While, in the ways named in the foregoing sections, there arise direct taxes, there simultaneously arise, and insensibly diverge, the taxes eventually distinguished as indirect. These begin as demands made on those who have got considerable quantities of commodities exposed in transit, 564 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS* or on sale ; and of which parts, originally offered as presents, are subsequently seized as dues. Under other heads I have referred to the familiar fact that travellers among rude peoples make propitiatory gifts ; and by frequent recurrence the reception of these generates a claim. Narratives of recent African explorers confirm the statements of Livingstone, who describes the Portuguese traders among the Quanga people as giving largely, because “ if they did not secure the friendship of these petty chiefs, many slaves might be stolen with their loads while passing through the forests ; ” and who says of a Balonda chief that “ he seemed to regard these presents as his proper dues, and as a cargo of goods had come by Senhor Pascoal,he entered the house for the purpose of receiving his share.” Various cases show that instead of attempting to take all at the risk of a fight, the head man enters into a compromise under which part is given without a fight ; as instance the habitual arrangement with Bedouin tribes, which compound for robbery of travellers by amounts agreed upon ; or as instance the mountain Bhils of India, whose chiefs have “ seldom much revenue except plunder,” w T ho have officers “ to obtain information of unpro- tected villagers and travellers,” and who claim “ a duty on goods passing their hills : ” apparently a composition accepted when those who carry the goods are too strong to be robbed without danger. Where the protection of individuals depends mainly on family-organizations and clan-organizations, the subject as well as the stranger, undefended when away from his home, similarly becomes liable to this qualified black mail. Now to the local ruler, now to the central ruler, according to their respective powers, he yields up part of his goods, that possession of the rest may be guaranteed him, and his claims on buyers enforced. This state of things was illustrated in ancient Mexico, where — “ Of all the goods which were brought into the market, a certain portion was paid in tribute to the king, who was on his part obliged to do justice to the merchants, and to protect their property and their persons.” REVENUE. 565 We trace tlie like in the records of early European peoples. Part of the revenue of the primitive Greek king, consisted of “ the presents paid for licences to trade ” — presents which in all probability were at first portions of the commodities to be sold. At a later period in Greece there obtained a practice that had doubtless descended from this. “To these men [magistrates of markets] a certain toll or tribute was paid by all those who brought anything to sell in the market.” In western Europe indirect taxation had a kindred origin. The trader, at the mercy of the ruler whose territory he entered, had to surrender part of his merchandise in con- sideration of being allowed to pass. As feudal lords, swoop- ing down from their castles on merchants passing along neighbouring roads or navigable rivers, took by force portions of what they had, when they did not take all; so their suzerains laid hands on what they pleased of cargoes enter- ing their ports or passing their frontiers: their shares gradually becoming defined by precedent. In England, though there is no clear proof that the two tuns which the king took from wine-laden ships (wine being then the chief import) was originally an unqualified seizure ; yet, since this quantity was called “the king’s prisage” we have good reason for suspecting that it was so ; and that though, after- wards, the king’s officer gave something in return, this, being at his option, was but nominal. The very name “ customs,” eventually applied to commuted payments on imports, points back to a preceding time when this yielding up of portions of cargoes had become established by usage. Confirmation of this inference is furnished by the fact that internal traders were thus dealt with. So late as 1309 it was complained “ that the officers appointed to take articles for the king’s use in fairs and markets, took more than they ought, and made a profit of the surplus.” Speaking generally of indirect taxes, we may say that arising when the power of the ruler becomes sufficient to change gifts into exactions, they at first differ from other 566 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. exactions simply in this, that they are enforced on occasions when the subject is more than usually at the ruler's mercy ; either because he is exposing commodities for sale where they can be easily found and a share taken ; or because he is transferring them from one part of the territory to another, and can be readily stopped and a portion demanded ; or because he is bringing commodities into the territory, and can have them laid hands on at one of the few places of convenient entrance. The shares appropriated by the ruler, originally in kind, are early commuted into money where the commodities are such as, by reason of quantity or dis- tance, he cannot consume : instance the load-penny payable at the pit's mouth on each waggon-load to the old-English kings. And the claim comes to be similarly commuted in other cases, as fast as increasing trade brings a more abundant circulating medium, and a greater quantity of produced and imported commodities ; the demanded portions of which it becomes more difficult to transport and to utilize. § 546. No great advantage would be gained by here going into details. The foregoing general facts appear to be all that it is needful for us to note. From the outset the growth of revenue has, like that growth of the political headship which it accompanies, been directly or indirectly a result of war. The property of conquered enemies, at first goods, cattle, prisoners, and at a later stage, land, coming in larger share to the leading warrior, increases his predominance. To secure his good will, which it is now important to do, propitiatory presents and help in labour are given; and these, as his power further grows, become periodic and compulsory. Making him more despotic at the same time that it augments his kingdom, continuance of this process increases his ability to enforce contribu- tions, alike from his original subjects and from tributaries ; while the necessity for supplies, now to defend his kingdom, now to invade adjacent kingdoms, is ever made the plea for REVENUE. 567 increasing his demands of established kinds and for making new ones. Under stress of the alleged needs, portions of their goods are taken from subjects whenever they are ex- posed to view for purposes of exchange. And as the primitive presents of property and labour, once voluntary and variable, but becoming compulsory and periodic, are eventually com- muted into direct taxes ; so these portions of the trader’s goods which were originally given for permission to trade and then seized as of right, come eventually to be transformed into percentages of value paid as tolls and duties. But to the last as at first, and under free governments as under despotic ones, war continues to be the usual reason for imposing new taxes or increasing old ones ; at the same time that the coercive organization in past times developed by war, continues to be the means of exacting them. CHAPTER XVII. THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. § 547. Preceding chapters have prepared the way for framing conceptions of the two fundamentally-unlike kinds of political organization, proper to the militant life and the industrial life, respectively. It will be instructive here to arrange in coherent order, those traits of the militant type already incidentally marked, and to join with them various dependent traits; and in the next chapter to deal in like manner with the traits of the industrial type. During social evolution there has habitually been a min- gling of the two. But we shall find that, alike in theory and in fact, it is possible to trace with due clearness those oppo- site characters which distinguish them in their respective complete developments. Especially is the nature of the organization which accompanies chronic militancy, capable of being inferred a priori and proved a posteriori to exist in numerous cases. While the nature of the organization accompanying pure industrialism, of which at present we have little experience, will be made clear by contrast ; and such illustrations as exist of progress towards it will become recognizable. Two liabilities to error must be guarded against. We have to deal with societies compounded and re-compounded in various degrees ; and we have to deal with societies which, differing in their stages of culture, have their structures elaborated to different extents. We shall be misled, there- fore, unless our comparisons are such as take account of un- likenesses in size and in civilization. Clearly, characteristics of the militant type which admit of being displayed by a vast THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 569 nation, may not admit of being displayed by a horde of savages, though this is equally militant. Moreover, as insti- tutions take long to acquire their finished forms, it is not to be expected that all militant societies will display the organization appropriate to them in its completeness. Eather may we expect that in most cases it will be incompletely displayed. In face of these difficulties the best course will be to con- sider, first, what are the several traits which of necessity mili- tancy tends to produce; and then to observe how far these traits are conjointly shown in past and present nations distinguished by militancy. Having contemplated the society ideally organized for war, we shall be prepared to recognize in real societies the characters which war has brought about. § 548. For preserving its corporate life, a society is im- pelled to corporate action ; and the preservation of its cor- porate life is the more probable in proportion as its corporate action is the more complete. For purposes of offence and defence, the forces of individuals have to be combined ; and where every individual contributes his force, the probability of success is greatest. Numbers, natures, and circumstances being equal, it is clear that of two tribes or two larger societies, one of which unites the actions of all its capable members while the other does not, the first will ordinarily be the victor. There must be an habitual survival of commu- nities in which militant cooperation is universal. This proposition is almost a truism. But it is needful here, as a preliminary, consciously to recognize the truth that the social structure evolved by chronic militancy, is one in which all men fit for fighting act in concert against other societies. Such further actions as they carry on they can carry on separately ; but this action they must carry on jointly. § 549. A society’s power of self-preservation will be great in proportion as, besides the direct aid of all who can fight, 570 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. there is given the indirect aid of all who cannot fight. Sup- posing them otherwise similar, those communities will sur- vive in which the efforts of combatants are in the greatest degree seconded by those of non-combatants. In a purely militant society, therefore, individuals who do not bear arms have to spend their lives in furthering the maintenance of those who do. Whether, as happens at first, the non-com- batants are exclusively the women ; or whether, as happens later, the class includes enslaved captives; or whether, as happens later still, it includes serfs; the implication is the same. For if, of two societies equal in other respects, the first wholly subordinates its workers in this way, while the workers in the second are allowed to retain for themselves the produce of their labour, or more of it than is needful for maintaining them ; then, in the second, the warriors, not otherwise supported, or supported less fully than they might else be, will have partially to support themselves, and will be so much the less available for war purposes. Hence in the struggle for existence between such societies, it must usually happen that the first will vanquish the second. The social type produced by survival of the fittest, will be one in which the fighting part includes all who can bear arms and be trusted with arms, while the remaining part serves simply as a permanent commissariat. An obvious implication, of a significance to be hereafter pointed out, is that the non-combatant part, occupied in sup- porting the combatant part, cannot with advantage to the self-preserving power of the society increase beyond the limit at which it efficiently fulfils its purpose. For, otherwise, some who might be fighters are superfluous workers ; and the fighting power of the society is made less than it might be. Hence, in the militant type, the tendency is for the body of warriors to bear the largest practicable ratio to the body of workers. § 550. Given two societies of which the members are all THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 571 either warriors or those who supply the needs of warriors, and, other things equal, supremacy will he gained by that in which the efforts of all are most effectually combined. In open warfare joint action triumphs over individual action. Military history is a history of the successes of men trained to move and fight in concert. Not only must there be in the fighting part a combination such that the powers of its units may be concentrated, but there must be a combination of the subservient part with it. If the two are so separated that they can act independently, the needs of the fighting part will not be adequately met. If to be cut off from a temporary base of operations is danger- ous, still more dangerous is it to be cut off from the per- manent base of operations ; namely, that constituted by the body of non-combatants. This has to be so connected with the body of combatants that its services may be fully available. Evi- dently, therefore, development of the militant type involves a close binding of the society into a whole. As the loose group of savages yields to the solid phalanx, so, other things equal, must the society of which the parts are but feebly held together, yield to one in which they are held together by strong bonds. § 551. But in proportion as men are compelled to co- operate, their self-prompted actions are restrained. By as much as the unit becomes merged in the mass, by so much does he lose his individuality as a unit. And this leads us to note the several ways in which evolution of the militant type entails subordination of the citizen. His life is not his own, but is at the disposal of his society. So long as he remains capable of bearing arms lie has no alternative but to fight when called on ; and, where militancy is extreme, he cannot return as a vanquished man under penalty of death. Of course, with this there goes possession of such liberty only as military obligations allow. He is free to pursue his 572 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. private ends only when the tribe or nation has no need of him ; and when it has need of him, his actions from hour to hour must conform, not to his own will but to the public will. So, too, with his property. Whether, as in many cases, what he holds as private he so holds by permission only, or whether private ownership is recognized, it remains true that in the last resort he is obliged to surrender whatever is demanded for the community’s use. Briefly, then, under the militant type the individual is owned by the State. While preservation of the society is the primary end, preservation of each member is a secondary end —an end cared for chiefly as subserving the primary end. § 552. Fulfilment of these requirements, that there shall be complete corporate action, that to this end the non-com- batant part shall be occupied in providing for the combatant part, that the entire aggregate shall be strongly bound together, and that the units composing it must have their individualities in life, liberty, and property, thereby sub- ordinated, presupposes a coercive instrumentality. No such union for corporate action can be achieved without a power- ful controlling agency. On remembering the fatal results caused by division of counsels in war, or by separation into factions in face of an enemy, we see that chronic militancy tends to develop a despotism ; since, other things equal, those societies will habitually survive in which, by its aid, the corporate action is made complete. And this involves a system of centralization. The trait made familiar to us by an army, in which, under a com- mander-in-chief there are secondary commanders over large masses, and under these tertiary ones over smaller masses, and so on down to the ultimate divisions, must characterize the social organization at large. A militant society requires a regulative structure of this kind, since, otherwise, its THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 573 corporate action cannot be made most effectual. Without such grades of governing centres diffused throughout the non- combatant part as well as the combatant part, the entire forces of the aggregate cannot be promptly put forth. Unless the workers are under a control akin to that which the fighters are under, their indirect aid cannot be insured in full amount and with due quickness. And this is the form of a society characterized by status — a society, the members of which stand one towards another in successive grades of subordination. From the despot down to the slave, all are masters of those below and subjects of those above. The relation of the child to the father, of the father to some superior, and so on up to the absolute head, is one in which the individual of lower status is at the mercy of one of higher status. § 553. Otherwise described, the process of militant organi- zation is a process of regimentation, which, primarily taking place in the army, secondarily affects the whole com- munity. The first indication of this we trace in the fact everywhere visible, that the military head grows into a civil head — usually at once, and, in exceptional cases, at last, if militancy continues. Beginning as leader in war he becomes ruler in peace ; and such regulative policy as he pursues in the one sphere, he pursues, so far as conditions permit, in the other. Being, as the non-combatant part is, a permanent commis- sariat, the principle of graduated subordination is extended to it. Its members come to be directed in a way like that in which the warriors are directed — not literally, since by dis- persion of the one and concentration of the other exact paral- lelism is prevented ; but, nevertheless, similarly in principle. Labour is carried on under coercion ; and supervision spreads everywhere. To suppose that a despotic military head, daily maintain- 574 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ing regimental control in conformity with inherited traditions, will not impose on the producing classes a kindred control, is to suppose in him sentiments and ideas entirely foreign to his circumstances. § 554. The nature of the militant form of government will be further elucidated on observing that it is both positively regulative and negatively regulative. It does not simply restrain ; it also enforces. Besides telling the individual what he shall not do, it tells him what he shall do. That the government of an army is thus characterised needs no showing. Indeed, commands of the positive kind given to the soldier are more important than those of the negative kind : fighting is done under the one, while order is maintained under the other. But here it chiefly concerns us to note that not only the control of military life but also the control of civil life, is, under the militant type of govern- ment, thus characterized. There are two ways in which the ruling power may deal with the private individual. It may simply limit his activities to those which he can carry on without aggression, direct or indirect, upon others ; in which case its action is negatively regulative. Or, besides doing this, it may prescribe the how, and the where, and the when, of his activities — may force him to do things which he would not spontaneously do — may direct in greater or less detail his mode of living ; in which case its action is positively regula- tive. Under the militant type this positively regulative action is widespread and peremptory. The civilian is in a condition as much like that of the soldier as difference of occupation permits. And this is another way of expressing the truth that the fundamental principle of the militant type is compulsory co- operation. While this is obviously the principle on which the members of the combatant body act, it no less certainly must be the principle acted on throughout the non-combatant body, if military efficiency is to be great; since, otherwise. THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 575 the aid which the non-combatant body has to furnish cannot be insured. § 555. That binding together by which the units of a militant society are made into an efficient fighting structure, tends to fix the position of each in rank, in occupation, and in locality. In a graduated regulative organization there is resistance to change from a lower to a higher grade. Such change is made difficult by lack of the possessions needed for filling superior positions ; and it is made difficult by the opposition of those who already fill them, and can hold inferiors down. Preventing intrusion from below, these transmit their respec- tive places and ranks to their descendants ; and as the principle of inheritance becomes settled, the rigidity of the social structure becomes decided. Only where an “egali- tarian despotism ” reduces all subjects to the same political status — a condition of decay rather than of development — does the converse state arise. The principle of inheritance, becoming established in respect of the classes which militancy originates, and fixing the general functions of their members from generation to generation, tends eventually to fix also their special functions. Not only do men of the slave-classes and the artizan-classes succeed to their respective ranks, but they succeed to the particular occupations carried on in them. This, which is a result of the tendency towards regimentation, is ascribable primarily to the fact that a superior, requiring from each kind of worker his particular product, has an interest in replacing him at death by a capable successor ; while the worker, prompted to get aid in executing his tasks, has an interest in bringing up a son to his own occupation : the will of the son being powerless against these conspiring interests. Under the system of compulsory cooperation, therefore, the prin- ciple of inheritance, spreading through the producing organi- zation, causes a relative rigidity in this also. 576 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. A kindred effect is shown in the entailed restraints on movement from place to place. In proportion as the indi- vidual is subordinated in life, liberty, and property, to his society, it is needful that his whereabouts shall be constantly known. Obviously the relation of the soldier to his officer, and of this officer to his superior, is such that each must be ever at hand ; and where the militant type is fully developed the like holds throughout the society. The slave cannot leave his appointed abode ; the serf is tied to his allotment ; the master is not allowed to absent himself from his locality without leave. So that the corporate action, the combination, the cohesion, the regimentation, which efficient militancy necessitates, imply a structure which strongly resists change. § 556. A further trait of the militant type, naturally accompanying the last, is that organizations other than those forming parts of the State-organization, are wholly or par- tially repressed. The public combination occupying all fields, excludes private combinations. For the achievement of complete corporate action there must, as we have seen, be a centralized administration, not only throughout the combatant part but throughout the non- combatant part ; and if there exist unions of citizens which act independently, they in so far diminish the range of this centralized administration. Any structures which are not portions of the State-structure, serve more or less as limita- tions to it, and stand in the way of the required unlimited subordination. If private combinations are allowed to exist, it will be on condition of submitting to an official regulation such as greatly restrains independent action ; and since private combinations officially regulated are inevitably hin- dered from doing things not conforming to established routine, and are thus debarred from improvement, they cannot habitually thrive and grow. Obviously, indeed, such com- binations, based on the principle of voluntary cooperation, THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 577 are incongruous with social arrangements based on the prin- ciple of compulsory cooperation. Hence the militant type is characterized by the absence, or comparative rarity, of bodies of citizens associated for commercial purposes, for propagating special religious views, for achieving philan- thropic ends, &c. Private combinations of one kind, however, are congruous with the militant type — the combinations, namely, which are formed for minor defensive or offensive purposes. We have, as examples, those which constitute factions, very general in militant societies ; those which belong to the same class as primitive guilds, serving for mutual protection ; and those which take the shape of secret societies. Of such bodies it may be noted that they fulfil on a small scale ends like those which the whole society fulfils on a large scale — the ends of self-preservation, or aggression, or both. And it may be further noted that these small included societies are organized on the same principle as the large including society — the principle of compulsory cooperation. Their governments are coercive : in some cases even to the extent of killing those of their members who are disobedient. § 557. A remaining fact to be set down is that a society of the militant type tends to evolve a self-sufficient sustain- ing organization. With its political autonomy there goes what we may call an economic autonomy. Evidently if it carries on frequent wars against surrounding societies, its commercial intercourse with them must be hindered or pre- vented : exchange of commodities can go on to but a small extent between those who are continually fighting. A mili- tant society must, therefore, to the greatest degree practicable, provide internally the supplies of all articles needful for carrying on the lives of its members. Such an economic state as that which existed during early feudal times, when, as in France, “ the castles made almost all the articles used in them,” is a state evidently entailed on groups, small or 578 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. large, wliicli are in constant antagonism with surrounding groups. If there does not already exist within any group so circumstanced, an agency for producing some necessary article, inability to obtain it from without will lead to the establishment of an agency for obtaining it within. Whence it follows that the desire “ not to be dependent on foreigners ” is one appropriate to the militant type of society. So long as there is constant danger that the supplies of needful things derived from other countries will be cut off by the breaking out of hostilities, it is imperative that there shall be maintained a power of producing these supplies at home, and that to this end the required structures shall be maintained. Hence there is a manifest direct relation between militant activities and a protectionist policy. § 558. And now having observed the traits which may be expected to establish themselves by survival of the fittest during the struggle for existence among societies, let us observe how these traits are displayed in actual societies, similar in respect of their militancy but otherwise dissimilar. Of course in small primitive groups, however warlike they may be, we must not look for more than rude outlines of the structure proper to the militant type. Being loosely aggre- gated, definite arrangement of their parts can be carried but to a small extent. Still, so far as it goes, the evidence is to the point. The fact that habitually the fighting body is co- extensive with the adult male population, is so familiar that no illustrations are needed. An equally familiar fact is that the women, occupying a servile position, do all the unskilled labour and bear the burdens ; with which may be joined the fact that not unfrequently during war they carry the supplies, as in Asia among the Bhils and Khonds, as in Polynesia among the New Caledonians and Sandwich Islanders, as in America among the Comanches, Mundrucus, Patagonians : their office as forming the permanent commissariat being thus clearly shown. We see, too, that where the enslaving of THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 579 captives has arisen, these also serve to support and aid the combatant class ; acting during peace as producers and during war joining the women in attendance on the army, as among the New Zealanders, or, as among the Malagasy, being then exclusively the carriers of provisions, &c. Again, in these first stages, as in later stages, we are shown that private claims are, in the militant type, over-ridden by public claims. The life of each man is held subject to the needs of the group ; and, by implication, his freedom of action is similarly held. So, too, with his goods ; as instance the remark made of the Brazilian Indians, that personal property, recognized but to a limited extent during peace, is scarcely at all recog- nized during war ; and as instance Hearne’s statement con- cerning certain hyperborean tribes of North America when about to make war, that “ property of every kind that could be of general use now ceased to be private.” To which add the cardinal truth, once more to be repeated, that where no political subordination exists war initiates it. Tacitly or overtly a chief is temporarily acknowledged ; and he gains permanent power if war continues. From these beginnings of the militant type which small groups show us, let us pass to its developed forms as shown in larger groups. “ The army, or what is nearly synonymous, the nation of Dahome,” to quote Burton’s words, furnishes us with a good example : the excessive militancy being indicated by the fact that the royal bedroom is paved with skulls of enemies. Here the king is absolute, and is regarded as supernatural in character — he is the “ spirit and of course he is the religious head — he ordains the priests. He absorbs in himself all powers and all rights : “ by the state-law of Dahome ... all men are slaves to the king.” He “ is heir to all his subjects;” and he takes from living subjects whatever he likes. When we add that there is a frequent killing of victims to carry messages to the other world, as well as occasions on which numbers are sacrificed to supply deceased kings with attend- ants, we are shown that life, liberty, and property, are at the 580 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. entire disposal of the State as represented by its head. In both the civil and military organizations, the centres and sub- centres of control are numerous. Names, very generally given by the king and replacing surnames, change “with every rank of the holder;” and so detailed is the regimenta- tion that “the dignities seem interminable.” There are numerous sumptuary laws ; and, according to Waitz, no one wears any other clothing or weapons than what the king gives him or allows him. Under penalty of slavery or death, “ no man must alter the construction of his house, sit upon a chair, or be carried on a hammock, or drink out of a glass,” without permission of the king. The ancient Peruvian empire, gradually established by the conquering Yncas, may next be instanced. Here the ruler, divinely descended, sacred, absolute, was the centre of a system which minutely controlled all life. His headship was at once military, political, ecclesiastical, judicial; and the entire nation was composed of those who, in the capacity of soldiers, labourers, and officials, were slaves to him and his deified ancestors. Military service was obligatory on all taxable Indians who were capable ; and those of them who had served their prescribed terms, formed into reserves, had then to work under State-superintendence. The army having heads over groups of ten, fifty, a hundred, five hundred, a thousand, ten thousand, had, besides these, its superior com- manders of Ynca blood. The community at large was subject to a parallel regimentation : the inhabitants registered in groups, being under the control of officers over tens, fifties, hundreds, and so on. And through these successive grades of centres, reports ascended to the Ynca-governors of great divisions, passing on from them to the Ynca; while his orders descended “ from rank to rank till they reached the lowest.” There was an ecclesiastical organization similarly elaborate, having, for example, five classes of diviners ; and there was an organization of spies to examine and report upon the doings of the other officers. Everything was under public THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 581 inspection. There were village-officers who overlooked the ploughing, sowing, and harvesting. When there was a defi- ciency of rain, measured quantities of water were supplied by the State. All who travelled without authority were punished as vagabonds ; but for those who were authorized to travel for public purposes, there were establishments sup- plying lodging and necessaries. “ It was the duty of the decurions to see that the people were clothed and the kinds of cloth, decorations, badges, &c., to be worn by the different ranks were prescribed. Besides this regulation of external life there was regulation of domestic life. The people were required to “ dine and sup with open doors, that the judges might be able to enter freely;” and these judges had to see that the house, clothes, furniture, &c., were kept clean and in order, and the children properly disciplined : those who mis- managed their houses being flogged. Subject to this minute control, the people laboured to support this elaborate State- organization. The political, religious, and military classes were exempt from tribute ; while the labouring classes when not serving in the army, had to yield up all produce beyond that required for their bare sustenance. Of the whole empire, one-third was allotted for supporting the State, one-third for supporting the priesthood who ministered to the manes of ancestors, and the remaining third had to support the workers. Besides giving tribute by tilling the lands of the Sun and the King, the workers had to till the lands of the soldiers on duty, as well as those of incapables. And they also had to pay tribute of clothes, shoes, and arms. Of the lands on which the people maintained themselves, a tract was apportioned to each man according to the size of his family. Similarly with the produce of the flocks. Such moiety of this in each dis- trict as was not required for supplying public needs, was periodically shorn, and the wool divided by officials. These arrangements were in pursuance of the principle that “ the private property of each man was held by favour of the Ynca, and according to their laws he had no other title to it.” Thus 582 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the people, completely possessed by the State in person, pro- perty, and labour, transplanted to this or that locality as the Ynca directed, and, when not serving as soldiers, living under a discipline like that within the army, were units in a cen- tralized regimented machine, moved throughout life to the greatest practicable extent by the Ynca’s will, and to the least practicable extent by their own wills. And, naturally, along with militant organization thus carried to its ideal limit, there went an almost entire absence of any other organization. They had no money; “they neither sold clothes, nor houses, nor estates and trade was represented among them by scarcely anything more than some bartering of articles of food. So far as accounts of it show, ancient Egypt presented phenomena allied in their general, if not in their special, cha- racters. Its predominant militancy during remote unrecorded times, is sufficiently implied by the vast population of slaves who toiled to build the pyramids ; and its subsequent con- tinued militancy we are shown alike by the boasting records of its kings, and the delineations of their triumphs on its temple-walls. Along with this form of activity we have, as before, the god-descended ruler, limited in his powers only by the usages transmitted from his divine ancestors, who was at once political head, high-priest, and commander-in-chief. Under him was a centralized organization, of which the civil part was arranged in classes and sub-classes as definite as were those of the militant part. Of the four great social divi- sions — priests, soldiers, traders, and common people, beneath whom came the slaves — the first contained more than a score different orders ; the second, some half-dozen beyond those constituted by military grades ; the third, nearly a dozen ; and the fourth, a still greater number. Though within the ruling classes the castes were not so rigorously defined as to prevent change of function in successive generations, yet Herodotus and Diodorus state that industrial occupations descended from father to son : “ every particular trade and manufacture THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 583 was carried on by its own craftsmen, and none changed from one trade to another.” How elaborate was the regimentation may be judged from the detailed account of the staff of officers and workers engaged in one of their vast quarries : the numbers and kinds of functionaries paralleling those of an army. To support this highly-developed regulative organi- zation, civil, military, and sacerdotal (an organization which held exclusive possession of the land) the lower classes laboured. “ Overseers were set over the wretched people, who were urged to hard work more by the punishment of the stick than words of warning.” And whether or not official oversight included domiciliary visits, it at any rate went to the extent of taking note of each family. “ Every man was required under pain of death to give an account to the magis- trate of how he earned his livelihood.” Take, now, another ancient society, which, strongly con- trasted in sundry respects, shows us, along with habitual mili- tancy, the assumption of structural traits allied in their fundamental characters to those thus far observed. I refer to Sparta. That warfare did not among the Spartans evolve a single despotic head, while in part due to causes which, as before shown, favour the development of compound political heads, was largely due to the accident of their double king- ship : the presence of two divinely-descended chiefs pre- vented the concentration of power. But though from this cause there continued an imperfectly centralized government, the relation of this government to members of the community was substantially like that of militant governments in general. Not withstanding the serfdom, and in towns the slavery, of the Helots, and notwithstanding the political subordination of the Periceki, they all, in common with the Spartans proper, were under obligation to military service : the working func- tion of the first, and the trading function, so far as it existed, which was carried on by the second, were subordinate to the militant function, with which the third was exclusively occu- pied. And the civil divisions thus marked re-appeared in 584 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the military divisions : “ at the battle of Platea every Spartan hoplite had seven Helots, and every Perioeki hoplite one Helot to attend him.” The extent to which, by the daily military discipline, prescribed military mess, and fixed contributions of food, the individual life of the Spartan was subordinated to public demands, from seven years upwards, needs mention only to show the rigidity of the restraints which here, as elsewhere, the militant type imposes — restraints which were further shown in the prescribed age for marriage, the preven- tion of domestic life, the forbidding of industry or any money- seeking occupation, the interdict on going abroad without leave, and the authorized censorship under which his days and nights were passed. There was fully carried out in Sparta the Greek theory of society, that “ the citizen belongs neither to himself nor to his family, but to his city.” So that though in this exceptional case, chronic militancy was prevented from developing a supreme head, owning the individual citizen in body and estate, yet it developed an essentially identical relation between the community as a whole and its units. The community, exercising its power through a compound head instead of through a simple head, completely enslaved the individual. While the lives and labours of the Helots were devoted exclusively to the support of those who formed the military organization, the lives and labours of those who formed the military organization were exclusively devoted to the service of the State : they were slaves with a difference. Of modern illustrations, that furnished by Eussia will suffice. Here, again, with the wars which effected conquests and consolidations, came the development of the victorious commander into the absolute ruler, who, if not divine by alleged origin, yet acquired something like divine 'prestige. “ All men are equal before God, and the Prussians’ God is the Emperor,” says De Custine: “the supreme governor is so raised above earth, that he sees no difference between the serf and the lord.” Under the stress of Peter the Great's wars, which, as the nobles complained, took them away from their homes, “not. THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 585 as formerly, for a single campaign, but for long years,” they became “ servants of the State, without privileges, without dignity, subjected to corporal punishment, and burdened with onerous duties from which there was no escape.” “Any noble who refused to serve ['the State in the Army, the Fleet, or the Civil Administration, from boyhood to old age/] was not only deprived of his estate, as in the old times, but was declared to be a traitor, and might be condemned to capital punishment.” “ Under Peter,” says Wallace, “ all offices, civil and military,” were “ arranged in fourteen classes or ranks and he “ defined the obligations of each with microscopic minuteness. After his death the work was carried on in the same spirit, and the tendency reached its climax in the reign of Nicholas.” In the words of De Custine, “ the tchinn [the name for this organization] is a nation formed into a regiment ; it is the military system applied to all classes of society, even to those who never go to war.” With this universal regimentation in structure went a regi- mental discipline. The conduct of life was dictated to the citizens at large in the same way as to soldiers. In the reign of Peter and his successors, domestic entertainments were appointed and regulated ; the people were compelled to change their costumes ; the clergy to cut off their beards ; and even the harnessing of horses was according to pattern. Occupa- tions were controlled to the extent that “ no boyard could enter any profession, or forsake it when embraced, or retire from public to private life, or dispose of his property, or travel into any foreign country, without the permission of the Czar.” This omnipresent rule is well expressed in the close of certain rhymes, for which a military officer was sent to Siberia : — “ Tout se fait par ukase ici ; C’est par ukase que 1’on voyage, C’est par ukase que l’on rit.” Taking thus the existing barbarous society of Dahomey, formed of negroes, the extinct semi-civilized empire of the 586 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Yncas, whose subjects were remote in blood from these, the ancient Egyptian empire peopled by yet other races, the community of the Spartans, again unlike in the type of its men, and the existing Russian nation made up of Slavs and Tatars, we have before us cases in which such similarities of social structure as exist, cannot be ascribed to inheritance of a common character by the social units. The immense contrasts between the populations of these several societies, too, varying from millions at the one extreme to thousands at the other, negative the supposition that their common struc- tural traits are consequent on size. Nor can it be supposed that likenesses of conditions in respect of climate, surface, soil, flora, fauna, or likenesses of habits caused by such con- ditions, can have had anything to do with the likenesses of organization in these societies ; for their respective habitats present numerous marked unlikenesses. Such traits as they one and all exhibit, not ascribable to any other cause, must thus be ascribed to the habitual militancy characteristic of them all. The results of induction alone would go far to warrant this ascription ; and it is fully warranted by their correspondence with the results of deduction, as set forth above. § 559. Any remaining doubts must disappear on observing how continued militancy is followed by further development of the militant organization. Three illustrations will suffice. When, during Roman conquests, the tendency for the suc- cessful general to become despot, repeatedly displayed, finally took effect — when the title imperator , military in its primary meaning, became the title for the civil ruler, showing us on a higher platform that genesis of political headship out of mili- tary headship visible from the beginning — when, as usually happens, an increasingly divine character was acquired by the civil ruler, as shown in the assumption of the sacred name Augustus, as well as in the growth of an actual worship of him ; there simultaneously became more pronounced those THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 587 further traits which characterize the militant type in its developed form. Practically, if not nominally, the other powers of the State were absorbed by him. In the words of Duruy, he had — “ The right of proposing, that is, of making laws ; of receiving and trying appeals, i.e. the supreme jurisdiction ; of arresting by the tribu- nitian veto every measure and every sentence, i.e. of putting his will in opposition to the laws and magistrates ; of summoning the senate or the people and presiding over it, i.e. of directing the electoral assemblies as he thought fit. And these prerogatives he will have not for a single year but for life ; not in Rome only . . . but throughout the empire ; not shared with ten colleagues, but exercised by himself alone ; lastly, without any account to render, since he never resigns his office.” Along with these changes went an increase in the number and definiteness of social divisions. The Emperor — “ Placed between himself and the masses a multitude of people regu- larly classed by categories, and piled one above the other in such a way that this hierarchy, pressing with all its weight upon the masses under- neath, held the people and factious individuals powerless. What remained of the old patrician nobility had the foremost rank in the city; . . . below it came the senatorial nobility, half hereditary ; below that the moneyed nobility or equestrian order — three aristocracies super- posed. . . . The sons of senators formed a class intermediate between the senatorial and the equestrian order. ... In the 2nd century the senatorial families formed an hereditary nobility with privileges.” At the same time the administrative organization was greatly extended and complicated. “ Augustus created a large number of new offices, as the superintend- ence of public works, roads, aqueducts, the Tiber-bed, distribution of corn to the people. . . . He also created numerous offices of procurators for the financial administration of the empire, and in Rome there were 1,060 municipal officers.” The structural character proper to an army spread in a double way : military officers acquired civil functions and function- aries of a civil kind became partially military. The magis- trates appointed by the Emperor, tending to replace those appointed by the people, had, along with their civil authority, military authority ; and while “ under Augustus the prefects of the pretorium were only military chiefs, . . . they gradually possessed themselves of the whole civil authority, and finally 588 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. became, after tlie Emperor, the first personages in the empire.” Moreover, the governmental structures grew by incorporating bodies of functionaries who were before independent. “ In his ardour to organize everything, he aimed at regimenting the law itself, and made an official magistracy of that which had always been a free profession” To enforce the rule of this extended administration, the army was made permanent, and subjected to severe discipline. With the continued growth of the regulating and coercing organization, the drafts on producers increased ; and, as shown by extracts in a pre- vious chapter concerning the Roman regime in Egypt and in Gaul, the working part of the community was reduced more and more to the form of a permanent commissariat. In Italy the condition eventually arrived at was one in which vast tracts were “ intrusted to freedmen, whose only consideration was . . . how to extract from their labourers the greatest amount of work with the smallest quantity of food.” An example under our immediate observation may next be taken — that of the German Empire. Such traits of the militant type in Germany as were before manifest, have, since the late war, become still more manifest. The army, active and passive, including officers and attached function- aries, has been increased by about 100,000 men; and changes in 1875 and 1880, making certain reserves more available, have practically caused a further increase of like amount. Moreover, the smaller German States, having in great part surrendered the administration of their several contingents, the German army has become more consolidated ; and even the armies of Saxony, Wiirtemberg, and Bavaria, being sub- ject to Imperial supervision, have in so far ceased to be in- dependent. Instead of each year granting military supplies, as had been the practice in Prussia before the formation of the North German Confederation, the Parliament of the Empire was, in 1871 , induced to vote the required annual sum for three years thereafter ; in 1874 it did the like for the succeeding seven years ; and again in 1880 the greatly THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 589 increased amount for the augmented army was authorized for the seven years then following : steps obviously surrendering popular checks on Imperial power. Simultaneously, military officialism has been in two w 7 ays replacing civil officialism. Subaltern officers are rewarded for long services by appoint- ments to civil posts — local communes being forced to give them the preference to civilians ; and not a few members of the higher civil service, and of the universities, as well as teachers in the public schools, having served as “ volunteers of one year/’ become commissioned officers of the Landwehr. During the struggles of the so-called Kulturkampf, the eccle- siastical organization became more subordinated by the political. Priests suspended by bishops were maintained in their offices ; it was made penal for a clergyman publicly to take part against the government ; a recalcitrant bishop had his salary stopped ; the curriculum for ecclesiastics was pre- scribed by the State, and examination by State-officials re- quired ; church discipline was subjected to State-approval ; and a power of expelling rebellious clergy from the country was established. Passing to the industrial activities we may note, first, that through sundry steps, from 1873 onwards, there has been a progressive transfer of railways into the hands of the State ; so that, partly by original construction (mainly of lines for military purposes), and partly by pur- chase, three-fourths of ail Prussian railways have been made government property ; and the same percentage holds in the other German States : the aim being eventually to make them all Imperial. Trade interferences have been extended in various ways — by protectionist tariffs, by revival of the usury laws, by restrictions on Sunday labour. Through its postal service the State has assumed industrial functions — presents acceptances, receives money on bills of exchange that are due, as also on ordinary bills, which it gets receipted; and until stopped by shopkeepers’ protests, undertook to pro- cure books from publishers. Lastly there come the measures for extending, directly and indirectly, the control over popular 590 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. life. On the one hand there are the laws under which, up to the middle of last year, 224 socialist societies have been closed, 180 periodicals suppressed, 317 books, &c., forbidden; and under which sundry places have been reduced to a partial state of siege. On the other hand may be named Prince Bismarck’s scheme for re-establishing guilds (bodies which by their regulations coerce their members), and his scheme of State-insurance, by the help of which the artizan would, in a considerable degree, have his hands tied. Though these measures have not been carried in the forms proposed, yet the proposal of them sufficiently shows the general ten- dency. In all which changes we see progress towards a more integrated structure, towards increase of the militant part as compared with the industrial part, towards the replacing of civil organization by military organization, towards the strengthening of restraints over the individual and regulation of his life in greater detail.* The remaining example to be named is that furnished by our own society since the revival of military activity — a revival which has of late been so marked that our illustrated papers are, week after week, occupied with little else than scenes of warfare. Already in the first volume of The Prin- ciples of Sociology , I have pointed out many ways in which the system of compulsory cooperation characterizing the militant type, has been trenching on the system of voluntary cooperation characterizing the industrial type ; and since those passages appeared (July, 1876), other changes in the same direction have taken place. Within the military organization itself, we may note the increasing assimilation of the volunteer forces to the regular army, now going to the extent of proposing to make them available abroad, so that instead of defensive action for which they were created, they # Tliis chapter was originally published in the Contemporary Review for Sept., 1881. Since that date a further movement of German society in the same general direction has been shown by the pronounced absolutism of the imperial rescript of Jan., 1882, endorsing Prince Bismarck’s scheme of State- socialism. THE MILITANT TYPE OP SOCIETY. 591 can be used for offensive action; and we may also note that the tendency shown in the army during the past genera- tion to sink the military character whenever possible, by putting on civilian dresses, is now checked by an order to officers in garrison towns to wear their uniforms when off duty, as they do in more militant countries. Whether, since the date named, usurpations of civil functions by military men (which had in 1873-4 gone to the extent that there were 97 colonels, majors, captains, and lieutenants employed from time to time as inspectors of science and art classes) have gone further, I cannot say ; but there has been a mani- fest extension of the militant spirit and discipline among the police, who, wearing helmet-shaped hats, beginning to carry revolvers, and looking upon themselves as half soldiers, have come to speak of the people as “ civilians.” To an increasing extent the executive has been over-riding the other govern- mental agencies ; as in the Cyprus business, and as in the doings of the Indian Viceroy under secret instructions from home. In various minor ways are shown endeavours to free officialism from popular checks ; as in the desire expressed in the House of Lords that the hanging of convicts in prisons, entrusted entirely to the authorities, should have no other witnesses; and as in the advice given by the late Home Secretary (on 11th May, 1878) to the Derby Town Council, that it should not interfere with the chief constable (a mili- tary man) in his government of the force under him — a step towards centralizing local police control in the Home Office. Simultaneously we see various actual or prospective exten- sions of public agency, replacing or restraining private agency. There is the “ endowment of research,” which, already par- tially carried out by a government fund, many wish to carry further ; there is the proposed act for establishing a registra- tion of authorized teachers ; there is the bill which provides central inspection for local public libraries; there is the scheme for compulsory insurance — a scheme showing us in an instructive manner the way in which the regulating policy 592 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. extends itself : compulsory charity having generated impro- vidence, there comes compulsory insurance as a remedy for the improvidence. Other proclivities towards institutions belonging to the militant type, are seen in the increasing demand for some form of protection, and in the lamentations uttered by the “ society papers ” that duelling has gone out. Nay, even through the party which by position and function is antagonistic to militancy, we see that militant discipline is spreading ; for the caucus-system, established for the better organization of liberalism, is one which necessarily, in a greater or less degree, centralizes authority and controls individual action. Besides seeing, then, that the traits to be inferred a priori as characterizing the militant type, constantly exist in societies which are permanently militant in high degrees, we also see that in other societies increase of militant activity is followed by development of such traits. § 560. In some places I have stated, and in other places implied, that a necessary relation exists between the structure of a society and the natures of its citizens. Here it will be well to observe in detail the characters proper to, and habitually exemplified by, the members of a typically militant society. Other things equal, a society will be successful in war in proportion as its members are endowed with bodily vigour and courage. And, on the average, among conflicting societies there will be a survival and spread of those in which the physical and mental powers called for in battle, are not only most marked but also most honoured. Egyptian and Assyrian sculptures and inscriptions, show us that prowess was the thing above all others thought most worthy of record. Of the words good, just, &c., as used by 'the ancient Greeks, Grote remarks that they “ signify the man of birth, wealth, influence and daring, whose arm is strong to destroy or to protect, whatever may be the turn of his moral sentiments ; THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 593 while the opposite epithet, bad, designates the poor, lowly, and weak, from whose dispositions, be they ever so virtuous society has little to hope or to fear.” In the identification of virtue with bravery among the Eomans, we have a like im- plication. During early turbulent times throughout Europe, the knightly character, which was the honourable character, primarily included fearlessness : lacking this, good qualities were of no account ; but with this, sins of many kinds, great though they might be, were condoned. If, among antagonist groups of primitive men, some tole- rated more than others the killing of their members— if, while some always retaliated others did not ; those which did not retaliate, continually aggressed on with impunity, would either gradually disappear or have to take refuge in unde- sirable habitats. Hence there is a survival of the unfor- giving. Further, the lex tcdionis , primarily arising between antagonist groups, becomes the law within the group ; and chronic feuds between component families and clans, every- where proceed upon the general principle of life for life. Under the militant regime revenge becomes a virtue, and failure to revenge a disgrace. Among the Fijians, who foster anger in their children, it is not infrequent for a man to commit suicide rather than live under an insult; and in other cases the dying Fijian bequeathes the duty of inflicting vengeance to his children. This sentiment and the resulting practices we trace among peoples otherwise wholly alien, who are, or have been, actively militant. In the remote East may be instanced the Japanese. They are taught that “with the slayer of his father a man may not live under the same heaven ; against the slayer of his brother a man must never have to go home to fetch a weapon ; with the slayer of his friend a man may not live in the same State.” And in the West may be instanced France during feudal days, when the relations of one killed or injured were required by custom to retaliate on any relations of the offender — even those living at a distance and knowing nothing of the matter. Down to 594 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the time of the Abbe Brantome, the spirit was such that that ecclesiastic, enjoining on his nephews by his will to avenge any unredressed wrongs done to him in his old age, says of himself — “ I may boast, and I thank God for it, that I never received an injury without being revenged on the author of it. 9 ' That where militancy is active, revenge, private as well as public, becomes a duty, is well shown at the present time among the Montenegrins — a people who have been at war with the Turks for centuries. “ Dans le Montenegro,’ 9 says Boue, “ on dira d’un homme d’une natrie [clan] ayant tue un individu d 9 une autre : Cette natrie nous doit une tete, et il faut que cette dette soit acquittee, car qui ne se venge pas ne se sancitie pas.” Where activity in destroying enemies is chronic, destruc- tion will become a source of pleasure ; where success in sub- duing fellow-men is above all things honoured, there will arise delight in the forcible exercise of mastery; and with pride in spoiling the vanquished, will go disregard for the rights of property at large. As it is incredible that men should be courageous in face of foes and cowardly in face of friends, so it is incredible that the other feelings fostered by perpetual conflicts abroad should not come into play at home. We have just seen that with the pursuit of vengeance outside the society, there goes the pursuit of ven- geance inside the society; and whatever other habits of thought and action constant war necessitates, must show their effects on the social life at large. Facts from various places and times prove that in militant communities the claims to life, liberty, and property, are little regarded. The Dahomans, warlike to the extent that both sexes are warriors, and by whom slave-hunting invasions are, or were, annually undertaken “ to furnish funds for the royal exchequer, 99 show their bloodthirstiness by their annual “ customs, 99 at which multitudinous victims are publicly slaughtered for the popu- lar gratification. The Fijians, again, highly militant in their activities and type of organization, who display their reckless- THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 595 ness of life not only by killing their own people for cannibal feasts, but by destroying immense numbers of their infants and by sacrificing victims on such trivial occasions as launch- ing a new canoe, so much applaud ferocity that to commit a murder is a glory. Early records of Asiatics and Europeans show us the like relation. What accounts there are of the primitive Mongols, who, when united, massacred western peoples wholesale, show us a chronic reign of violence, both within and without their tribes ; while domestic assassina- tions, which from the beginning have characterized the mili- tant Turks, continue to characterize them down to our own day. In proof that it was so with the Greek and Latin races it suffices to instance the slaughter of the two thousand helots by the Spartans, whose brutality was habitual, and the murder of large numbers of suspected citizens by jealous Eoman emperors, who also, like their subjects, manifested their love of bloodshed in their arenas. That where life is little regarded there can be but little regard for liberty, follows necessarily. Those who do not hesitate to end another’s activities by killing him, will still less hesitate to restrain his activities by holding him in bondage. Militant savages, wdiose captives, when not eaten, are enslaved, habitually show us this absence of regard for fellow-men’s freedom, which characterizes the members of militant societies in general. How little, under the regime of war, more or less markedly displayed in all early historic societies, there was any sen- timent against depriving men of their liberties, is suffi- ciently shown by the fact that even in the teachings of primitive Christianity there was no express condemnation of slavery. Naturally the like holds with the right of property. Where mastery established by force is honourable, claims to possession by the weaker are likely to be little respected by the stronger. In Fiji it is considered chief-like to seize a subject’s goods; and theft is virtuous if undis- covered. Among the Spartans “ the ingenious and success- ful pilferer gained applause with his booty.” In mediaeval 596 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Europe, with perpetual robberies of one society by another there went perpetual robberies within each society. Under the Merovingians “the murders and crimes it [The Ecclesias- tical History of the Franks ] relates, have almost all for their object the possession of the treasure of the murdered per- sons.’' And under Charlemagne plunder by officials was chronic : the moment his back was turned, “ the provosts of the king appropriated the funds intended to furnish food and clothing for the artisans." ( Where warfare is habitual, and the required qualities most needful and therefore most honoured, those whose lives do not display them are treated with contempt, and their occupations regarded as dishonourable. In early stages labour is the business of women and of slaves — conquered men and the descendants of conquered men ; and trade of every kind, carried on by subject classes, long continues to be identified with lowness of origin and nature. In Dahomey, “ agricul- ture is despised because slaves are employed in it." “ The Japanese nobles and placemen, even of secondary rank, entertain a sovereign contempt for traffic." Of the ancient Egyptians Wilkinson says, “ their prejudices against mecha- nical employments, as far as regarded the soldier, were equally strong as in the rigid Sparta." “ For trade and commerce the [ancient] Persians were wont to express extreme con- tempt," writes Rawlinson. That progress of class-differentia- tion which accompanied the conquering wars of the Romans, was furthered by establishment of the rule that it was dis- graceful to take money for work, as also by the law forbid- ding senators and senators’ sons from engaging in speculation. And how great has been the scorn expressed by the militant classes for the trading classes throughout Europe, down to quite recent times, needs no showing. That there may be willingness to risk life for the benefit of the society, there must be much of the feeling called patriot- ism. Though the belief that it is glorious to die for one’s country cannot be regarded as essential, since mercenaries THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 597 figlit without it ; yet it is obvious that such a belief conduces greatly to success in war ; and that entire absence of it is so unfavourable to offensive and defensive action that failure and subjugation will, other things equal, be likely to result. Hence the sentiment of patriotism is habitually established by the survival of societies the members of which are most characterized by it. With this has to be united the sentiment of obedience. The possibility of that united action by which, other things equal, war is made successful, depends on the readiness of indivi- duals to subordinate their wills to the will of a commander or ruler. Loyalty is essential. In early stages the manifes- tation of it is but temporary ; as among the Araucanians who, ordinarily showing themselves “ repugnant to all subordina- tion, are then [when war is impending] prompt to obey, and submissive to the will of their military sovereign ” appointed for the occasion. And with development of the militant type this sentiment becomes permanent. Erskine tells us that the Fijians are intensely loyal: men buried alive in the founda- tions of a king's house, considered themselves honoured by being so sacrificed ; and the people of a slave district “ said it was their duty to become food and sacrifice for the chiefs." So in Dahomey, there is felt for the king “ a mixture of love and fear, little short of adoration." In ancient Egypt again, where “ blind obedience was the oil which caused the harmo- nious working of the machinery ” of social life, the monu- ments on every side show with wearisome iteration the daily acts of subordination — of slaves and others to the dead man, of captives to the king, of the king to the gods. Though for reasons already pointed out, chronic war did not generate in Sparta* a supreme political head, to whom there could be shown implicit obedience, yet the obedience shown to the political agency which grew up was profound : individual wills were in all things subordinate to the public will ex- pressed by the established authorities. Primitive Rome, too, though without a divinely-deseended king to whom submis- 598 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. sion could be shown, displayed great submission to an ap- pointed king, qualified only by expressions of opinion on special occasions ; and the principle of absolute obedience, slightly mitigated in the relations of the community as a whole to its ruling agency, was unmitigated within its com- ponent groups. That throughout European history, alike on small and on large scales, we see the sentiment of loyalty dominant where the militant type of structure is pronounced, is a truth that will be admitted without detailed proof. From these conspicuous traits of nature, let us turn to certain consequent traits which are less conspicuous, and which have results of less manifest kinds. Along with loyalty naturally goes faith — the two being, indeed, scarcely separable. Eeadiness to obey the commander in war, implies belief in his military abilities ; and readiness to obey him during peace, implies belief that his abilities extend to civil affairs also. Imposing on men’s imaginations, each new con- quest augments his authority. There come more frequent and more decided evidences of his regulative action over men’s lives ; and these generate the idea that his power is boundless. Unlimited confidence in governmental agency is fostered. Generations brought up under a system which con- trols all affairs, private and public, tacitly assume that affairs can only thus be controlled. Those who have experience of no other regime are unable to imagine any other regime . In such societies as that of ancient Peru, for example, wdiere, as we have seen, regimental rule was universal, there were no materials for framing the thought of an industrial life spon- taneously carried on and spontaneously regulated. By implication there results repression of individual initia- tive, and consequent lack of private enterprise. In propor- tion as an army becomes organized, it is reduced to a state in which the independent action of its members is forbidden. And in proportion as regimentation pervades the society at large, each member of it, directed or restrained at every turn, has little or no power of conducting his business otherwise THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 599 than by established routine. Slaves can do only what they are told by their masters ; their masters cannot do anything that is unusual without official permission ; and no permission is to be obtained from the local authority until superior autlio- . rities through their ascending grades have been consulted. { Hence the mental state generated is that of passive accept- ance and expectancy. Where the militant type is fully developed, everything must be done by public agencies ; not only for the reason that these occupy all spheres, but for the further reason that did they not occupy them, there would arise no other agencies : the prompting ideas and sentiments having been obliterated. ( There must be added a concomitant influence on the intel- lectual nature, which cooperates with the moral influences just named. Personal causation is alone recognized, and the conception of impersonal causation is prevented from develop- ing. The primitive man has no idea of cause in the modern sense. The only agents included in his theory of things are living persons and the ghosts of dead persons. All unusual occurrences, together with those usual ones liable to variation, he ascribes to supernatural beings. And this system of inter- pretation survives through early stages of civilization ; as we see, for example, among the Homeric Greeks, by whom wounds, deaths, and escapes in battle, were ascribed to the enmity or the aid of the gods, and by whom good and bad acts were held to be divinely prompted. Continuance and development of militant forms and activities maintain this way of thinking. ( In the first place, it indirectly hinders the discovery of causal relations. The sciences grow out of the arts — begin as generalizations of truths which practice of the arts makes manifest. In proportion as processes of production multiply in their kinds and increase in their complexities, more numerous uniformities come to be recognized ; and the ideas of necessary relation and physical cause arise and develop. Consequently, by discouraging industrial progress, militancy checks the replacing of ideas of personal agency by ideas of 600 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. impersonal agency. In the second place, it does the like by direct repression of intellectual culture. Naturally a life occupied in acquiring knowledge, like a life occupied in industry, is regarded with contempt by a people devoted to arms, j The Spartans clearly exemplified this relation in ancient times ; and it was again exemplified during feudal ages in Europe, when learning w 7 as scorned as proper only for clerks and the children of mean people. And obviously, in propor- tion as warlike activities are antagonistic to study and the spread of knowledge, they further retard that emancipation from primitive ideas which ends in recognition of natural uniformities. In the third place, and chiefly, the effect in question is produced by the conspicuous and perpetual expe- rience of personal agency which the militant regime yields. In the army, from the commander-in-chief down to the private undergoing drill, every movement is directed by a superior; and throughout the society, in proportion as its regimentation is elaborate, things are hourly seen to go thus or thus according to the regulating wills of the ruler and his subordinates. In the interpretation of social affairs, personal causation is consequently alone recognized. History comes to be made up of the doings of remarkable men ; and it is tacitly assumed that societies have been formed by them. Wholly foreign to the habit of mind as is the thought of impersonal causation, the course of social evolution is unper- ceived. The natural genesis of social structures and functions is an utterly alien conception, and appears absurd when alleged. The notion of a self-regulating social process is unintelligible. So that militancy moulds the citizen into a. form not only morally adapted but intellectually adapted— a form which cannot think away from the entailed system. § 561. In three ways, then, we are shown the character of the militant type of social organization. Observe the con- gruities which comparison of results discloses. Certain conditions, manifest a priori, have to be fulfilled by THE MILITANT TYPE OF SOCIETY. 601 a society fitted for preserving itself in presence of anta- gonist societies. To be in the highest degree efficient, the corporate action needed for preserving the corporate life must be joined in by every one. Other things equal, the fighting power will be greatest where those who cannot fight, labour exclusively to support and help those who can : an evident implication being that the working part shall be no larger than is required for these ends. The efforts of all being utilized directly or indirectly for war, will be most effectual when they are most combined ; and, besides union among the combatants, there must be such union of the non-combatants with them as renders the aid of these fully and promptly available. To satisfy these requirements, the life, the actions, and the possessions, of each individual must be held at the service of the society. This universal service, this combina- tion, and this merging of individual claims, pre-suppose a despotic controlling agency. That the will of the soldier- chief may be operative when the aggregate is large, there must be sub-centres and sub-sub-centres in descending grades, through whom orders may be conveyed and enforced, both throughout the combatant part and the non-combatant part. As the commander tells the soldier both what he shall not do and what he shall do ; so, throughout the militant community at large, the rule is both negatively regulative and positively regulative : it not only restrains, but it directs : the citizen as well as the soldier lives under a system of compulsory cooperation. Development of the militant type involves increasing rigidity, since the cohesion, the combination, the subordination, and the regulation, to which the units of a society are subjected by it, inevitably decrease their ability to change their social positions, their occupations, their locali- ties. On inspecting sundry societies, past and present, large and small, which are, or have been, characterized in high degrees by militancy, we are shown, a posteriori , that amid the dif- ferences due to race, to circumstances, and to degrees of 602 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. development, there are fundamental similarities of the kinds above inferred a priori. Modern Dahomey and Russia, as well as ancient Peru, Egypt, and Sparta, exemplify that owning of the individual by the State in life, liberty, and goods, which is proper to a social system adapted for war. And that with changes further fitting a society for warlike activities, there spread throughout it an officialism, a dictation, and a superintendence, akin to those under which soldiers live, we are shown by imperial Rome, by imperial Germany, and by England since its late aggressive activities. Lastly comes the evidence furnished by the adapted cha- racters of the men who compose militant societies. Making success in war the highest glory, they are led to identify good- ness with bravery and strength. Revenge becomes a sacred duty with them ; and acting at home on the law of retaliation which they act on abroad, they similarly, at home as abroad, are ready to sacrifice others to self : their sympathies, con- tinually deadened during war, cannot be active during peace. They must have a patriotism which regards the triumph of their society as the supreme end of action ; they must pos- sess the loyalty whence flows obedience to authority; and that they may be obedient they must have abundant faith. With faith in authority and consequent readiness to be directed, naturally goes # relatively little power of initiation. The habit of seeing everything officially controlled fosters the belief that official control is everywhere needful; while a course of life which makes personal causation familiar and negatives experience of impersonal causation, produces an inability to conceive of any social processes as carried on under self- regulating arrangements. And these traits of individual nature, needful concomitants as we see of the militant type, are those which we observe in the members of actual militant societies. CHAPTER XVIII. THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. § 562. Having nearly always to defend themselves against external enemies, while they have to carry on internally the processes of sustentation, societies, as remarked in the last chapter, habitually present us with mixtures of the structures adapted to these diverse ends. Disentanglement is not easy. According as either structure predominates it ramifies through the other : instance the fact that where the militant type is much developed, the worker, ordinarily a slave, is no more free than the soldier; while, where the industrial type is much developed, the soldier, volunteering on specified terms, acquires in so far the position of a free worker. In the one case the system of status, proper to the fighting part, pervades the working part ; while in the other the system of contract, proper to the working part, affects the fighting part. Especi- ally does the organization adapted for war obscure that adapted for industry. While, as we have seen, the militant type as theoretically constructed, is so far displayed in many societies as to leave no doubt about its essential nature, the industrial type has its traits so hidden by those of the still- dominant militant type, th^t its nature is nowhere more than very partially exemplified.) Saying thus much to exclude expectations which cannot be fulfilled, it will be well also to exclude certain probable misconceptions. In the first place, industrialism must not be confounded with industriousness. Though the members of an industrially- organized society are habitually industrious, and are, indeed, 17 604 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. when the society is a developed one, obliged to be so ; yet it must not be assumed that the industrially-organized society is one in which, of necessity, much work is done. Where the society is small, and its habitat so favourable that life may be comfortably maintained with but little exertion, the social relations which characterize the industrial type may co- exist with but very moderate productive activities. It is not the diligence of its members which constitutes the society an industrial one in the sense here intended, but the form of cooperation under which their labours, small or great in amount, are carried on. This distinction will be best under- stood on observing that, conversely, there may be, and often is, great industry in societies framed on the militant type. In ancient Egypt there was an immense labouring population and a large supply of commodities, numerous in their kinds, produced by it. Still more did ancient Peru exhibit a vast community purely militant in its structure, the members of which worked unceasingly. We are here concerned, then, not with the quantity of labour but with the mode of organi- zation of the labourers. A regiment of soldiers can be set to construct earth- works; another to cut down wood; another to bring in water ; but they are not thereby reduced for the time being to an industrial society. The united individuals do these several things under command; and having no private claims to the products, are, though industrially oc- cupied, not industrially organized. And the same holds throughout the militant society as a whole, in proportion as the regimentation of it approaches completeness. The industrial type of society, properly so called, must also be distinguished from a type very likely to be con- founded with it — the type, namely, in which the component individuals, while exclusively occupied in production and distribution, are under a regulation such as that advocated by socialists and communists. For this, too, involves in another form the principle of compulsory cooperation. Directly or indirectly, individuals are to be prevented from THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 605 severally and independently occupying themselves as they please ; are to be prevented from competing with one another in supplying goods for money; are to be prevented from hiring themselves out on such terms as they think fit. There can be no artificial system for regulating labour which does not interfere with the natural system. To such extent as men are debarred from making whatever engagements they like, they are to that extent working under dictation. No matter in what way the controlling agency is constituted, it stands towards those controlled in the same relation as does the controlling agency of a militant society. And how truly the regime which those who declaim against competition would establish, is thus characterized, we see both in the fact that communistic forms of organization existed in early societies which were predominantly warlike, and in the fact that at the present time communistic projects chiefly originate among, and are most favoured by, the more warlike societies. A further preliminary explanation may be needful. The structures proper to the industrial type of society must not be looked for in distinct forms when they first appear. Con- trariwise, we must expect them to begin in vague unsettled forms. Arising, as they do, by modification of pre-existing structures, they are necessarily long in losing all trace of these. For example, transition from the state in which the labourer, owned like a beast, is maintained that he may work exclusively for his master's benefit, to the condition in which he is completely detached from master, soil, and locality, and free to work anywhere and for anyone, is through gradations. Again, the change from the arrangement proper to militancy, under which subject-persons receive, in addition to main- tenance, occasional presents, to the arrangement under which, in place of both, they received fixed wages, or salaries, or fees, goes on slowly and unobtrusively. Once more it is observable that the process of exchange, originally indefinite, has become definite only where industrialism is considerably developed. Barter began, not with a distinct intention of 606 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. giving one thing for another thing equivalent in value, but it began by making a present and receiving a present in return; and even now in the East there continue traces of this primitive transaction. In Cairo the purchase of articles from a shopkeeper is preceded by his offer of coffee and cigarettes; and during the negotiation which ends in the engagement of a dahabeah , the dragoman brings gifts and expects to receive them. Add to which that there exists under such conditions none of that definite equivalence which characterizes ex- change among ourselves : prices are not fixed, but vary widely with every fresh transaction. So that throughout our interpretations we must keep in view the truth, that the structures and functions proper to the industrial type dis- tinguish themselves but gradually from those proper to the militant type. Having thus prepared the way, let us now consider what are, a priori , the traits of that social organization wdiich, entirely unfitted for carrying on defence against external enemies, is exclusively fitted for maintaining the life of the society by subserving the lives of its units. As before in treating of the militant type, so here in treating of the indus- trial type, we will consider first its ideal form. § 563. While corporate action is the primary requirement in a society which has to preserve itself in presence of hostile societies, conversely, in the absence of hostile societies, corporate action is no longer the primary requirement. The continued existence of a society implies, first, that it shall not be destroyed bodily by foreign foes, and implies, second, that it shall not be destroyed in detail by failure of its members to support and propagate themselves. If danger of destruction from the first cause ceases, there remains only danger of destruction from the second cause. Sustentation of the society will now 7 be achieved by the self-sustentation and multiplication of its units. If his own welfare and the welfare of his offspring is fully achieved by each, the welfare THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 607 of the society is by implication achieved. Comparatively little corporate activity is now required. Each man may maintain himself by labour, may exchange his products for the products of others, may give aid and receive payment, may enter into this or that combination for carrying on an undertaking, small or great, without the direction of the society as a whole. The remaining end to be achieved by public action is to keep private actions within due bounds ; and the amount of public action needed for this becomes small in proportion as private actions become duly self- bounded. So that whereas in the militant type the demand for cor- porate action is intrinsic, such demand for corporate action as continues in the industrial type is mainly extrinsic — is called for by those aggressive traits of human nature which chronic warfare has fostered, and may gradually diminish as, under enduring peaceful life, these decrease. § 564. In a society organized for militant action, the indi- viduality of each member has to be so subordinated in life, liberty, and property, that he is largely, or completely, owned by the State ; but in a society industrially organized, no such subordination of the individual is called for. There remain no occasions on which he is required to risk his life while destroying the lives of others ; he is not forced to leave his occupation and submit to a commanding officer; and it ceases to be needful that he should surrender for public purposes whatever property is demanded of him. Under the industrial regime the citizen’s individuality, instead of being sacrificed by the society, has to be defended by the society. Defence of his individuality becomes the society’s essential duty. That after external protection is no longer called for, internal protection must become the cardinal function of the State, and that effectual discharge of this function must be a predominant trait of the industrial type, may be readily shown. 608 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. For it is clear that, other things equal, a society in which life, liberty, and property, are secure, and all interests justly regarded, must prosper more than one in which they are not ; and, consequently, among competing industrial societies, there must be a gradual replacing of those in which personal rights are imperfectly maintained, by those in which they are perfectly maintained. So that by survival of the fittest must be produced a social type in which individual claims, con- sidered as sacred, are trenched on by the State no further than is requisite to pay the cost of maintaining them, or rather, of arbitrating among them. For the aggressiveness of nature fostered by militancy having died out, the corporate function becomes that of deciding between those conflicting claims, the equitable adjustment of which is not obvious to the persons concerned. § 565. With the absence of need for that corporate action by which the efforts of the whole society may be utilized for war, there goes the absence of need for a despotic controlling agency. Not only is such an agency unnecessary, but it cannot exist. For since, as we see, it is an essential requirement of the industrial type, that the individuality of each man shall have the fullest play compatible with the like play of other men’s individualities, despotic control, showing itself as it must by otherwise restricting men’s individualities, is neces- sarily excluded. Indeed, by his mere presence an autocratic ruler is an aggressor on citizens. Actually or potentially exercising power not given by them, he in so far restrains their wills more than they would be restrained by mutual limitation merely. § 566. Such control as is required under the industrial type, can be exercised only by an appointed agency for ascer- taining and executing the average will; and a representative agency is the one best fitted for doing this. THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 609 Unless tlie activities of all are homogeneous in kind, which they cannot be in a developed society with its elaborate divi- sion of labour, there arises a need for conciliation of diver- gent interests; and to the end of insuring an equitable adjustment, each interest must be enabled duly to express itself. It is, indeed, supposable that the appointed agency should be a single individual. But no such single individual could arbitrate justly among numerous classes variously occu- pied, without hearing evidence : each would have to send representatives setting forth its claims. Hence the choice would lie between two systems, under one of which the representatives privately and separately stated their cases to an arbitrator on whose single judgment decisions depended ; and under the other of which these representatives stated their cases in one another’s presence, while judgments were openly determined by the general consensus. Without insist- ing on the fact that a fair balancing of class -interests is more likely to be effected by this last form of representation than by the first, it is sufficient to remark that it is more congruous with the nature of the industrial type ; since men’s indi- vidualities are in the smallest degree trenched upon. Citizens who, appointing a single ruler for a prescribed time, may have a majority of their wills traversed by his during this time, surrender their individualities in a greater degree than do those who, from their local groups, depute a number of rulers ; since these, speaking and acting under public inspec- tion and mutually restrained, habitually conform their deci- sions to the wills of the majority. § 567. The corporate life of the society being no longer in danger, and the remaining business of government being that of maintaining the conditions requisite for the highest indi- vidual life, there comes the question — What are these condi- tions ? Already they have been implied as comprehended under the administration of justice ; but so vaguely is the meaning 610 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. of this phrase commonly conceived, that a more specific state- ment must be made. J ustice then, as here to be understood, means preservation of the normal connexions between acts and results — the obtainment by each of as much benefit as his efforts are equivalent to — no more and no less. Living and working within the restraints imposed by one another’s presence, justice requires that individuals shall severally take the consequences of their conduct, neither increased nor decreased. The superior shall have the good of his superiority ; and the inferior the evil of his inferiority. A veto is there- fore put on all public action which abstracts from some men part of the advantages they have earned, and awards to other men advantages they have not earned. That from the developed industrial type of society there are excluded all forms of communistic distribution, the inevi- table trait of which is that they tend to equalize the lives of good and bad, idle and diligent, is readily proved, F or when, the struggle for existence between societies by war having ceased, there remains only the industrial struggle for existence, the final survival and spread must be on the part of those societies which produce the largest number of the best indi- viduals — individuals best adapted for life in the industrial state. Suppose two societies, otherwise equal, in one of which the supe- rior are allowed to retain, for their own benefit and the benefit of their offspring, the entire proceeds of their labour ; but in the other of which the superior have taken from them part of these proceeds for the benefit of the inferior and their offspring. Evidently the superior will thrive and multiply more in the first than in the second. A greater number of the best children will be reared in the first ; and eventually it will outgrow the second. It must not be inferred that private and voluntary aid to the inferior is negatived, but only public and enforced aid. Whatever effects the sympathies of the better for the worse spontaneously produce, cannot, of course, be interfered with ; and will, on the whole, be beneficial. For while, on the average, the better will not carry such efforts so THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 611 far as to impede their own multiplication, they will carry them far enough to mitigate the ill-fortunes of the worse with- out helping them to multiply. § 568. Otherwise regarded, this system under which the efforts of each bring neither more nor less than their natural returns, is the system of contract. We have seen that the regime of status is in all ways proper to the militant type. It is the concomitant of that graduated subordination by which the combined action of a fighting body is achieved, and which must pervade the fighting society at large to insure its corporate action. Under this regime , the relation between labour and produce is traversed by authority. As in the army, the food, clothing, &c., received by each soldier are not direct returns for work done, but are arbitrarily apportioned, while duties are arbitrarily enforced ; so throughout the rest of the militant society, the superior dictates the labour and assigns such share of the returns as he pleases. But as, with declining militancy and growing industrialism, the power and range . of authority decrease while uncontrolled action increases, the relation of contract becomes general ; and in the fully-developed industrial type it becomes universal. Under this universal relation of contract when equitably administered, there arises that adjustment of benefit to effort which the arrangements of the industrial society have to achieve. If each as producer, distributor, manager, adviser, teacher, or aider of other kind, obtains from his fellows such payment for his service as its value, determined by the demand, warrants; then there results that correct appor- tioning of reward to merit which ensures the prosperity of the superior. § 569. Again changing the point of view, we see that whereas public control in the militant type is both positively regulative and negatively regulative, in the industrial type it 612 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. is negatively regulative only. To the slave, to the soldier, or to other member of a community organized for war, authority says — “ Thou shalt do this ; thou shalt not do that/’ But to the member of the industrial community, authority gives only one of these orders — “ Thou shalt not do that.” Bor people who, carrying on their private transactions by voluntary cooperation, also voluntarily cooperate to form and support a governmental agency, are, by implication, people who authorize it to impose on their respective activities, only those restraints which they are all interested in maintaining — the restraints which check aggressions. Omitting criminals (who under the assumed conditions must be very few, if not a vanishing quantity), each citizen will wish to preserve unin- vaded his sphere of action, while not invading others’ spheres, and to retain whatever benefits are achieved within it. The very motive which prompts all to unite in upholding a public protector of their individualities, will also prompt them to unite in preventing any interference with their individuali- ties beyond that required for this end. Hence it follows that while, in the militant type, regi- mentation in the army is paralleled by centralized adminis- tration throughout the society at large ; in the industrial type, administration, becoming decentralized, is at the same time narrowed in its range. Nearly all public organizations save that for administering justice, necessarily disappear; since they have the common character that they either aggress on the citizen by dictating his actions, or by taking from him more property than is needful for protecting him, or by both. Those who are forced to send their children to this or that school, those who have, directly or indirectly, to help in sup- porting a State priesthood, those from whom rates are demanded that parish officers may administer public charity, those who are taxed to provide gratis reading for people who will not save money for library subscriptions, those whose businesses aie carried on under regulation by inspectors, those who have to pay the costs of State science-and-art-teaching. State THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 613 emigration, &c., all have their individualities trenched upon, either by compelling them to do what they would not spon- taneously do, or by taking away money which else would have furthered their private ends. Coercive arrangements of such kinds, consistent with the militant type, are inconsistent with the industrial type. § 570. With the relatively narrow range of public organi- zations, there goes, in the industrial type, a relatively wide range of private organizations. The spheres left vacant by the one are filled by the other. Several influences conspire to produce this trait. Those motives which, in the absence of that subordination necessi- tated by war, make citizens unite in asserting their indi- vidualities subject only to mutual limitations, are motives which make them unite in resisting any interference with their freedom to form such private combinations as do not involve aggression. Moreover, beginning with exchanges of goods and services under agreements between individuals, the principle of voluntary cooperation is simply carried out in a larger way by individuals who, incorporating themselves, contract with one another for jointly pursuing this or that business or function. And yet again, there is entire con- gruity between the representative constitutions of such private combinations, and that representative constitution of the public combination which we see is proper to the industrial type. The same law of organization pervades the society in general and in detail. So that an inevitable trait of the industrial type is the multiplicity and heterogeneity of asso- ciations, political, religious, commercial, professional, philan- thropic, and social, of all sizes. § 571. Two indirectly resulting traits of the industrial type must be added. The first is its relative plasticity. So long as corporate action is necessitated for national self- preservation — so long as, to effect combined defence or offence, 614 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. there is maintained that graduated subordination which ties all inferiors to superiors, as the soldier is tied to his officer — so long as there is maintained the relation of status, which tends to fix men in the positions they are severally bom to ; there is insured a comparative rigidity of social organization. But with the cessation of those needs that initiate and pre- serve the militant type of structure, and with the establish- ment of contract as the universal relation under which efforts are combined for mutual advantage, social organization loses its rigidity. No longer determined by the principle of inheri- tance, places and occupations are now determined by the principle of efficiency ; and changes of structure follow when men, not bound to prescribed functions, acquire the functions for which they have proved themselves most fit. Easily modi- fied in its arrangements, the industrial type of society is therefore one which adapts itself with facility to new require- ments. § 572. The other incidental result to be named is a ten- dency towards loss of economic autonomy. While hostile relations with adjacent societies continue, each society has to be productively self-sufficing ; but with the establishment of peaceful relations, this need for self- sufficingness ceases. As the local divisions composing one of our great nations, had, while they were at feud, to produce each for itself almost everything it required, but now per- manently at peace with one another, have become so far mutually dependent that no one of them can satisfy its wants without aid from the rest; so the great nations themselves, at present forced in large measure to maintain their economic autonomies, will become less forced to do this as war de- creases, and will gradually become necessary to one another. While, on the one hand, the facilities possessed by each for certain kinds of production, will render exchange mutually advantageous ; on the other hand, the citizens of each will, under the industrial regime , tolerate no such restraints on THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 615 their individualities as are implied by interdicts on exchange or impediments to exchange. With the spread of industrialism, therefore, the tendency is towards the breaking down of the divisions between nationalities, and the running through them of a common organization : if not under a single government, then under a federation of governments. § 573. Such being the constitution of the industrial type of society to be inferred from its requirements, we have now to inquire what evidence is furnished by actual societies that approach towards this constitution accompanies the progress of industrialism. As, during the peopling of the Earth, the struggle for ex- istence among societies, from small hordes up to great nations, has been nearly everywhere going on ; it is, as before said, not to be expected that we should readily find examples of the social type appropriate to an exclusively industrial life. Ancient records join the journals of the day in proving that thus far no civilized or semi-civilized nation has fallen into circumstances making needless all social structures for resisting aggression; and from every region travellers’ ac- counts bring evidence that almost universally among the uncivilized, hostilities between tribes are chronic. Still, a few examples exist which show, with tolerable clearness, the outline of the industrial type in its rudimentary form — the form which it assumes where culture has made but little pro- gress. We will consider these first; and then proceed to disentangle the traits distinctive of the industrial type as exhibited by large nations which have become predominantly industrial in their activities. Among the Indian hills there are many tribes belonging to different races, but alike in their ‘partially-nomadic habits. Mostly agricultural, their common practice is to cultivate a patch of ground while it yields average crops, and when it is exhausted to go elsewhere and repeat the process. They have 616 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. fled before invading peoples, and have here and there found localities in which they are able to carry on their peaceful occupations unmolested : the absence of molestation being, in somes cases, due to their ability to live in a malarious atmo- sphere which is fatal to the Aryan races. Already, under other heads, I have referred to the Bodo and to the Dhimals as wholly unmilitary, as lacking political organization, as being without slaves or social grades, and as aiding one another in their heavier undertakings ; to the Todas, who, leading tranquil lives, are “ without any of those bonds of union which man in general is induced to form from a sense of danger/’ and who settle their disputes by arbitration or by a council of five ; to the Mishmies as being unwarlike, as having but nominal chiefs, and as administering justice by an assembly ; and I have joined with these the case of a people remote in locality and race — the ancient Pueblos of North America — who, sheltering in their walled villages and fighting only when invaded, similarly united with their habitually industrial life a free form of government : “ the governor and his council are [were] annually elected by the people.” Here I may add sundry kindred examples. As described in the Indian Government Report for 1869 — 70, “the ‘ white Karens’ are of a mild and peaceful disposi- tion, . . . their chiefs are regarded as patriarchs, who have little more than a nominal authority ; ” or, as said of them by Lieut. McMahon, “ they possess neither laws nor dominant authority.” Instance, again, the “ fascinating ” Lepchas ; not industrious, but yet industrial in the sense that their social relations are of the non-militant type. Though I find nothing specific said about the system under which they live in their temporary villages ; yet the facts told us sufficiently imply its uncoercive character. They have no castes ; “ family and political feuds are alike unheard of amongst them;” “ they are averse to soldiering ; ” they prefer taking refuge in the jungle and living on wild food “ to enduring any injustice or harsh treatment ” — traits winch negative ordinary political THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 617 control. Take next the “ quiet, unoffensive ” Santals, who, while they fight if need be with infatuated bravery to resist aggression, are essentially unaggressive. These people “ are industrious cultivators, and enjoy their existence unfettered by caste.” Though, having become tributaries, there habi- tually exists in each village a head appointed by the Indian Government to be responsible for the tribute, &c. ; yet the nature of their indigenous government remains sufficiently clear. While there is a patriarch who is honoured, but who rarely interferes, “ every village has its council place, . . . where the committee assemble and discuss the affairs of the village and its inhabitants. All petty disputes, both of a civil and criminal nature, are settled there.” What little is told us of tribes living in the Shervaroy Hills is, so far as it goes, to like effect. Speaking generally of them, Shortt says they “ are essentially a timid and harmless people, addicted chiefly to pastoral and agricultural pursuits ; ” and more specifically describing one division of them, he says “ they lead peaceable lives among themselves, and any dispute that may arise is usually settled by arbitration.” Then, to show that these social traits are not peculiar to any one variety of man, but are dependent on conditions, I may recall the before-named instance of the Papuan Arafuras, who, without any divisions of rank or hereditary chieftainships, live in harmony, controlled only by the decisions of their assembled elders. In all which cases we may discern the leading traits above indicated as proper to societies not impelled to corpo- rate action by war. Strong centralized control not being required, such government as exists is exercised by a council, informally approved— a rude representative government ; class-distinctions do not exist, or are but faintly indicated — the relation of status is absent ; whatever transactions take place between individuals are by agreement ; and the func- tion which the ruling body has to perform, becomes substan- tially limited to protecting private life by settling such disputes as arise, and inflicting mild punishments for small offences. 618 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Difficulties meet us when, turning to civilized societies, we seek in them for traits of the industrial type. Consoli- dated and organized as they have all been by wars actively carried on throughout the earlier periods of their existence, and mostly continued down to recent times ; and having simultaneously been developing within themselves organiza- tions for producing and distributing commodities, which have little by little become contrasted with those proper to mili- tant activities ; the two are everywhere presented so mingled that clear separation of the first from the last is, as said at the outset, scarcely practicable. Radically opposed, however, as is compulsory cooperation, the organizing principle of the militant type, to voluntary cooperation, the organizing prin- ciple of the industrial type, we may, by observing the decline of institutions exhibiting the one, recognize, by implication, the growth of institutions exhibiting the other. Hence if, in passing from the first states of civilized nations in which war is the business of life, to states in which hostilities are but occasional, we simultaneously pass to states in which the ownership of the individual by his society is not so con- stantly and strenuously enforced, in which the subjection of rank to rank is mitigated, in which political rule is no longer autocratic, in which the regulation of citizens’ lives is dimi- nished in range and rigour, while the protection of them is increased ; we are, by implication, shown the traits of a de- veloping industrial type. Comparisons of several kinds disclose results which unite in verifying this truth. Take, first, the broad contrast between the early condition of the more civilized European nations at large, and their later condition. Setting out from the dissolution of the Roman empire, we observe that for many centuries during which conflicts were effecting consolidations, and dissolutions, and re-consolidations in endless variety, such energies as were not directly devoted to war were devoted to little else than supporting the organizations which carried on war : the working part of each community did not exist for its own THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 619 sake, but for the sake of the fighting part. While militancy was thus high and industrialism undeveloped, the reign of superior strength, continually being established by societies one over another, was equally displayed within each society. From slaves and serfs, through vassals of different grades up to dukes and kings, there was an enforced subordination by which the individualities of all were greatly restricted. And at the same time that, to carry on external aggression or resistance, the ruling power in each group sacrificed the personal claims of its members, the function of defending its members from one another was in but small degree discharged by it : they were left to defend themselves. If with these traits of European societies in mediaeval times, we com- pare their traits in modern times, we see the following essential differences. First, with the formation of nations covering large areas, the perpetual wars within each area have ceased ; and though the wars between nations which from time to time occur are on larger scales, they are less frequent, and they are no longer the business of all freemen. Second, there has grown up in each country a relatively large population which carries on production and distribution for its own maintenance ; so that whereas of old, the working part existed for the benefit of the fighting part, now the fighting part exists mainly for the benefit of the working part — exists ostensibly to protect it in the quiet pursuit of its ends. Third, the system of status, having under some of its forms disappeared and under others become greatly miti- gated, has been almost universally replaced by the system of contract. Only among those who, by choice or by conscrip- tion, are incorporated in the military organization, does the system of status in its primitive rigour still hold so long as they remain in this organization. Fourth, with this de- crease of compulsory cooperation and increase of voluntary cooperation, there have diminished or ceased many minor restraints over individual actions. Men are less tied to their localities than they were ; they are not obliged to profess 620 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. certain religious opinions ; they are less debarred from ex- pressing their political views; they no longer have their dresses and modes of living dictated to them; they are comparatively little restrained from forming private com- binations and holding meetings for one or other purpose — political, religious, social. Fifth, while the individualities of citizens are less aggressed upon by public agency, they are more protected by public agency against aggression. Instead of a regime under which individuals rectified their private wrongs by force as well as they could, or else bribed the ruler, general or local, to use his power in their behalf, there has come a regime under which, while much less self-protection is required, a chief function of the ruling power and its agents is to administer justice. In all ways, then, we are shown that with this relative decrease of militancy and relative increase of industrialism, there has been a change from a social order in which individuals exist for the benefit of the State, to a social order in which the State exists for the benefit of individuals. When, instead of contrasting early European communities at large with European communities at large as they now exist, we contrast the one in which industrial development has been less impeded by militancy with those in which it has been more impeded by militancy, parallel results are apparent. Between our own society and continental societies, as for example, France, the differences which have gradually arisen may be cited in illustration. After the con- quering Normans had spread over England, there was esta- blished here a much greater subordination of local rulers to the general ruler than existed in France ; and, as a result, there was not nearly so much internal dissension. Says Hallam, speaking of this period, “ we read very little of private wars in England.” Though from time to time, as under Stephen, there were rebellions, and though there were occasional fights between nobles, yet for some hundred and fifty years, up to the time of King John, the subjection main- THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 621 tained secured comparative order. Further, it is to be noted that such general wars as occurred were mostly carried on abroad. Descents on our coasts were few and unimportant, and conflicts with Wales, Scotland, and Ireland, entailed but few intrusions on English soil. Consequently, there was a relatively small hindrance to industrial life and the growth of social forms appropriate to it. Meanwhile, the condition of France was widely different. During this period and long after, besides wars with England (mostly fought out on French soil) and wars with other countries, there were going on everywhere local wars. From the 10th to the 14th century perpetual fights between suzerains and their vassals occurred, as well as fights of vassals with one another. Not until towards the middle of the 14th century did the king begin greatly to predominate over the nobles ; and only in the 15th century was there established a supreme ruler strong enough to prevent the quarrels of local rulers. How great was the repression of industrial development caused by internal conflicts, may be inferred from the exaggerated language of an old writer, who says of this period, during which the final struggle of monarchy with feudalism was going on, that “ agriculture, traffic, and all the mechanical arts ceased/’ Such being the contrast between the small degree in which industrial life was impeded by war in England, and the great degree in which it was impeded by war in France, let us ask — what were the political contrasts which arose. The first fact to be noted is that in the middle of the 13th century there began in England a mitigation of villeinage, by limitation of labour-services and commutation of them for money, and that in the 14th century the trans- formation of a servile into a free population had in great measure taken place ; while in France, as in other continental countries, the old condition survived and became worse. As Mr. Freeman says of this period — “in England villeinage was on the whole dying out, while in many other countries it was getting harder and harder.” Besides this spreading sub- 622 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. stitution of contract for status, which, taking place first in the industrial centres, the towns, afterwards went on in the rural districts, there was going on an analogous enfranchise- ment of the noble class. The enforced military obligations of vassals were more and more replaced by money payments or scutages ; so that by King John’s time, the fighting services of the upper class had been to a great extent compounded for, like the labour services of the lower class. After dimi- nished restraints over persons, there came diminished invasions of property. By the Charter, arbitrary tallages on towns and non-military king’s tenants were checked ; and while the aggressive actions of the State were thus decreased, its pro- tective actions were extended : provisions were made that justice should be neither sold, delayed, nor denied. All which changes were towards those social arrangements which we see characterize the industrial type. Then, in the next place, we have the subsequently-occurring rise of a represen- tative government ; which, as shown in a preceding chapter by another line of inquiry, is at once the product of industrial growth and the form proper to the industrial type. But in France none of these changes took place. Villeinage remain- ing unmitigated continued to comparatively late times ; com- pounding for military obligation of vassal to suzerain was less general ; and when there arose tendencies towards the esta- blishment of an assembly expressing the popular will, they proved abortive. Detailed comparisons of subsequent periods and their changes would detain us too long : it must suffice to indicate the leading facts. Beginning with the date at which, under the influences just indicated, parliamentary government was finally established in England, we find that for a century and a half, down to the Wars of the Boses, the internal disturbances were few and unimportant compared with those which took place in France ; and at the same time (remembering that the wars between England and France, habitually taking place on French soil, affected the state of France more than that of England) we note that THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 623 France carried on serious wars with Flanders, Castille and Navarre besides the struggle with Burgundy: the result being that while in England popular power as expressed by the House of Commons became settled and increased, such power as the States General had acquired in France, dwindled away. Not forgetting that by the Wars of the Boses, lasting over thirty years, there was initiated a return towards absolutism; let us contemplate the contrasts which subse- quently arose. For a century and a half after these civil con- flicts ended, there were but few and trivial breaches of internal peace ; while such wars as went on with foreign powers, not numerous, took place as usual out of England. During this period the retrograde movement which the Wars of the Boses set up, was reversed, and popular power greatly in- creased ; so that in the words of Mr. Bagehot, “ the slavish parliament of Henry VIII. grew into the murmuring parlia- ment of Queen Elizabeth, the mutinous Parliament of James I., and the rebellious parliament of Charles I." Mean- while France, during the first third of this period, had been engaged in almost continuous external wars with Itaty, Spain, and Austria ; while during the remaining two-thirds, it suffered from almost continuous internal wars, religious and political : the accompanying result being that, notwith- standing resistances from time to time made, the monarchy became increasingly despotic. Fully to make manifest the different social types which had been evolved under these different conditions, we have to compare not only the respec- tive political constitutions but also the respective systems of social control. Observe what these were at the time when there commenced that reaction which ended in the French revolution. In harmony with the theory of the militant type, that the individual is in life, liberty, and property, owned by the State, the monarch was by some held to be the universal proprietor. The burdens he imposed upon landowners were so grievous that a part of them preferred abandoning their estates to paying. Then besides the taking of property by 624 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the State, there was the taking of labour. One-fourth of the working days in the year went to the corvees , due now to the king and now to the feudal lord. Such liberties as were allowed, had to be paid for and again paid for : the municipal privileges of towns being seven times in twenty-eight years withdrawn and re-sold to them. Military services of nobles and people were imperative to whatever extent the king demanded ; and conscripts were drilled under the lash. At the same time that the subjection of the individual to the State was pushed to such an extreme by exactions of money and services that the impoverished people cut the grain while it was green, ate grass, and died of starvation in multitudes, the State did little to guard their persons and homes. Con- temporary writers enlarge on the immense numbers of high- way robberies, burglaries, assassinations, and torturings of people to discover their hoards. Herds of Vagabonds, levying blackmail, roamed about ; and when, as a remedy, penalties were imposed, innocent persons denounced as vagabonds were sent to prison without evidence. No personal security could be had either against the ruler or against powerful enemies. In Paris there were some thirty prisons where untried and unsentenced people might be incarcerated ; and the “ brigand- age of justice *’ annually cost suitors forty to sixty millions of francs. While the State, aggressing on citizens to such extremes, thus failed to protect them against one another, it was active in regulating their private lives and labours. Eeligion was dictated to the extent that Protestants were im- prisoned, sent to the galleys, or whipped, and their ministers hanged. The quantity of salt (on which there was a heavy tax) to be consumed by each person was prescribed ; as were also the modes of its use. Industry of every kind was super- vised. Certain crops were prohibited ; and vines destroyed that were on soils considered unfit. The wheat that might be bought at market was limited to two bushels ; and sales took place in presence of dragoons. Manufacturers were regulated in their processes and products to the extent that THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 625 there was destruction of improved appliances and of goods not made according to law, as well as penalties upon in- ventors. Eegulations succeeded one another so rapidly that amid their multiplicity, government agents found it difficult to carry them out ; and with increasing official orders there came increasing swarms of public functionaries. Turning now to England .at the same period, we see that along with progress towards the industrial type of political structure, carried to the extent that the House of Commons had become the predominant power, there had gone a progress towards the accompanying social system. Though the subjection of the individual to the State was considerably greater than now, it was far less than in France. His private rights w^ere not sacrificed in the same unscrupulous way ; and he was not in danger of a lettre de cachet. Though justice was very imper- fectly administered, still it was not administered so wretchedly: there was a fair amount of personal security, and aggressions on property were kept within bounds. The disabilities of Protestant dissenters were diminished early in the century ; and, later on, those of Catholics. Considerable freedom of the press was acquired, showing itself in the discussion of political questions, as well as in the publication of par- liamentary debates ; and, about the same time, there came free speech in public meetings. While thus the State aggressed on the individual less and protected him more, it interfered to a smaller extent with his daily transactions. Though there was much regulation of commerce and industry, yet it was pushed to no such extreme as that which in France subjected agriculturists, manufacturers, and merchants, to an army of officials who directed their acts at every turn. In brief, the contrast between our state and that of France was such as to excite the surprise and admiration of various French writers of the time ; from whom Mr. Buckle quotes numerous passages showing this. Most significant of all, however, are the changes in England itself, first retrogressive and then progressive, that occurred 626 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. during the war-period which extended from 1775 to 1815, and during the subsequent period of peace. At the end of the last century and the beginning of this, reversion towards ownership of the individual by the society had gone a long way. “ To statesmen, the State, as a unit, was all in all, and it is really difficult to find any evidence that the people were thought of at all, except in the relation of obedience.” “ The Government regarded the people with little other view than as a taxable and soldier-yielding mass.” While the militant part of the community had greatly developed, the industrial part had approached towards the condition of a permanent commissariat. By conscription and by press-gangs, was carried to a relatively vast extent that sacrifice of the citizen in life and liberty which war entails ; and the claims to property were trenched on by merciless taxation, weighing down the middle classes so grievously that they had greatly to lower their rate of living, while the people at large were so distressed (partly no doubt by bad harvests) that “ hun- dreds ate nettles and other weeds.” With these major aggres- sions upon the individual by the State, went numerous minor aggressions. Irresponsible agents of the executive were empowered to suppress public meetings and seize their leaders : death being the punishment for those who did not disperse when ordered. Libraries and news-rooms could not be opened without licence ; and it was penal to lend books without permission. There were “ strenuous attempts made to silence the press and booksellers dared not publish works by obnoxious authors. “ Spies were paid, witnesses were suborned, juries were packed, and the habeas corpus Act being constantly suspended, the Crown had the power of imprison- ing without inquiry and without limitation.” While the Government taxed and coerced and restrained the citizen to this extent, its protection of him was inefficient. It is true that the penal code was made more extensive and more severe. The definition of treason was enlarged, and numerous offences were made capital which were not capital before ; so that THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 627 there was “ a vast and absurd variety of offences for which men and women were sentenced to death by the score there was “ a devilish levity in dealing with human life.” But at the same time there was not an increase, but rather a decrease, of security. As says Mr. Pike in his History of Crime in England , “ it became apparent that the greater the strain of the conflict the greater is the danger of a reaction towards violence and lawlessness.” Turn now to the opposite picture. After recovery from the prostration which prolonged wars had left, and after the dying away of those social per- turbations caused by impoverishment, there began a revival of traits proper to the industrial type. Coercion of the citizen by the State decreased in various ways. Voluntary enlist- ment replaced compulsory military service ; and there dis appeared some minor restraints over personal freedom, as instance the repeal of laws which forbade artizans to travel where they pleased, and which interdicted trades-unions. With these manifestations of greater respect for personal freedom, may be joined those shown in the amelioration of the penal code: the public whipping of females being first abolished ; then the long list of capital offences being reduced until there finally remained but one ; and, eventually, the pillory and imprisonment for debt being abolished. Such penalties on religious independence as remained disappeared ; first by removal of those directed against Protestant Dissenters, and then of those which weighed on Catholics, and then of some which told specially against Quakers and Jews. By the Parliamentary Eeform Bill and the Municipal Reform Bill, vast numbers were removed from the subject classes to the governing classes. Interferences with the business- transactions of citizens were diminished by allowing free trade in bullion, by permitting joint-stock banks, by abolish- ing multitudinous restrictions on the importation of com- modities — leaving eventually but few which pay duty. More- over while these and kindred changes, such as the removal of restraining burdens on the press, decreased the impedi- 628 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ments to free actions of citizens, the protective action of the State was increased. By a greatly-improved police system, by county courts, and so forth, personal safety and claims to property were better secured. Not to elaborate the argument further by adding the case of the United States, which repeats with minor differences the same relations of phenomena, the evidence given ade- quately supports the proposition laid down. Amid all the complexities and perturbations, comparisons show us with sufficient clearness that in actually-existing societies those attributes which we inferred must distinguish the industrial type, show themselves clearly in proportion as the social activities are predominantly characterized by exchange of services under agreement. § 574. As, in the last chapter, we noted the traits of cha- racter proper to the members of a society which is habitually at war; so here, w T e have to note the traits of character proper to the members of a society occupied exclusively in peaceful pursuits. Already in delineating above, the rudi- ments of the industrial type of social structure as exhibited in certain small groups of unwarlike peoples, some indications of the accompanying personal qualities have been given ; but it will be well now to emphasize these and add to them, before observing the kindred personal qualities in more advanced industrial communities. Absence of a centralized coercive rule, implying as it does feeble political restraints exercised by the society over its units, is accompanied by a strong sense of individual freedom, and a determination to maintain it. The amiable Bodo and Dhimals, as we have seen, resist “ injunctions injudiciously urged with dogged obstinacy.” The peaceful Lepchas “ un- dergo great privations rather than submit to oppression or injustice.” The “ simple-minded Santal ” has a “ strong natural sense of justice, and should any attempt be made to coerce him, he flies the country.” Similarly of a tribe not THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 629 before mentioned, tbe Jakuns of the South Malayan Peninsula, who, described as “ entirely inoffensive,” personally brave but peaceful, and as under no control but that of popularly- appointed heads who settle their disputes, are also described as “ extremely proud the so-called pride being exemplified by the statement that their remarkably good qualities “ induced several persons to make attempts to domesticate them, but such essays have generally ended in the J akuns’ disappearance on the slightest coercion.” "With a strong sense of their own claims, these uii warlike men display unusual respect for the claims of others. This is shown in the first place by the rarity of personal collisions among them. Hodgson says that the Bodo and the Dhimals “ are void of all violence towards their own people or towards their neighbours.” Of the peaceful tribes of the Neilgherry Hills, Colonel Ouchterlony writes : — “ drunkenness and violence are unknown amongst them.” Campbell remarks of the Lepchas, that “ they rarely quarrel among themselves.” The Jakuns, too, “ have very seldom quarrels among themselves;” and such disputes as arise are settled by their popularly-chosen heads “without fighting or malice.” In like manner the Arafuras “ live in peace and brotherly love with one another.” Further, in the accounts of these peoples we read nothing about the lex talionis. In the absence of hostilities with adja- cent groups there does not exist within each group that “ sacred duty of blood-revenge ” universally recognized in military tribes and nations. Still more significantly, we find evidence of the opposite doctrine and practice. Says Campbell of the Lepchas — “ they are singularly forgiving of injuries . . . making mutual amends and concessions.” Naturally, with respect for others’ individualities thus shown, goes respect for their claims to property. Already in the preliminary chapter I have quoted testimonies to the great honesty of the Bodo and the Dhimals, the Lepchas, the Santals, the Todas, and other peoples kindred in their form of social life ; and here I may add further ones. Of the Lepchas, 630 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Hooker remarks : — “ in all my dealings with these people, they proved scrupulously honest.” “ Among the pure Santals,” writes Hunter, “ crime and criminal officers are unknown while of the Hos, belonging to the same group as the Santals, Dalton says, “ a reflection on a man’s honesty or veracity may be sufficient to send him to self-destruction.” Shortt testifies that “ the Todas, as a body, have never been convicted of heinous crimes of any kind and concerning other tribes of the Shervaroy Hills, he states that “ crime of a serious nature is unknown amongst them.” Again of the Jakuns we read that “ they are never known to steal anything, not even the most insignificant trifle.” And so of certain natives of Malacca who “ are naturally of a commercial tarn,” Jukes writes : — “ no part of the world is freer from crime than the district of Malacca ;” “ a few petty cases of assault, or of disputes about property . . . are all that occur.” Thus free from the coercive rule which warlike activities necessitate, and without the sentiment which makes the needful subordination possible — thus maintaining their own claims while respecting the like claims of others — thus devoid of the vengeful feelings which aggressions without and within the tribe generate ; these peoples, instead of the bloodthirstiness, the cruelty, the selfish trampling upon in- feriors, characterizing militant tribes and societies, display, in unusual degrees, the humane sentiments. Insisting on their amiable qualities, Hodgson describes the Bodo and the Dhimals as being “ almost entirely free from such as are unamiable.” Bemarking that “ while courteous and hos- pitable he is firm and free from cringing,” Hunter tells us of the Santal that he thinks “ uncharitable men” will suffer after death. Saying that the Lepchas are “ ever foremost in the forest or on the bleak mountain, and ever ready to help, to carry, to encamp, collect, or cook,” Hooker adds — “ they cheer on the traveller by their unostentatious zeal in his service ; ” and he also adds that, “ a present is divided equally amongst many, without a syllable of discontent or grudging THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 631 look or word” Of the Jakuns, too, Favre tells us that “ they are generally kind, affable, inclined to gratitude and to beneficence : ” their tendency being not to ask favours but to confer them. And then of the peaceful Arafuras we learn from Kolff that — “ They have a very excusable ambition to gain the name of rich men, by paying the debts of their poorer villagers. The officer [M. Bik], whom I quoted above, related to me a very striking instance of this. At Affara he was present at the election of the village chiefs, two indi- viduals aspiring to the station of Orang Tua. The people chose the elder of the two, which greatly afflicted the other, but he soon after- wards expressed himself satisfied with the choice the people had made, and said to M. Bik, who had been sent there on a commission, ‘ What reason have I to grieve ; whether I am Orang Tua or not, I still have it in my power to assist my fellow villagers.’ Several old men agreed to this, apparently to comfort him. Thus the only use they make of their riches is to employ it in settling differences.” With these superiorities of the social relations in perma- nently peaceful tribes, go superiorities of the domestic rela- tions. As I have before pointed out (§ 327), while the status of women is habitually very low in tribes given to war and in more advanced militant societies, it is habitually very high in these primitive peaceful societies. The Bodo and the Dhimals, the Kocch, the Santals, the Lepchas, are monogamie, as were also the Pueblos ; and along with their monogamy habitually goes a superior sexual morality. Of the Lepchas Hooker says — “ the females are generally chaste, and the marriage tie is strictly kept.” Among the Santals “ unchas- tity is almost unknown,” and "divorce is rare.” By the Bodo and the Dhimals, “ polygamy, concubinage and adultery are not tolerated ; ” “ chastity is prized in man and woman, married and unmarried.” Further it is to be noted that the behaviour to women is extremely good. “ The Santal treats the female members of his family with respect ; ” the Bodo and the Dhimals “ treat their wives and daughters with con- fidence and kindness ; they are free from all out-door work whatever.” And even among the Todas, low as are the forms of their sexual relations, "the wives are treated by their 632 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. husbands with marked respect and attention.” Moreover, we are told concerning sundry of these unwarlike peoples that the status of children is also high ; and there is none of that distinction of treatment between boys and girls which characterizes militant peoples. Of course on turning to the civilized to observe the form of individual character which accompanies the industrial form of society, we encounter the difficulty that the per- sonal traits proper to industrialism, are, like the social traits, mingled with those proper to militancy. It is mani- festly thus with ourselves. A nation which, besides its occasional serious wars, is continually carrying on small wars with uncivilized tribes — a nation which is mainly ruled in Parliament and through the press by men whose school- discipline led them during six days in the w r eek to take Achilles for their hero, and on the seventh to admire Christ — a nation wffiich, at its public dinners, habitually toasts its army and navy before toasting its legislative bodies ; has not so far emerged out of militancy that we can expect either the institutions or the characteristics proper to industrialism to be shown with clearness. In independence, in honesty, in truthfulness, in humanity, its citizens are not likely to be the equals of the uncultured but peaceful peoples above de- scribed. All we may anticipate is an approach to those moral qualities appropriate to a state undisturbed by inter- national hostilities ; and this we find. In the first place, with progress of the regime of contract has come growth of independence. Daily exchange of ser- vices under agreement, involving at once the maintenance of personal claims and respect for the claims of others, has fostered a normal self-assertion and consequent resistance to unauthorized power. The facts that the word “ indepen- dence/’ in its modern sense, was not in use among us before the middle of the last century, and that on the continent independence is less markedly displayed, suggest the con- nexion between this trait and a developing industrialism. THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 633 The trait is shown in the multitudinousness of religious sects, in the divisions of political parties, and, in minor ways, by the absence of those “ schools ” in art, philosophy, &c., which, among continental peoples, are formed by the submission of disciples to an adopted master. That Englishmen show, more than their neighbours, a jealousy of dictation, and a determi- nation to act as they think fit, will not, I think, be disputed. The diminished subordination to authority, which is the obverse of this independence, of course implies decrease of loyalty. Worship of the monarch, at no time with us reach- ing the height it did in France early in the last century, or in Russia down to recent times, has now changed into a respect depending very much on the monarch's personal character. Our days witness no such extreme servilities of expression as were used by ecclesiastics in the dedication of the Bible to King J ames, nor any such exaggerated adulations as those addressed to George III. by the House of Lords. The doctrine of divine right has long since died away ; belief in an indwelling supernatural power (implied by the touching for king’s evil, &e.) is named as a curiosity of the past ; and the monarchical institution has come to be defended on grounds of expediency. So great has been the decrease of this senti- ment which, under the militant regime, attaches subject to ruler, that now-a-days the conviction commonly expressed is that, should the throne be occupied by a Charles II. or a George IV., there would probably result a republic. And this change of feeling is shown in the attitude towards the Government as a whole. For not only are there many who dispute the authority of the State in respect of sundry matters besides religious beliefs, but there are some who passively resist what they consider unjust exercises of its authority, and pay fines or go to prison rather than submit. As this last fact implies, along with decrease of loyalty has gone decrease of faith, not in monarchs only but in govern- ments. Such belief in royal omnipotence as existed in ancient Egypt, where the power of the ruler was supposed to 634 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. extend to tlie other world, as it is even now supposed to do in China, has had no parallel in the West; but still, among European peoples in past times, that confidence in the soldier- king essential to the militant type, displayed itself among other ways in exaggerated conceptions of his ability to rectify mischiefs, achieve benefits, and arrange things as he willed. If we compare present opinion among ourselves with opinion in early days, we find a decline in these credulous expecta- tions. Though, during the late retrograde movement towards militancy, State-power has been invoked for various ends, and faith in it has increased ; yet, up to the commencement of this reaction, a great change had taken place in the other direction. After the repudiation of a State-enforced creed, there came a denial of the State’s capacity for determining religious truth, and a growing movement to relieve it from the function of religious teaching ; held to be alike needless and injurious. Long ago it had ceased to be thought that Government could do any good by regulating people’s food, clothing, and domestic habits ; and over the multitudinous processes carried on by producers and distributors, constitut- ing immensely the larger part of our social activities, we no longer believe that legislative dictation is beneficial. More- over, every newspaper by its criticisms on the acts of ministers and the conduct of the House of Commons, betrays the diminished faith of citizens in their rulers. Nor is it only by contrasts between past and present among ourselves that we are shown this trait of a more developed industrial state. It is shown by kindred contrasts between opinion here and opinion abroad. The speculations of social reformers in France and in Germany, prove that the hope for benefits to be achieved by State-agency is far higher with them than with us. Along with decrease of loyalty and concomitant decrease of faith in the powers of governments, has gone decrease of patriotism — patriotism, that is, under its original form. To fight “ for king and country ” is an ambition which now-a- THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 635 days occupies but a small space in men’s minds ; and though there is among us a majority whose sentiment is represented by the exclamation — “ Our country, right or wrong ! ” yet there are large numbers whose desire for human welfare at large, so far overrides their desire for national prestige, that they object to sacrificing the first to the last. The spirit of self-criticism, which in sundry respects leads us to make un- favourable comparisons between ourselves and our continental neighbours, leads us more than heretofore to blame ourselves for wrong conduct to weaker peoples. The many and strong reprobations of our dealings with the Afghans, the Zulus, and the Boers, show that there is a large amount of the feeling- reprobated by the “ Jingo ’’-class as unpatriotic. That adaptation of individual nature to social needs, which, in the militant state, makes men glory in war and despise peaceful pursuits, has partially brought about among us a converse adjustment of the sentiments. The occupation of the soldier has ceased to be so much honoured, and that of the civilian is more honoured. During the forty years’ peace, the popular sentiment became such that “ soldiering ” was spoken of contemptuously; and those who enlisted, habitually the idle and the dissolute, were commonly regarded as having completed their disgrace. Similarly in America before the late civil war, such small military gatherings and exercises as from time to time occurred, excited general ridicule. Mean- while we see that labours, bodily and mental, useful to self and others, have come to be not only honourable but in a considerable degree imperative. In America the adverse comments on a man who does nothing, almost force him into some active pursuit; and among ourselves the respect for industrial life has become such that men of high rank put their sons into business. While, as we saw, the compulsory cooperation proper to militancy, forbids, or greatly discourages, individual initiative, the voluntary cooperation which distinguishes industrialism, gives free scope to individual initiative, and develops it by 636 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. letting enterprise bring its normal advantages. Those who are successfully original in idea and act, prospering and multiplying in a greater degree than others, produce, in course of time, a general type of nature ready to undertake new things. The speculative tendencies of English and American capitalists, and the extent to which large undertakings, both at home and abroad, are carried out by them, sufficiently indicate this trait of character. Though, along with consider- able qualifications of militancy by industrialism on the con- tinent, there has occurred there, too, an extension of private enterprise; yet the fact that while many towns in France and Germany have been supplied with gas and water by English companies, there is in England but little of kindred achieve- ment by foreign companies, shows that among the more industrially-modified English, individual initiative is more decided. There is evidence that the decline of international hostili- ties, associated as it is with the decline of hostilities between families and between individuals, is followed by a weakening of revengeful sentiments. This is implied by the fact that in our own country the more serious of these private wars early ceased, leaving only the less serious in the form of duels, which also have at length ceased : their cessation coinciding with the recent great development of industrial life — a fact with which may be joined the fact that in the more militant societies, France and Germany, they have not ceased. So much among ourselves has the authority of the lex talionis waned, that a man whose actions are known to be prompted by the wish for vengeance on one who has injured him, is reprobated rather than applauded. With decrease of the aggressiveness shown in acts of violence and consequent acts of retaliation, has gone decrease of the aggressiveness shown in criminal acts at large. That this change has been a concomitant of the change from a more militant to a more industrial state, cannot be doubted by one who studies the history of crime in England. Says THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 637 Mr. Pike in his work on that subject, “ the close connexion between the military spirit and those actions which are now legally defined to be crimes, has been pointed out, again and again, in the course of this history.” If we compare a past age in which the effects of hostile activities had been less qualified by the effects of peaceful activities than they are in our own age, we see a marked contrast in respect of the numbers and kinds of offences against person and property. We have no longer any English buccaneers ; wreckers have ceased to be heard of; and travellers do not now prepare themselves to meet highwaymen. Moreover, that flagitious- ness of the governing agencies themselves, which was shown by the venality of ministers and members of Parliament, and by the corrupt administration of justice, has disappeared. With decreasing amount of crime has come increasing repro- bation of crime. Biographies of pirate captains, suffused with admiration of their courage, no longer find a place in our literature ; and the sneaking kindness for “ gentlemen of the road,” is, in our days, but rarely displayed. Many as are the transgressions which our journals report, they have greatly diminished ; and though in trading transactions there is much dishonesty (chiefly of the indirect sort) it needs but to read Defoe's English Tradesman , to see how marked has been the improvement since his time. Nor must we forget that the change of character which has brought a decrease of unjust actions, has brought an increase of beneficent actions ; as seen in paying for slave-emancipation, in nursing the wounded soldiers of our fighting neighbours, in philanthropic efforts of countless kinds. § 575. As with the militant type then, so with the indus- trial type, three lines of evidence converge to show us its essential nature. Let us set down briefly the several results, that we may observe the correspondences among them. On considering what must be the traits of a society organized exclusively for carrying on internal activities, so as 638 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. most efficiently to subserve the lives of citizens, we find them to be these. A corporate action subordinating individual actions by uniting them in joint effort, is no longer requisite. Contrariwise, such corporate action as remains has for its end to guard individual actions against all interferences not necessarily entailed by mutual limitation : the type of society in which this function is best discharged, being that which must survive, since it is that of which the members will most prosper. Excluding, as the requirements of the industrial type do, a despotic controlling agency, they imply, as the only congruous agency for achieving such corporate action as is needed, one formed of representatives who serve to express the aggregate will. The function of this controlling agency, generally defined as that of administering justice, is more specially defined as that of seeing that each citizen gains neither more nor less of benefit than his activities normally bring ; and there is thus excluded all public action involving any artificial distribution of benefits. Tire regime of status proper to militancy having disappeared, the regime of contract which replaces it has to be universally enforced; and this negatives interferences between efforts and results by arbitrary apportionment. Otherwise regarded, the industrial type is distinguished from the militant type as being not both posi- tively regulative and negatively regulative, but as being negatively regulative only. With this restricted sphere for corporate action comes an increased sphere for individual action ; and from that voluntary cooperation which is the fundamental principle of the type, arise multitudinous private combinations, akin in their structures to the public com- bination of the society which includes them. Indirectly it results that a society of the industrial type is distinguished by plasticity ; and also that it tends to lose its economic autonomy, and to coalesce with adjacent societies. The question next considered was, whether these traits of the industrial type as arrived at by deduction are inductively verified ; and we found that in actual societies they are visible THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 639 more or less clearly in proportion as industrialism is more or less developed. Glancing at those small groups of uncultured people who, wholly unwarlike, display the industrial type in its rudimentary form, we went on to compare the structures of European nations at large in early days of chronic mili- tancy, with their structures in modem days characterized by progressing industrialism ; and we saw the differences to be of the kind implied. We next compared two of these societies, France and England, which were once in kindred states, but of which the one has had its industrial life much more repressed by its militant life than the other ; and it became manifest that the contrasts wdrich, age after age, arose between their institutions, were such as answer to the hypo- thesis. Lastly, limiting ourselves to England itself, and first noting how recession from such traits of the industrial type as had shown themselves, occurred during a long war-period, we observed how, during the subsequent long period of peace beginning in 1815, there were numerous and decided ap- proaches to that social structure which we concluded must accompany developed industrialism. We then inquired what type of individual nature accom- panies the industrial type of society ; with the view of seeing whether, from the character of the unit as well as from the character of the aggregate, confirmation is to be derived. Certain uncultured peoples whose lives are passed in peaceful occupations, proved to be distinguished by independence, resistance to coercion, honesty, truthfulness, forgivingness, kindness. On contrasting the characters of our ancestors during more warlike periods with our own characters, we see that, with an increasing ratio of industrialism to militancy, have come a growing independence, a less-marked loyalty, a smaller faith in governments, and a more qualified patriotism ; and while, by enterprising action, by diminished faith in authority, by resistance to irresponsible power, there has been shown a strengthening assertion of individuality, there has accompanied it a growing respect for the individualities of 640 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. others, as is implied by the diminution of aggressions upon them and the multiplication of efforts for their welfare. To prevent misapprehension it seems needful, before closing, to explain that these traits are to be regarded less as the immediate results of industrialism than as the remote results of non-militancy. It is not so much that a social life passed in peaceful occupations is positively moralizing, as that a social life passed in war is positively demoralizing. Sacrifice of others to self is in the one incidental only ; while in the other it is necessary. Such aggressive egoism as accom- panies the industrial life is extrinsic ; whereas the aggressive egoism of the militant life is intrinsic. Though generally unsympathetic, the exchange of services under agreement is now, to a considerable extent, and may be wholly, carried on with a due regard to the claims of others — may be constantly accompanied by a sense of benefit given as well as benefit received; but the slaying of antagonists, the burning of their houses, the appropriation of their territory, cannot but be accompanied by vivid consciousness of injury done them, and a consequent brutalizing effect on the feelings — an effect wrought, not on soldiers only, but on those who employ them and contemplate their deeds with pleasure. The last form of social life, therefore, inevitably deadens the sympathies and generates a state of mind which prompts crimes of trespass ; while the first form, allowing the sympathies free play if it does not directly exercise them, favours the growth of altru- istic sentiments and the resulting virtues. Note. — This reference to the natural genesis of a higher moral nature, recalls a controversy some time since carried on. In a “Symposium” pub- lished in the 'Nineteenth Century for April and May, 1877, was discussed “ the influence upon morality of a decline in religious belief : ” the question eventually raised being whether morality can exist without religion. Not much difficulty in answering this question will be felt by those who, from the conduct of the rude tribes described in this chapter, turn to that of Europeans during a great part of the Christian era ; with its innumerable and immeasurable public and private atrocities, its bloody aggressive wars, its ceaseless family-vendettas, its bandit barons and fighting bishops, its massa- cres, political and religious, its torturings and burnings, its all-pervading crime THE INDUSTRIAL TYPE OF SOCIETY. 641 from the assassinations of and by kings down to the lyings and petty thefts of slaves and serfs. Nor do the contrasts between our own conduct at the present time and the conduct of these so-called savages, leave us in doubt con- cerning the right answer. When, after reading police reports, criminal assize proceedings, accounts of fraudulent bankruptcies, &c., which in our journals accompany advertisements of sermons and reports of religious meetings, we learn that the “ amiable ” Bodo and Dhimals, who are so “ honest and truthful,” “ have no word for God, for soul, for heaven, for hell ” (though they have ancestor-worship and some derivative beliefs), we find ourselves unable to recognize the alleged connexion. If, side by side with narratives of bank-frauds, rail way -jobbings, turf-chicaneries, &e., among people who are anxious that the House of Commons should preserve its theism untainted, wo place descriptions of the “ fascinating ” Lepchas, who are so “ wonderfully honest,” but who “ profess no religion, though acknowledging the existence of good and bad spirits ” (to the last of whom only they pay any attention), we do not see our way to accepting the dogma which our theologians think so obviously true ; nor will acceptance of it be made easier when we add the description of the conscientious Santal, who “ never thinks of making money by a stranger,” and “ feels pained if payment is pressed upon him ” for food offered j but concerning whom we are told that “ of a supreme and beneficent God the Santal has no conception.” Admission of the doctrine that right conduct depends on theological conviction, becomes difficult on reading that the Yeddahs who are “ almost devoid of any sentiment of religion ” and have no idea “ of a Supreme Being,” nevertheless “ think it perfectly inconceivable that any person should ever take that which does not belong to him, or strike his fellow, or say anything that is untrue.” After finding that among the select of the select who profess our established creed, the standard of truthfulness is such that the statement of a minister concerning cabinet transactions is distinctly falsified by the statement of a seceding minister ; and after then recalling the marvellous veracity of these godless Bodo and Dhimals, Lepchas, and other peaceful tribes having kindred beliefs, going to such extent that an imputation of falsehood is enough to make one of the Hos destroy himself ; we fail to see that in the absence of a tlieistic belief there can be no regard for truth. When, in a weekly journal specially repre- senting the university culture shared in by our priests, we find a lament over the moral degradation shown by our treatment of the Boers — when we are held degraded because we have not slaughtered them for successfully resist- ing our trespasses — when we see that the “ sacred duty of blood revenge,” which the cannibal savage insists upon, is insisted upon by those to whom the Christian religion was daily taught throughout their education ; and when, from contemplating this fact, we pass to the fact that the unreligious Lepchas “ are singularly forgiving of injuries,” the assumed relation between humanity and theism appears anything but congruous with the evidence. If, with the ambitions of our church-going citizens, who (not always in very honourable ways) strive to get fortunes that they may make great displays, and gratify themselves by thinking that at death they will “ cut up well,” we compare the ambitions of the Arafuras, among whom wealth is desired that 642 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. its possessor may pay tlie debts of poorer men and settle differences, we are obliged to reject the assumption that “ brotherly love ” can exist only as a consequence of divine injunctions, with promised rewards and threatened punishments ; for of these Araf uras we read that — “ Of the immortality of the soul they have not the least conception. To all my enquiries on the subject they answered, ‘No Arafura has ever returned to us after death, therefore we know nothing of a future state, and this is the first time we have heard of it.* Their idea was, when you are dead there is an end of you. Neither have they any notion of the creation of the world. They only answered, ‘ None of us were aware of this, we have never heard anything about it, and therefore do not know who has done it all.’ ” The truth disclosed by the facts is that, so far as men’s moral states are con- cerned, theory is almost nothing and practice is almost everything. No matter how high their nominal creed, nations given to political burglaries to get “ scientific frontiers,” and the like, will have among their members many who “ annex ” others’ goods for their own convenience ; and with the orga- nized crime of aggressive war, will go criminality in the behaviour of one citizen to another. Conversely, as these uncultivated tribes prove, no matter how devoid they are of religious beliefs, those who, generation after genera- tion remaining unmolested, inflict no injuries upon others, have their altru- istic sentiments fostered by the sympathetic intercourse of a peaceful daily life, and display the resulting virtues. We need teaching that it is impossible to join injustice and brutality abroad with justice and humanity at home. What a pity these Heathens cannot be induced to send missionaries among the Christians ! CHAPTER XIX. POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. § 576. In the foregoing chapters little has been said concerning the doctrine of Evolution at large, as re-illus- trated by political evolution ; though doubtless the observant reader has occasionally noted how the transformations de- scribed conform to the general law of transformation. Here, in summing up, it will be convenient briefly to indicate their conformity. Already in Part II, when treating of Social Growth, Social Structures, and Social Functions, the outlines of this correspondence were exhibited ; but the materials for exemplifying it in a more special way, which have been brought together in this Part, may fitly be utilized to emphasize afresh a truth not yet commonly admitted. That under its primary aspect political development is a process of integration, is clear. By it individuals originally separate are united into a whole ; and the union of them into a whole is variously shown. In the earliest stages the groups of men are small, they are loose, they are not unified by subordination to a centre. But with political progress comes the compounding, re-compounding, and re-re-compounding of groups until great nations are produced. Moreover, with that settled life and agricultural development accompanying poli- tical progress, there is not only a formation of societies covering wider areas, but an increasing density of their popu- lations. Further, the loose aggregation of savages passes into 644 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the coherent connexion of citizens ; at one stage coercively bound to one another and to their localities by family-ties and class-ties, and at a later stage voluntarily bound together by their mutually-dependent occupations. Once more, there is that merging of individual wills in a governmental will, which reduces a society, as it reduces an army, to a consolidated body. An increase of heterogeneity at the same time goes on in many ways. Everywhere the horde, when its members co- operate for defence or offence, begins to differentiate into a predominant man, a superior few, and an inferior many. With that massing of groups which war effects, there grow out of these, head chief, subordinate chiefs, and warriors; and at higher stages of integration, kings, nobles, and people : each of the two great social strata presently becoming dif- ferentiated within itself. When small societies have been united, the respective triune governing agencies of them grow unlike : the local political assemblies falling into subordina- tion to a central political assembly. Though, for a time, the central one continues to be constituted after the same manner as the local ones, it gradually diverges in character by loss of its popular element. While these local and central bodies are becoming contrasted in their powers and structures, they are severally becoming differentiated in another way. Origi- nally each is at once military, political, and judicial; but by and by the assembly for judicial business, no longer armed, ceases to be like the politico-military assembly; and the politico-military assembly eventually gives origin to a con- sultative body, the members of which, when meeting for political deliberation, come unarmed. Within each of these divisions, again, kindred changes subsequently occur. While themselves assuming more specialized forms, local judicial agencies fall under the control of a central judicial agency ; and the central judicial agency, which has separated from the original consultative body, subdivides into parts or courts which take unlike kinds of business. The central political POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 645 body, too, where its powers do not disappear by absorption in those of the supreme head, tends to complicate; as in our own case by the differentiation of a privy council from the original consultative body, and again by the differentiation of a cabinet from the privy council : accompanied, in the other direction, by division of the consultative body into elective and non-elective parts. While these metamorphoses are going on, the separation of the three organizations, legislative, judicial, and executive, progresses. Moreover, with progress in these major political changes goes that progress in minor political changes which, out of family-governments and clan-govern- ments, evolves such governments as those of the tything, the gild, and the municipality. Thus in all directions from primitive simplicity there is produced ultimate complexity, through modifications upon modifications. With this advance from small incoherent social aggre- gates to great coherent ones, which, while becoming integrated pass from uniformity to multiformity, there goes an advance from indefiniteness of political organization to definiteness of political organization. Save inherited ideas and usages, nothing is fixed in the primitive horde. But the dif- ferentiations above described, severally beginning vaguely, grow in their turns gradually more marked. Class-divisions, absent at first and afterwards undecided, eventually acquire great distinctness : slaves, serfs, freemen, nobles, king, become separated, often by impassable barriers, and their positions shown by mutilations, badges, dresses, &c. Powers and obli- gations which were once diffused are parted off and rigorously maintained. The various parts of the political machinery come to be severally more and more restricted in their ranges of duties ; and usage, age by age accumulating precedents, brings every kind of official action within prescribed bounds. This increase of definiteness is everywhere well shown by the development of laws. Beginning as inherited sacred injunc- tions briefly expressed, these have to be applied after some prescribed method, and their meanings in relation to par- 646 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. ticular cases made clear. Rules of procedure become step by step detailed and formal, while interpretations change the general command into specialized commands to meet incidental circumstances; and gradually there grows up a legal system everywhere precise and fixed. How pronounced is this tendency is interestingly shown in our system of Equity, which, arising to qualify the unduly defined and rigid applications of Law, itself slowly multiplied its tech- nicalities until it grew equally defined and rigid. To meet an obvious criticism it must be added that these changes from societies which are small, loose, uniform, and vague in structure, to societies which are large, compact, multiform, and distinct in structure, present varieties of characters under varieties of conditions, and alter as the conditions alter. Different parts of a society display the transformation, according as the society’s activities are of one or other kind. Chronic war generates a compulsory cohesion, and produces an ever-greater heterogeneity and defi- niteness in that controlling organization by which unity of action is secured ; while that part of the organization which carries on production and distribution, exhibits these traits of evolution in a relatively small degree. Conversely, when joint action of the society against other societies decreases, the traits of the structure developed for carrying it on begin to fade ; while the traits of the structure for carrying on pro- duction and distribution become more decided : the increasing cohesion, heterogeneity, and definiteness, begin now to be shown throughout the industrial organization. Hence the phenomena become complicated by a simultaneous evolution of one part of the social organization and dissolution of another part — a mingling of changes well illustrated in our own society. § 577. With this general conception before us, which, without more detailed recapitulation of the conclusions reached, will sufficiently recall them, we may turn from POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 647 retrospect to prospect ; and ask through what phases political evolution is likely hereafter to pass. Such speculations concerning higher political types as we may allow ourselves, must be taken with the understanding that such types are not likely to become universal. As in the past so in the future, local circumstances must be influential in determining governmental arrangements; since these depend in large measure on the modes of life which the climate, soil, flora, and fauna, necessitate. In regions like those of Central Asia, incapable of supporting considerable populations, there are likely to survive wandering hordes under simple forms of control. Large areas such as parts of Africa present, which prove fatal to the higher races of men, and the steaming atmospheres of which cause enervation, may continue to be inhabited by lower races of men, subject to political arrangements adapted to them. And in con- ditions such as those furnished by small Pacific Islands, mere deficiency of numbers must negative the forms of government which become alike needful and possible in large nations. Recognizing the fact that with social organisms as with indi- vidual organisms, the evolution of superior types does not entail the extinction of all inferior ones, but leaves many of these to survive in habitats not available by the superior, we may here restrict ourselves to the inquiry — What are likely to be the forms of political organization and action in societies that are favourably circumstanced for carrying social evolu- tion to its highest stage ? Of course deductions respecting the future must be drawn from inductions furnished by the past. We must assume that hereafter social evolution will conform to the same principles as heretofore. Causes which have everywhere produced certain effects must, if they continue at work, be expected to produce further effects of like kinds. If we see that political transformations which have arisen under cer- tain conditions, admit of being carried further in the same directions, we must conclude that they will be carried further 648 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. if the conditions are maintained ; and that they will go on until they reach limits beyond which there is no scope for them. Not indeed that any trustworthy forecast can be made concerning proximate changes. All that has gone before unites to prove that political institutions, fundamentally determined in their forms by the predominance of one or other of the antagonist modes of social action, the militant and the industrial, will be moulded in this way or in that way according as there is frequent w T ar or habitual peace. Hence we must infer that throughout approaching periods, every- thing will depend on the courses which societies happen to take in their behaviour to one another — courses w T hich cannot be predicted. On the one hand, in the present state of armed preparation throughout Europe, an untoward accident may bring about wars which, lasting perhaps for a generation, will re-develop the coercive forms of political control. On the other hand, a long peace is likely to be accompanied by so vast an increase of manufacturing and commercial activity, with accompanying growth of the appropriate political struc- tures within each nation, and strengthening of those ties between nations which mutual dependence generates, that hostilities will be more and more resisted and the organization adapted for the carrying them on will decay. Leaving, however, the question — What are likely to be the proximate political changes in the most advanced nations ? and inferring from the changes which civilization has thus far wrought out, that at some time, more or less distant, the industrial type will become permanently established, let us now ask — What is to be the ultimate political regime ? § 578. Having so recently contemplated at length the political traits of the industrial type as inferable a priori , and as partially exemplified a posteriori in societies most favour- ably circumstanced for evolving them, there remains only to present these under a united and more concrete form, wfith POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 649 some dependent ones which have not been indicated. We will glance first at the implied political structures, and next at the implied political functions. What forms of governmental organization must be the out- come of voluntary cooperation carried to its limit ? We have already seen that in the absence of those appliances for coercion which accompany the militant type, whatever legis- lative and administrative structures exist, must be, in general and in detail, of directly or indirectly representative origin. The presence in them of functionaries not deriving their powers from the aggregate will, and not changeable by the aggregate will, would imply partial continuance of that regime of status which the regime of contract has, by the hypothesis, entirely replaced. But assuming the exclusion of all irre- sponsible agents, what particular structures will best serve to manifest and execute the aggregate will ? This is a question to which only approximate answers can be given. There are various possible organizations through which the general consensus of feeling and opinion may display itself and issue in action ; and it is very much a question of con- venience, rather than of principle, which of these shall be adopted. Let us consider some of their varieties. The representatives constituting the central legislature may form one body or they may form two. If there is but one, it may consist of men directly elected by all qualified citizens; or its members may be elected by local bodies which have themselves arisen by direct election ; or it may include members some of whom are elected in the one way and some in the other. If there are two chambers, the lower one may arise in the first of the three ways named ; while the second arises in one of several ways. It may consist of members chosen by local representative bodies ; or it may be chosen by the lower chamber out of its own number. Its members may either have no test of eligibility, or they may be required to have special qualifications : experience in administration, for example. Then besides these various forms of the 650 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. legislature, there are the various modes in which it may be partially or wholly replaced. Entire dissolution and re- election of one body or of both bodies may occur at intervals, either the same for the two or different for the two, and either simultaneously or otherwise ; or the higher body, though representative, may be permanent, while the lower is change- able; or the changing of one or both, at given intervals, may be partial instead of complete — a third or a fourth may vacate their seats annually or biennially, and may or may not be eligible for re-election. So, too, there are various modes by which the executive may originate con- sistently with the representative principle. It may be simple or it may be compound ; and if compound, the members of it may be changeable separately or altogether. The political head may be elected directly by the whole community, or by its local governing bodies, or by one or by both of its central representative bodies ; and may be so elected for a term or for life. His assistants or ministers may be chosen by him- self ; or he may choose one who chooses the rest ; or they may be chosen separately or bodily by one or other legis- lature, or by the two united. And the members of the ministry may compose a group apart from both chambers, or may be members of one or the other. Concerning these, and many other possible arrangements which may be conceived as arising by modification and com- plication of them (all apparently congruous with the require- ment that the making and administration of laws shall con- form to public opinion) the choice is to be guided mainly by regard for simplicity and facility of working. But it seems likely that hereafter, as heretofore, the details of constitutional forms in each society, will not be determined on d 'priori grounds, or will be but partially so determined. We may conclude that they will be determined in large measure by the antecedents of the society ; and that between societies of the industrial type, there will be differences of political organization consequent on genealogical differences. Recog- POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. G51 nizing tlie analogies furnished by individual organizations, which everywhere show us that structures evolved during the earlier stages of a type for functions then requisite, usually do not disappear at later stages, but become re- moulded in adaptation to functions more or less different; we may suspect that the political institutions appropriate to the industrial type, will, in each society, continue to bear traces of the earlier political institutions evolved for other purposes ; as we see that even now the new societies growing up in colonies, tend thus to preserve marks of earlier stages passed through by ancestral societies. Hence we may infer that societies which, in the future, have alike become com- pletely industrial, will not present identical political forms ; but that to the various possible forms appropriate to the type, they will present approximations determined partly by their own structures in the past and partly by the structures of the societies from which they have been derived. Eecognizing this probability, let us now ask by what changes our own political constitution may be brought into congruity with the requirements. Though there are some who contend that a single body of representatives is sufficient for the legislative needs of a free nation, yet the reasons above given warrant the suspicion that the habitual duality of legislatures, of which the rudi- ments are traceable in the earliest political differentiation, is not likely to be entirely lost in the future. That spontaneous division of the primitive group into the distinguished few and the undistinguished many, both of which take part in deter- mining the actions of the group — that division which, with reviving power of the undistinguished many, reappears when there is formed a body representing it, which cooperates with the body formed of the distinguished few in deciding on national affairs, appears likely to continue. Assuming that as a matter of course two legislative bodies, if they exist hereafter, must both arise by representation, direct or indirect, it seems probable that an upper and a lqwer chamber may 19 652 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. continue to display a contrast in some degree analogous to that which they have displayed thus far. For however great the degree of evolution reached by an industrial society, it cannot abolish the distinction between the superior and the inferior —the regulators and the regulated. Whatever ar- rangements for carrying on industry may in times to come be established, must leave outstanding the difference between those whose characters and abilities raise them to the higher positions, and those who remain in the lower. Even should all kinds of production and distribution be eventually carried on by bodies of cooperators, as a few are now to some extent, such bodies must still have their appointed heads and com- mittees of managers. Either from an electorate constituted not, of course, of a permanently-privileged class, but of a class including all heads of industrial organizations, or from an electorate otherwise composed of all persons occupied in administration, a senate may perhaps eventually be formed consisting of the representatives of directing persons as dis- tinguished from the representatives of persons directed. Of course in the general government, as in the government of each industrial body, the representatives of the class regu- lated must be ultimately supreme ; but there is reason for thinking that the representatives of the regulating class might with advantage exercise a restraining power. Evidently the aspect of any law' differs according as it is looked at from above or from below — by those accustomed to rule or by those accustomed to be ruled. The two aspects require to be coordinated. Without assuming that differences between the interests of these bodies will, to the last, make needful dif- ferent representations of them, it may reasonably be con- cluded that the higher, experienced in administration, may with advantage bring its judgments to bear in qualifying the judgments of the lower, less conversant with affairs ; and that social needs are likely to be most effectually met by laws issuing from their joint deliberations. Far from suggesting an ultimate unification of the two legislative bodies, the facts POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 653 of evolution, everywhere showing advance in specialization, suggest rather that one or both of such two bodies, now characterizing developed political organizations, will further differentiate. Indeed we have at the present moment indi- cations that such a change is likely to take place in our own House of Commons. To the objection that the duality of a legislative body impedes the making of laws, the reply is that a considerable amount of hindrance to change is desirable. Even as it is now among ourselves, immense mis- chiefs are done by ill-considered legislation ; and any change which should further facilitate legislation would increase such mischiefs. Concerning the ultimate executive agency, it appears to be! an unavoidable inference that it must become, in some way or other, elective ; since hereditary political headship is a trait of the developed militant type, and forms a part of that regime of status which is excluded by the hypothesis. Guided by such evidence as existing advanced societies afford us, we may infer that the highest State-office, in what- ever way filled, will continue to decline in importance ; and that the functions to be discharged by its occupant will become more and more automatic. There requires an instru- mentality having certain traits which we see in our own executive, joined with certain traits which we see in the executive of the United States. On the one hand, it is need- ful that the men who have to carry out the will of the majority as expressed through the legislature, should be removable at pleasure ; so that there may be maintained the needful subordination of their policy to public opinion. On the other hand, it is needful that displacement of them shall leave intact all that part of the executive organization re- quired for current administrative purposes. In our own case these requirements, fulfilled to a considerable extent, fall short of complete fulfilment in the respect that the political head is not elective, and still exercises, especially over the foreign policy of the nation, a considerable amount of power, In 654 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. the United States, while these requirements are fulfilled in the respect that the political head is elective, and cannot compromize the nation in its actions towards other nations, they are not fulfilled in the respect that far from being an automatic centre, having actions restrained by a ministry responsive to public opinion, he exercises, during his term of office, much independent control. Possibly in the future, the benefits of these two systems may be united and their evils avoided. The strong party antagonisms which accompany our state of transition having died away, and the place of supreme State-officer having become one of honour rather than one of power, it may happen that appointment to this place, made during the closing years of a great career to mark the nation’s approbation, will be made without any social perturbation, because without any effect on policy; and that, meanwhile, such changes in the executive agency as are needful to harmonize its actions with public opinion, will be, as at present among ourselves, changes of minis- tries. Rightly to conceive the natures and workings of the central political institutions appropriate to the industrial type, we must assume that along with the establishment of them there has gone that change just named in passing — the decline of party antagonisms. Looked at broadly, political parties are seen to arise directly or indirectly out of the conflict between militancy and industrialism. Either they stand respectively for the coercive government of the one and the free government of the other, or for particular institutions and laws belonging to the one or the other, or for religious opinions and organiza- tions congruous with the one or the other, or for principles and practices that have been bequeathed by the one or the other, and survived under alien conditions. Habitually if we trace party feeling to its sources, we find on the one side maintenance of, and on the other opposition to, some form of inequity. Wrong is habitually alleged by this side against that ; and there must be injustice either in the thing done or POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 655 in the allegation concerning it. Hence as fast as the regime of voluntary cooperation with its appropriate ideas, senti- ments, and usages, pervades the whole society — as fast as there disappear all those arrangements which in any way trench upon the equal freedom of these or those citizens, party warfare must practically die away. Such differences of opinion only can remain as concern matters of detail and minor questions of administration. Evidently there is approach to such a state in proportion as the graver injus- tices descending from the militant type disappear. Evidently, too, one concomitant is that increasing subdivision of parties commonly lamented, which promises to bring about the result that no course can be taken at the dictation of any one moiety in power ; but every course taken, having the assent of the average of parties, will be thereby proved in harmony witli the aggregate will of the community. And clearly, with this breaking up of parties consequent on growing indivi- duality of nature, all such party-antagonisms as we now know must cease. Concerning local government we may conclude that as centralization is an essential trait of the militant type, de- centralization is an essential trait of the industrial type. With that independence which the regime of voluntary cooperation generates, there arises resistance not only to dictation by one man, and to dictation by a class, but even to dictation by a majority, when it restrains individual action in ways not necessary for maintaining harmonious social relations. One result must be that the inhabitants of each locality will object to be controlled by the inhabitants of other localities, in matters of purely local concern. In respect of such laws as equally apply to all individuals, and such laws as affect the inhabitants of each locality in their intercourse with those of other localities, the will of the majority of the community will be recognized as authorita- tive; but in respect of arrangements not affecting the com- munity at large, but affecting only the members forming one 656 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. part, we may infer that there will arise such tendency to resist dictation by members of other parts, as will involve the carrying of local rule to the greatest practicable limit. Municipal and kindred governments may be expected to exercise legislative and administrative powers, subject to no greater control by the central government than is needful for the concord of the whole community. Neither these nor any other speculations concerning ulti- mate political forms can, however, be regarded as anything more than tentative. They are ventured here simply as foreshadowing the general nature of the changes to be anti- cipated ; and in so far as they are specific, can be at the best but partially right. We may be sure that the future will bring unforeseen political arrangements along with many other unforeseen things. As already implied, there will pro- bably be considerable variety in the special forms of the political institutions of industrial societies : all of them bearing traces of past institutions which have been brought into congruity with the representative principle. And here I may add that little stress need be laid on one or other speciality of form ; since, given citizens having the pre- supposed appropriate natures, and but small differences in the ultimate effects will result from differences in the machinery used. § 579. Somewhat more definitely, and with somewhat greater positiveness, may we, I think, infer the political functions carried on by those political structures proper to the developed industrial type. Already these have been generally indicated ; but here they must be indicated some- what more specifically. We have seen that when corporate action is no longer needed for preserving the society as a whole from destruction or injury by other societies, the end which remains for it is that of preserving the component members of the society from destruction or injury by one another: injury, as here POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 657 interpreted, including not only immediate, but also remote, breaches of equity. Citizens whose natures have through many generations of voluntary cooperation and accompanying regard for one another’s claims, been moulded into the appro- priate form, will entirely agree to maintain such political institutions as may continue needful for insuring to each that the activities he carries on within limits imposed by the activities of others, shall bring to him all the directly-resulting benefits, or such benefits as indirectly result under voluntary agreements ; and each will be ready to yield up such small portion of the proceeds of his labour, as may be required to maintain the agency for adjudicating in complex cases where the equitable course is not manifest, and for such legislative and administrative purposes as may prove needful for effecting an equitable division of all natural advantages. Resistance to extension of government beyond the sphere thus indicated, must eventually have a two-fold origin — egoistic and altruistic. In the first place, it cannot be supposed that citizens having the characters indicated, w T ill, in their corporate capacity, agree to impose on themselves individually, other restraints than those necessitated by regard for one another’s spheres of action. Each has had fostered in him by the dis- cipline of daily life carried on under contract, a sentiment prompting assertion of his claim to free action within the implied limits ; and there cannot therefore arise in an aggre- gate of such, any sentiment which would tolerate further limits. And that any part should impose such further limits on the rest, is also contrary to the hypothesis ; since it pre- supposes that political inequality, or status, which is excluded by the industrial type. Moreover, it is manifest that the taking from citizens of funds for public purposes other than those above specified, is negatived. For while there will ever be a unanimous desire to maintain for each and all the conditions needful for severally carrying on their private activities and enjoying the products, the probabilities are 658 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. immense against agreement for any other public end. And in the absence of such agreement, there must arise resistance by the dissentients to the costs and administrative restraints required for achieving such other end. There must be dis- satisfaction and opposition on the part of the minority from whom certain returns of their labours are taken, not for fulfilling their own desires, but for fulfilling the desires of others. There must be an inequality of treatment which does not consist with the rigime of voluntary cooperation fully carried out. At the same time that the employment of political agencies for other ends than that of maintaining equitable relations among citizens, will meet with egoistic resistance from a minority who do not desire such other ends, it will also meet with altruistic resistance from the rest. In other words, the altruism of the rest wull prevent them from achieving such further ends for their own satisfaction, at the cost of dissatisfaction to those who do not agree with them. To one who is ruled by a predominant sentiment of justice, the thought of profiting in any w T ay, direct or indirect, at the expense of another, is repugnant ; and in a community of such, none will desire to achieve by public agency at the cost of all, benefits which a part do not participate in, or do not wish for. Given in all citizens a quick sense of equity, and it must happen, for example, that while those who have no children will protest against the taking away of their pro- perty to educate the children of others, the others will no less protest against having the education of their children partially paid for by forced exactions from the childless, from the unmarried, and from those whose means are in many cases less than their own. So that the eventual limi- tation of State-action to the fundamental one described, is insured by a simultaneous increase of opposition to other actions and a decrease of desire for them. § 580. The restricted sphere for political institutions thus POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 659 inferred as characterizing the developed industrial type, may also be otherwise inferred. Tor this limitation of State-functions is one outcome of that process of specialization of functions which accompanies organic and super-organic evolution at large. Be it in an animal or be it in a society, the progress of organization is constantly shown by the multiplication of particular struc- tures adapted to particular ends. Everywhere we see the law to be that a part which originally served several pur- poses and achieved none of them well, becomes divided into parts each of which performs one of the purposes, and, acquiring specially-adapted structures, performs it better. Throughout the foregoing chapters we have seen this truth variously illustrated by the evolution of the governmental organization itself. It remains here to point out that it is further illustrated in a larger way, by the division which has arisen, and will grow ever more decided, between the func- tions of the governmental organization as a whole, and the functions of the other organizations which the society in- cludes. Already we have seen that in the militant type, political control extends over all parts of the lives of the citizens. Already we have seen that as industrial development brings the associated political changes, the range of this control decreases : ways of living are no longer dictated ; dress ceases to be prescribed ; the rules of class-subordination lose their peremptoriness; religious beliefs and observances are not insisted upon ; modes of cultivating the land and carrying on manufactures are no longer fixed by law ; and the exchange of commodities, both within the community and with other communities, becomes gradually unshackled. That is to say, as industrialism has progressed, the State has re- treated from the greater part of those regulative actions it once undertook. This change has gone along with an in- creasing opposition of citizens to these various kinds of con- trol, and a decreasing tendency on the part of the State to 660 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. exercise them. Unless we assume that the end has now been reached, the implication is that with future progress of in- dustrialism, these correlative changes will continue. Citizens will carry still further their resistance to State-dictation ; while the tendency to State-dictation will diminish. Though recently, along with re-invigoration of militancy, there have gone extensions of governmental interference, yet this is in- terpretable as a temporary wave of reaction. We may expect that with the ending of the present retrograde movement and resumption of unchecked industrial development, that in- creasing restriction of State-functions which has unquestion- ably gone on during the later stages of civilization, will be resumed ; and, for anything that appears to the contrary, will continue until there is reached the limit above indi- cated. Along with this progressing limitation of political functions, has gone increasing adaptation of political agencies to the protecting function, and better discharge of it. During unqualified militancy, while the preservation of the society as a whole against other societies was the dominant need, the preservation of the individuals forming the society from destruction or injury by one another, was little cared for ; and in so far as it was cared for, was cared for mainly out of re- gard for the strength of the whole society, and its efficiency v for war. But those same changes which have cut off so many political functions at that time exercised, have greatly developed this essential and permanent political function. There has been a growing efficiency of the organization for guarding life and property ; due to an increasing demand on the part of citizens that their safety shall be insured, and an increasing readiness on the part of the State to respond. Evidently our own time, with its extended arrangements for administering justice, and its growing wish for codifi- cation of the law, exhibits a progress in this direction ; which will end only when the State undertakes to administer civil justice to the citizen free of cost, as it now undertakes. POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 661 free of cost, to protect his person and punish criminal aggres- sion on him. And the accompanying conclusion is that there will be simultaneously carried further that trait which already characterizes the most industrially-organized societies — the performance of increasingly-numerous and increasingly-im- portant functions by other organizations than those which form departments of the government. Already in our own case private enterprise, working through incorporated bodies of citizens, achieves ends undreamed of as so achievable in primitive societies ; and in the future, other ends undreamed of now as so achievable, will be achieved. § 581. A corollary having important practical bearings may be drawn. The several changes making up the trans- formation above indicated, are normally connected in their amounts ; and mischief must occur if the due proportions among them are not maintained. There is a certain right relation to one another, and a right relation to the natures of citizens, which may not be disregarded with impunity. The days when “ paper constitutions ” were believed in have gone by — if not with all, still with instructed people. The general truth that the characters of the units determine the character of the aggregate, though not admitted overtly and fully, is yet admitted to some extent — to the extent that most politically-educated persons do not expect forthwith completely to change the state of a society by this or that kind of legislation. But when fully admitted, this truth carries with it the conclusion that political institutions can- not be effectually modified faster than the characters of citizens are modified ; and that if greater modifications are by any accident produced, the excess of change is sure to be undone by some counter-change. When, as in France, people undisciplined in freedom are suddenly made politically free, they show by some plebiscite that they willingly deliver over their power to an autocrat, or they work their parliamentary 662 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. system in such way as to make a popular statesman into a dictator. When, as in the United States, republican insti- tutions, instead of being slowly evolved, are all at once created, there grows up within them an agency of wire- pulling politicians, exercising a real rule which overrides the nominal rule of the people at large. When, as at home, an extended franchise, very soon re-extended, vastly augments the mass of those who, having before been controlled are made controllers, they presently fall under the rule of an organized body that chooses their candidates and arranges for them a political programme, which they must either accept or be powerless. So that in the absence of a duly- adapted character, liberty given in one direction is lost in another. Allied to the normal relation between character and in- stitutions, are the normal relations among institutions them- selves ; and the evils which arise from disregard of the second relations are allied to those which arise from disregard of the first. Substantially there is produced the same general effect. The slavery mitigated in one direction is intensified in another. Coercion over the individual, relaxed here is tightened there. For, as we have seen, that change which accompanies development of the industrial type, and is involved by the progress towards those purely equitable relations which the regime of voluntary cooperation brings, implies that the political structures simultaneously become popular in their origin and restricted in their functions. But if they become more popular in their origin without becoming more restricted in their functions, the effect is to foster arrangements which benefit the inferior at the expense of the superior ; and by so doing work towards degradation. Swayed as individuals are on the average by an egoism which dominates over their altruism, it must happen that even when they become so far equitable in their sentiments that they will not commit direct injustices, they will remain liable to commit injustices of indirect kinds. And since the majority must ever be formed POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 663 of the inferior, legislation, if unrestricted in its range, will inevitably be moulded by them in such way as more or less remotely to work out to their own advantage, and to the disadvantage of the superior. The politics of trades’-unions exemplify the tendency. Their usages have become such that the more energetic and skilful workmen are not allowed to profit to the full extent of their capacities ; because, if they did so, they would discredit and disadvantage those of lower capacities, who, forming the majority, establish and enforce the usages. In multitudinous ways a like tendency must act through a political organization, if, while all citizens have equal powers, the organization can be used for other purposes than administering justice. State-machineries worked by taxes falling in more than due proportion on those whose greater powers have brought them greater means, will give to citizens of smaller powers more benefits than they have earned. And this burdening of the better for the benefit of the worse, must check the evolution of a higher and more adapted nature : the ultimate result being that a community by which this policy is pursued, will, other things equal, fail in competition with a community which pursues the purely equitable policy, and will eventually disappear in the race of civilization. In brief, the diffusion of political power unaccompanied by the limitation of political functions, issues in communism. Tor the direct defrauding of the many by the few, it sub- stitutes the indirect defrauding of the few by the many : evil proportionate to the inequity, being the result in the one case as in the other. § 582. But the conclusion of profoundest moment to which all lines of argument converge, is that the possibility of a high social state, political as well as general, fundamentally de- pends on the cessation of war. After all that has been said it is needless to emphasize afresh the truth that persistent militancy, maintaining adapted institutions, must inevitably 664 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. prevent, or else neutralize, changes in the direction of more equitable institutions and laws ; while permanent peace will of necessity be followed by social ameliorations of every kind. From war has been gained all that it had to give. The peopling of the Earth by the more powerful and intelligent races, is a benefit in great measure achieved ; and what remains to be done, calls for no other agency than the quiet pressure of a spreading industrial civilization on a barbarism which slowly dwindles. That integration of simple groups into compound ones, and of these into doubly com- pound ones, which war has effected, until at length great nations have been produced, is a process already carried as far as seems either practicable or desirable. Empires formed of alien peoples habitually fall to pieces when the coercive power which holds them together fails ; and even could they be held together, would not form harmoniously-w~orking wholes : peaceful federation is the only further consolidation to be looked for. Such large advantage as war has yielded by developing that political organization which, beginning with the leadership of the best warrior has ended in complex governments and systems of administration, has been fully obtained ; and there only remains for the future to preserve and re-mould its useful parts while getting rid of those no longer required. So, too, that organization of labour initiated by war — an organization which, setting out with the relation of owner and slave and developing into that of master and servant, has, by elaboration, given us industrial structures having numerous grades of officials, from head-directors down to foremen — has been developed quite as far as is requisite for combined action ; and has to be hereafter modified, not in the direction of greater military subordination, but rather in the opposition direction. Again, the power of continuous application, lacking in the savage and to be gained only under that coercive discipline which the militant type of society establishes, has been already in large measure acquired by the civilized man; and such further degree of it as is needed. POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 665 will be produced under the stress of industrial competition in free communities. Nor is it otherwise with great public 'works and developed industrial arts. Though, in the canal cut by the Persians across the isthmus of Athos, and again in a canal of two miles long made by the Fijians, we see both that war is the first prompter to such undertakings and that the despotic rule established by it is the needful agency for carrying them out ; yet we also see that industrial evolu- tion has now reached a stage at which commercial advantage supplies a sufficient stimulus, and private trading corporations a sufficient power, to execute works far larger and more numerous. And though from early days when flint arrow- heads were chipped and clubs carved, down to present days when armour-plates a foot thick are rolled, the needs of defence and offence have urged on invention and mechanical skill ; yet in our own generation steam-hammers, hydraulic rams, and multitudinous new appliances from locomotives to telephones, prove that industrial needs alone have come to furnish abundant pressure whereby, hereafter, the industrial arts will be further advanced. Thus, that social evolution which had to be achieved through the conflicts of societies with one another, has already been achieved ; and no further benefits are to be looked for. J Only further evils are to be looked for from the conti- nuance of militancy in civilized nations. The general lesson taught by all the foregoing chapters is that, indispensable as has been this process by which nations have been conso- lidated, organized, and disciplined, and requisite as has been the implied coercion to develop certain traits of individual human nature, yet that, beyond the unimaginable amount of suffering directly involved by the process, there has been an unimaginable amount of suffering indirectly involved ; alike by the forms of political institutions necessitated, and by the accompanying type of individual nature fostered. And they show by implication that for the diminution of this suffering, not only of the direct kind but of the indirect kind, the one 666 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. thing needful is the checking of international antagonisms and the diminution of those armaments which are at once cause and consequence of them. With the repression of militant activities and decay of militant organizations, will come amelioration of political institutions as of all other insti- tutions. Without them, no such ameliorations are permanently possible. Liberty overtly gained in name and form will be unobtrusively taken aw T ay in fact. It is not to be expected, however, that any very marked effects are to be produced by the clearest demonstration of this truth — even by a demonstration beyond all question. A general congruity has to be maintained between the social state at any time necessitated by circumstances, and the accepted theories of conduct, political and individual. Such acceptance as there may be of doctrines at variance with the temporary needs, can never be more than nominal in degree, or limited in range, or both. The acceptance which guides conduct will always be of such theories, no matter how logically indefensible, as are consistent with the average modes of action, public and private. All that can be done by diffusing a doctrine much in advance of the time, is to facilitate the action of forces tending to cause advance. The forces themselves can be but in small degrees increased; but something may be done by preventing mis-direction of them. Of the sentiment at any time enlisted on behalf of a higher social state, there is always some (and at the present time a great deal) which, having the broad vague form of sympathy with the masses, spends itself in efforts for their welfare by multiplication of political agencies of one or other kind. Led by the prospect of immediate beneficial results, those swayed by this sympathy are unconscious that they are helping further to elaborate a social organization at variance with that required for a higher form of social life, and are, by so doing, increasing the obstacles to attainment of that higher form. On a portion of such the foregoing chapters may have some effect by leading them to con- POLITICAL RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT. 667 sider whether the arrangements they are advocating involve increase of that public regulation characterizing the militant type, or whether they tend to produce that greater indi- viduality and more extended voluntary cooperation, charac- terizing the industrial type. To deter here and there one from doing mischief by imprudent zeal, is the chief proxi- mate effect to be hoped for. END OF VOL. IL REFERENCES. To find tlie authority for any statement in the text, the reader is to proceed as follows : — Observing the number of the section in which the statement occurs, he will first look out, in the following pages, the corresponding number, which is printed in conspicuous type. Among the references succeeding this number, he will then look for the name of the tribe, people, or nation concerning which the statement is made (the names in the references standing in the same order as that which they have in the text) ; and that it may more readily catch the eye, each such name is printed in Italics. In the parenthesis following the name, will be found the volume and page of the work referred to, preceded by the first three or four letters of the author’s name ; and where more than one of his works has been used, the first three or four letters of the title of the one containing the particular statement. The meanings of these abbreviations, employed to save the space that would be occupied by frequent repetitions of full titles, is shown at the end of the references ; where will be found arranged in alphabetical order, these initial syllables of authors’ names, &c., and opposite to them the full titles of the works referred to. § 343. Australians (Mit. ii, 68 ; i, 87 ; i, 84 ; Aug. i, 59) — Tasmanians (Bon. pp. 3,37, 226) — Esquimaux (reference lost)— Comanches (Banc, i, 519) — Araucanians (Smith, 195) — Bedouins (Bur. iii, 43) — Arabs (Lyon, 53) — Abys- sinians (Duf. 172) — Balonda (Liv. “Mis. Tra.” 276) — Malagasy (Ell. “Hist, of Mad.” i, 258) — Samoans (Tur. 289). § 344. Chinese (Wil. S. W. ii, 68) — Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.” i, 319 ; ii, 369) — Tongans (Mar. ii, 78,100) — Ancient Mexicans (Dur. i, ch. 26) — Peru (Gar. bk. ii, ch. 12) — Japanese (Ale. i, 63) — England (Whar. 469) — Sandwich Islanders ( Ell. “Hawaii,” 365-67) — Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.” ii, ch. 7) — Nicaraguans (Ovi. bk. xlii, ch. 2 & 3) — Hebrews (Kue. i, 292-3). § 345. Tongans (Mar. i, 146, note) — Fijians (Wil. Rev. J. — ) — Siamese (Loub. i, 353) — Chinese (Wil. S. W. i, 313) — * Japanese ( Stein. 348). § 346. Mongol (Timk.i, 19 6) —Philippines (Jag. 161) — Chita - gong Hill Tribes (Lew. 46) — Burmese (Fyt. ii, 69) — Samoans (Tur. 346) — Esquimaux (Beech, i, 345) — New Zealanders (Cook, “Last Voy.” 49) — Snake Indians (Lew. & Cl. 266) — Comanches (Mar. 29) — Fuegians (Snow, i, 263 ; Loango (Bat. in “Pink. Voy.” xvi, 331) — Batoka (Liv. “Miss. Tra.” 551) — Balonda (Liv. “ Miss. Tra.” 296) — Loango (Ast. iii, 238) — Fiji (Wil. Rev. J. i, 37) — Australians (Mit. i, 247) — New Zealanders (Ang. ii, 32-75) — Central REFERENCES, 669 South Africa (Liv. “Miss. Tra.” 448 )— Shoshones (Banc, vi, 438 ) — Australians (Ang. i, 59) — Vate (Ersk. 334) — Samoan (Tur. 194) — Africa (Liv. “ Miss. Tra.” ii, 49) — Peruvians (Cie. ch. 44) — Egyptians (Wilk. plates) — Moslem (Klunz. 106) — Tahitians (Wal. “ Hawk. Voy.” i, 447) — Kaffirs (Bar. i, 75) — Tasmanians (West, ii, 7 ) — Arabs (Bak. “Nile Trib.” 125). § 347. Pata- gonians (Falk. 121-2) — Madagascar (Ell. “ Hist. Mad.” ii, 258) — Samoans (Tur. 348 ) — Fijians (Ersk. 254 ) — Ashantees (Dup. 43 ) — Yorubas (Lan. i, 125) Madagascar (Drur. 218 ) — China (Staun. 345 ) — Samoa (Tur. 314 ) — Madagascar (Ell. “ Visits,” 127 ) — Japanese (Stein. 69) — Chinese (Mil. 94) — Borne (Beck. 213) — Assyrians (Raw. i, 503-4) — Mexico (Her. iii, 202-3 ; Torq. bk. ix, ch. 20; — Nicaragua (Squ. ii, 340 ) — Peru (Piz. 225 ; Xer. 48 ) — Chibchas (Pied. bk. i, ch. 5 ) — Uganda (Speke 294 ) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 294) — Abyssinians (Duf. 71 ; Bru. iv, 454, 417 ) — Japanese (Koem. 55-6) — Egypt (Eb. i, 352) — New Zealand (Thom, i, 114) — China (Hue. “Trav. in Tar.” ii, 261 ; Gutz. ii, 311 ; Will. 5. W., i, 331-2 ; ii, 68-9)— Japanese (Dick. 283; Mit. ii, 43) — France (Vul. pas- sim ; Cher. Diet. 536-7) — England (Nob. passim) — Peru (Acos. bk. v, ch. 6) — Madagascar (Ell. “ Hist. Mad.” i, 356) — England (Nob. 96 & passim) — France (Vul. passim). § 349. Vate (Tur. 393) — Shoshones (Banc, i, 438) — Mish- mis (Coop. 190) — Santals (Sher. “ Jour. As. Soc. Bengal,” xx, 582) — Kooseas (Lich. i, 288) — Ashanti (Beech. — ) — Ceris and Opatas (Banc, i, 581) — Chi- cliimecs (Banc, i, 629). § 350. Hebrews (Judges, vii, 25; 1 Samuel xvii, 54) — Chichimecs (Banc, i, 629) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 408) — Mundrucus (Hen. 475) — New Zealanders (Thom, i, 130) — Congo (Tuck. 101) — Ashantee (Dup. 227) — Persia (Mor. “ Sec. Jour.” 186) — Timour (Gib. 1131)— Dahomey (Bur. i, 218 ; Dal. 76) — Northern Celebes (reference lost) — Dyaks (Boyle, 170) Kukis (Fisher, Jour. As. Soc. Ben. ix, 836) — Borneo (St. John “ Far East,” ii, 28). § 351. Ashantee (Ram. & Kiih. 130)— Tahitians (Cook, “ Hawk. Voy.” ii, 161) — Vate (Tur. 393) — Boigu (Geog. Soc. 1876, letter from Mr. Stone of Sept. 7, 1875) — Tupis (South, i, 222) — Caribs (Edw. i, 45) — Moxos (Hutch. “ The Pa- rana,” 34) — Central Americans (Fan. 314-5) — Poland (Gib. 1116) — Constantine (Gib. 811) — Montenegro (The Times, Dec. 14, 1876). § 352. Mexicans (Cam. iii, 134 ; Sah. bk. ix, c. 15) — Yucatan (Her. iv. 174) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 408) — Shoshones (Lew. & Cl. 309) — Nagas (Grange, Jour. As. Soc. Ben. ix, 959) — Mandans (Cat. i, 136) — Cochimis (Banc, i, 567). § 353. Mexicans (Banc, i, 581) — Californians (Banc, i, 380) — Khonds (Macph. 57) — Egyptians (Dun. i, 131) — Abyssinians (Bruce vi, 116-17 ; d’Heri. 188-9)— Hebrews (l Sam. xviii, 25). § 354. Osages (Tylor “ Prim. Cult.” 2nd ed. i, 416) — Ojibways (Hind ii, 123). § 355. Salic (Salic Law, lxiv, 9; Lehuerou, ii, 370 )—Jeivs, 2 Mac. xv, 30 ; 2 Sam. iv, 12). § 356. Gauls (Diod. v, 2) — Timour (Gib. 1130)— Khonds (Macph. 57) — Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.”i, 488)— Greeks (Pot. ii, 109-10)— Fijians (U.S. Ex. Ex. iii, 79) — Flemish (Cher. 358) — French (Leb. vi, 127). §357. Scotland (Bur. i, 398) — Khonds (Macph. 46) — Athenians (Grote iv, 222) — Fiji (Wil. i, 31 ; Ersk. 454) — Panthay (Baber) — Fiji (Ersk. 454) — Shoshones (Banc, i, 433) — Chichimecs (Banc, i, 629) — Hebreivs (1 Sam. xi, 1-3) — Bulgarians (Gib. 975). § 358. Araucanians (Thomp. i, 406) — Bac- trians (Dun. i, 174) — Hebrews (Judges i, 6-7)— Fiji (Wil. i, 30; i, 197-8; i, 177) — Charruas (Hutch. 48 et seq.) — Mandans (Lew. & Cl. 86) — Tonga (Mar. ii, 210) — Australians (Mit.ii, 345) — Hottentot (Pink. Voy. xvi, 141 ) — Egypt (Wilk. i, 307) — Japanese (Busk, 241) — Europe (Lex Gomb, xxvi, 4 ; Lex Wisig. viii. 6, 2) — England (“Leges Gul.” i, cap. 7). § 359. Central Americans (Her. iv, 135) — Ashantees (Ram. & Kuh. 216) — Anc. Mexico (Clav. bk. vii, c. 17) — Honduras (Her. iv, 140) — Miztecas (Her. iii, 262-3) — Zapotecas (Her. vii. 269) Hebrews (Knobel ex. w. Lev. 214) — Burmese (Sang. 124) — Gond (For. 164) — Astrachan (Bell i, 43 )— Hebreivs (2 Kings xix; Lay. ii, 288; Van-Len. ii, 688). § 360. Sandwich Islands (Ell. “ Hawaii,” 146 ; Cook “ Sec. Voy.” ii, 69) — Australians (Ang. ii, 217 ; Hay. i, 103) — Anc. Peruvians (Cieza, chs. 47, 49) — Damaras (Gal. 148) — Sierra Leone (Wint. i, 104). § 361. Britain (Cox and Jones, 88)— Kalmucks(Psi\. i, 194) — Chinese (Wil. S.W. ii, 2 2 4)— Greeks and 670 CEREMONIAL INSTITUTIONS. Homans (Smith, “ Sm. Die. Ant .”s.v. “Coma”) — Nootkas (Banc. i, 19 5 )— Caribs (Ed. i, 53) — Nicaragua (Her. iii, 298) — Central Americans (Cog. bk. iv. ch. 4) — Ancient Mexicans (Zur. 110-111 ) — Chib chas (Pied, bk. i,ch. 2)— Itzaex(Fan.3\S) — Ottomans (Pax. ii, 87) — Greeks (Beck. “ Charicles” 452-55) — Franks (Guer. “Polyp.” i, 300 ; Agath. ii, 49 ; Greg, iii, 18) — Japanese ( Busk, 144) — Samoans (Tur. “Polynesia,” 205) — New Caledonians (Jour. Ethn. Soc. iii, 56 )— Europe (Due. 87) — Clovis and Alaric (Due. 88) — Dacotahs (Lew. & Cl. 54) — Caribs (Ed. i, 53) — Hebrevjs (Lev. xxi, 5 ; Jer. xvi, 6) — Greeks and Romans (Smith, “Sm. Die. of Ant.” s.v. “ Coma”) — Greeks (Pot. ii, 198-9 ; Jebb. 46 ; Beck. “ Charicles,” 398; Smith, “ Sm.Dic. of Ant.” s.v . “ Coma ”) — Romans (reference lost) — Hebrews (Jer. xli. 5) — Arabians (Krehl, 23) — Ancient Peru (Acosta, bk. y, ch. 5) — Sandwich Islanders (Ell. “Hawaii,” 29) — Tahitians (Hawk’s.Voy. i, 468) — France (Guizot “ Col.” i). § 362 . Spoleto (Gib. 987) — Phrygian (Dun. i, 531) — Mexicans (Brin. 147) — Hottentots (Kol. i, 112) — Phoenicians (Movers) — San Salvador (Pal. 87) — il/oses(Exod. iv, 24-26)— Antiochus (Macc. i, 48-60) — Mattathias (Macc. ii,45-6) — Hyrcanus (Jos. Ant.xiii, 9, 1) — Aristobulus (Jos. Ant. xiii, 11, 3) — Tongans (Mar. ii, 79) — Berbers (Kohl. 45). § 363 . Kaffirs (Gard. 264) — Jews (Jerem. xli, 5) — Samoans (Tur. 187) — Central Americans (Mart. 338). § 364 . Huns (Jor. 49) — Turks (Pell. 29) — Lace- dcemonians (Pot. ii, 204) — Hebrews (Levit. xix, 28) — Scandinavians (Heims- kringla Saga, caps. 4-10) — Andamans (Trans. Eth. Soc. N.S. ii, 36) — Aheokuta (Bur. i, 104) — Cuebas (Banc, i, 753) — Peruvians (Cieza, cap. 88) — Sandwich Islanders (Cook “Sec. Voy.” ii, 152) — Parian Indians (Banc, i, 771) — Uaupes (Wal. Wl)Sandwich Islanders (Ell. “Hawaii,” 146)— Eastern (Grim. iv, 241) — Hebrews (Deut. xxxii, 5 ; Rev. vii, 2-3 ; xiv, 1, 9, 10) — Arabs (Thom. 66) — Christians' ( Kal. ii, 429 30) — Mexico (Torq. bk. ix, ch. 31) — Angola (Bast. 76) — Tongans (Mar. ii, 2G8) — Borneo (Boyle, 223) — Panuco (Witt ii, 288) — New Zealanders (Ang. i, 315) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 23). § 365 . Bechuanas (Lich. ii, 331) — Damaras (And. 224) — Congo (Tuck. 80) — Itsaex (Pan. 313) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 35, — Arawaks (Schom. ii, 458). § 368 . Ancient Peruvians (Gar. bk. ii, ch. 4). § 369 . Mexico (Torq. bk. xiv, ch. 9) — Chibchas (Sim. 251) — Yucatan (Landa, § xx) — Tahitians (Forst. 370) — Fiji (Wil. i, 28) — Tahiti (Ell. “Pol. Res.” i, 319) — Fiji (Ersk. 431) — Malagasy (Drur. 220). § 370 . Tim- buctoo (Cail. ii, 53) — Kaffirs (Lich. i, 286) — Koosa (Lich. i, 271) — Vera Pas (Torq. bk. xi, ch. 19) — Chibchas (Pied. bk. i, ch. 5) — Mexicans (Tern, i, 404-5) — Peru (Guz. 91) — Hebrews (2 Chron. ix ; 1 Sam. x, 27) — Japan (Dick. 391 ; Koem. 49) — China (Chin. Rep. iii, 110-11) — Burmah (Yule, 76) — Merovingians (Gall, ii, 647) — England (Rob. 20). § 371 . Persia (Mai. ii, 478-9) — Tonga (Mar. i, 231) — Mexicans (Dur. i, ch. 25) — Meztillan (Tern, ii, 289) — Montezuma (Gal. i, 116 ; Tern, i, 404-5) — Merovingians and Carolingians (Waitz ii, 557; iv, 91-5-8 ; Guer. “ St. Pere,” introd. ; Leber, vii, 418 ; Guer. “ St. Pere,” in- trod.) — English (Stubbs, i, 278). § 372 . Chibchas (Pied. bk. ii, ch. 4) — Sumatra (Mars. 211) — India (Drew, 15) — Anglo-Saxons (Broom, 26) — Normans (Mozley, s. v. “ Orig. Writ.”)— Kir gliis (Mitch. 248) — France (Guizot, iii, 260; Chtr. voce “ Epices”) — English (Rob. 1 ; Scob. ii, 148-394 ; Stubbs, i, 384) — Russia (Cust. 53) — Spain (Rose, i, 79) — Bechuanas ( Bur. i, 544) — Dahomey (For. i, 34)— East (VanLen.ii, 592). § 373 * Congo (Tuck. 115) —Tonquin (Tav.) — New Caledonians (Tur. 88) — Veddah (Trans. Eth. S.L. N.S. ii, 301) — Dyaks (Brooke, i, 73) — Greeks (Guhl, 283) — Zulu (Gard. 96) — Hebrews (Levit. i) — Greeks (Pot. i, 239) — Hebrews (l Sam. xxi, 6) — England (Hook, 541). § 374 . Ancient Mexico (Saha. bk. iii, ch. 1, § 3-4) — Kukis (Stewart, Jour. R.A.S. Ben. xxiv, 630) — Battas (Mars. 386) — Bustars (His. 17) — Dahomey (Bur. ii, 151, et seq . ; For. i, 174)— Ashantees (Beech. 188)— Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.” ii, 271) — Central America (Ovi. bk. xlii, ch. 2) — Greeks (Pot. i, 172, 247) — Early Christians ( Hook, 540) — Mediceval (Guer. “N. Dame,” xiv). § 375 . China (Staun. 351) — Kukis (But. 94) — Dahomey (For. ii, 243) — Germans (Tac. xiv.) — French (Due. 20 ; Mons. i, ch. 59). § 376 . Australians (Cook “Hawk. Voy.” iii, 634) — Osbyaks (Bell ii, 189) — Julijunda (Park, l GO) — North American REFERENCES. 671 Indians (Cat. i, 2*22, note) — Yucatanese (Landa, § xxiii) — Japanese (Mifc. i, 112 ; i, 142) — Himalayas (Mark. 108) — Bootan (Tur. 73, 233) — Rome (Cor. 120) — France (Meril, 115). § 379. Jolojfs (Mol. 31, 42) — Kaffirs (Shooter, 99) — Ancient Peruvians (Cieza, ch. 74 ; Xer. Reports, 68) — Mexico (Tem.- Comp. ii, 332, &c.) — Asliantee (Beech. 94-6) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 296) — Mada- gascar (Ell. “ Visits,' ” 127) — Siam (Bowr. ii, 108) — Mogul (Tav. “Hist.” 67) — Jummoo (Drew, “ North. Bar.” 47) — Japan (Koem. 49, 66, 11) — France (de Tocq. bk. ii, ch. xii). § 380. Spain (Rose i, 119) — Japan (Koem. 51 ; 46). § 381. Wahhabees (Pal. ii, 110) — Persia (Tav. “Travels,” bk. v, ch. xvi, 235) — Africa (Grant, 48) — French (Rules of Civility (1685). § 383. Shoshones (Lew. & Cl. 265) — BatoJca (Liv. “ Miss. Tra.” 551) — Tonga (For.st. 361)— Africa (Laird i, 192) — East Peru (Gar. bk. iii, ch. 2; Est. 94). § 384. Chibcha (Sim. 264) — Borghoo (Lan. ii, 183)— Asia (Camp. 147; Bowr.ii, 270) — Polynesia (Cook, 304)— Jews (2 Sam. ix, 6) — Bithynia (Mom. ii, 31 1) — Bootan (Tur. 80) — Coast Negroes (Bos, 317) — Brass (Laird i, 97) — Congo (Tuck. 125) — Niger (All. & T. i, 391) — Russia (Sel. iii, 279) — China (Will. S. W. ii, 68) — Hebrews (1 Kings i, 23 ; Gen. xxxiii, 3; Gen. xvii, 17; Dan. ii, 46) — Mon- gols (Pall, ii, 170) — Japanese (Koem. 50). § 385. Dahomey (Bur. i, 261) — Mexicans (Dur. i, 207)— New Caledonians (Ersk. 356) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 261) — Siam (Bowr. i, 128) — Cambodia (Bowr. ii, 31) — Zulu (Gard. 203) — Loango (Ast. iii, 221) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 250; ii, 45) — Japan (Dick. 30) — China (“Pink. Voy.” vii, 238) — Europe (Alie. 197-8) — Japanese (Chin. Rep. iii, 260) — China (Will. S. W. ii, 68 — Soosoos (Wint. i, 122)— Samoa (Tur. 332) — Ancient Mexicans (Cam. ii, 200) — Chinese (Will, ii, 68) — Congoese (Bas. 143). § 386. Loango (Ast. iii, 238, in “ Pink. Voy.” xvi) — Uganda (Speke, 331) — Balonda (Liv. “Miss. Tra.” 276-96) — Karague (Grant, 140)— Fiji (Will, i, 35) — Eboe (Laird i, 388) — Ancient Mexicans (Diaz, ch. 71) — Abyssinians (Har. iii, 170)— Malagasy (Dru. 415-67) — Ancient Peru (Xer. 68) — Persia (Por. i, 464) — Tonga (Mar. i, 227)— Arabian (Pax. ii, 43) — Mexico (Clav. bk. vi, ch. 8) — Peru (Acos. bk. v, ch. 4; Gar. bk. ii, ch. 8) — Greeks (Smith’s “ Sm. Die. of Ant.” s.v. “ Saltatio.”)— Pepin (Gall, v, 433). § 387. Africa (Bur. i, 259- 60 ; All. & T. i, 345 ; Liv. “Miss. Tra.” 276, 296 ; All. & T. i, 391) — Jews (Jos. “ Wars,” ii, 15) — Turkey (White ii, 239 ; i, 232) — Jews (1 Kings xx, 32 ; Josh, vii, 6). § 388. Uganda (Grant, 224) — Chinese (Doo. 86-7) — Mongol (Hue i, 54) — Malagasy (Drur. 78) — Siamese (Loub. i, 179) — Unyan- yembe (Grant, 52) — Sumatra (Mars. 281) — Greeks (reference lost) — Siamese (Bowr. ii, 128) — China (Will. S. W. ii. 68). § 389. Fijians (Ersk. 297) — Otaheitans (Cook, Hawk. Voy. ii, 84) — Soudan (Tylor, “Early Hist.” 50 — Uganda (Speke, 374) — Abyssinia (Har. iii, 171) — Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.” ii, 352 ; Eorst. 361) — Gold Coast (Oruic. ii, 282 ; Bur. i, 337) — Spain (Ford “ Gatherings,” 249) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 49) — Gold Coast (Cruic. ii, 282) — Ancient America (And. 58; Tern, i, 113 — Burmah (Yule, 79) — Persia (Mor. i, 241) — Ancient Mexico (Diaz, ch. 91) — Peru (And. 58 ) — Dahomey (Dal. Intro, vii)— France (Com. ii, 3; St. Sim. xi, 378) — Hebrews (Isa. xxxii, 11) — East (Pax. ii, 136) — Peru (Gar. bk. vi, ch. 21) — Damaras (And. 231) — Turks (White ii, 96). § 390. Toorkee (Grant, 333) — Slave Coast (Bos. 317). § 391. China (Gray i, 211) — Mosquitos (Banc, i, 741) — Arabs (Mai. 8 ; Nieb. ii. 247) — Uganda (Grant, 228). § 392. Poles (Spen. “Germany,” i, 156-7) — Turkish (White ii, 303) — Siam (Bowr. i, 127; Loub. vi, 178) — Russia (reference lost). § 393. Tupis (Stade, 59 & 151) — Africa (Mol. 288) — Delhi (Wils. letter) — Sandwich Is. (Ell. “Hawaii,” 357) — France (Sain. ch. 69) — Spain (Ford “ Handbook,” § 17, 53). § 394. France (Cher. Diet, ii, 1131) — Hebrews (2 Sam. xiv, 22 ; Isaiah xlviii, 20 ; 2 Kings xvi, 7) — Europe (Luc. 90) — India (Wils. letter)— Samoan (Tur. 348). § 395. Siam (Bowr. i, 127) — Turkey (White ii, 52) — Bulgarians (Times, 12 Dec. 1876) — French (Sully ii, 78) — Delhi (Tav. “Hist.” 84-5) — France (Mon. iii, 152) — Chinese (Gray i, 211) — India (Pax. ii , 74 ; Wils. letter) — Persians (Tav. bk. v, ch. iii, 205). § 396. Snakes (Lew. & Cl. 266) — Araucanians (Smith, 195) — Arabs (Lyon, 53) — 672 CEREMONIAL INSTITUTIONS, Chinese (Halde ii, 185) — France (Mon. ii, 165-6). § 397. Abipones (Dob. ii, 204) — Samoa (Ersk. “ West Pac.” 107) — Javans (Raf. i, 366 ) — Mexican (Gal. i, 28) — Kaffirs (Shooter, 221) — Samoa (Ersk. “ West Pac.” 43) — Siam (Bowr. i, 276) — China (Chin. Rep. iv, 157) — Siam (Bowr. i, 127-8) — Chinese (Halde ii, 177) — Siamese (Loub. i, 168) — Japanese (Stein. 209) — Germany (Ger. 124 ; May. i, 394) — France (Chal. ii, 31) — Samoa (Tur. “Poly.” 340). § 398. Dacotahs (Bur. 144) — Veddahs (Bailey, Transactions Ethnological Society, London, N. S., ii, 298) — China (Chin. Rep. iv, 157). § 400. Tupis (South, i, 222) — Creeks (reference lost) — Nicaragua (Ovi. bk. xxix, ch. 12) — Fiji ( Wil. i, 55) — Mexico (Dur. i, 102-3) — Fiji (Ersk. 443). § 401. Twpis (South, i, 239) — Guatemala (Xim. 163) — Dahomey (Bur. ii, Ap. iv.) — Usambara (Krapf, 395) — Zulu (Gard. 91 ; Shooter, 290) — Kaffir (Shooter, 98) — Samoa (Ersk. 43) — Burmah ( Daily News , 24 Mar. 1879). § 402. Tartars (Pink.Yoy.vii, 591) — Madagascar (Ellis “Hist.” i, 261 ) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 262) — Ancient Mexicans (Mot. 31) — Kasias (Jour. A. S.B. xiii, 620). § 403. China and Japan (Ale. ii, 343) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 273)— Asia (Tav. ‘‘Hist.” 24) — Zulus (Gard. 91) — Japanese (Mit. i, 202) — Siam (Bowr. i, 275) — China (Hue. i, 268) — Siam (Pink. Yoy. ix, 586) — Russia (Wahl, 35) — Dyaks (St. John ii, 103) — Kasias (Jour, xiii, 620) — Becliuana (Thomp. i, 174). § 404. Teutonic (Mul. ii. 280). § 405. King (Mul. ii, 284— Abyssinia ( Bruce iv, 4 5 2)— France (Cher. 66-7 ) — Merovingian ( Mich. i, 69). § 406. Samoa (Tur. “ Poly.” 281 ) — Siam ( Turpin “Pink. Yoy.” ix, 584 ; Loub. i, 238) — Chinese (Will. S.W. ii, 71 ; and i, 521) — Rome (Mom. ii, 347-8) — Mecklenburgh (Spen. “Ger.” i, 44) — Spain (Ford “ Handbook,” §xvii, 52). § 407. Dahomey (Bur. i, 52) — Burman (Yule, 194) — China (Wil. S.W. i, 317) — Europe (Ger. 9i) — Russia (Sala, 252). § 408. Kami (Grant. 92) — Uganda (Speke, 290) — Chichimecs (Church. Yoy.iv, 513 — Yucatanese (Lan. § xxix). § 409. Japan (Busk, 21) — Madagascar (Ell. “ Visits,” 178) — Uganda (Speke, 375) — Japan (Dick. 49) — Hebreivs (Ew. iii, 73) — Zeus (Pau. Grsec. Des. ix, c. 40, §6) — Franks (Waitz. ii, 130; Greg, vii, 33; Bullet in Leber xiii, 259-65) — Araucanians (Thom, i, 404) — Uganda (Speke, 429) — France (Quich. ref. lost). § 410. Peruvians (Gar. bk. vii, c. 6 ; Mark. “ Reports,” 53) — Sandwich Is. (Ell. “ Hawaii,” 126) — Fijians (U. S. Ex. Ex. iii, 79) — Chibchas (Sim. 269) — Mexicans (Clav. bk. vii, chs. 22 & 24). § 411. Thlinlceets (Banc, i, 109) — China (Halde, i, 278). § 412. Africa (Speke, ref. lost; Heug. 92) — Greeks (Guhl, 232) — Sandwich Is. (Cook “Hawk. Yoy.” ii, 192) — Tonga (Cook “ Hawk. Yoy.” i, 87 ) — Fundah (Laird i, 202) — Arabs (Pal. 153, new ed.) — Gaul (Quich. 25-31 ; 57-66) — Rome (Guhl, 485) — Madagascar (Ell. “Hist.” i, 279 — Siam (Loub. i, 75) — Mongol (Bell “ Pink. Voy.” vii; 357) — France (Legrand D’Aussy, Fab. ii, 231*2) — China (Staun. 244) — Japan (Koem. 43). § 413. Guatemala (Urrutia, Athenceum, 1856, p. 1537) — Chibchas (Pied. bk. i, ch. 2) — Cimbri (Aikin, 17) — Ashantee (Dup. 71) — Malagasy (Ell. “ Hist.” i, 283) — Dakotas (Lew & Cl. 44) — Kukis (Jour. As. Soc. Bengal, xxiv, 646) — Dyaks (Boyle, 95) — New Zealand (Thom, i, 164) — Mandans( Cat. i, 100) — Nagas (Jour. As. Soc. Ben. viii, 464) — Hottentots (Kol. i, 198) — Snakes (Lew. & Cl. 315) — Congo (Tuck. 362) — Chibchas (Acos. 219) — Mexicans (Clav. bk. vii, ch. 22) — Ava (Syme in “Pink. Yoy.” ix, 495) — Chibchas (Sim. 253) — Peru (Gar. bk. iv, ch. 11) — France (reference lost) — New Zealanders (Cook “ Hawk. Voy.” iii, 457) — Astrachan (Bell, i, 43). § 414. Rome (Mom. ii, 316-17 ; Guhl, 497-8) — France (reference lost). § 415. Tahitians (Ell. “Pol. Res.” ii, 354) — Rome (Mom. i, 69) — Mexicans (Torq. bk. xiv, ch. 4 ) — Peru (Gar. bk. i, ch. 213) — Rome (Guhl, 480) — Russia (Cust. 163; Wag. ii, 21) — Germany (Spen. ii, 176). § 416. Lombock (Wal. i, 344) — Burma (Yule, 163) — Siam (Bowr. 125 ) — Dacotahs (School, iv, 69) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 106) — Mislimis (Jour. As. Soc. Ben. v, 195) — Bambarans (Cail. i, 377) — Gold Coast (Bos. 112). § 417. Guatemala (Juar. 194-5) — Tanna (Tur. “Poly.” 77) — Mexicans (Dur. i, 55; Her. iii, 198) — Hottentot (Kol. i, 50-51) — Egyptians ( Wilk. v, 279-82). § 418. Mexico (Clav. bk. vii, ch. 20) — Dahomey (Dal. 98; Bur. i, 217) — Japan (Stein. 53 ) — Burmah (Yule, 139; Sang. 127 ; Sj me i, 112 & 218-19). § 419. Chib - REFERENCES. 673 chas (Sim. 253) —Madagascar (Ell. “Hist.” i, 283) — Homans (Guhl, 513) — - Japan (Koem. 70) — China (Will. S.W. i, 401) — Turkey (White, i, 43) — Siam (Bowr. 117) — Congo (Bas. “Af. R.” 57) — Assyrians (Raw. i, 495) — India (Bur. iii, 141) — Siam (Bowr. i, 425) — China (Gutz. ii, 278) — Java (Raf. i, 312) — Ancient America (Torq. bk. xi, ch. 18) — Dahomey (Waitz, ii, 87) — Siamese (Bowr. i, 116) — Jololoffs (Bas. “ Af. R.” 57). § 420 . Tasma- nians (Bon. 64) — Australia (Sturt ii, 54) — Khoncl (Macph. 56) — Tahiti (Ell. “Poly.” i, 221) — Fijians (U. S. Ex. iii, 332) — Fiji (See. 179) — Chibchas (Sim. 253) — San Salvador (Her. iv, 149) — Peru (Acos. bk. iv, ch. 22). § 421 . Society Islands (Forst. 27l) — Fijian (Ersk. “ West Pac.” 430) — 'Sumatra (Mars. 47 ) — Tahiti (Ell. “Poly.” i, 173) — Karague (Speke 210 & 231) — Tahiti (Cham. s.v. “Ava”) — Guatemala (Xim. 157). § 424 . Fiji (Will, i, 39) — Darfur (reference lost) — Burgundy (Quich. 298-9) — France (Le Roi, see Ste. Beuve). § 425 . Hew Zealand (Ang. i, 319; Thom, i, 190). § 428 . Abyssinia (Bruce vi, 16) — Mexicans (Clay. bk. yi, ch. 20). § 429 . Fiji (Ersk. “West Pac.” 462; Wil. i, 39; i, 37) — Uganda (Speke 298; Stan, i, 369 ; Speke 256 & 258) - Siamese (Bowr. i, 435) — Fiji (U. S. Ex. Ex. iii, 326) — Loango (Ast. iii, 226) — Ashantee (Cruic. i, 109) — Siamese (Loub. i, 186 & 172) — China (Nieulioffi in yii, “Pink. Voy.” 265; Hue “Chin. Empire,” i, 212) — Japan (Dick. 45) — Russia (Cust. 93) — Siamese (Loub. i, 172; Bowr. i, 435) — Burma (Syme, i, 282-3) — China (Will. S.W. i, 509; Hue, Chin, ii, 289). § 431 . Russia (Cust. 160). § 432 . China (Will. S.W. i, 509). § 437 . Santals (Hunt, i, 248) — Sowrahs (Shortt, Pt. iii, 38) — Todas (Hark. 18; Metz, 13; Hark. 17) — Tipperahs (Hunt. “ Stat.” yi, 53) — Marias [ Goads'] (Glas. No. xxxix, 41) — Khonds (Macph. yii, 196) — Santals (Hunt, i, 215-6) — Lepchas (Camp. “ J. E. S. L.” July, 1869) — Bodo Sf Dhimals (Hodg. xyiii, 745) — Carnatics (Hunt. “Die.” 9-10) — Chakmas (Hunt. “ Stat.” yi, 48) — Santals (Hunt, i, 215-6 ; Dalt. 217) — Bodo Sf Dhimals (Hodg. xyiii, 745) — Lepchas (Hook, i, 175; Camp. “ J. E. S. L.” July, 1869) — New Guinea (D’Alb. in “Trans. Col. Inst.” Dec. 17, 1878) — Fijians (Ersk. i. 272) — Dahomey (Burt, i, 195, note ; ibid, ii, 190, note) — Mexicans (Tern. Comp, i, 212 ; Clay. bk. yi, ch. 18; Diaz. ch. 28; Her. iii, 208-9 ; ibid, iv, 213) — Cent. Americans (Land. § xxiv; Gall, i, 104; Her. iii, 223; Pres. bk. i, ch. 4; Her. iv, 174) — Veddahs (Bail, ii, 228; Ten. ii, 444; Prid. 460). § 442 . Digger Indians (Kel. i, 252) — Chaco Indians (Hutch. 280) — Bedouins (Pal. 15) — Unyoro (Bak. “ Eth. Trans.” 1867) — New Zealand (Hawk, iii, 470) — Beluchees (“ Jour. Eth. Soc.” i, 109) — Greeks (Cur. i, 115-6) — Carolingians (Dun. i, 101). § 443 . 'Egyptians (Wilk. i, 330-336) — Roman (Lact. cc. 7, 23, Salv. bk. v) —France (Guiz. iii, 251-2; Clam, i, 355-438 ; ii, 160-230 ; i, pp. xxv-vi) — Gwalior (“ The Statesman,” Aug. 1880, 218-19) — Byzantium (Gib. ch. Iii). § 446 . Rome (Dur. iii, 126-7). § 448 . Bechuanas (Burch, ii, 532) — Greeks (Horn. “Iliad,” bk. i )— Khonds (Macph. 43). § 449 . Semi - notes and Snakes (School, v, 260) — Peruvians (Squ. Peru, 18, 19; Cie. ch. xiii) — Abors (Dal. “ Jour. As. Soc. Bengal,” xiv, 426) — Damaras (Gal. 232-3) — Rookies (Stew. “ Jour. As. Soc. Bengal,” xxiv, 633) — Mishmees (Coop. 228) — Bachassins (Burch, ii, 512). § 450 . Bushmen (Lich. ii, 194) — Rock Veddahs (Ten. ii, 440) — S. Americans (Humb. ii, 412) — Athenians (Gro. iii, 88) — Romans (Mom. i, 65) — Greeks (Gro. iii, 77) — Rome (Coul. 135-8; Mom. i, 67) — India (Maine, 106-7) — Greeks (Gro. ii, 312-3). § 451 . Karens (Mason, “ J. A. S. B.” xxxvii, Pt. ii, 152) — Hottentots (Kol. i, 287) — New Cal. (Tur. 84) — Samoa (Tur. 290) — Israelites (Dun. ii, 99) — Greece (Gro. iv, 431; ii, 359) — Fulbe (Bar. ii, 509) — Damaras (Gal. “ Jour. Roy. Geo. Soc.,” 1852, 159) — Peru (Onde. Narratives, 152-3) — Greece (Gro. ii, 393). § 452 . Patagonians (Falk. 121 2) — Chinooks (Kane, 214) — Kalmucks , Spc. (Pallas, i, 188) — Abipones 674 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. (Dob. ii, 105 ) — Balonda (Liv. 208 ) — Kukis (M’Cull. Selecs. xxvii, 58) — American Indians { Mor. 341 ) — Britain (Bur. ii, 152-3; Mart, i, 343) — - Mexicans (Zurita, 240 ) — Peru (Garc. bk. iy, ch. 8, and bk. v, ch. 9 ) — Japanese (Dickson 305). § 454. Fuegians ([Cook] “ Hawkesworth’s Voyages, ” ii, p. 58 ) — Coroados (Spix and Martius ii, 244). § 455. Podo and Dhimals (Ilodg. 157 )—Lepchas (Camp. “ J. E. S. L.,” July, 1869). §456. 1 V.A. Indians (Kane, 214 ) — NootJcas (Banc, i, 195) — Vera Paz (Xim. 202-3) — Honduras (Her. iv, 135 ) — Dyaks (St. J. i, 104). § 457. Few Zealanders (Thom.i, 148 ) — Sandwich Islands (Ellis, 397 ) — Fiji (Ersk. W.Pac. 461) — Scot. (Maine, E. I., 133 ) — British (Pear. 1-12 ) — Fnglish (Stubbs ii, 493 ) — Scotland (Innes, Mid. Ages 141-2). § 458. Fgypt (Shar. I, 66 ; Ken. II, 42 ) — Borne (Mom. i, 95 ) — Germans (Stubbs 30-31, note ) — Fnglish (Kem. i, 69 ; Hall, M.A. ch. yiii ) — Egyptians (Wilk. [S.B. in new ed.] I, 150 ) — Roman (Coul., K. d. D. M., xcix, 246 ) — England (Hall, M. A. ch. ii, pt. i; Bee. i, 34-6). § 459. Banish (Maine, E. 1.84-5) — Med. Fur . (Free, H.C. i, 96-7). § 460. Fijians (See. 179 ; U. S. Ex. Ex. iii, 73) — Sand- wich Islanders (Ellis, 7 ) — Tahitians (Ellis’s “Pol. Res.” ii, 16 ) — Africa (Rea. 241). § 461. Sandwich Islanders (Ell. “ Haw.” 392). § 462. China (Gutz. ii, 305 ) — France (Cher. “ Hist.” ii, 116-8; Warn, i, 549-50) — Hottentots (Thomp. ii, 30 ) — Bechuanas (Burch, ii, 347 ) — ChinooJcs (Wai. iii, 338 ) — Albania (Boue. iii, 254) — Maine, E. H. of I. 134 ) — France (A. L. F. ii, 645). § 464. Australians (Sm. i, 103) — Chippewas , &c. (School. C. P. 137, et seq .) — Cent. Amer. (Banc, i, 702 ) — Khonds (Macph. 32 and 27) — New. Zea. (Thom. 95 ) — Tahitians (Ell. P. R. ii, 363) — Madag. (Ell. M. i, 378 ) — Phoenicians (Mov. ii, 540 — 1 ) — Greeks (Gro. ii, 92) — Pr. Ger. (Tac. Ger. xi in Free. “Eng. Const.” 17 ) — Iceland (Mall. N. A. 291-5 ) — Swiss (Free. E. C. pp. 1-7 ) — Old Fng. (Free. E. C. 60). § 466. Greenlanders (Crantz i, 164-5 ) — Australians (Sturt ii, 117, 276) — Salish (Hale in U. S. Ex. Ex. vi, 207-8; Domenech’s Deserts, ii, 343-4) — Bodo and Dhimals (Hodg. 157 ) — Australians (Grey ii, 240 ) — Snakes (L. and C. 306) — Chinooks (L. and C. 443 ) — Dakotas (School, ii, 182) — Creeks (School, i, 275 ) — Khirgiz (Wood, 338 ) — Ostyaks (“ Rev. Sib.” ii, 269 ) — Nag as (But. 146) — For. Hottentots (Thomp. ii, 30 ) — Kaffirs (Lich. i, 286). § 467. Tupis (Sou. i, 250 ) — Juangs (Dalt. 156) — Kor. Hottentots (Thomp. ii, 30 ) — Kaffirs (Shoo. 102 ) — Damaras (“Jour. Eth. Soc.” iii, 2) — Arauca - nians (Smi. 243 ) — Dyalcs (Broo. i, 129 ) — Malagasy (Ell. H. M. i, 146) — Savages (Lubb. “ Orig. of Civil.,” 303) . § 468. Arafuras (Kolf. 161) — Khirgiz (Mich. 248 ) — Sumatrans (Mars. 217) — Madag. (Ell. “ Hist. Madag.” i, 377 ) — Fast Africans (Bur. C. A. ii, 360 ) — Javans (Raff, i, 274) - — Sumatra (Mars. 217 ) — Ashantee (Beech. 90, et seq.). § 469. Congo (Proy. Pink, xvi, 577) — Dahomans (Bur. i, 263). § 471. Nicobarians (Bast, ii, 384 ) — Haidahs (Banc, i, 168 ) — Californians (Banc, i, 348) — Navajos (Banc, i, 508 ) — Angamies (Stew. “ J. A. S. B.” xxiv, 650 ) — Loiver Californians (Banc, i, 365 ) — Flatheads (Banc, i, 275 ) — Sound Indians (Banc. i, 217) — Loiver Californians (Banc, i, 565) — Chippewayans (Frank. 159) — Coroados (Spix, ii, 244) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 102) — Bedouins (“Rambles in Syria,” p. 9) — African (Bur. “Ab.” i, 276). § 472. Khonds (Camp. 50) — Cent. India (Fcrs. 9) — Bushmen (Burch, i, 458) — Fuegians (Fitz. ii, 178) - — Rock Veddahs (Ten. ii, 440) — Dyalcs (St. J. i, 375) — Caribs (Edw. i, 48) Bushmen (Lich. ii, 194) — Tasmanians (Lloyd, 56 ; [Dove] Tas. J. i, 253) — Tapajos (Bates, 271) — Bedouins (Bur. iii, 44) — Greece (Gro. ii, 87)— Scot. (Martin, 101) — Snake Indians (L. and C. 306) — Creeks (School, v, 279) — Comanches (School, ii, 130) — Coroados (Spix, ii, 234) — Ostyaks (“ Rev. Sib.’* ii, 269) — Tacullies (Banc, i, 123) — Tolewas (Banc, i, 348) — Spokanes (Wilkes’ Xar. in U. S. Ex. Ex. iv, 475-6 ) — Navajos (Banc, i, 50S ) — Dors (Heuglin, 395 ) — Arabs (Burck. i, 300 ) — Sumatra (Mars. 211). § 473. Austra • REFERENCES. 675 lians (“Trans. Eth. Soc.,” New Ser. iii, 256) — Comanches (School, i, 231) — Flatheads (Banc, i, 275) — Dyalcs (Low, 209; St. J. i, 223) — Caribs (Edw. i, 48) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 103) — Egypt (Tay. 16) — Rome (Mom. i, 79) — Germans (Sohm. i, 9) — French (Ranke, i, 75). § 474. ThlinJceets (Banc, iii, 148) — Fuegians (Fitz. ii, 178) — Tasmanians (Bon. 175) — Haidahs (Banc, iii, 150) — Dakotas (School, iv, 495) — Obbo (Baker, i, 317-9) — Mexicans (Banc, iii, 295; Clay. bk. vii, ch. 7) — Chibchas (Pied. bk. ii, ch. 17) — Egypt (Brug. i, 406) — Jews (“Supernatural Religion,” i, 117) — Amazulu (Call. 310, note 86). § 475. Egypt (Shar. ii, 2) — Coroados (Spix, ii, 244) — Santals (Hunt, i, 216) — Khonds (Macph. 47). § 476. Raida hs (Banc, i, 187) — Fiji (See. 232) — Tahitians (Ell. P. R. ii, 346; Hawk, ii, 121) — - Madagascar (Ell. H. M. i, 342) — Reru (Grom. ch. 124; Garc. bk. iv, ch. 9) — Egypt (Bru. 44 in Wilk. i, 160 -2) — Ceglon (Ten. i, 479; ii, 459) — New Caledonia (Zur. 426) — Madagascar (Ell. i, 342) — Abyssinia (Bruce iv, 488) — Timmanees (Wint. i, 124) — Kaffir (Arb. 149) — Aragon (Hall, ii, 43-4). §477. Amazulu (Call. 208; 390)— KuJcis (Stew. “ J.A.S.B.” xxiv, 625) — Tahitians (Ell. P.R. ii, 341) — Tonga (Mar. ii, 76) — Reru, (Grarc. bk. i, ch. 23) — Egyptians (Wilk. i, 321-2; Brug. ii, 35-36) — Siam (Turp. 591) — Aryans (Giro, i, 618) — Chibchas (P. Simon, 261-2). §478. Chinooks (L. and C. 443; Wai. iii, 338) — Ratagonians (Falk. 121) — Borneo (Low, 183) — Sabines (Seel. 71) — Germans (Dunh. i, 17) — Dyaks (Boy. 183) — Kalmucks (Pall, i, 188) — Araucanians (Thomp. i, 4 5) — Kaffirs (Lich. i, 286) — Greeks (Gtlad. iii, 11) — Karens (Mason, “ J.A.S.B.” xxxvii, Pt. ii, 131) — Congo (Bast. Af. R. 58) — Yariba (Lan. Clap, ii, 223) — Ibu (All. and T. i, 234) — Kukis (But. 91) — Greeks (Glad. iii, 51) — Rome (Seel. 55-6) — Germany (Hall, ii, 67-68) — French (Hall. ch. i) — Merovingians (Wai. [Geo.] 45-6, 102) — France (Meray Trouv. 45-6; Boss. bk. iv, art. 1; St. Sim. iii, 69). § 479. Zulus (Mann “ T.E.S.” New Series, v, 291) — Bheels (Mai. “ C.I.” i, 551) — Loango (Ast. iii, 223; Proy. Pink, xvi, 557) — Wasoro (Bur. C.A, ii, 360) — Msamhara (Krapf 384, note ) — Dahome (Bur. i, 226) — Malagasi (Ell. H.M. i, 341) — - Sandwich Islands (Ell. Haw. 401) — Siam (Bowr. i, 423) — Burmah (Sang. 58)— China (Gutz. ii, 252) — Japan (Ad. i, 11). § 480. Tonga (Ersk. 126) — Gondar (Harr, iii, 10, 34) — Bhotan (Ren. 15-16) — Japan (Ad. i, 74, 17; Tits. 223. Ad. i, 11, 70) — Merovingian (Egin. 123-4). §483. Arafuras (Kolf. 161) — Todas (Shortt “ T.E.S.L.,” N.S., vii, 241) — Bodo and Dhimdls (“T.A.S.B.,” xviii, 708) — Papuans (Kolf. 6) — Lepchas (Camp. “ J.E.S.L.” July 1869) — Nagas (Stew. “J.A.S.B.” xxiv, 608; Grange “J.A.S.B.” ix, 950) — Comanches (School, ii, 130; Banc, i, 509) — Central America (Squi. ii, 340-1) — Nagas (Stew. “ J.A.S.B.” xxiv, 607) — Africa (Bur. “ Abeo.” i, 276). §485. Greece (Toz. 284-5; Her. 14; Gro. ii, 104) — Scotland (Ske. iii, 323-4) — Crete (Cur. ii, 182; ii, 178-9) — Corinth (Gro. iii, 2) — Sparta (Gro. ii, 612) — Latins (Mom. i, 30; 80; 87; 84). § 486. Venice (Sis. i, 300-313)— Netherlands (Gra. 10, 11, 20; Mot. i, 34) — Switz. (Vieus. 39) — Grisons (May’s “ Democ.” i, 355) — San. Mar. (Bent, in “ Fraser’s Mag.” for Dec. 1880). § 487. Ital. Repub. (Sis. [Lard.] 21; Sis. i, 374; Sis. [Lard.] 22; 83). §488. Sparta (Gro. ii, 467; 485) — Rome (Mom. ii, 326) — Ital. Repub. (Hall, i, 368; Sis. [Lard.] 280) — Holland (May, ii, 17-18) — Berne (May’s “Democ.” i, 373) — Venice (Sis. [Lard.] 121) — Greece (Gro. iv, 25; Cur. i, 250) — Romans (Macch. iii, 428-9) — Ital. Repub. (Sis. [Lard.] 80) — Athens (Gro. iii, 182-3-4) — Rome (Mom. i, 98; i, 53) — Italian Repub. (May’s “ Democ.” i, 281-2). § 490. Samoa (Tur. 284) — Fulahs (L. and O. ii, 85) — Mandingo St. (Park i, 18). § 491. Italian Rep. (Sis. [Lard.] 22) — Roles (Dunh. 278-9; 285) — Hun- garians (Levy, 165) — Germans (Stubbs, i, 55) — Merov. (Rich. 119-20) — - Appenzell (Lav. 65) — Uri (Free. 5) — Scandinavia (C. and W., i, 258 and 20 676 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. 101) — Tatars (Gib. ii, 16) — Sparta (Gro. iii, 7). § 492. Kaffirs (Licli. i, 286) — Bechuanas (Moff. 248) — Wanyamwezi (Bur. C. A. ii, 360) — Ashantee (Beech. 90) — Mexico (Zur. 106; Clay. bk. yiii, ch. 13) — Vera Paz (Tor. bk. xi, ch. 20) — Poland (Dunh. 278-9; 282) — Germans (Hall, ii, 92) — Madag. (Ell. M. ii, 252) — Hebrews (I Samuel, ch. XV)— Tahitians (Ell. P.K. ii, 486) — Mexicans (Sah. bk. yiii, ch. 24) — Egypt (Wilk. i, 159) — France (Both. F., 317-20 ; Gui.iii, 249). § 493. Denmark (C. and W. i, 262- 3) — France (Bich. 119-20) — Madag. (Ell. H. M., i, 378) — England (Free. 60). § 494. Egypt (Wilk. i, 160) — Persia (Mai. i, 549-50 ; ii, 303 ; Baw. iii, 223) — China (Will, i, 324) — France (Boss. Pol. bk. iy, art. 1; y, 4; Sey. Pul. i, 8-9; St-Sim. iii, 69) — Pome (Mom. i, 71-2; ii, 361; iii, 361) — ■ Poland (Dunh. 2S2). § 496. Scandinavia (O. and W., i, 158) — Hun - gary (Patfc. i, 66 ; i, 253-4) — Pome (Dur. iii, 376-8). § 498. Greece (Gro. iii, 126, 129) — Italy (Sis. [L.] 23-4; 291) — Spain (Dun. iv, 158) — England (Hume, chap. xii). § 499. Spain (Hall. [4th Ed.] 251) — France (Hall. [4th] 143 — Scotland (Burt, ii, 168). § 500. Scandinavia (Mall. 291-5) — France (Guiz. i, 355; Mor. (2) 379-80) — England (Stubbs, i, 397) — Holland (Mot. i, 32) — Anglo- Sax. (Stubbs, i, cont. of ch. vii) — Spain (Dun. iv, 158) — England (Stubbs, i, 398). § 501. England (Hume, appen. ii ; Stubbs, i, 117)— -France (Hall. [4th Ed.] 121) — Spain (Hall. 4, 262 ; 263 ; 265) — France (Dar. [2] ii, 57-8 ; Clam, ii, 3-4 ; Dar. i, 7 8) — Scotland (Innes, “Leg. An.,” 116). § 502. France (Ord. ii, 201) — Hungary (Levy, 165) — Scotland (Innes, “Leg. An.,” 119)— England (Hume, chap. xvih). § 504. Egypt (Wilk. i, 324-5; v, 295-6) — Assyria (Baw. iv, 175) — England (Kem. ii, 105-11) — Hebrews (Ew. iii, 266-7) — Pome (Dur. iii, 175) — France (Gon. 322) — Eggarahs (All. and T. i, 327) — Mizteca (Her. iii, 261). § 505. Carolingian (Stubbs, i, 344) — Normans and Old English (Stubbs, i, 344) — Scot. (Innes, 120 — 1) — Pussia (Fowler, i, 379) — France (Jer. ii. ch. 2, 158-9; Kit. iii, 210) — England (Turn, vi, 132). § 508. Tahiti (Ell. P. B. ii, 267) — England (Kem. ii, 142) — France (Gui. iii, 233) — Mexico , fyc. (Zur. 66-7) — Chibchas (Acos. 188-90) — Med . Europe (Maine, V. C. [3rd Ed.] 235-6). § 509. England (Free, i, 80; Fis. 301; Hall. M.A. ch. viii). § 510. Feudal (Maine, E. 1.77) — France (Mau. cvii, 585) — Persians (Baw. iy, 418; 427-8) — Pome (Dur. v, 83-4) — France (Thie. T. C. i, 365-6; Cher. Hist, ii, 138-9) — England (Hall. C. H. ch. xii). § 511. Bedouins (Burck. 5; Pal. “ Ency. Brit.” ii, 249) — Irish (Maine, E. I. 105-7) — Albania (Boue, ii, 86; iii, 359) — England (You. 147). § 512. Mexico (Zur. 50 -62) — Pussia (Lav. 8, 1) — Teutons (Stubbs, i, 49; Caesar, vi, 22; Kem. i, 56-7) — Bakwains (Liv. S.A. 14) — Japan (Ale. ii, 241-2) — Franks (Kem. i, 238) — England (Thor, i, 274; 386; 450) — Pussia (Kou. 228-9). § 513. England (Kem. i, 240-3; Stu. 68) — Peru (Pres, i, 143) — Mexico (Clav. bk. vii, ch. 5 ; Gom. 438) — Egypt (Heer. ii, 139) — Greece (Her. § 5) — China (Will. M. K. i, 388) — India (Gho. in Cal. Pev. for 1880) — Scandinavia (Aug. Thierry, quoted by Mazaroz, 85 ; Bren, lxviii) — England (Bren, cxxix). § 516. Siam (Loub. 237-8) — Ashantee (Beech. 129) — Fulahs (L. ar.d O. 86) — Pome (Mom. i, 99-100). § 517. Suevi (Stubbs, i, 14). § 518. Guaranis (Waitz, iii, 422) — Nicaragua (Squ. ii, 341) — Bedouins (Burck. i, 296-7) — Tahiti (Forst. 377) — Hebrews (2 Sam. xxi, 17) — Carolingian (Waitz, iv, 522-3) — Japan (Adam, i, 15- 16) — Peru (Pres. Peru, bk. i, ch. 2). § 519. Hottentots (Kol. i, 815) — Malagasy (Ell. H. M. ii, 253) — Chibchas (Sim. 269) — Pome (Coul. C. A. 148) * — Germans (Stubbs, i, 30) — Old England (Kem. i, 69) — France (Kitchin, i, 399 ; Froiss. i, 168) — Sparta (Gro. ii, 614) — i2owe(Mom. i, 98-9). § 520. France (Banke, i, 83). § 522. Chinooks (Waitz, iii, 338) — Arabs (Bur. iii, 47) — Italy (Sis [L.] 90) — France (Maine, Fort. Pev. Nov., 1881, p. 614) England (Bee, i, 153-4) — France (Gui. iii, 180). § 523. Hot ten- REFERENCES* 677 tots (Kol. i, 294-9 ) — Greece (Giro, ii, 99-100 ) — Rome (Mom. i, 159) — Ger • mans ( Tac. Germ. xii ) — Danes (C. and W. i, 230 ) — Irish (Les. in “ Fort. Rev.” March 1875). § 524 . Hebrews (Deut. xxi, 19 ) — Romans (Mom. i, 158) — France (Join. ch. xii ) — Carolingian (Mor. C. C. E. [2] 379-80; Sohm, i, § 16). § 525 . Zulus (Arb. 140 )—Fggarahs (All. and T. i, 326) — Ger- mans (Tac. Germ. c. 7 ) — Scandinavia (Grim, i, 93-4). § 526 . Rent (Her. iv, 337 ) — Germany (Dunh. i, 120 ) — France (Bay. i, 70-1 ) — Scotland (Innes, “ L. A.” 221 ) — Fngland (Stubbs, i, 391; i, 600 ).— France (Hall, 126-7). § 527 . Bedouins (“ Ram. in Syria,” p. 9 ) — Mexicans (Dur. i, 216 ) — Athens (Cur. ii, 450 ) — France and Germany (Black, iii, 41 ) — France (Due. 11-12; A. L., F., v. 346-7; Dar. (2) i, 273 ) — Fngland (Fis. 238; Stubbs, ii, 268). § 528 . (Maine, “ E, 1.” 288-9). § 529 . Sand- wich I, (Ell. 399 ) — Bechuanas (Burck. i, 544-5 )- — Karens (Mason, “ J. A. S. B.” xxxvii, pt. ii, 131 ) — France (Koenigs. 185-6). § 530 . Scandinavia (Mall. 117 ) — Egypt (Rec. ii, 11; xii, 47-8 ) — Bern (Santa Cr. 107; Gar. bk. i, ch. 23 ) — Tahitians (Ell. P. ii, 235 ) — Todas (Metz, 17 ) — Hebrews (2 Sam. v. 22-25 ) — India (Maine, “A. L.” 18 ) — Greece (Gro. ii, 111; Her. 48) — France (Hinc. D. O. P. ii, 201). § 531 . Assyrians (Lay. ii, 473 -4) — Greeks (Tie. 217-8; Coul. 221 )—Fgypt (Wilk. i, 164). § 532 . Zulus (Arb. p. 16, note ) — Peru (Pres. bk. i, ch. 2 ) — Mexicans (Tern. Comp, i, 78) — Japan (Pemb. Yoy. vi, 624-5 ) — France (Greg, vii, 21 ) — Peruvians (Garc. bk. ii, ch. 12 ) — Japan (Ale. 63 ) — Rome (Mom. i, 159 ) — Salic (Gui. i, 463-4 ) — Scotland (Innes, 197 ) — Fngland (Stubbs, i, 183). § 533 . Chippewayans (School, v, 177 ) — Shoshones (Banc, i, 435 ) — Haidahs (Bams, i, 168 )— Sandwich I. (Ell. H. A00)— Greece (Gro. ii, 108, 110-11, 130)— Rome (Maine, “ A. L.” 372; Mom. ii, 130 ) — Basutos (Arb. 37 ) — Abyssinia (Par. ii, 204 ) — Sumatra (Mars. 249, 220 ) — Dakotas (School, ii, 185) — 2V". Americans (Kane, 115 ) — Dakotas (Mor. 331 ) — Araucanians (Thomp. i, 405). § 536 . Bushmen (Lich. ii, 194 ) — Chippeivayans (Banc, i, 118) — Arawaks (J. R. G. S. ii, 231). § 537 . Ahts (Banc, i, 191 ) — Comanches (School, i, 232 ) — Brazilians (Yon Martius in “ J. R. G. S.” ii, 195) — Chip- pewayans (School, v, 177 ) — Bedouins (Burck. i, 228). § 538 . Recha - bites, d^c. (Ew. iv, 79-80; Kue. i, 181-2 ) — Dakotas (School, ii, 185) — Comanches (School, ii, 131 ) — Iroquois (Mor. 326 ) — Bechuanas (Burck. ii, 531 ) — Damaras (And. 114) —Kafirs (Shoot. 16 ) — Koosas (Lich. i, 271 ) — Few Zealanders (Thom. 96 ) — Sumatrans (Mars. 244 ) — Mexicans (Sart. 6 7-8) — Damaras (And. 147 ) — Todas (Marsh. 206)— Congo (Pink, xvi, 168 ) — Slavs (Lav. 185 ) — Swiss (Lav. 82 ) — Hebrews (May, i, 362 ) — Rome (Mom. i, 160, 193) — Teutons (Stubbs i, 49-50). § 539 . Drentlie (Lav. 282) — Ar- dennes (Lav. 301 ) — Lombardy (Lav. 214 ) — France (Lav. 212 ) — Abyssinia (Bruce iv, 462 ) — Kongo (Art. iii, 258 ) — Mexico (Tern. Comp, i, 254) —Iceland (Mall. 289 ) — Swiss (Lav. 83). § 540 . Slavs (Lav. 189 ; i, 194-5) — Lombardy (Lav. 216). § 542 . Dakotas (School, iv, 69 ) — Abipones (Dob. ii, 106 ) — Patagonians (Falk. 121-2 ) — Greece (Gro. ii, 84; 85) — Germans (Tac. xv ) — Fngland (Dyer 3 ) — Guaranis (Wai. iii, 442 ) — Rome (Mom. i, 275). § 543 . Loango (Proy. Pink, xvi, 577 ) — Tongans (Mars. i, 231) — Cashmere (Drew 68-70) — Kaffirs (Shoot. 104) — Sandwich Islands (Ell. H. 292) — Mexico (Zur. 251) — Yucatan (Landa § xx) — Guatemala, Sfc. (Zur. 407 )— Madagascar (Ell. M. i, 316)— Fiji (See. 232 )— Tahiti (Ell. P.R. ii, 361). § 544 . Fngland (Stubbs ii, 562-3). § 545 . Quanga and Balonda (Liv. S. A. 296, 307 )—Bhils (Mai. i, 551-2) ; 185)— Mexico (Clav. bk. vii, ch. 37) — Greece (Glad, iii, 62 ; Pot. i, 97) — Fngland (Ling, iii, 7). § 557 . France (Dar. 537). § 558 . Americans (Hearne,151) — Dahomey (Bur. i, 220-5; 226 ; Dalz. 175 ; Bur. i, 248 ; i, 52, note) — Peru (Gar. bk. ii, chap, xv ; bk. vi, chap, viii ; Bias, v, 3) — Fgypt (Shar. i, 123 ; Brug. i, 51 ; Shar. i, 182) — Sparta (Gro. ii, 506; ii, 527) — Russia (Cust. ii, 2; Wal. 678 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. I, 419-21; I, 419; i, 305, 440; Oust, ii, 142; Bell, ii, 237). § 559 . Rome (Dur. iii, 155-60; iii, 183-7,9; iii, 173-4; iii, 172-3; iii, 176) — Italy (Sis. 8-9). § 560. Greeks (Gro. ii, 88) — Jajpan (Mit. i, 32) — France (Corn, xxvii (1873) 72) — Montenegro (Boue ii, 86) — Dahomey (For. i, 20) — Sparta (Thirl, i, 329) — Merovingian (Amp. ii, 305 ; Martin ii, 448) — Dahomey (Bur. ii, 248) — Japan (M. and C., 34) — Egypt (Wilk. i, 189)— Persia (Raw. iv, 202) — Araucanians (Thomp. i, 406) — Fiji (Ersk. 464) — • Dahomey (Dalz. 69) — Egypt (Brug. i, 53). § 573 . Tenae (Dalt. 35)— Todas (Shortt pt. i, 9) — Pueblos (Banc, i, 546) — Karens (Gov. Stat. p.64; McM. 81) — Lepchas (Hook, i, 129-30; Camp. J.E. S. L. 1869, 150-1) — Santdls (Hunt, i, 214; ditto Stat. xiv, 330) — Shervaroy (Shortt, pt. ii, 7) — Todas (Shortt, pt. i, 7-9; Hark. 16-17) — Arafuras (Kolff 161-3) — England (Hall., chap, viii) — France (L6v. ii, 47-8) — England (Free. Sk. 232; Bage. Eng. Const.) — France (Taine’3 “ Ancien Regime”) — England (Mart. Intro. 21-2-3; Buck, i, 445-50; Pike, ii, 574). § 574 . Dodo and D. (Hodg. J. A.S.B., xviii, 745) — Lepchas (Camp. J.E.S., July 1869) — Santa l (Hunt, i, 209 ; Sher. J.A.S.B xx, 554) — JaJcuns (Favre in J.I.A. ii) — Podo and D. (Hodg. J.A.S.B. xviii, 745) — Neilgherry H. (Ouch. 69) — Lepchas (Camp. J.E.S. (1869) 150-1) — Arafuras (Kolf. 161-3) — Lepchas (Camp. J.E.S. July 1869; Hook, i, 175-6) — Santdls (Hunt, i, 217) — Hos (Dalt. 206) — Todas (Shortt, pt, i, 1) — Shervaroy H. (Shortt, ii, 78) — JaJcuns (Favre J.I.A. ii) — Malacca (Jukes, 219-20)— Podo and D. (Hodg. J.A.S.B. xviii, 745) — Santdl (Hunt, i, 209-10) — Lepchas (Hook, i, 175-6; 129-30) — ■ Arafuras (Kolf. 163-4) — Lepchas (Hook, i, 134) — Santdls (Hunt. 208) — Podo and Dhimals (Hodg. J.A.S.B. xviii, 707) — Santdl (Hunt, i, 217) — ■ Podo and Dhimals (Hodg. i, 150) — Todas (T.E.S. vii, 254). Note to Chap. XVIII. Poda and Dhimals (Hodg. “ Kocch,” 162) — Lepchas (Hook, i, 135) — Santdl (Hunt, i, 215-6 ; i, 181) — Lepchas (Camp. J.E.S. July 1869)— Arafuras (Kolf. 159-60). TITLES OF WORKS REFERRED TO. Acos. — Acosta (Joaq.) Compendio Historico del Descubrimiento y Coloni* zacion de la Nueva Granada. Paris, 1848. Ad. — Adams. History of Japan. Ale. — Alcock (Rutherford Sir) The Capital of Tycoon. 2 vol. 8vo. 1863. A.L.F. — Anciennes lois franQaises y ed. Jourdain, Isambert, and Decrusy, 28 vol. Paris, 1828 ff. All. and T. — Allen (W.) and Thomson (Dr.) Narrative of Expedition to River Niger in 1841. London, 1848. Amp. — Ampere (J. J.) Histoire litteraire de la France avant le douz. siecle . 3 vol. Paris, 1839. And. — Anderson (C. John) LaJce Ngami. London, 1856. Arb. — Arbousset (T.) and Daumas Narrative of an Exploratory Tour to the north-east of the Cape of Good Hope . Trans. 8vo. Cape Town, 1846. Ast. — Astley (T.) Collection of Voyages and Travels. London, 1745-7. Bage. — Bagehot’s (Walter) English Constitution. Bail. — Bailey in Journal Ethnological Society. Vol. 2. Bali. — Baker (Sir Samuel) Ethnological Transactions. 1867. „ n The Nile Tributaries of Abyssinia . London, 1867. v REFERENCES. 079 Banc. — Bancroft (H. H.) The Native Races of the Pacific States of North America. London, 1876. Bart. — Barth (H.) Travels and Discoveries in Noidh and Central Africa . London, 1858. Bast. — Bastian (A.) Mensch. „ „ Africanische Reisen. Bremen, 1859. Bates. — Bates (Henry W.) Naturalist on River Amazon. 2nd Ed. London, 1864. Bay. — Bayard (Chev.) History of. Trans. Kindersley. London, 1844. Beech. — Beecham (John) Ashantee and the Gold Coast. London, 1841. Bell. — Bell’s History of Russia in Lard . Cyclopedia. Bent. — Bent (J. Theodore) in Fraser's Magazine for December, 18S0. Bird. — Bird (Miss) Unbeaten Tracies in Japan. 1881. Black. — Blackstone’s Commentaries , adapted by R. Malcolm Kerr, LL.D. 4th Ed. London, 1876. Bias. — Bias Yalera in Garcillasso. Bon. — Bonwick (James) Daily Life and Origin of the Tasmanians. London, 1870. Boss. — Bossuet (J. B.) Politique ( CEuvres choisies ). 5 toI. Paris, 1868. Boue. — Boue (Am.) La Turkie en Furope. 4 yol. 1841. Bowr. — Bowring (Sir John) The Kingdom and People of Siam. 2 yol., 8vo. 1857. Boy. — Boyle (F.) Adventures among the Dyaks of Borneo. 8yo. 1865. Bren. — Brentano (Lujo) On the History and Development of Gilds in Toulman Smith’s compilation of gild-ordinances. London, 1870. Broo. — Brookes (Chas.) Ten Years in Sarawak. Bru. — Bruce (Jas.) Travels to Discover the Source of the Nile . Edinburgh and London, 1804. Brug. — Brugsch (Dr. W.) History of Fgypt. Buck. — Buckle (H. T.) History of Civilization. 2nd (lib.) Ed. 1858. Bur. — Burton (R. F.) Mission to Gelele , King of Dahome. p. 8ro. 1864. „ „ „ Abeokuta and the Camaroon Mountains. 2 yol., 8yo. 1863. „ ,, „ Lake Regions of Central Africa. 2 yol. 8vo. 1860. „ „ „ Pilgrimage to El-Medinah and Meccah . London, 1851. Burch. — Burchell (W. J.) Travels into the Interior of Southern Africa. Burck. — Burckhart (J. L.) Notes on the Bedouins and Wahabys. London, 1850. Burck. — Burckliardt (B.) Travels in Arabia. London, 1829. Burt. — Burton (John Hill) History of Scotland from Agricola's Invasion to the Revolution 0/I688. Edinburgh, 1867-70. But. — Butler (Major John) Travels and Adventures in Assam. London, 1855. C. & W. — Crichton and Wheaton’s History of Scandinavia in Edinburgh Cab. Liby. Camp., J.E.S.L. — Campbell in Journal Ethnological Society. London. Camp. — Campbell (John, Major-General) Wild Tribes of Khondistan. London, 1864. Call. — Callaway (Rev. Canon) The Religious System of the Amazulu. Natal, 1868-70. Cher. — Clieruel (A.) Diet, historique des institutions , moeurs et coutumes de la France. 4to. Ed. Paris, 1874. „ „ „ Historic de V administration monarchique en France, 2 vol. Paris, 1855. Cie. — Cieza de Leon (P. de) Travels. Markham’s Translation (Hakluyt Society). 6S0 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Clam. — Clamageran (J. J.) Histoire de Vimpot en France. 3 vol. Paris, 1867-70. Clar. — Clarke ( See Lewis and Clarke). Clav. — Clavigero (Fr. S.) The History of Mexico [1780]. Translated by Ch. Cullen. London, 1787. Coop. — Cooper (J. J.) Mishmee Hills. London, 1873. Coul. — Coulanges (F. de) Histoire des institutions politiques de Vancienne France. Yol. i. Paris, 1874. „ „ „ in Revue des deux Mondes . Yol. xcix. Corn. — Cornhill Magazine. Crantz. — Crantz (David) History of Greenland, London, 1820. Cur. — Curtius History of Greece. Cust. — Custine’s (de) Fmpire of the Czar . Trans. 1843. „ ,, „ La Russie en 1839. D’Alb. — D’Albert.is (Signor) In Transactions of Royal Colonial Institution , Dec. 17, 1878. Palt. — Dalton (Col. E. J.) Descriptive Fthnoloyy of Bengal, Calcutta, 1872. Dalt. — Dalton in Journal Asiatic Society of Bengal. Dalz. — Dalzel (Arch.) History of Dahomey. 1793. Dar. — Dareste de la Chavanne (C.) Histoire des Classes Agricoles. 2me ed. Paris, 1858. „ „ „ Histoire de V Administration en France . 2 vols. Paris, 18 18. Diaz. — Diaz de Castillo (Bernal) Memoirs [1598]. Translated by F. Ingram Lockhart. London, 1841. Dob. — Dobrizhoffer (Martin) Account of the Abipones . Trans. London, 1822. Domenech. — Domenech (Abbe) Seven Years * Residence in the Great Deserts of North America. 2 vols. 8vo. 1860. Dove. — Tasmanian Journal. Drew. — Drew (Fred). The Jummoo and Cashmere Territories. 1875. Due. — Ducange (Ch. Dufresne, Sieur) Dissertations sur Vhistoire de Saint Louys : appended to his Glossarium. Paris, 1846. Dun. — Duncker (M.) Geschichte des Alterthums. 4 Aufl. Leipzig, 1868. Dunh. — Dunham’s History of Germany (in Lardner’s Cyclopaedia). „ „ History of Roland „ „ „ „ History of Spain ,, „ Dur. — Duran (Fr. D.) Historia de las Indias de Nueva Espana. Publ. por J. Ramirez. Yol. i. Mexico, 1867. Dur. — Duruy (Y.) Histoire des Domains. Paris, 1876. „ „ ,, Histoire de France. Nouv. ed. Paris, 1860. Dyer. — Dyer (J. F. Thistleton) British Popular Customs, Past and Present. Loudon, 1876. Ed.— Edwards (B.) History of the British West Indies. London, 1819. Egin. — Eginhardus, Life of the Emperor Karl the Great. Trans. Glaistcr. London, 1877. Ell. — Ellis (Rev. W.) Tour through Hawaii. 8yo. 1826. „ ,, „ Polynesian Researches. 2 vols. 8vo. 1829. „ „ „ History of Madagascar. 2 vol. 8vo. 1838. Ersk. — Erskine (Capfc. J. E.) Journal of a Cruize among the Islands of the Western Pacific. 8vo. 1853. Ew. — Ewald (H.) The History of Israel . Translated by T. E. Carpenter. London, 1867, &c. Falk. — Falkner. Description of Patagonia. Fav. — Favre (Rev. P.) In Journal of the Indian Archipelago • Yol. ii* Singapore. REFERENCES. 681 Fis. — Fischel (E.) The 'English Constitution. Translated by R. J. Shee. 1867. Fitz. — Fitzroy (Admiral) Narrative of the Surveying Voyages of the “ Adven • ture ” and u Beagle f 1826-30, &c. 3 vols. 8vo. 1840. For. — Forbes (F. E). Dahomey and the Dahomans. 1851. For. — Forsyth (Captain J.) Highlands of Central India. Second Edition. London, 1872. Forst. — Forster (Dr. J. R.) Observations during a Voyage round the World . 4 to. 1778. Fowl. — Fowler (Geo ) Lives of the Sovereigns of Russia. 8vo. 1852. Frank. — Franklin’s (Capt. J.) Narrative of Journey to Shores of Bolar Sea . London, 1823. Free. — Freeman (Ed. A.) The Growth of the English Constitution. London 1876. „ „ „ General SJcetch. 1874. Froiss. — Froissart. Chronicles of England , France , and Spain. Trans. Johnes. 2 vols. London, 1844. Gal. — Gallatin (A.) Notes onthe Semi- civilized Nations of Mexico, Yucatan , and Central America (in Transactions of the American Ethnological Society ). Yol. i. New York, 1845. Gal. — Galton (F.) In Journal Royal Geographical Society. 1852. Gar. — Garcillasso de la Vega, First Part of the Royal Commentaries of the Yncas. Translated by Cl. R. Markham. London, 1869-71. (Hakluyt Society) . Gho. — Ghosh (Jogendra Chandra) Caste in India , in Calcutta Review for 1880. Gib. — Gibbon’s Fall of the Roman Empire. Glad. — Gladstone (W. E.) Studies on Homer. Oxford University Press, 1858. Glas. — Glasfind in Selections from the Records of Government of India . (Foreign Department.) Gom. — Gomara (F. Lopez de) Historia General de las Indias. Gomme.— Gomme (G. L.) Primitive FolJc Moots. London, 1880. Gon. — Goncourt (E. & J. de) Histoire de la Societe franq. pendant la Revo • lution. 2nd Ed. Paris, 1854. Gov. Stat. — Government Statement on the Moral and Material Progress of India for 1869-70. Gra. — Gratton (Thos. Collyn) History of the Netherlands. (In Lardner’s Cyclo.) Greg. — Gregorii Turon, Historia Ecclesiastica Francorum . 2 vols. Paris, 1836-8. Grey. — Grey (Sir Geo.) Journals of tivo Expeditions of Discovery in Aus- tralia. London, 1841. Grim. — Grimm (Jacob) Teutonic Mythology . Trans. Stallybrass. Gro. — Grote’s History of Greece. 2nd Ed. London, 1849. Guiz. — Guizot (F.) The History of Civilization. Trans. Hazlitt. 3 vols. London, 1871. Gutz. — Gutzlaff (Rev. C.) China Opened. 2 vols. 8vo. 1838. Hale. — Hale in U. S. Ex. Ex. Hall. — Hallam, Europe in the Middle Ages. 11th Ed. „ „ ,, „ Reprint of 4th Ed. 1869. Hark. — Harkness (Capt. Henry) The Neilgherry Hills. Roy. 8vo. 1832. Har. — Harris (W. C.) Highlands of ^Ethiopia. London, 1844. Hawk. — Hawkesworth (Dr. J.) Account of Voyages of Discovery in the Southern Hemisphere. London, 1773. Haz. — Hazlitt (W. Carew) History of the Venetian Republic . London, 1860. 682 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Hearne. — Hearne (Sami.) Journey from Prince of Wales's Fort to the Northern Ocean. Dublin, 1796. Heer. — Heeren, African Researches. 1832-40. Her. — Hermann (Chas. Fredk.) A Manual of the Political Antiquities of Greece. Trans. Oxford, 1836. Her. — Herrera (Ant. de) The General History of the vast Continent and Islands of America [1601], Translated by J. Stephens. London, 1725-6. Heug. — Heuglin (Th. yon) Reise in das Gebiet des Weissen Nil . Leipzig und Heidelburg, 1869. Hine. — Hincmar, De Or dine PalatU. Hodg. — Hodgson (B. H.) Kocch , Bodo , and Dhimal Tribes. Hook. — Hooker (J. Dalton) Himalayan Journals. London, 1854. Hue. — Hue (Pretre Missionnaire) Recollections of a Journey through Tar - tary , Thibet , and China. Translated by Hazlitt. 2 yols. 1852. „ „ „ The Chinese Empire. 2 vols. 1855. Humb. — Humboldt’s Personal Narrative of Travels to the Equinoctial Regions of America. 1852. (Bohn.) Hume. — Hume’s (D.) History of England. Hunt.— Hunter (W. W.) Annals of Rural Bengal. London, 1868. „ „ „ A Statistical Account of Bengal. London, 1876. „ ,, ,, A comparative Dictionary of the Languages of India and High Asia. Prelim. Dissert. London, 1868. Hutch. — Hutchinson (T. J.l Buenos Ayres , Sfc. London, 1865. Innes. — Innes (Cosmo) Scotland in the Middle Ages. 8vo. 1860. „ „ Lectures on Scotch Legal Antiquities. 1872. J.A.S.B. — Journal of the Asiatic Society , Bengal . Jer. — Jervis (VV. H.) History of the Gallican Church. 2 yols. London, 1872. J.E S. — Journal of the Ethnological Society. London. Join. — Joinville (J. Sire de) Saint Louis. Trans. Hutton. London, 1868. Jukes. — Jukes (J. B.) Voyage of H.M.S. “ FlyP 1842-6. Kane.— Kane (Paul) Wanderings of an Artist among Indians of North America. London, 1859. Kel. — Kelly (W.) Excursion to California. London, 1851. Kem. — Kemble (J. M.) The Saxons in England. 2 yols. 8vo. 1848. Ken. — Kenrick (Rev. John) Ancient Egypt under the Pharaohs. 2 vols. 8vo. 1850. Kit. — Kitchen (G-. W.) A History of France. 3 vols. London, 1873. Koenigs. — Koenigswarter (L. J.) Histoire de V organisation de la famille en France. Paris, 1851. Kol. — Kolben (P.) Present State of the Cape of Good Hope. Translated by- Medley. 8 vo. 1731. Kolf — Kolffe (D. H.) Voyages of the Dutch brig u DomegaP Translated by Earl. 8vo. 1840. Kou. — Koutorga (M.) Essai sur V organisation de la Tribu . Trad, par M. Chopin. Kue. — Kuenen (A.) The Religion of Israel. Translated by A. H. May. London, 1874-5. L. & O. — Laird (Macgregor), and Oldfield (R. A. K.) Expedition into In~ terior of Africa. London, 1837. Lact. — Lactantius, De Mortibus Persecutorum. Landa. — Landa (Diego de) Relation des Choses de Yucatan [1566] Texte Espagnol et traduction franqaise. Par M. Brasseur de Bourbourg. Paris, 1864. Lan. — Lander (Richard) Records of Capt. Clapperton's last Expedition London, 1830. REFERENCES. 683 Lav. — Lavcleye (Emile de) Primitive Property. 1878. Lay. — Layard (A. H.) Manners and Arts of Ancient Assyrians . 2 vols. Roy. 8vo. 1846. Lei. — Lelevel (Joachim) Histoire de Pologne. Paris, 1844. Les. —Leslie (Prof.) in Port. Rev. for 1875. Ley. — Levasseur (C.) Histoire des classes ouvrieres . 1st and 2nd Series. 4 vols. Paris, 1859-67. L. & C.— Lewis & Clarke (Capts.) Travels to the Source of the Missouri , Sfc. London, 1814. Levy. — Levy (Daniel) If Autriche-Hongrie, ses Institutions et ses Nationalites . Paris, 1.871. Lich. — Lichtenstein (Henry) Travels in Southern Africa in the years 1803-6. Liv. — Livingstone (D.) South Africa. London, 1861. Lloyd. — -Lloyd (Greo. Thos.) Thirty-three years in Tasmania and Victoria . Cr. 8vo. 1862. Loub. — Loubere (M. de la) Du Royaume de Siam en 1687-88. Amsterdam, 1691. Low. — Low (Hugh) Sarawak, its Inhabitants and Productions. 8vo. 1848. Lubb. — Lubbock (Sir John) The Origin of Civilization and the Primitive Condition of Man. London, 1870. Macch. — Macchiavelli (Nic.) M.’s works, translated by Farnworth. 1775. Macph. — Macpherson, Report upon the Khonds of Ganjani and Cuttack . Calcutta, 1842. Maine. — Maine (H. S.) History of Parly Institutions. „ „ „ Village Communities in the Past and West. 8vo. 1871. Mai. — Malcolm (Sir J.) Memoir of Central India. 3rd Ed. 2 vols. 8vo. 1832. „ ,, „ History of Persia. Mall. — Mallet (P. H.) Northern Antiquities. Translated by Bishop Percy. London, 1847. M. & C. — Manners and Customs of Japan. Mann. — Mann, Transactions Pthnological Society. New Series, v. Mar. — Mariner (W.) Account of the Natives of the Tonga Islands. 2 vols. 8vo. 1818. Mars. — Marsden (W.) History of Sumatra. 3rd Ed. 4to. 1811. Marsh. — Marshall (Lieut. -Col. W. E.) A Phrenologist among the Todas . London, 1873. Martin. — Martin (H.) Histoire de la Prance . Yols. i, iii (Ed. 1855-61), others, 2nd Ed. Paris, 1844. Martin. — Martin (M.) Account of the Western Isles of Scotland. 1716. Mart. — Martineau (Harriet) History of Pngland during the Thirty Years' Peace. 1849-50. Library Ed. ,, „ „ Introduction to History of Thirty Years' Peace. Bohn’s Ed. Mason. — Mason, Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal. Mau. — Maury in Revue des Deux Mondes. May. — May (Sir Thos. Erskine) Democracy in Purope. London, 1877. May. — Mayer (S.) Die Rechte der Israeliten , Athener u. Romer. Leipzig, 1862. Maz. — Mazoroz (J. P.) Histoire des Corporations Frangaises $ arts et metiers. Paris, 1878. M’Cull. — M’Culloch, Selections from Records of Government of India. McM. — McMahon (Lieut. A. R.) The Karens of the Golden Chersonese . Moray. —Moray (A.) La vie au temps des trouveres. Paris, 1873. 684 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS. Metz. — Metz (Rev. F.) Tribes Inhabiting the Neilgherry Hills. Mich. — Michie (Alex.) Siberian Overland Route. London, 1864. Mit. — Mitford (A. B.) Tales of Old Japan. 2 vols. p. 8vo. 1871. Mitch. — Mitchell (Sir T. L.) Journal of Expedition into New South Wales . 2nd Ed. 2 vols. 8vo. 1839. Moff. — Moffat (Robt.) Missionary labours and Scenes in South Africa . Mom. — Mommsen, History of Rome. Dickson’s Trans. 1862. Mor. — Morgan (L. H.) League of the Iroquois . Rochester, 1851. Mor. — Morier in Cobden Club Essays. Mot. — Motley (J. L.) Rise of the Dutch Republic. 1861. Mov. — Movers (F. C.) Die Phoenizier. Bonn u. Berlin, 1841, &c. Onde. — Ondegardo (Pe de) Narratives of the Rites and Laws of the Yncas . Translated by Markham. London, 1878. Ord. — Ordonnances des rois de France. Paris, 1723, ff. Ouch. — Ouchterlony (Col.) A Geographical and Statistical Memoir of a Survey of the Neilgherry Hills [printed with Shortt’s Hill Ranges ]. 1847. Pal. — Palgrave (W. J.) Narrative of a Year's Journey through Central and Eastern Arabia. London, 1865. Pall. — Pallas (P. S.) Voyages en different es Provinces de V Empire de Russie , Sfc. Par. — Parkyn (Mansfield) Life in Abyssinia. London, 1853. Park. — Park (Mungo) Travels in Interior Districts of Af rica. 1816. Patt. — Patterson (Arthur J.) The Magyars : their Country and Institutions . London, 1869. Pear. — Pearson (C. H.) The Early and Middle Ages of England. 1867. Pemb. — Pemberton' s Voyages. Pied. — Piedrahita (L. Fernandez de) Historia del Nuevo Regno de Granada. Amberes, 1688. Pike. — Pike (L. O.) History of Crime in England. 1871. Prid. — Pridliam (Chas.) Historical, Political, and Statistical Account of Ceylon. 2 vols. 8vo. 1849. Pot. — Potter (J., d.d.) Archcelogica Grceca, or the Antiquities of Greece . Edinburgh, 1827. Pres. — Prescott (VY. H.) Conquest of Peru. London, 1847. Proy (Pink). — Proyart in Pinkerton's Travels. Raf. — Raffles (Sir T. S.) History of Java. 2 vols. 4to. 1817. Ram. — Rambles in Syria. Ranke. — Ranke, The Civil Wars and Monarchy in France. Trans. 2 vols* London, 1852. Raw. — Rawlmson (G-.) Five Ancient Monarchies. 4 vols. 1862-7. Rea. — Reade (W. Winwood) Savage Africa. 8vo. 1S63. Rec. — Records of the Past , being English Translations of the Assyrian and Egyptian Monuments. London. Ree. — Reeves (J.) History of the English Law. Ren. — Rennie (Dr. D. F.) Rhotan and the Story of the Dooar War. London, 1866. Rev. Sib. — Revelations of Siberia. London, 1853. Rich. — Richter (Gr.) Annalen der deutsche Geschichte im Mittelalter. Halle, 1873. Roth. — Roth (P.) Feudalitat und Tint erthanenverb and. Weimar, 1863. Saha. — Sahagun (Fr. Bernardino de) Historia General de las Cosas de Nueva Espdha [1569]. De la a luz C. M. de Bustamente. Mexico, 1829-30. Salv. — Salvianus, De Gubernatione Dei. Sang. — Sangermano (Father) Description of the Rurmese Empire. Roy. 4to. Rome, 1833. REFERENCES. 685 Santa C. — Santa Cruz in Narratives of the Rites and Laws of the Yncas . Translated by Cl. R. Markham. London, 1873 (Hakluyt Society). Sart. — Sartorius (C.) Mexico. Edited by Dr. Gaspey. London, 1858. School. — Schoolcraft (H. R.) Expedition to the Sources of the Mississippi River . London, 1855. „ „ „ Travels in the Central Portions of the Missis • sippi Valley . New York, 1825. See. — Seeman (B.) Vita; an Account of a Mission to the Vitian or Fijian Islands. 8vo. Cambridge, 1862. Seel. — Seeley (J. R.) Lectures and Essays. 8vo. London, 1870. Sex. — Sevigne (Madam de) Her Correspondents and Contemporaries . By the Comtesse de Puliga. 2 vols. London, 1873. Shar. — Sharpe (Samuel) History of Egypt. 3rd Ed. 2 vols. 8vo. 1852. Sliortt. — Shortt (Dr, J.) Hill Ranges of S.S. India . Madras, 1871. ,, „ „ Transactions of the Ethnological Society. London, 1880. Sher. — Sherville in J.A.S.B. Shoot. — Shooter (Rev. Jos.) The Kafirs of Natal and the Zulu Country . 8 vo. 1857. Sim. — Simon (P.). Tercera ( y Cuartd) Noticia de la Segunda Parte de las Noticias His toriales de las Conquistas de Tierra Firme en el Nuevo Reyno de Granada. 1624, In Kingsboroughls Antiquities of Mexico , Vol. viii. Sis. — Sismondi (J. C. L, de) History of the Italian Republics (in Lard- ner’s Cyclopaedia). ,, „ „ Histoire des Republiques Italiennes. Nouv. ed. 16 vols. 8ro. 1826. Ske. — Skene (W. F.) Celtic Scotland. 1880. Sm. — Smith (R. Brough) Aborigines of Victoria. London, 1878. Smith. — Smith (E. R.) The Araucanians. London, 1855. Sohm. — Sohm (R.) Die frankische Reichs-und Gerichts-verfassung . Weimar 1871. Sou. — Southey (Rob.) History of Brazil. 3 vols. 4to. 1*810-19. Spix. — Spix and Martius, Travels in Brazil. Trans. London, 1824. Squi. — Squier (E. G.) Nicaragua. New York, 1852. „ „ „ Observations on the Geography and Archaeology of Peru. London, 1 870. St. J. — St.John’s (Spenser) Life in the Forests of the Far East. 2 vols. 8yo. 1862. St. Sim. — Saint-Simon (Due de) Memoirs of abridged by St. John. 4 vols. London, 1857. Stew. — Stewart in Journal Asiatic Society , Bengal. Stubbs. — Stubbs (Wm.) The Constitutional History of England. 3rd Ed. Oxford, 1880. Stiu’t. — Sturt (Capt. Chas.) Two Expeditions into the Interior of Southern Australia. Sup. Rel. — Supernatural Religion. 2nd Ed. 1874. Tac. — Tacitus Germania. Taine. — Taine (H.) V Ancien Regime. Trans. Tay. — Taylor (Dr. W. C.) Student's Manual of Ancient History (Egypt). 2 vols. 12mo. 1843. Ten. — Tennant (Sir J. Emerson) Sketches of the Natural History of Ceylon. p. 8yq. 1861. „ „ „ Ceylon ; an Account of the Island , 8pc. 2 vols. 8vo. 1859. Tern. — Ternaux-Compans (H.) Recueil de Pieces relatives a la Conguete du Mexigue. Paris, 1838-40. 686 POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS, Thirl. — Thirwall’s History of Greece in Lardner’s Cyclopaedia. Thom. — Thomson’s (Dr. A. S.) The Story of New Zealand Past and Present . 2 yols. Cr. 8vo. 1859. Thomp. — Thompson (Geo.) Travels and Adventures in Southern Africa. Thomp. — Thompson (G. A.) Alcedo’s Geogr. arid Historical Dictionary of America, Sec. London, 1812. Thor. — Thorpe (B.) Diplomat arium Anglicum (Evi Saxonici, a Collection of English Charters, fyc. 8vo. 1865. Tie. — Tiele (C. P.) Outlines of the History of Religion to the Spread of the Universal Religion. London, 1877. Translated from the Dutch by J. E. Carpenter. London, 1877. Tits. — Titsingh (J.) Annates des Empereurs de Japon . Trad, par Klaproth. Roy. 4to. 1834. Tor. — Torquemada (J. de) Monarquia Indiana, con el origin y Guerras de los Indios occidentales , Sfc. 3 yols. fol. Madrid, 1723. Toz. — Tozer (Rev. Hy. Fanshawe) Lectures on the Geography of Greece « London, 1873. Tur. — Turner (Key. W,) Nineteen Years in Polynesia . Turn. — Turner's (Sharon) History of England. 12 yols. London, 1839, Turp. — Turpin’s Siam in PinlcertorC s Travels. U. S. Ex. — United States Exploring Expedition. Yieus. — Yieusseaux (A.) History of Switzerland. London, 1840. Waitz. — Waitz (Dr. Theodor) Introduction to Anthropology . 1863. Wal. — Wallace’s Russia. Warn. — Warnkoenig (L. A.) Franzosische Staats-und Rechtsgeschichte. 2 yols. Basel, 1846. Wil. — Williams (Rev. J.) Fiji and the Fijians. 2 yols. Cr. 8vo. 1860. Wil. — Williams (S. Wells) The Middle Kingdom. 1848. Wilk. — Wilkinson (Sir J. G.) Manners and Customs of the Ancient Eqyptians. New edition, revised and corrected by Samuel Birch LL.D., D.C.L., &c. Wilkes — Wilkes’ (Capt.) Narrative in United States Exploring Expedition. Wint. — Winterbottom, Account of the Native Africans in the Neighbourhood of Sierra Leone. London, 1803. Wood. — Wood (Lieut. J.) Journey to the Source of River Oxits , London* 1841. Xim. — Ximenes (F.) Las Historias del Origin de los Indios de Guatemala „ You. — Young (Ernest) Anglo-Saxon Family Law. Zur. — Zurita (A.) Rapport sur les Chefs de la Nouvelle Espagne. Ternaux* Compans. Paris, I84G. u The American Constitution is the most Wonderful work ever struck off at a given time by the brain and purpose of man T— W 4 E, Gladstone* HISTORY Formation OF THE of the Constitution OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA. By GEORGE BANCROFT. Uniform withy and a continuation of the author's u History of the United States T 2 Vols., 8vo* Cloth, $2.50 per voL These volumes, while published separately, really form the eleventh and twelfth volumes of the ” History of the United States,” being directly connected with volume ten, last published. “ This long-expected continuation of the magnum opus of Mr. Bancroft has come at last, and, alike in perfection of style and fullness of contents, it abun« dantly justifies the more than Horatian delay brought by the venerable author to its preparation. In the grave and judicial summing up of its judgments on the great men and the great events here passed in review, it does not suffer at all by comparison with the immortal work of Thucydides, and it differs from the poigu- ant brevity of Tacitus only because Mr. Bancroft is broader and more liberal in his philosophy .”— New York Herald. ” Mr. George Bancroft, in his eighty -second year— an age which few men reach, and at which few of those who do reach it retain the disposition or the capacity for protracted literary labor— sends out to the world a work which, in its clear- ness and strength of diction, its breadth of scope, its wealth of fresh material, and its philosophic grasp of events and their causes, would have reflected honor upon his prime. His ‘ History of the Formation of the Constitution of the United States of America’ may be viewed either as a continuation of his previous ‘His- tory of the United States,’ or as an independent work ; and, Viewed in either aspect, it is a contribution to our literature of singular value and importance.’-— Boston Journal. “ It is nearly a half-century since George Bancroft published the first volume of the work by which his reputation has chiefly been made, and on which alone it will rest in after-time. He now gives to the world two additional volumes of his colossal undertaking, for, although possessing another title, they, in truth, are but a part of the work begun so long ago. As now known, his ‘History of the United States ’ ends with the peace. These volumes, therefore, take up the narrative where volume ten (the last one published) leaves it off, and thus become as much a continuation of the story as if they followed as volumes eleven and twelve of the ‘ History of the United States.’ "—New York Times. “ In the historical literature of the world, Bancroft’s History is a recognized authority concerning the period which it covers. It is not merely a narrative, but a philosophical treatise, dealing with causes and principles as well as events, and tracing with remarkable skill the progress of enlightenment and liberal ideas. The same plan that was followed in the first ten has been faithfully pur- sued in these last two volumes, to which the student may turn with pride and find stored up for his use the facts he seeks.”— Chicago Tribune. For sale by all booksellers ; or sent by mail, post-paid, on receipt of price. New York : D. APPLETON k CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street THE HISTORY OF EHGLAID IN THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY. By W. E. H. LECKY, Author of “ History of the Rise and Influence of the Spirit of Rationalism in Europe,” etc. Volumes III and IV, extending from the accession of George III to 1784. tlie opening year of Pitt's first ministry, and covering the period of the American Revolution. Published by arrangement with the author. Large 12mo. Uniform with Vols. I and If of which new editions are now ready. The 4 vols*, cloth, $2*25 each* 44 This section of the work covers the first twenty-two years of the reign of George III, a period which,, in its bearing on constitutional, political, and social problems, was the most pregnant in the modern history of Great Britain, it was during these momentous years that the relation of the Crown to a Ministry representing the House of Commons was definitely fixed, that the necessity of parliamentary reform and the expediency of abolishing Catholic disabilities were distinctly recognized, and that the influence of the newspaper press acquired Unprecedented weight among political agencies, and called for new guarantees of freedom by changes in the law of libel. This was the period of Burke's most potent and exemplary activity, of the Middlesex election in which Wilkes played a part analogous to that taken by Bradlaugh in our own day, of the ministries of Bute, Grenville, Rockingham, Chatham, Shelburne, and the younger Pitt. “At home and abroad this quarter of a century was memorable for conquests and revolutions. The affairs of the East India Company were administered by Clive, and the vast accessions of territory in Bengal were supplemented by those resulting from the war with Hyder Ali. In America the discontent of the thirteen colonies had ripened into open revolt, and all the phases of the contest are ex- hibited in these volumes, up to the last year of exhaustion and inaction which preceded the final peace. Simultaneous with this movement on the other side of the Atlantic was the growth of political discontent in Ireland, which culminated in the demand for legislative independence. All of these topics are carefully discussed by Mr. Lecky. and the spirit which he evinces is so candid and impartial that his conclusions will be listened to with attention and respect, even where they run counter to the reader’s individual opinions and predilections.”— New York Sun. “ The directness and lucidity of style, the copiousness of information, and the manifest endeavor to be strictly accurate and impartial, which were strongly marked characteristics of the earlier volumes, are dominant features also in these. His work, so far as it has progressed, will be by common consent awarded its place as the most important and impartial history of the period.” — Boston Journal. 44 The two new volumes of Lecky’s 4 History of England ’ will prove of special interest to Americans, as they cover the period of the American Revolution, and treat of statesmen, soldiers, authors, and philosophers, whose memories are enshrined in the hearts of the American people. His history of this period will present many points of interest when compared with that of the American his- torian Bancroft, whose latest work, by a happy coincidence, is simultaneously published with Mr. Lecky’s.”— Chicago Journal . For sale by all booksellers ; or sent by mail , post-paid , on receipt of price . New York; D. APPLETON & CO., 1 , 3, & 5 Bond Street. THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY HERBERT SPENCER. FIRST PRINCIPLES. 1 vol. $2.00. CONTENTS. Part I.*- The Unknowable. 1 Religion and Science. 4. The Relativity of all Knowl 2. Ultimate Religious Ideas. 3. Ultimate Scientific Ideas. edge. The Reconciliation. Part II.— The Knowable. 1. Philosophy defined. 2. The Data of Philosophy. 3. Space, Time, Matter, Motion, and Force. 4 . The Indestructibility of Matter. 5. The Continuity of Motion. 6. The Persistence of Force. 7. The Persistence of Relations among Forces. 8. The Transformation and Equiv- alence of Forces. 9. The Direction of Motion. 10. The Rhythm of Motion. 11 . Recapitulation, Criticism, and Recommencement. 12 . Evolution and Dissolution. 24. Summary (con. (con. (con- 13. Simple and Compound Evolu- tion. 14. The Law of Evolution. 15. The Law of Evolution tinued). 16. The Law of Evolution tinued). 17. The Law of Evolution eluded). 1 8. The Interpretation of Evolution. 19. The Instability of the Homoge* neous. 20. The Multiplication of Effects. 21. Segregation. 22. Equilibration. 23. Dissolution, and Conclusion. THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY, 2 vols. $4.00. CONTENTS OF VOL. I. Part I. — The Data of Biology. 1. Organic Matter. 2. The Actions of Forces on Or- ganic Matter. 8. The Reactions of Organic Mat- ter on Forces. 7. The Scope of Biology. 4. Proximate Definition of Life. 5. The Correspondence between Life and its Circumstances. 6. The Degree of Life varies as the Degree of Correspondence. 2 spencer’s SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY- Part II. 1. Growth. 2. Development. 3. Function. 4. Waste and Repair. 6. Adaptation. 0 Individuality. -The Inductions of Biology. 7. Genesis. 8. Heredity. 9. Variation. 10. Genesis, Heredity, and Varia- tion. 11. Classification. 12. Distribution. Part III.— The Evolution of Life. 1. Preliminary. 2. General Aspects of the Special- Creation Hypothesis. 5. General Aspects of the Evolu- tion Hypothesis. 4. The Arguments from Classifica- tion. 6. The Arguments from Embryol- ogy. 6. The Arguments from Morphol- ogy. 7. The Arguments from Distribu- tion. 8. How is Organic Evolution caused ? 9. External Factors. 10. Internal Factors. 11. Direct Equilibration. 12. Indirect Equilibration. 13. The Cooperation of the Factors. 14. The Convergence of the Evi- dences. CONTEXTS OF VOL. II. Part IV. — Morphological Development. 1. The Problems of Morphology. 2. The Morphological Composition of Plants. 8. The Morphological Composition of Plants (continued). 4. The Morphological Composition of Animals. 6. The Morphological Composition of Animals (continued). 6. Morphological Differentiation in Plants. 7. The General Shapes of Plants. 8. The Shapes of Branches. 9. The Shapes of Leaves. 10. The Shapes of Flowers. 11. The Shapes of Vegetal Cells. 12. Changes of Shape otherwise caused. 13. Morphological Differentiation in Animals. 14. The General Shapes of Animals. 15. The Shapes of Vertebrate Skele- tons. 16. The Shapes of Animal Cells. 17. Summary of Morphological De- velopment. Part V.— Physiological Development. 1. The Problems of Physiology. 2. Differentiations among the Out- er and Inner Tissues of Plants. 3. Differentiations among the Out- er Tissues of Plants. 4. Differentiations among the In- ner Tissues of Plants. 5. Physiological Integration in Plants. 6. Differentiations between the Outer and Inner Tissues of Animals. 7. Differentiations among the Out- er Tissues of Animals. 8. Differentiations among the In- ner Tissues of Animals. 9. Physiological Integration in In imals. 10. Summary of Physiological Development. spencer’s synthetic philosophy. 3 Part VI. — Laws of Multiplication. 1. The Factors. 2. A priori Principle. 3. Obverse a priori Principle. 4. Difficulties of Inductive Verifi- cation. 5. Antagonism between Growth and Asexual Genesis. 6. Antagonism between Growth and Sexual Genesis. *J. Antagonism between Develop- ment and Genesis, Asexual and Sexual. A Criticism on Professor Owen’s The- ory of the Vertebrate Skeleton. 8. Antagonism between Expendi- ture and Genesis. 9. Coincidence between High Nu- trition and Genesis. 10. Specialties of these Rela- tions. 11. Interpretation and Qualifica- tion. 12. Multiplication of the Human Race. 13. Human Evolution in the Fu- ture. On Circulation and the Formation of Wood in Plants. Appendix. THE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY, 2 vols. $4.00. CONTENTS OF VOL. /. Part I. — The Data of Psychology. 1. The Nervous System. 2. The Structure of the Nervous System. 3. The Functions of the Nervous System. 4. The Conditions essential to Ner- vous Action. 5. Nervous Stimulation and Ner- vous Discharge. 6. Aestho-Physiology. Part II. — The Inductions of Psychology. 1. The Substance of Mind. 2. The Composition of Mind. 3. The Relativity of Feelings. 4. The Relativity of Relations be- tween Feelings. 5. The Revivability of Feelings. Part III. — General Synthesis. 6. The Revivability of Relations between Feelings. 7. The Associability of Feelings. 8. The Associability of Relations between Feelings. 9. Pleasures and Pains. 1. Life and Mind as Correspon- dence. 2. The Correspondence as Direct and Homogeneous. 3. The Correspondence as Direct but Heterogeneous. 4. The Correspondence as extend- ing in Space. 5. The Correspondence as extend- ing in Time. 6. The Correspondence as increas- ing in Specialty. 7. The Correspondence as increas- ing in Generality. 8. The Correspondence as increas- ing in Complexity. 9. The Coordination of Correspon- dences. 10. The Integration of Correspon- dences. 11. The Correspondences in their Totality. i spencer's synthetic philosophy. 1 . 2 . 3. 4. 1 . 2 . 3. 4. 5 . 1 . 2 . 3. 4. 5. 6 . 7. 8 . 9. 10 . II. 12 . Part IV. — Special Synthesis. The Nature of Intelligence. 5. Instinct. The Law of Intelligence. 6. Memory. The Growth of Intelligence. 7. Reason. Reflex Action. 8. The Feelings. 9. The Will. Part V. — Physical Synthesis. A Further Interpretation need- ed. The Genesis of Nerves. The Genesis of Simple Nervous Systems. The Genesis of Compound Ner- vous Systems. The Genesis of Doubly Com- pound Nervous Systems. 6. Functions as related to these Structures. 7. Physical Laws as thus inter- preted. 8. Evidence from Normal Varia- tions. 9. Evidence from Abnormal Va- riations. 10. Results. Appendix. On the Action of Anaesthetics and Narcotics. CONTEXTS OF VOL. II. Limitation of the Subject. Compound Quantitative Reason- ing. Compound Quantitative Reason- ing (continued). Imperfect and Simple Quantita- tive Reasoning. Quantitative Reasoning in gen- eral. Perfect Qualitative Reasoning. Imperfect Qualitative Reason- ing. Reasoning in general. Classification, Naming, and Rec- ognition. The Perception of Special Ob- jects. The Perception of Body as pre- senting Dynamical, Statico- Dynamical, and Statical Attri- butes. The Perception of Body as pre- 25. senting Statico-Dynamical and 26. Statical Attributes. 27. The Perception of Body as presenting Statical Attri- butes. The Perception of Space. The Perception of Time. The Perception of Motion. The Perception of Resist- ance. Perception in general. The Relations of Similarity and Dissimilarity. The Relations of Cointension and Non-Cointension. The Relations of Coextension and Non-Coextension. The Relations of Coexistence and Non-Coexistence. The Relations of Connature and Non-Connature. The Relations of Likeness and Unlikeness. The Relation of Sequence. Consciousness in general. Results. Part VI. — Special Analysis. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20 . 21 . 22 . 23. 24. spencer's synthetic philosophy. 5 1 . 2 . 3. 4. 5. 6 . 7. 8 . 9 . 10 . 1 . 2 . 3. 4 1 . 2 . 3. 4. 5. 6 . 7. 8 . 9. 10 . 11 . 12 . 13. 14. Part VII.— General Analysis. The Final Question. The Assumption of Metaphysi- cians. The Words of Metaphysicians. The Reasonings of Metaphysi- cians. [ism. Negative Justification of Real- The Argument from Priority. The Argument from Simplicity. The Argument from Distinct- A Criterion wanted. [ness. Propositions qualitatively dis- tinguished. 11. The Universal Postulate. 12. The Test of Relative Validity. 13. Its Corollaries. 14. Positive Justification of Real- ism. 15. The Dynamics of Consciousness. 16. Partial Differentiation of Sub- ject and Object. 17. Completed Differentiation of Subject and Object. 18. Developed Conception of the Object. 19. Transfigured Realism. 6. Sociality and Sympathy. 6. Egoistic Sentiments. 7. Ego-Altruistic Sentiments. 8. Altruistic Sentiments. Part VIII. — Corollaries. Special Psychology. Classification. Development of Conceptions. Language of the Emotions. 9. Aesthetic Sentiments. THE PRINCIPLES OF SOCIOLOGY. Vol. I. $2.00. CONTENTS. Part I. — The Data of Sociology. Super-Organic Evolution. The Factors of Social Phenom- ena. Original External Factors. Original Internal Factors. The Primitive Man — Physical. The Primitive Man — Emotional. The Primitive Man — Intellec- tual. Primitive Ideas. The Ideas of the Animate and the Inanimate. The Ideas of Sleep and Dreams. The Ideas of Swoon, Apoplexy, Catalepsy, Ecstasy, and other Forms of Insensibility. The Ideas of Death and Resur- rection. The Ideas of Souls, Ghosts, Spirits, Demons. The Ideas of Another Life. 15. The Ideas of Another World. 16. The Ideas of Supernatural Agents. 17. Supernatural Agents as causing Epilepsy and Convulsive Ac- tions, Delirium and Insanity, Disease and Death. 18. Inspiration, Divination, Exor- cism, and Sorcery. 19. Sacred Places, Temples, and Altars ; Sacrifice, Fasting, and Propitiation; Praise, Prayer. 20. Ancestor- Worship in general. 21. Idol- Worship and Fetich- Wor- ship. 22. Animal-Worship. 23. Plant-Worship. 24. Nature-Worship. 25. Deities. 26. The Primitive Theory of Things. 27\ The Scope of Sociology. 6 spencer’s synthetic philosophy. Part II. — The Inductions of Sociology. 1 . What is a Society ? 2. A Society is an Organism. 3. Social Growth. 4. Social Structures. 6. Social Functions. 6. Systems of Organs. 7. The Sustaining System. 8. The Distributing System. 9. The Regulating System. 10. Social Types and Constitutions 11. Social Metamorphoses. 12. Qualifications and Summary. Part III.— The Domestic Relations. 1. The Maintenance of Species. 2. The Diverse Interests of the Species, of the Parents, and of the Offspring. 3. Primitive Relations of the Sexe3. 4. Exogamy and Endogamy. 5. Promiscuity. 6. Polyandry. 7. Polygyny. ' 8. Monogamy. 9. The Family. 10. The Status of Women. 11. The Status of Children. 12. Domestic Retrospect and Pros- pect. Yol. II. Part IV. — Ceremonial Institutions. $1.25. 1. Ceremony in general. 2. Trophies. 3. Mutilations. 4. Presents. 6. Visits. 6. Obeisances. CONTENTS. 7. Forms of Address. 8. Titles. 9. Badges and Costumes. 10. Further Class-Distinctions. 11. Fashion. 12. Ceremonial Retrospect and Prospect. Yol. II. Part Y. — Political Institutions. $ CONTENTS. 1. Preliminary. 2. Political Organization in gen- eral. 3. Political Integration. 4. Political Differentiation. 5. Political Forms and Forces. 6. Political Heads — Chiefs, Kings, etc. 7. Compound Political Heads. 8. Consultative Bodies. 9. Representative Bodies. 10. Ministries. 11. Local Governing Agencies. 12. Military Systems. 13. Judicial and Executive Systems. 14. Laws. 15. Property. 16. Revenue. 17. The Militant Type of Society. 18. The Industrial Type of Society. 19. Political Retrospect and Pros- pect. Yol. III. In Reparation. spencer’s synthetic philosophy. 7 THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALITY. Yol. I. Part I. — The Data of Ethics. $1.25. CONTENTS \ 1. Conduct in general. 2. The Evolution of Conduct. 3. Good and Bad Conduct. 4. Ways of judging Conduct. 6. The Physical View. 6. The Biological View. 7. The Psychological View. 8. The Sociological View. 9. Criticisms and Explanations. 10. The Relativity of Pains and Pleasures. 11. Egoism versus Altruism. 12. Altruism versus Egoism. 13. Trial and Compromise. 14. Conciliation. 15. Absolute Ethics and Relative Ethics. 16. The Scope of Ethics. Vol. II. In preparation . This philosophical system differs from all its predecessors in being solidly based on the sciences of observation and induction ; in repre- senting the order and course of Nature ; in bringing Nature and man, life, mind, and society, under one great law of action ; and in developing a method of thought which may serve for practical guidance in dealing with the affairs of life. “ The only complete and systematic statement of the doctrine of evolution with which I am acquainted is that contained in Mr. Herbert Spencer’s ‘System of Philosophy,’ a work which should be carefully studied by all who desire to know whither scientific thought is tending.” — T. H. Huxley. “ Mr. Spencer is one of the most vigorous as well as boldest thinkers that English speculation has yet produced.” — John Stuart Mill. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. THE MISCELLANEOUS WORKS or HERBERT SPENCER. EDUCATION: INTELLECTUAL, MORAL, AND PHYSICAL. 1 vol. $1.25. CONTENTS. \ What Knowledge is of most 2. Intellectual Education. Worth ? 3. Moral Education. 4. Physical Education. SOCIAL STATICS; OR, THE CONDITIONS ESSENTIAL TO HUMAN HAPPINESS SPEC! FIED, AND THE FIRST OF THEM DEVELOPED. 1 vol. $2.00. CONTENTS. Introduction. The Doctrine of Expediency. Lemma I. The Doctrine of the Moral Sense. Lemma II. Part I. 1. Definition of Morality. 3. The Divine Idea, and the Con- 2. The Evanescence of Evil. ditions of its Realization. Part II. 4. Derivation of a First Principle. 5. Secondary Derivation of a First Principle. 6. First Principle. [ciple. *7. Application of this First Prin- 8. The Rights of Life and Per- sonal Liberty. 9. The Right to the Use of the Earth. 10. The Right of Property. 11. The Right of Property in Ideas. 12. The Right of Property in Char- acter. 13. The Right of Exchange. 14. The Right of Free Speech. 15. Further Rights. 16. The Rights of Women. lY. The Rights of Children. spencer's miscellaneous works. 9 Part III. 18. Political Rights. 19. The Right to ignore the State. 20. The Constitution of the State. 21. The Duty of the State. 22. The Limit of State-Duty. 23. The Regulation of Commerce. 24. Religious Establishment. 25. Poor-Laws. 26. National Education. 27. Government Colonization. 28. Sanitary Supervision. [etc. 29. Currency, Postal Arrangements, 30. General Considerations. Part IV. 31. Summary. 32. Conclusion. THE STUDY OF SOCIOLOGY. 1 vol. $1.50. CONTENTS. 1. Our Need of it. 2. Is there a Social Science ? 3. Nature of the Social Science. 4. Difficulties of the Social Science. 5. Objective Difficulties. 6. Subjective Difficulties — Intel- lectual. 7. Subjective Difficulties — Emo- tional. 8. The Educational Bias. 9. The Bias of Patriotism. 10. The Class-Bias. 11. The Political Bias. 12. The Theological Bias. 13. Discipline. 14. Preparation in Biology. 15. Preparation in Psychology. 16. Conclusion. ILLUSTRATIONS OF UNIVERSAL PROG- RESS. 1 vol. $2.00. CONTENTS. 1. Progress: its Law and Cause. 2. Manners and Fashion. 3. The Genesis of Science. 4. The Physiology of Laughter. 5. The Origin and Function of Mu- 6. The Nebular Hypothesis, [sic. 7. Bain on the Emotions and the Will. 8. Illogical Geology. 9. Development Hypothesis. 10. The Social Organism. 11. Use and Beauty. 12. The Sources of Architectural Types. 13. The Use of Anthropomor- phism. ESSAYS: MORAL, POLITICAL, AND AESTHETIC. 1 vol. $2.00. CONTENTS. t. The Philosophy of Style. 3. The Morals of Trade. 2. Our Legislation. 4. Personal Beauty. 10 spencer’s miscellaneous works. 6. Representative Government. 6. Prison Ethics. 7. Railway Morals and Railway Policies. 8. Gracefulness. 9. State Tamperings with Money and Banks. 10. Parliamentary Reforms : the Dangers and the Safeguards. 11. Mill versus Hamilton — the Test of Truth. RECENT DISCUSSIONS In Science, Philosophy, and Morals. 1 vol. CONTENTS. 2 . 00 . 1. Morals and Moral Sentiments. 2. Origin of Animal- Worship. 8. The Classification of the Sci- ences. 4. Postscript : Replying to Criti- cisms. 5. Reasons for dissenting from the Philosophy of Comte. 6. Of Laws in general and the Or- der of their Discovery. 7. The Genesis of Science. 8. Specialized Administrations. 9. What is Electricity ? 10. The Constitution of the Sun. 11. The Collective Wisdom. 12. Political Fetichism. 13. Mr. Martineau on Evolution. DESCRIPTIVE SOCIOLOGY: A Cyclopaedia of Social Facts ; representing the Constitution of Every Type and Grade of Human Society. Classified and arranged by Herbert Spencer. Compiled and abstracted by David Duncan, M. A., Professor of Logic, etc., in the Presidency College, Madras ; Richard Scheppig, Ph. D. ; and James Collier. Royal folio. Parts I to VII, $4.00 each ; No. VIII (Double Number), $7.00. No. 1 . English. Compiled and abstracted by James Collier. No. 2. Ancient Mexicans, Central Americans, Chibchas, and An- cient Peruvians. Compiled and abstracted by Richard Scheppig, Ph. D. No. 3. Types of the Lowest Races. Negrito Races. Malayo- Polynesian Races. Compiled and abstracted by Professor David Duncan, M. A. No. 4. African Races. Compiled and abstracted by Professor David Duncan, M. A. No. 5. Asiatic Races. Compiled and abstracted by Professor David Duncan, M. A. No. 6. North and South American Races. Compiled and abstracted by Professor David Duncan, M. A. \ No. 7. Hebrews and Phoenicians. Compiled and abstracted by Rich- ard Scheppig, Ph. D. No. 8. French. Compiled and abstracted by James Collier. New York : D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street.