'YAILE«'¥]MII¥lEI^SlIir¥'' DIVINITY SCHOOL TROWBRIDGE LIBRARY RULING IDEAS IN EARLY AGES RULING IDEAS IN EARLY AGES AND, THEIR RELATION TO OLD TESTAMENT FAITH lectures delivered to graduates of the university of oxford BY J. B. MOZLEY, D.D. LATE CANON OF CHRIST CHORCH, AND REGIUS PROFESSOR OF DIVINITY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD third edition RIVINGTONS WATERLOO PLACE, LONDON MDCCCLXXXIV TO THE RIGHT HONOURABLE LORD BLACHFORD, IN MEMORY OF COLLEGE DAYS, WHEN HE FIRST LEARNT TO ESTIMATE IN HIM HIGH GIFTS OF MIND AND HEART, •THIS VOLUME IS INSCRIBED BY HIS AFFECTIONATE FRIEND, THE AUTHOR. Christ Church, Nov. 23, 1876. AD VERTISEMENT. The following course of ten Lectures was delivered to Graduates mostly engaged in tuition in Michaelmas and Lent terms, 1874-1875. Thp Lecture on St. Augustine's controversy with the Manichseans is one of a previous course, but is added here as bearing closely upon the main subject of the present volume. CONTENTS. LECTURE L ABRAHAM. Abraham the introducer of a new and pure religion — Early paganism could not conceive the worship of God — The character of Abraham as a man of independent thought — The conception of one God brought with it the question of the Divine justice — Abraham lived in the future — His prophetic look singled out by our Lord — Vestiges of prophecy among the heathen : the Sibyl — Physical side of prophecy : Bacon — Difference in the treatment of prophecy by paganism and true religion — Abraham's qualifications for founding a true religion — Abraham the father and also the apostle of his nation — Looking forward, he sees his own greatness as a founder — ^A posthumous name not a Gospel motive — The Gospel the tidings of a real immortality .... Pages 1-30 LECTURE il SACRIFICE OF ISAAC. Usual answer to objectors on the summary mode of dealing with human life in Old Testament — Bishop Butler — Certain Divine commands once proved by miracles would not be proved by them now — Eights of human life part of the moral progress of mankind — One remarkable want in the ancient mind : the idea of the individu ality of man — The slave, the wife, the son, all property of another — Oriental law — Spartan law — Eoman law — Prevalence of human sacrifices in ancient religions — These defective ideas traceable in Patriarchal Jewish minds — No opposing argument to a miracle in xii Contents. Abraham's mind — Abraham sacrifices a life which he thought his own — God suits His commands to the age — Self-surrender of the act — Out of an inferior state of ideas an act of sublime self- sacrifice was extracted — The rudeness of an age admits of exalted acts buUt on it — Every period of the world contributes a special moral beauty Pages ¦^i-d-^ LECTURE ill HUMAN SACRIFICES. Theory of one school that Abraham's sacrifice was after the pattern of the day — Scripture account plainly against this idea — The sacri fice of Isaac not an pfiering for sin but a trial of faith — No sin to be atoned for mentioned — Abraham believed that the victim would be restored to life — Argument that this would take away the merit, answered — The act designed as a type of the Great Propitiation — the Brazen Serpent — The heathen recognised the principle of sacrifice — Summary of this and preceding Lecture Pages 64-82 LECTURE IV. EXTERMINATING WARS. The right of God to the life of nations the same as to the life of indi- .viduals — Argument of objectors — Miracles — Samaritan village — Punishment of children for sins of fathers — Oriental practice of this mode of retribution — Justice sometimes becomes a passion All passion tends to the unreasonable, and makes objects for itself — Livy — Aristotle — Blood composes identity in Oriental justice — Israelites shared the general feeling — The command to > destroy whole nations did not ofiTend their ideas of justice Distinction in the mode of holding the principle — No resistance to it in. the moral sense in early ages — Modern society is pene trated by a sense of individuality . . . /Wf 8vio? Contents. xiii .LECTURE V. VISITATION OF THE SINS OF FATHERS UPON CHILDREN. The task of separating the permanent from the temporary parts of the law — The Sermon on the Mount — St. Paul only recognises the perfect law — What the Deity admits because of the hardness of men's hearts — Commands given in judicial anger — Balaam — The laws of marriage, divorce, retaliation — Second Commandment — In the old dispensation children sufiered judicially — We do not now understand the Second Commandment as judicial but didactic — ^So understood before the end of Jewish dispensation — Ezekiel — Bishop Taylor — Bishop Sanderson — Double aspect of extra ordinary Divine commands — Korah, Dathan, and Abiram ; Achan, Saul, etc. — Our interpretation of these acts differs from the contem porary one Pages 10 ^-¦i2<-^ LECTURE VL JAEL. In what light would an enthusiastic mind of that day view the Israelitish invasion? — Sight of a whole nation worshipping God — Ancient pagan world believed truth to belong to the few — Civil con stitution of Israel contrary to that of all heathen nations — Israel a theocracy — The Exodus — The promulgation of the Law — The entrance into Canaan — Extraordinary fact of a woman rousing her countrymen to war — St. Augustine's supposition : Jael must have known the state of affairs — Destruction of the inhabitants primary condition of conquest — This condition only suspended — Extracts from Dr. Stanley — The Judges not qivil but military rulers — Ofi&ce of Judge — Too commonly imagined that Jael was apart from the religious influences of the time — More probably one with Israel in faith — The Kenezites — Jehonadab — Jael's partizanship — Who Sisera was — His probable character and importance — Jael's history a fragment Pages \2(i-\ij2 xiv Contents, LECTURE VLL CONNECTION OF JAEL'S ACT WITH THE MORALITY OF HER AGE. The command on which Jael acted not one in the full sense of com mands to Christians — The treachery of her act — St. Paul's posiT tion on the duty of truth-speaking — When the bonds of charity are broken, does this affect the duty of truth ? — The argument of the murderer — Essential for a perfect defence of Jael that the command on which she acted should be without reserve — This a command in accommodation — Great omission of that day, idea of human individuality — Duke of Wellington's character of the Hindus — Does the defence of Jael's act imply approbation of the whole of Scripture % — Deborah judged according to the standard of her own day — Jael's a grand act, on the principle. Love your friend and hate your enemy — Different position of lying in civilisation and barbarism — The creed of Love your friend and hate your enemy fostered subtle mixtures of character — Es^it di corps-r-We are apt to suppose rude ages simple — What civilisation has done for truth and plain dealing . . Pages 153-179 LECTURE VIIL LAW OF RETALIATION. Biblical critics do not make allowance for a progressive revelation — Legislation must be legislation for the present moment — Principle of accommodation— Law of retaliation — Dean Alford on Matthew v. 38 : Thou shalt love thy neighbour and hate thine enemy — Effect of this law in creating es/prit de corps — Tacitus on the Jewish temper — The enemy not always a heathen to the Jew —Saul, Ahithophel— Enemy in the Gospel— Case where the enemy was also enemy of God— The damnatory Psahua Pages 180-200 Contents. xv LECTURE IX. RETALIATION : LAW OF GOEL. The law of Goel—Michaelis— Sanctioned by Moses— Nothing optional in this law — Mistake of commentators on the passion of revenge — The task imposed by the law of Goel — Men not always faithful to rights of the dead — Eude ages not without moderate tactics — Fines for murder — Hindus — Germans— Death for death the only way to meet murder — Reference to Lecture V. — Law of Goel not an inhuman idea to that age — Acts of modern enthusiasts — An imperfect idea may be moral at the root — Principle of accom modation—St. Augustine — God may command in judgment — Opinions of commentators : Calvin ; Theodoret ; TertuUian ; Chrysostom — Objectoi^'s mode of treating imperfect morality — Early struggles of the great principle of justice — Power at work in the Jewish dispensation .... Pages 201-221 LECTURE X. THE END THE TEST OF A PROGRESSIVE REVELATION. Answers to objectors to the foregoing argument — A progressive revelation may make use of imperfect moral standard — It looked forward — An inward mind in the system taught ex cathedrd — The Prophets — The end shows the design of the system — While accommodating itself to defective ideas it was eradicating them — No system of philosophy taught the rights of man — The Bible the charter of man's rights — Ancient empire founded on the insignificance of man — The vast body of philosophy and poetry formed by the Bible — Pascal — Great body of infidel literature founded on same idea — Shelley — The communion of man with God affected the relation of man with man — The law thus con tained the secret of his elevation — History shows the law to have been above the nation — The nation was terrified into a formal xvi Contents. obedience — The enforcement of law the task of one dispensation, its fruits of another — A progressive revelation must be judged by its end — Higher minds outgrew the law of their dispensation — Other nations stopped short — In the Jewish nation alone the law acted as a guide — The great prophetic order — The objector asks why should Divine Eevelation be subject to conditions? — The human wiU: its capacity of resistance — The whole question belongs to the fundamental difficulty of reconciling God's power with man's free wiU — Miracles — Temporary morals only a scaffolding Pages 222-253 LAST LECTURE. THE MANICH^ANS AND THE JEWISH FATHERS. St. Augustine as a controversialist — His qualifications — His first con troversy was with the Manichseans — Language of Manichaeanism — Hume taken with the theory — Extracts from Hume — John Stuart Mill on his father's sympathy with dualism — Zoroaster and the Magi — Manichseanism differed from the ordinary type of Oriental religions — Aimed at being a universal religion — Professed to incorporate certain doctrines of Christianity into its system — Acknowledged no true Incarnation — Objections of Manich^ans to Old Testament history — It held the family life of the Patriarchs in contempt, and endeavoured to substitute the Magi as forefathers instead of the Old Testament Saints — Faustus' language towards them — Answer of St. Augustine to these objections — He acknow ledges an imperfect morality in the Old Testament ages — This does not affect his estimate of the Patriarchs' high sanctity—^ Fundamental unity between Patriarchs and Apostles Pages 254-275 APPENDIX /'«^« 277-295 LECTURE L ABRAHAM. rpHE Patriarch Abraham comes before us in Scrip- -*- ture under the following main aspects : — 1. He comes before us as the introducer of a new and pure religious creed and worship — new, I say, for though the doctrine of one God was part of the prime- , val revelation, it had become much corrupted before Abraham's time. " Your fathers," said Joshua to the Israelites, " dwelt on the other side of the flood {i.e., the Euphrates) in old time, even Terah, the father of Abraham, and the father of Nachor : and they served other gods"^ [Note 1). The migration, then, from Chal- dsea was a religious one — ^the migration of a family which had cast off the gods of its country, adopted the worship of one God, and sought a new home where it might conduct this worship freely. And though the " call " of Abraham is mentioned in Genesis ^ as sub sequent to, in St. Stephen's statement^ as prior to, the journey from Chaldasa, the whole voice of sacred history declares Abraham to have been, under Divine inspiration, the leader of that whole movement which thus set up the worship of the true God in the place of idols, and separated his family from the corrupt religion of the world. " Put away," says Joshua, 1 Josh. xxiv. 2. ^ Gen. xii. 1. ' Acts vii. 2, 3. B 2 Abraham. " the gods which your fathers served on the other side the flood;" and "I took your father Abraham from the other side the flood." ^ Open idolatry then was the religion of the genera tion in which Abraham was born ; he was brought up and educated under it, it was in possession of the ground, and it pressed upon him with all the power of association and authority. But at a certain time of life Abraham comes before us as having rejected this creed and worship, having thrown off the chains of custom, and released himself from the thraldom of early associations : as holding the great doctrine of one God, whom he worships by means of a spiritual conception only, without the aid of figure or symbol. He comes before us as the re-introducer into the world of the great normal idea of worship ; — that idea which, descending through the Jewish and Christian dispensa tions in succession, is the basis of the religion of the whole modem civilised world — the worship of God. All ancient religion, as' distinguished from the primitive, laboured under the total inability of even conceiving the idea of the worshi/p of God. It split and went to pieces upon that rock ; acknowledging in a speculative sense one God, but not applying worship to Him. The local, the limited, the finite, was as such an object of worship ; the Infinite as such was not : the one was personal, the other impersonal ; man stood in re lation to the one, he could not place himself in relation to the other. We discover in the Patriarch whom God extricated from the self-imposed dilemma ^ Josh. xxiv. 14. Abraham. 3 of all ancient religion, and who was enabled to cast off the yoke of custom and embrace new truth, the strength of a true rational nature, as well as the devotion of a reformer of religious worship. A Divine revelation does not dispense with a certain character and certain qualities of mind in the person who is the instrument of it. A man who throws off the chains of authority and association must be a man of extra ordinary independence of mind, and strength of mind, although he does so in obedience to a Divine revelation; because no miracle, no sign or wonder which accom panies a revelation, can by its simple stroke force human nature from the innate hold of custom, and the ad hesion to, and fear of, established opinion ; can enable it to confront the frowns of men, and take up truth opposed to general prejudice, except there is in the man himself, who is the recipient of the revelation, a certain strength of mind and independence which concurs with the Divine intention. It is the Divine method and law that man should co-operate with God ; and that God should act by means of men who are fit ting instruments ; and this law implies that those who are God's instruments possess real character of their own ia correspondence with their mission. The mission to set up or propagate new truth required in Abraham's day, in the. natural character of him who had to execute it, something of the nature of what we call a religious reformer in modern times. The recipient of a new revelation must have self-reliance, otherwise he will not believe that he has received it ; he will not be sure of it against the force of current opinions, 4 Abraham. and men teUing him on every side that he is mis taken. Upon this principle then, that a Divine mission requires the proper man, we discern in Abraham the type which in modern language we call that of the man of thought, upon whom some deep truth has fastened with irresistible power, and whose mind dwells and feeds upon the conviction of it. The truth in the case of Abraham was the conception of one God. And we may observe this great thought was accompanied in his mind, as it has been in aU minds which have been profoundly convinced of it, by another, which naturally attaches to, it. We may recognise in Abraham's colloquy with God over the impending fate of Sodom, something like the appear ance of that great question which has always been connected with the doctrine of the Unity of God — the question of the Divine justice. The doctrine of the Unity of God raises the question of His justice for this reason, that-^one God, who is both good and omnipotent, being assumed — we immediately think. Why should He who is omnipotent permit that which He who is in His own nature supremely good, cannot desire, that is evil? The thought, it is true, does not come out in any regular or full form in this mysterious colloquy ; and yet it hovers over it; there are hints and forecastings of this great question, which is destined to trouble the human intellect, and to try faith, and to absorb meditation, as long as the world lasts. A shadow passes over, the air stirs sKghtly, and there is just that fragment Abraham. 5 of thought and questioning, which would be in place as the first dawn of a great controversy. " That be far from thee," " that the righteous should be as the wicked : " " shall not the Judge of aU the earth do right ? " ^ The Book of Job has been assigned a much later date than the received one, by some, on the ground that the deep vein of thought and sentiment in it, the perception of the difficulty relating to the Divine justice, belongs to a later, more philosophical age of mankind than that primitive one, — to an age of speculation. But it must be considered that this question arises immediately upon the adoption of the belief in one Supreme Being : so that, as soon as ever the belief in the unity of God is obtained, the question of His justice arises with it. We need not, therefore, on this sole account alter the date of the Book of Job, when even in the rudiments of thought which rise up in the colloquy over Sodom, we may see the beginnings of that expression of the deep sentiment of justice which the Book of Job gives with such fulness; and may recognise the germ of that question which still continues to perplex the human mind, and to agitate the atmosphere of human poetry and philosophy. 2. Abraham comes before us as a person who lives in the future, whose mind is cast forward, beyond the immediate foreground of his own day, upon a very remote epoch in the history of the world, and fixed upon a remarkable event in the most distant horizon of time, the nature of which is vague and 1 Gen. xviii. 25. 6 Abraham,. dimly known to him, but which is charged with momentous consequences, involving a change in the whole state of the world. The revelation is made to him, — "In thee shall all families of the earth be blessed ; " he looks onward perpetually to the accom plishment of this prediction. He has the idea in his mind of the world's progress, of a movement in the present order of things towards some great end and consummation. This is a remarkable state of mind. Ordinary men do not live in the future, and have very little idea that things wiU ever be different from what they are in their own day. The actual state of the world around them is the type of all existence in their eyes, and they cannot conceive another mould or form of .things, or even imagine that there ever can be another; they are crea tures of present time, nor do they ever entertain distinctly the idea of the future existence of the world at all. It is therefore a fact to arrest us, even if this was all we had — a man in a primitive age of the world, while he is standing upon the very threshold of time, having distinctly before his eyes the future existence of the world, and an improved condition of it. In the mind of Abraham, though the nature of the future is dim, the fact itself of a great future in store for the world is a clear conception ; he does not regard things as stationary, as always going to be what they are, but as in a state of progress ; he has the vision of a great change before him which is as yet in the extreme distance, but which, when it does come, will be a conspicuous benefit to the human Abraham. 7 race, a blessing in which all the families of the earth wiU share. This was a conception as foreign to an ordinary mind of Abraham's day, as it would be to such a mind now. Because his future is to us a known past, we might be apt to imagine that the conception would come as a matter of course ; and that people of that , early age of the world knew by an instinct that it was an early age, and the predecessor of a later one. But there was just as much difficulty in realising a future of the world then, as there is now. The present of that day made the same impression upon the genera tion of that day, that to-day's present does upon men of to-day ; it was as much a boundary of the world's horizon, and stood as much upon the very edge of time, as to-day stands. We observe therefore some thing very extraordinary, and something entirely opposed to the common habit of the human mind, in the Patriarch Abraham's fixed look into futurity, directed towards an indefinitely distant era of the world. Our Lord Himself has singled out this prophetic look of Abraham as something unex ampled in clearness, certainty, and fax-reaching extent. " Your father Abraham rejoiced to see my day ; and he saw it, and was glad." ^ This was a revelation made to him indeed ; but he is equal to the revelation, he em braces it and concurs in his whole power of mind with it. This is the first thing indeed we observe in con nection with the subject of early prophecy. It is the preliminary and general condition of mind in the pro- 1 John viii. 56. 8 Abraham. phetical person which arrests us ; — that he ha^ the future before him, that he thinks of the world's future, and realises that it has a future, and brings home to himself the unrolling powers of time. This fastening of the mind upon the future, to whatever extent and in whatever persons it existed in those very early ages of the world to which the dawn of prophecy belongs, is a most striking and remarkable feature of those ages ; and we know that it existed even under paganism. Upon the shores of the Mediterranean, in the region where the great Eoman poet meditated and himself listened to the prophetical strain, stands the traditional cave of the Cumaean Sibyl, — ^the repre sentative of ancient prophecy, as it existed and held its ground, not under the Judaic dispensation, but parallel with it, and mounting to a common source. It is difficult to speak of the Sibylline verses, corrupted as they were soon after the Christian era, so that the mass of the collection is obviously and glaringly spurious. There is a primitive residuum however, the style of which reveals a native source ; and the simple prediction for which Virgil testifies is enough to show the mind of the prophetess, not only with respect to the subject of prophecy, but with respect to that general grasp of the fact of a world's future, and that look that travels forward and ranges over the distant realms of time, which I have just mentioned. There is the Sibyl upon her watch-tower, with her eye carried onward to a distant horizon, which she but dimly descries, but which is marked to her prophetic eye with great events. But what an extraordinary Abraham. 9 state of mind is this to belong to any human being in the earliest and most primeval era of paganism I That any man or woman should take the trouble then to think of what would happen to the world a thousand years off ! Were there not plenty of important things to attend to then, without going into the future ? Was there not the routine of nature and the custom of society ? And did not every year and every day bring its present life and its pressing business, its im mediate interests, then as now? The sun rose and set, the seasons alternated; men ploughed in the spring and gathered in the autumn, and social life ran its round, and kings and states carried on their affairs, and wars and festivals, famine and plenty, grief and joy, made up the chequered life of man, the vicissi tudes of which seemed quite enough to occupy him. Why should one person go beyond this present scene, leap over generations, and think of the world as it would be after ages had passed away ? What an iso lated eccentric journey for thought I What a dream to take up and absorb the mind ! How strange an image it presents to us — yet this is the aspect in which the Sibyl comes before us. In the crowded and familiar scene of a then living and bustling paganism, she is the devotee to the world's hereafter ; consecrated to that idea and prospect, she gazes upon the last shore of time ; and her sacred brow is lifted up above the throng of common objects and concerns, that her eye may rest upon a mysterious distance and an unknown page of the future history of mankind ! It is strange, amid the scattered fragments which constituted human IO Abraham. society then, to see even the recognition by one person's mind of a common humanity — a humanity that had a career to run and an end to fulfil ; to see the great problem and riddle of man's existence acknowledged, and a solution expected, as the curtain which hung over the Divine scheme folded up and disclosed the final upshot of it. Amid the idolatry and cor ruptions of paganism, the reverence that was felt for the Sibyl is a curious and beautiful remnant of the early piety of the world, for which we are hardly pre pared, and which comes across us with a surprise which perplexes us. Is this really paganism that is speaking ? It cannot be. It is early prophecy which is stUl holding its ground on human nature, and in popular thought, as a sentiment ; obtaining from paganism a sacred rank for the Sibyl — a rank that has been continued by the Church. The Church has in corporated the holy prophetess of paganism in the root of the Christian body, and given her a place in the prophetical order by the side of the patriarchs and pro phets of old. She joins in the holy procession, which begins with Adam, Seth, and Enoch, and ends with the last Christian saint, martyr, and confessor : she is acknowledged in the Church's hymns ; and the coun tenance which the painter has given her, symbolical of her solemn gift, appears in the Christian gallery, window, and pictured roof. But the prophetic element in human nature has its development also on the physical side. The modem world's conception of its own future only pictures indeed the continuation of a present movement, and Abraham. ii does not cross the border of mystery ; yet it is an instance of the prophetic vein in human nature. To turn to Bacon's vision of the coming day : — the Novum Organum awakens us like a knock at the door ; it is the first bell that rings and gathers the whole peal, it is from first to last an announcement. It is coming, the great manifestation of nature ; it is not come yet, but it will be here soon ; it has been long coming, and we have waited for it, now it is all but come. " All the systems of philosophy hitherto have been only so many plays, only creations of fictitious and iinaginajy worlds ;" there have been "long periods of ages," and only some few observations. Intellect has not forwarded but impeded discovery, and " every thing has been abandoned to the mists of tradition, the whirl and confusion of argument, or the waves and mazes of chance." One man has invoked his own spirit, another has called in logic ; " the true path has not only been deserted but intercepted and blocked up, and experience has not only been neglected but rejected with disgust." ..." We cannot, therefore. wonder that no magnificent discoveries worthy of mankind have been brought to light, while men are satisfied and delighted with such scanty and puerile tasks. "^ All is vague and arbitrary, all is groping in the dark ; the human mind is always pressing forward in one direction, but it is unfit for transition. But there is going to be something, and it is this awakening and unfolding of a fresh moming which is the herald's * Novum Organum, Book I. 1 2 Abraham. call in the Novum Organum. There is the sensation of beiiig just on the borders of a great disclosure, while as yet aU at this moment sleeps ; of a new reign, of a world just going to break forth into life. This consti tutes the characteristic note, the prophetic current, of the Novum Organum ; we are shut out just at -present, nothing is seen ; but it is all announcement, all expecta tion, aU the stir of something coming, all the sound of trumpets, all the preparation for an era, all the break ing of a day. Bacon is seen in his principal aspect as a prophet, he lives just on the edge of an age of marvels, close upon it, stUl not in it, but foreseeing it ; he Hves in a future ; the precursor is gone forward out of his own age. He lives not amidst particulars, but only in a vision of general discovery. All wiU have the suddenness, the brightness, the inexplicableness of magic, though he foretells it and knows it is coming. Bacon insists upon the chance incident to discovery, how completely it wiU baulk aU people who think they have the road to it, who go upon premisses, and see their way to conclusions. " Had any one meditated on balistic machines and battering-rams as they were used by the ancients, whatever appUcation he might have exerted, and though he might have con sumed a whole life in the pursuit, yet would he never have hit upon the invention of flaming engines acting by means of gunpowder ; nor would any person who had made woollen manufactures and cotton the subject of his observation and reflection have ever discovered thereby the nature of the silkworm or of silk."^ ... "If ^ Novum Organum, Book IL Abraham. 13 before the discovery of the compass any one had said that an instrument had been invented by which the quarters and points in the heavens could be exactly taken and distinguished ; men would have entered into disquisitions on the refinement of astronomical instru ments, . . . but that a mere mineral or metaUic substance should yet in its motion agree with that of such bodies would have appeared absolutely in credible." ^ Thus do the great discoveries fiash forth Uke magic in Bacon's future, not as they were concerned with causes at aU — wUd conceptions, offsprings of chance, born amid the incongruous and heterogeneous. A man cannot set about making them ; each " comes not by any gradual improvement and extension of the arts, but merely by chance."^ How then does Bacon prophesy " a vast mass of inventions," an age of dis coveries, an " instauration," a fulfilment of hopes, the new light of axioms, the advancement of the sciences, the interpretation of Nature, and the reign of man ? How does he prophesy a harvest of discoveries and a manifestation of Nature ? Beeause he saw that though each discovery by itself may be a chance, when a great many men are attending to one subject, and people are set upon nature as an object of attention, the chances of discovery in connection with this subject must increase, and there must be a multiplication of this possibUity. He saw that the investigation of Nature was rising in men's minds ; that men were experimenting, and were beginning to attend to facts ^ Novum Orgarium, Book I. 2 Book .IL 14 Abraham. and real physical objects. Hence there arose that conclusion which constituted his prophecy. His mind was in acute sympathy with the growing mind of the world, his pulse moved with the growing beat of human thought and curiosity, though then but faint : he saw the immense difference in the mode of studying natural science which was inaugurated by this rising taste for facts, this putting aside of the idols of the human mind for the ideas of the Divine mind ; that is to say, " certain idle fictions of the imagination for the real stamp and impression of created objects, as they are found in nature."^ He saw a mere " handful of phenomena collected into a natural history." But foreseeing this, he foresaw a world of discovery ; for " if we had but any one who could a Gen. XV. 5. 28 Abraham. thy name great " — this is still a motive which suits an earUer dispensation better than a later one. The future actual existence of himself, where it is defi nitely and distinctly grasped, must throw into the shade the existence of his name. His name is not himself ; his name is only a reflection thrown off from himself. Himself, and what happens to himself, must be the important consideration to himself. His real immortality lies in the perpetuity of himself, not in that of his name, which cannot do him the sUghtest good where he does not exist, ¦if he wiU not then exist. The question what is to become of the shadow of himself left in this world must pale in interest, in proportion as his own real future existence is embraced. The motive of a posthumous reputation, then, is not a Gospel motive, because the Gospel is the tidings of real immortality, and that is its special appeal to man ; whereas the desire for posthu mous fame has nothing to do with a real immo3> tality. A man who has no notion but that his existence totaUy ends at death, can stUl derive pleasure from the anticipation of his fame after- death; and can enjoy now the foresight of a fact, which fact itself he will not exist then to enjoy, be cause that future fact is a proof of present success. It is indeed simply blind confusion, an hallucination of the reason, to mix up these two absolutely distinct desires; to identify the immortaUty of a name with the immortality of a person ; yet a debasing stupor and disorder of the inteUect does prevaU in this respect. Men, under the notion of a name, throw Abraham. 29 forward a false earthly existence beyond the grave, which satisfles them ; they imagine themselves now enjoying this posthumous name then when it is posthumous ; or, in other words, conceive themselves as dead and alive at the same time. Cannot reason break this iron yoke of Ulusion ? She can if she is asked to do so, but they do not ask her, and would rather their sleep was not broken or their mist dispelled. But though the desire for posthumous fame is not a motive of Gospel source, it is one of those motives of nature which the Gospel does not forbid in its proper place. The Gospel is not at war with a natural instinct of the heart : it only condemns a gross misconception about posthumous greatness — the confounding it with a real future Ufe — ^the selfish and unnatural dream of men who grasp at it as if they were reaUy going to enjoy it, and to enjoy it when it is posthumous.^ But let this bUnd confusion about it be cleared, and let the thing stand for what it is and nothing more ; and Christianity does not forbid a satisfaction being de rived from the anticipation of it. The accompUsher of a great work has a legitimate pleasure in that work, in himself being the doer of it, and in the knowledge of that circumstance by others. And why should not 1 " Sed nescio quomodo, animus erigena se, posteritatem semper ita prospiciebat, quasi, cum excessisset e vita, tum denique vioturus esset." — Cicero, De Seneetute, xxiii. 82. " Sed cum illi essent in civitate terrena, quibus propositus erat omnium pro ilia offlciorum finis, incolumitas ejus, et regnum non in caelo sed in terra ; non in vita eeterna, sed in decessione morientium et suo- cessione moriturorum : quid aliud amarent quam gloriam, qua volebant etiam post mortem tanquam vivere in ore laudantium 1 " — Aug. De Givit. Dei, lib. v. 1 4. 30 Abraham. posterity be among those others ? But a religious man, if he foresees this posthumous name, sees also a chasm which separates this naihe from himself, and with draws it from him as a selfish prize. A shadow rests upon it whieh precludes vulgar pride and seK-con- gratulation. The Patriarch saw himself emerge out of a whole contemporary world after death ; but such an ascent, which stands in oontro^t with present depres sion, is, although an elevating and inspiriting reflec tion, a mortifying and chastening one as weU; the good is not grasped, is not fastened on, is not enjoyed tangibly; it is a vision, a prophecy, an iminaterial form of greatness, the shadow of a substance which has never been possessed, the symbol of a deprivation, and a memento of mortaUty. LECTURE IL THE SACRIFICE OF ISAAC. TTT'HEN objections are raised against various actions ' ^ and courses of action represented as done and carried on by Divine command in the Old Testament, which involved a summary mode of dealing with human life, the answer is made, that God is the Lord of Ufe, the right to which ceases as soon as evidence exists of a Divine command to deprive men of it. " If it were commanded," says Butler, " to cultivate the principles, and act from the spirit of tieachery, in gratitude, cruelty ; the command would not alter the nature of the case, or the action, in any of these in stances. But it is quite otherwise in precepts which require only the doing an extemal action; for instance, taking away the property or life of another. For men have no right to either Ufe or property but what arises solely from the grant of God. When this grant is revoked, they cease to have any right at all in either : and when this revocation is made known, as surely it is possible it may be, it must cease to be unjust to deprive them of either."^ This defence then is undoubtedly, as a general and abstract statement, true and complete ; nor is there 1 Aiialogy, part ii. chap. ui. 32 The Sacrifice of Isaac. anything wanting to it, or that need be added to it, as an abstract position. It is unquestionable that if a command of God to kUl even an innocent person is made known to us, we have not only the right, but are under the strictest moral obUgation to kiU that person. But though a tme and perfect defence in the abstract, it leaves out one important point which ought to be supplied before the general defensive statement is appUed to a particular case — ^the point, viz., how the Divine command to perform such an action is made known to the person to whom it is asserted in Scripture to be made known. That is a question which it is essential to answer before the individual can be pronounced to have been justified in performing the act. Undoubtedly the right of man to Uve ceases as soon as ever evidence arises of a Divine command to deprive him of it; but when does such evidence arise ? The answer then which is given to this question is that the evidence arose by means of a miraculous mani festation through which the WUl of God was declared, that these actions should be done. And this is a true and correct answer. But it stiU has to be accounted for, how a miracle at that day was the evidence which it was of such a Divine command. Supposing at the present day, aiid under the present dispensation, a miracle were wrought in evidence of an aUeged com mand of God to any man to kUl an innocent son, would such a miracle be regarded as sufficient evidence of such a command? It cannot with any truth be asserted that it would. The Christian Church would The Sacrifice of Isaac. 33 obviously condemn the act, and would refuse to pronounce a miracle to be sufficient justification of it. The question of the rightness or wrongness of this class of actions belongs indeed to the great religious question of the warranting power of miracles, and the conditions of miraculous evidence. When we go then to the Scripture doctrine of miracles and of the evidence rising from miracles, we find, in the first place, that the general rule laid down is, that miracles are evidence of the Divine wUl ; and that a command which has the warrant of a miracle is to be regarded as coming from God. This is the law relating to this subject which Scripture both expresses in words, and assumes and supposes in its historical account of the courses of events, and of Divine Providence. But when we enter further into the teaching of Scripture on this subject, we discover that, together with this general mle respecting miracles, there is a coUateral principle inculcated ; viz., that a miracle may be permitted by God for the purpose of trial. Where, then, the authority of a miracle contra dicts any clear knowledge we have of the Divine wiU, any instructions from antecedent sources, this is the interpretation of it which Scripture enjoins upon us. We are warned that the miracle does not in such cases bear its primary and more natural interpretation as an evidence of the Divine wUl, but the secondary interpretation of it as a trial of moral strength in resist ing that apparent evidence, — of the moment and from without, — in favour of a more real evidence of His wU] which we have from antecedent sources or from within. 34 The Sacrifice of Isaac. Thus it i^ laid down in the Old Testament that a miracle cannot authorise an act of idolatry ; and in the New Tes tament that a miracle cannot authorise the acceptance of any doctrine manifestly opposed to the Gospel revela tion. In such cases we are plainly told that the purpose of the miracle is not evidence but trial ; that it is in tended to test our faith ; to prove us, whether we give way to the more tangible and extemal kind of appeal against a deep inward persuasion of a moral and reli gious kind, or whether we adhere loyally to the inner law in spite of the outer pretension of authority, A miracle is thus not represented in Scripture as absolutely ^ and of itself evidence of a Divine command : rather it is expressly represented as not being. We find that it Ues under conditions ; that it is limited by our own know ledge gained from other and prior sources of the Divine wUl ; that it is checked by the internal evidence of moral and religious truths, — ^whether principles of beUef, or rules of conduct, — which, either express revelation, or God's natural enlightening Providence has imparted to us. The Scriptural check, e.g., would be the same against a miracle, on the side of idolatry, whether we supposed the unity of God to have been arrived at by natural reason or by special revelation. The rule of Scripture in substance is that no great moral or reli gious principle or law of conduct of which we are practically, upon general antecedent grounds, certain, can be upset even by a real miracle ; but that when the two come into coUision as evidence, the miracle must give way and the moral conviction stand ; that no miracle, in short, can outweigh a plain duty ; and that The Sacrifice of Isaac. > 35 a real miracle might be wrought, and yet it would be wrong to do the act which the miracle enjoined. If, then, a certain class of Divine commands which were proved by miracles in one age of mankind could not be proved by the same evidence now, this must arise in consequence of some difference in the con ceptions of mankind in former ages and in our own, in consequence of which such commands were suitable to an earlier period of the world and not to a later, and were adapted for proof by miracles then, and are not adapted for that mode of proof now. If, e.g., a miracle was in a former age sufficient evidence of a Divine command to destroy life, and now it is not, it must be that we are now possessed with a principle in such strong disagreement with homicide, that the alternative of the miracle being only permitted as a trial necessarUy becomes more reasonable now than that of its being proof of a command ; whereas this principle did not exist in equal force and strength in the mind of a former age, and therefore the miracle was taken in its more obvious meaning as proof of a Divine cbmmandment. It must be, in short, that the command was accommodated to the age in which it was given, and was therefore adapted to be proved by a miracle ; whereas now such a command would be in opposition to a higher law and general enUghtenment, that would resist the authority of the miracle : which mode of proof would consequently be unfitted for it. To kUl another, even an innocent man, is so far indeed from being itself contrary to moraUty, that nothing can be more certain than if it were knovm 36 The Sacrifice of Isaac. that God ordered us to take away the Ufe of an innocent man, it would be strictly obligatory upon us to do so. But though this is undoubtedly trae ia speculation and as a supposition, yet in practice the rights of human life are so strongly felt now, they are so intimate a part of the moral progress of mankind, and the responsibUity of violating them is so tre mendous, that no miracle could practically act as sufficient evidence to warrant the infraction of them, and the destruction of the life of an innocent person. Because a miracle is, by the express law of Scripture,| always subject to the possibUity that it may be sent for our trial in resisting, instead of our faith in obeying it. But if there is any case in the world in wliich this condition would operate, it is in the case of a supposed miraculous command to take away the life of an innocent man. Although therefore in theory the Divine command to kUl him, supposed to he known, would be strictly obUgatory, nor would the innocence of the man be any contradiction to it, yet in practice the difficulty is so great of its becoming!* known, that such a command would be virtuaUy; nugatory ; a miracle could be the only evidence of it, and that, by the law of Scripture, has been disabled to act as evidence. The act of kUling another, as being simply an external act, is not, indeed, in any contra diction whatever to a right state of the affections, but the act itself does not the less require justification ; a Divine command alone can be that justification ; and no evidence under the circumstances can be given of a Divine command. The Sacrifice of Isaac. 37 What was the difference then in the conceptions of mankind in a former age, compared with the present, which renders a miracle evidence of Divine command to kUl then, whereas it could not be such evidence now ? When we examine the ancient mind all the world over, one very remarkable want is apparent in it, viz. a tme idea of the individuality of man ; an ade quate conception of him as an independent person, — a substantial being in himself, whose life and existence was his own. Man always figures as an appendage to somebody — the subject to the monarch, the son to the father, the wife to the husband, the slave to the master. He is the function or circumstance of some body else. The slave was a piece of property — KT^fjfia ilJi\fivxov, and the old Hindu law divided " cattle into bipeds and quadrupeds." The laws of Manu insert the persons of the wife and the son in the person of the head of the famUy, as if they were absorbed and incorporated in it, just as the several members are absorbed and embraced in the unity of the body. " A man is perfect when he consists of himself, his wife, and his son."^ Their property belongs to the man, because "they belong to him,"^ upon which ground he could seU or give away his son for a slave. Stories from the Brahmanas show that an Aryan father had power of life and death over a son.^ Oriental civU law formally recognised the judicial principle of extending the parent's guUt and punish ment to the children, which it could have done only 1 Sir W. Jones, vol. viii. p. 8. ^ Ibid., p. 398. 3 Max Miiller's History of Sanscrit Literature, p. 408. 38 The Sacrifice of Isaac. under a defective idea of the child's individuaUtyl treating the chUd as a mere appendage of the father. In a public execution the criminal's whole famUy was punished by the same judicial sword which infficted death upon himself: nor was this done upon the ground of any special command from an avenging deity, which indeed was not needed for it, but only as an exercise of the simple right of civU justice— a| right not indeed always acted upon, but stUl rooted in law, and ready for use whenever the civU authority? thought fit to fall back upon it. We see, indeed, both in the poUtical institutions and superstitions of antiquity, regulations and practices; which obviously imply, as the necessary condition of their existence, a totally different idea of human indi- viduaUty, and of human rights, from that with which modern society and Christian society is animated. We find that this State and that that State had what appear to us most extraordinary, most eccentric and anomalous laws, in the sphere of human rights ; radi caUy, as it seems to us, clashing with those rights,. We are at first disposed to lay the blame entirely. upon the particular states and lawgivers. But when we see one state after another involved in the charge^ it graduaUy becomes clear to us, that though par ticular states may have got out of an acknowledged principle stronger and rougher consequences and worked it to a harsher issue than others did, there must have been some universal defective conception of human rights in those ages, to have made these particular laws and customs of certain states pos- The Sacrifice of Isaac. 39 sible. A lawgiver cannot act against the universal opinion of mankind in his day; if he institutes any particular infringement of human rights, there must be a premiss for that infringement in a uni versal defective conception of mankind at that day. Thus the law of Lycurgus for the destruction of weakly infants in Sparta at the very birth, would have been impossible, had there not been all over the world then a very different conception of the right of the human being with respect to his own life than what exists now. With us the rights of man com mence with his very birth; and an infant an hour old has an independent right and property in his own life, which the whole world cannot take away from him. Had that been the received idea in the age of Lycurgus, he could not have founded this Spartan rule ; but it was not. Mankind had not embraced as yet the true notion of human individuality ; man was an appendage to some man or some body. That the infant was treated as the pure property of the state in Sparta, was a result which rose upon an universal defective assumption regarding man in that stage of human progress ; it was a harsh and cruel use of that assumption, but it could not have arisen without that assumption as its condition. This great defect of conception was indeed deeply fixed in the Eoman law. As a code for the regula tion of property, the Eoman law commands our admiration; its assumptions, its distinctions, its fictions, are of the highest legal merit ; its whole structure was based upon nature and common sense. 40 The Sacrifice of Isaac. and it carried into the most intricate detaUs and appUcations an instinctive standard of equity, of which it never lost sight. The contrast therefore is aU the greater when from the regulation of property we tum to its deaUngs with persons. In the former we have an anticipation of modem civilisation, and we feel ourselves amid modem ideas, and in the atmosphere of our own courts. In the latter we are consigned to barbarism again. The criminal law of Eome took low ground in its estimate of a large class of crimes, which it treated as civU wrongs oiUy ; but its great blot was the domestic code. The son was the property of the father, without rights, without substantial being, in the eye of Eoman law. The father had the power of life and death over him ; was the proprietor of aU the wealth he acquired. The wife, again, was the property of her husband, an owner ship of which the moral result was most disastious. The Eoman ladies, as the arts and refinements of Ufe advanced, disdained the harsh yoke of true matrimony, — not only did the sacramental ceremony of the con- farreatio faU almost entirely into disuse, but even the stricter civU marriage, the conventio,'wSkS, neglected; and in its place was substituted a contract which left either party the liberty to dissolve the connection at wUl, out of which arose the matrimonial picture of Juvenal — Kunt octo mariti Quinque per autumnos.* The same defective idea of human individuaUty and the rights of life is shown in a very different ^ Satire vi. 228. The Sacrifice of Isaac. 41 fact, which has a horrible prominence in the history of ancient reUgions, viz. the prevalence of human sacrifice. It is impossible to suppose that any super stition, however strong, could have so trampled upon the natural right of life, as the custom of human sacrifice did, had there been at the time that idea of the natural right of life existing in the human mind ; that is to say, if that idea had existed in any definite shape. The very selfishness of man, and the very instinct of self-preservation, would in that case have made him stand up for his own Ufe, against the claims of a monstrous and cmel power. If we suppose such a strict and accurate sense of the right of the indi vidual to his own life as we have now, no superstition however ferocious could possibly have had force enough to withstand that sense, and sacrifice individuals wholesale. There could not therefore have been then that strict sense of the right and property of the in dividual in his own life that there is now ; and the institution of human sacrifice thus impUed as the condition of its own estabhshment the defective idea of the rights of the individual man. With these facts before us, we may understand how deeply fixed in the mind of ancient society was the idea of one man belonging to another ; how long a time it must have required to uproot that idea, and how in truth nothing but a new religion could do it. Even Eome, with aU her later material civUisation, could never completely embrace the notion, which lies at the bottom of all modern law and religion, that every man is himself, an individual being with an in- 42 The Sacrifice of Isaac. dependent existence of his own and independent rights. The y^s naturale of the individual is indeed so self- evident now, that we can hardly conceive society with out it; and we are apt to suppose that it must have been equaUy self-evident to any human being, in any age, who had the simple exercise of his reason. But all history shows that, so far from this idea having been always obvious to the human understanding, it has on the contrary been the slow and gradual growth of ages. Nor perhaps is the consideration valueless, that in the early stages of society, before civU govemment was formed, and before man had become a trained and dis ciplined being, as in a degree he is now, some strong idea such as that which is contained in saying — ^You belong to' another, you are the property of another, — may have been necessary to contiol and keep in bounds' the native insolence and wUd pride, the obstinacy, the fierceness, the animal caprice, the rage, the spite, the passion, of the human creature. When man was rude and government was weak, there was wanted for the control of man some idea which could fasten upon bim and overcome him, and be in the stead of govem ment and civUisation. Such an idea was this one. The nature that can be coerced by nothing else can be tamed by an idea. InstU from his earliest infancy into man the idea that he belongs to another, is the' property of another, let everything around proceed upon this idea, let there be nothing to interfere with it or rouse suspicions in his mind to the contrary, and he wUl yield entirely to that idea. He wUl take his own deprivation of right, the necessity of his own The Sacrifice of Isaac. 43 subservience to another, as a matter of course. And that idea of himself wUl keep him in order. He wUl grow up with the impression that he has not the right of ownership in himself; — in his passions, any more than he has in his work. He wUl thus be coerced from within himself, but not hy himself; i.e., not by an active faculty of self-command, but by the passive re ception of an instUled notion which he has admitted into his own mind, and which has fastened upon him so strongly that he cannot shake it off. Do we not feel that we are apt to think of ourselves as others think of us ? and that not by a rational act of judgment but a mere passive yielding to an im pression from vnthout. Let people around us think poorly of us, and we think poorly of ourselves, at least it requires an effort not to do so ; the oppositioti to surrounding influence taxes our self-reUance. Hence it is that, as an ordinary rule, it is not good for a man either to live with or even see much of another who habituaUy depreciates him ; such intercourse tends to lower his spirit. For though a man's self-reliance ought to be tested, it ought to be tested fairly, it ought not to have a constant weight thrown upon it. To return then to the Old Testament facts, — we may observe that the same defective idea of human individuality, and the right and property of the in dividual in his own life, which prevaUed in early ages generally, is traceable even in the Patriarchal and Jewish mind. It would indeed be expecting too much from a rude nation under slow training for higher truth, that they should not partake of the general 44 The Sacrifice of Isaac. notions of the world at that time regarding the natural rights of man. This latter is in truth, though its root is in our moral nature, an idea of the civU or poUtical order, and therefore it is not an idea of which a purely reUgious dispensation. Patriarchal or Jewish, guaranteed the present communication. It is an idea which is part of the civiUsation of mankind, and we might as weU expect at once civiUsation in the early stages of human society, as expect this idea of the true individuality of man in those stages. We do not in deed, in identifying it with civiUsation, disconnect it with morals : civUisation has its m^oral side in those ideas which relate to the rights of man, — which belong to the realm of justice, and the development of which is a development and manifestation of justice. StiU, though it is the moral side of civUisation to which those ideas belong, they are a part of civilisation: they are poUtical ideas. They come under the poUtical head ; they appertain to mankind in their aspect of a community as a subject of social order; they con cern man in society, and in relation to his brother man. They are therefore poUtical ideas, and belong to the growth of civiUsation, It cannot therefore be any reflection upon Patriarchal life and ethics to say that in that early age they were defective in ideas of that order. Nor is there any reason why we should impose upon ourselves the supposition that the ages of the Patriarchs, or the age of Moses, Joshua, or even David, had the same exact sense of the natural right of the individual man that the world now, after ages of Divine schooUng, has attained ; for this would be to The Sacrifice of Isaac. 45 be guUty of antedating the effect to the cause, and to expect beforehand that very standard whieh was to foUow after or from the course of the Divine dis pensations ; — that very estimate and point of view in the beginning of the Divine education which was to be the end and the result of it. That man was made in the image of God was indeed the original tmth which contained the independent and true indi viduaUty of the being; but this germinal truth wanted development, and Patriarchal Ufe was antecedent to that development. It is not unworthy of notice that the degree of the jus naturale of the individual with reference to his own life, and his own property in it, is not even yet an entirely settled question in the world; that upon the primary article of the right to deprive man of Ufe, men are not even yet agreed ; and while the generality maintain the justice of taking it away in self-defence, or for the punishment of crime, a con siderable minority deny the right of civil justice to interfere with human life; and one sect maintains the absolute inviolabUity of human life. If the question then of the degree of the individual's right and property in life is not even yet decided, and considerable uncertainty stUl attaches to it, this may help us to understand in what obscurity the whole question of the right of Ufe might Ue in the earUest ages of the vs^orld, when law was first emerg ing out of a state of nature, and before the rights of the nUer had undergone any scmtiny : and to under stand too how this obscurity could exist even in the 46 The Sacrifice of Isaac. Patriarchal mind, without any reflection upon it, simply by reason of the age of the world to which it belonged. Human power is a limited idea in modem society, — ^how far its rights extend with respect to the individual : but then human power was an unlimited idea, without definite boundary or check; what it could do or what it could not do to the individual was aU in confusion ; and in the haze which rested upon this whole subject, one idea was dominant, viz. that one man belonged to another, and was an appendage to another, the son to the father, the servant to the master, and the Uke. The principle of the inviolabiUty of human life was indeed always admitted in a degree, but it was the degree of the inviolabiUty upon which the morality of particular in terferences with Ufe, and the sufficiency of particular reasons for that interference, hinged. It must be remembered that this conception of man, as the property of and the appendage to another, is not one which involves any cruelty, any harsh ness. A father may regard his son as being, as a matter of, right, his property ; and yet this very son may be to him his dearest treasure, and the loss of him may be the bitterest grief. The idea does not interfere with the tenderest inward relations of a father to him. When Eeuben says, " Slay my two sons, if I bring him not to thee"^ — the speech ^ Gen. xiii. 37. "Among the Jews, as among most nations of an tiquity, the parental power was absolutely despotic, even to life and ' death. The Mosaic law, however, enacted that a guilty son could not be punished with death, except by the judicial sentence of the commu nity." — Milman's History of the Jeies, vol. i. p. 22. The Sacrifice of Isaac. 47 certainly shows that the father of the Patriarchal age regarded the son as belonging to him, as being in a way his property, so that as a matter of right his Ufe was lawfuUy at his disposal. But it does not show want of paternal affection, or that he made the offer in any other spirit than that of self-sacrifice ; as a surrender just of the very article of property which was dearest to him, when the preservation of the whole community was at stake ; and a hostage and pledge for the safety of Jacob's beloved son seemed to be wanted in the severe extremity. The idea of property is in no contradiction at aU to love ; human love regards the being ; and the rights with respect to the being do not alter the being. This is a question of what you can do to another : his own value to you, dearness to you, is another thing. The Ufe may be worth anything to you ; but the jus — the particular right, your power over it, is a distinct idea. It might be said in some despotisms, the power only heightens the love ; because the absolute dependence of another would be an actual claim upon affec tion, and his being at your mercy would give him at once an acceptableness in your sight. Undoubtedly the defective conception of human individuaUty was an opening for cruelty and oppres sion, and the greatest practical enormities ; but it does not in itself involve them. As proofs of the existence of this universal defective conception in ancient society, I referred above to Sparta, Eome, and the prevalence of human sacrifices. But though this original defect of conception was a condition of the 48 The Sacrifice of Isaac. rise of these inhuman codes and this ferocious practice, and though they could not have arisen without it, this is not to say that the mere defect of conception itself amounted to inhumanity, or that it necessarUy produced inhumanity. It was in itself a neutral inteUectual defect. And though the savage character of some communities founded cmel and oppressive practices upon it, there is no reason why it may not have existed in other communities and in the Jewish, without such results, and with the tone of society not brutaUsed and made cruel by it. With this defective idea, then, of human indi viduality, with this way of regarding one man as belonging to another man, established in the ancient mind and in the Patriarchal mind generaUy, we come to the act of the great Patriarch. In the present age, with the principle of human individuaUty and right now developed and become the law of our con duct to man, an interference on our part with the life of the human independent being, supposed to be inno cent, is so utterly incongruous, that a miracle on the side of such an act would necessarily be interpreted by us as a trial of faith, and not as evidence of a Divine command. But in the Patriarch's age there was not that moral-poUtical conception of man which consti tutes this counterbalance to the miracle, and therefore he gave the miracle that interpretation which was the more obvious one, and which was in fact intended by God, of evidence of a Divine command. In his case there was the miracle, but there was not the weight in the opposite scale— the evidence within which conflicted The Sacrifice of Isaac. 49 with the evidence without. There was not that idea, which it belonged to the subsequent Divine education to develop in the world — the principle that a man is an independent individual being, in distinction to his being the appendage of another man. We are struck immediately in the Scripture account of the sacrifice of Isaac with the habitual sense of ownership — as distinct from conferred momentary command, — with the entire absence of aU struggle in the mind of the Patriarch ; how he simply regards his son as a treasure of his own which he has to give up, a treasure which is dearer to him than any other earthly thing, and which it is the greatest trial of his life to part with, but which is StiU his own, belonging to him and appropriate to him to surrender. This is the impression which the whole of the scene itself raises. Indeed, if any one imagines that the idea of property in the human being could be incompatible with the greatest tenderness of affection, such an unreasonable notion must vanish with the solemn and beautiful account in Scripture. The tenderness of affection for the son, in the very act of surrendering him as his property, is prominent in this picture. But stUl he is the property ; the ancient idea of the son as belonging to the father pervades the whole account. It is as his own property that he surrenders and sacrifices the son. No description of this wonderful transaction could have more clearly exhibited how entirely consistent the sense of property in the individual is with the value, the preciousness, of that individual. If there reaUy were any one who E 50 The Sacrifice of Isaac. could suppose that a man's interest and delight in something that belonged to him was less because it belonged to him ; that his property was less dear to him because it was his property ; such an extraordi nary inference would certainly be whoUy confuted by this passage of Bible history. If any one could reaUy think that the transcendent greatness of the sacrifice and the surrender, would be in the least affected by the circumstance that what a man was called upon to surrender was a treasure of his own, something which belonged to him, something which was part of himself, such a mistake must be corrected by this descriptioH;.| The son in this representation belongs to the father; and when we come to examine and authenticate that impression we find it is what the whole history of the ancient mind verifies. The father, according to the ideas of the age, regarded the son as his own, in such a sense as made the sacrifice a sacrifice of what belonged to the father, and which was appropriate to the father to surrender. But at the present day the man belongs ^ to himself and not to another ; his life is his own ; and to sacrifice that Ufe is to sacrifice what is the property : of that man and of no other, to give up that which is not yours to give. The great Patriarch was thus a natural subject of a Divine command to sacrifice his son ; because, in consequence of the earlier ideas then prevailing, nothing interposed between his own convictions and the authority of the miracle; but a miracle to do such an act would be utterly incon gruous at the present day, when no external evidence to sacrifice another's life could possibly outweigh; The Sacrifice of Isaac. 5 1 the strong internal convictions which forbid the inter ference with it. The general conclusion is, that according to the very conditions of miraculous evidence laid down in Scripture, civUisation must in some cases affect the relevancy of miracles as evidence of Divine commands. Abstractedly the Lord of human life can command the destmction of that life ; but the question before us is a question not of abstiact propositions only, but of what there is evidence of; and civiUsation affects the question of evidence; affects it upon the principles of Scripture itself. The Scripture law of miraculous evidence qualifies and checks that evidence by the rival force of inward moral grounds and principles. The unity of God was no sooner estabUshed than miracles were nugatory in favour of idolatry ; and the truths of the Gospel were no sooner established than miracles became nugatory in favour of another gospel. And this Scriptural principle of counteraction to miraculous evidence must apply as weU to any other moral grounds and principles of which we feel certain, and which have established themselves in our moral standard. But civilisation does create such grounds and principles in our minds, because civUisation is not entirely a material movement but is also a moral movement — moral in regard to some principles of human right and practice. In the moral progress of mankind in the later ages of the world, the intense conviction has sprung up of certain tiuths respecting man, and certain principles of right and justice in regard to man; and these principles within us become 52 The Sacrifice of Iscmc. counter-evidence to the authority of miracles, when those profess to command acts which are in an opposite direction. In those cases, therefore, the growth of civilisation affects the authority of miracles and the argument from miracles. For the more certain we become of any truth regarding God or man, the more are we out of the power of being convinced by a miracle which woiUd lead in a contrary direction to that truth. In this way the progress of mankind must gradually exclude certain homicidal acts, as subjects of Divine command, upon miraculous evidence. The Scripture philosophy of miracles enforces a fresh modification of the doctrine of miraculous evidence, upon fresh moral convictions arising. Before the ideas of natural right were developed, homicidal Divine command was capable of miraculous evidence; but suppose these ideas developed, then the inviard anta gonism to the acts is so strong that they cannot be surmounted by anything miraculous that is only out ward; and the altemative becomes unavoidable, that the miracle is for the other purpose mentioned in Scripture, viz. the trial of faith, and not the support of a command. But in this state of the case, in which the miracu lous evidence of a certain class of Divine commands is necessarUy neutralised, it becomes impossible to sup pose that there wUl be the Divine commands ; and therefore what has been said amounts to this, that God adapts His commands to different ages. It is unreason able to suppose that God would now work miracles in cases in which His own educating providence has The Sacrifice of Isaac. 5 3 neutraUsed them as evidence of His commands : that is to say. He would not now give the com mand. But that He would not give such commands now, is not to say that He might not give them in a former age, when such commands had an appropriate and natural mode of proof; viz. by miracles — that is, by the full evidence which miracles had, before that evidence was modified by the ideas which His own educatory providence has since instUled. God adapts His employment of miracles to the state of evidence ; which, upon the Scriptural rule, differs with man's dif ferent states of enUghtenment ; and with the evidence for the commands, necessarily also withdraws the com mands ; and thus we come, as to the ultimate position, to the rule of Divine wisdom, that God suits His com mands to the age ; and gives or withholds them accord ing as man is a natural recipient of them. It wUl indeed be denied by some that such miracles to command such acts ever really took place ; and it will be said that these were simply actions of the age, inspired, both on their good and their bad side, by the spirit of the age in which they were done. But such a question as this, however necessary to meet in its proper place, is not one which appertains to the particular section of Old Testament inquiry now under discussion. In examining the morality of the Old Testament, we must take the actions of the Old Testament history as they are there given ; we are not concerned with other actions, or, what is the same thing, with the actions as otherwise described. An objector to Scripture history may consider himself 54 The Sacrifice of Isaac. necessitated by his own ideas to make a fundamental difference in the account of these classes of actions as given in Scripture ; he may not beUeve in miracles, and, in accordance with this beUef, he may refuse to hold that these classes of actions were ever commanded by miracles. But we are not concerned upon the point now under discussion with such a conjectural speculation as this, which would assign a different basis to the actions of the Old Testament. Upon the question of the morality of the Old Tes tament, we must assume the actions of the Old Testa ment as they stand ; for the moral standard of the Old Testament cannot be responsible for any other. The Bible cannot be made responsible for actions which are not contained in it, — for other actions than those which it describes ; for actions grounded upon different motives and different reasons and premisses. In the case of the homicidal class of actions, the evidence of a Divine command constitutes, in the Old Testament, the very ground of their justification ; this special authorisation is no superfluity, but the absolute need of the transaction, without which it is unwarrant able and indefensible. The defective idea of the indi vidual's right, inherent in the age, was indeed the condition of the acceptance of the miraculous evidence ofthe command when given ; but it did not authorise the act of itself, without the command. It was the Divine command, then, which made, according to the standard of the Old Testament, the distinction between the patriarchal acts in violation of human life, and the heathen ones, which were in violation of the same The Sctcrifice of Isaac. 5 5 principle; and we may add as well, between some Jewish homicidal acts and others. No one could pos sibly compare the ground upon which the sacrifice of Isaac stands in the Old Testament, with the ground upon which Jephthah's sacrifice of his daughter stands. The latter is mentioned as a simple fact, without the shadow of an approval ; because indeed it was, like the heathen acts of that kind, unauthorised. The former is extoUed as the very model of faith and self-surrender. The punishment of the chUdren on account of the father's crime was prohibited in the Jewish code, and was, as a matter of human law, condemned.^ It was the special Divine command which alone was regarded as authorising it in the Old Testament. But it will be said, perhaps. Can we suppose God taking advantage of an actually inferior state of ideas in the world, in order to give a particular command, which He would not give in an age of higher and more mature ideas ? Can we suppose Him working a miracle for it then, because, in an inferior state of ideas on moral subjects, a miracle could not be in conffict with intemal evidence ? It may be repUed that such a discriminating proceeding would doubt less be an instance of accommodation ; but why not of wise accommodation ? It seems to belong suitably to the Divine Governor of the world to extract out of every state of mankind the highest and most noble acts to which the special conceptions of the age can give rise, and direct those earUer ideas and modes of thinking toward such great moral achievements ^ Deut. xxiv. 16. 56 The Sacrifice of Isaac. as are able to be founded upon them. If there is a progress in 'ideas, why should not one stage as weU as another, a former stage as weU as a later, a rader as well as a more enUghtened, express itself according to its own model, and present to God the various 'developments in act, of the same fundamentaUy virtuous wUl ? Let man show forth all the good that he is capable of, in the mode and manner in which he is capable of it. If in earlier ages he was unshackled by the later ideas of the individual's right and property in Ufe, and if it so happened that a very wonderful and extraordinary self-sacrifice could be drawn out of this very want in the age, why should not the human mind be directed in the way of that sacrifice, and that great reUgious self-surrender be extracted from it by a Divine command ? Such an act was the sacrifice of Isaac, and such was the state of ideas which preceded it as the conditions of the act. The self-sacrifice in the act is obvious from the history. It was, in the first place, neither more nor less than to all appearance total ruin — the downfall of every hope, and the coUapse of a life. To an ordinary man of business even, if he has any spirit, the breakdown of a life's work is a dreadful thought ; because he wants to feel — and it is a legitimate want — ^that he has done something, and that he has been somebody. But the Patriarch had through Ufe felt himself the minister and instrument of a great Divine design with respect to mankind: he had Uved with a gigantic prospect before him, with an immense expanding blessing, which was one The Sacrifice of Isaac. 57 day to include aU nations and be the restoration of the world. This vast plan then, his part in which had been the work of his life, and had fiUed his mind with immeasurable hopes, as it had been sown in his son, would perish with his son. Then all was over, and his life had come to nothing. This is one side of the act of self-sacrifice, but it is not all ; for the chUd himself, he upon whom such a promise hung, such boundless hope, such a vast calculation, and who was loved all the more with a father's love because he was the harbinger of the prophet's great ness, the symbol of life's purpose answered ; — he was to be surrendered too. Such was the act of the sacrifice of Isaac. But it required the particular state of ideas in the world at that time, and the defective state of ideas respecting the right of the individual man, for this great act to be brought out. Without those ideas it could not have been the subject of Divine command, having evidence that it was a Divine command ; a miracle woidd not be evidence to us that God bade a father kiU an innocent son : if it was, as it was, evidence to Abraham, it was because that clear idea of the individual right, which involved the inviolabiUty of life, did not exist in his age as it does in ours ; it was because the Patriarch of that day had the political ideas of his day, — of one person belonging to another, and the son being the append age of the father. It was out of an inferior state of ideas in regard to human right, out of a lower poUtical sense, that an act of romantic and sublime self-sacrifice was extracted ; and the very want in the 58 The Sacrifice of Isaac. age was used as a means of developing the religion of the man. And this was a step which it was suit able for the Governor of the world to take ; because it enlarged the amount of human virtue, it made even the shortcomings of the time subservient to the per fection of the individual ; and it brought out a great reUgious act which was to be a lesson and a type to aU ages. It must be observed that great acts are a decided part of the providential plan for the education of mankind. The pecuUar and superior force of acts in this direction, as compared with general chmracter, is gained upon a principle which is very inteUigible. A great act gathers up and brings to a focus the whole habit and general character of the man. The act is dramatic, while the man's habit or character is didactic only ; and what is more, there is a limitation in character which there is not in an act. There is a boundlessness in an act. It is not a divided, balanced thing, but is like an immense spring or leap. The whole of the man is in it, and at one great stroke is revealed. A great act has thus a place in time ; it is like a great poem, a great law, a great battle, any great event ; it is a movement ; it is a type which fructifies and reproduces itself. Single acts are trea sures. They are like new ideas in people's minds. There is something in them which moulds, which lifts up to another level, and gives an impulse to human nature. If we examine any one of those signal acts which are historical, we shall find that they could none of them have been done but for some one great idea The Sacrifice of Isaac. 59 vnth which the person was possessed, and to which he had attached himself. Thus, if we examine the act of Titus Manlius in executing his son, after crowning him victor, in justice to the violated majesty of Eoman law, there must have been in his mind a kind of boundless idea of Eome, — of what Eome was ; that it was greater than any conceivable form of greatness, and transcended aU imaginable empire. Eome was to him the impersonation of supreme order, uncon querable wUl, indestructible power. Eome was eternal. He then who disobeyed Eome must die ; even the youthful victor in the first fiush of triumph; and while the father's heart leapt with pride, the Eoman general must be inflexible. Thus the famous heathen's seK-sacrifice rested upon a boundless idea of the state to which he belonged, and the power to which he owed aUegiance. In the mind of the Patriarch in the place of a great power of earth must be substituted the boundless idea of an invisible Power ; where in the heathen father's mind Eome stood, there was God. The Lord of this universe has the right to all we have, and everything must be surrendered to Him upon demand. But upon an Almighty Being rose boundless hope too — the vastness of conception which Scripture speciaUy attri butes to Abraham. Hope in the ordinary type, is partly sight ; when Ught has begun to dawn, and the first signs of restoration and renewal appear. Hope is the first sight we catch of returning good, that first gleam of it which heralds and represents the end. But hope which is seen is not hope. It is hope while 6o The Sacrifice of Isaac. all is dark around us, — whUe as yet there is no visible link between us and the end, — that exhibits the prin ciple in its greatness and in its true energy. And this hope must rest upon that ultimate Power at the very root of things which can reverse every catastrophe and rectify aU mistakes. To hold on to this root is hope withdrawn into its last fastness ; and, without aid from any sight, grasping with an iron force the rock itseU, the foundation of Sovereign WiU upon which the uni verse stands, and saying to itself, " The whole may shake, if this foundation remaineth sure." This was the infiiUte hope of Abraham. Doubtless whUe he lifted up the knife to slay his son, the sun was turned to darkness to him, the stars left their places, and earth and heaven vanished from his sight ; to the eye of sense aU was gone that life had built up, and the promise had come actuaUy to an end for evermore; but to the friend of God all was stUl as certain as ever, all absolutely sure and fixed ; the end, the promise, nay even the son of the promise, even he in the fire of the burnt-offering was not gone, because that was near and close at hand which could restore ;— the great Power which could reverse every thing. A voice within said, AU this can be undone, ? and can pass away Uke a dream of the night ; and the heir was safe in the strong hope of him who " accounted that God was able to raise bim up even from the dead." Do you say then that such an act could not be done now ? That is aU the more reason why it should have been done ; — why it should have been done when The Sacrifice of Isaac. 6i it could be done ; when the state of evidence admitted of it ; when the primitive standard of human rights gave the son to be the property of the father, to be surrendered by him, upon a call, as his own treasure. That idea, — ^that very defective idea of the age, — it was, which rendered possible the very point of the act, the unsurpassable pang of it, the self-inflicted martjrrdom of human affection, the death of the son in wUl, by the father's hand. That idea of the age therefore was used to produce that special fruit which it was adapted to produce ; the particular great spiritual act of which it suppUed the possibiUty, and which was the most splendid flower of this stock. If the idea of the age was rude, the act was not the less spiritual which it enabled to be done ; because the idea of the age only founded the proprietary right of the father, the spirit uality of the act lay in the surrender of the son. The surrender itself was of the highest Gospel type, as being the offering up of the deepest treasure of a man's heart ; that which gave him the sharpest agony to part with. And, indeed, we may observe that however rude was the state of ideas which enabled the act to be done, the act itself has been the appropriated lesson not so much of earlier ages as of later, not so much of Jewish times as of Christian : the moral did not come out so clearly in Jewish history ; it reserved itself tUl Judaism had passed away and given place to the Gospel; and though an act of earliest time had its main instructive strength in latest. The distinction then is most important, and should be always kept io 62 . The Sacrifice of Isaac. mind, between that state of ideas which enables an act to be done and the act itself. Those were doubtless primitive and rude ideas as to the rights of the indi vidual and the inviolabUity of life, which made the Divine command to slay an innocent son credible, and a miracle sufficient proof of it ; but the spirituality of the surrender was not in the least affected by that circumstance. The •^^os of the act, the faith, the tmst, the resignation, were the same. The act is whoUy distinct from the evidence of the obligation to it; the evidence was affected by the age; an etemal and spiritual type distinguished the act. Thus, far from any lowering effect attaching to the principle that God makes use of the ruder conditions of the human mind, and accommodates His commands to diBferent ages, on the contrary, this principle has produced the highest result. The rudeness of the age admits of having the most exalted acts buUt upon it, and acts which last as exemplars through future ages of enUghtenment. This principle does not permit the earUer conditions of human thought to Ue faUow and barren, but extiacts out of every state of the human mind its proper effort, and makes the best of every age m keeping with its fundamental ideas. Every period of the world contributes the special expression of moral beauty and greatness of which it admits ; and that magnificent and extraordinary act of romantic morals which cannot be obtained from a higher state of civUisation is extiacted from a lower. Never again, mdeed, whUe the world lasts, can that The Sacrifice of Isaac. 63 act be done within the Church of God : but that it has been done is the wealth of the Church and of man kind ; and is the fruit of the spiritual poUcy of that Great Being who has educated the world, and who has worked to the highest advantage every stage in the moral progress of mankind. LECTURE IIL HUMAN SACRIFICES. I DEVOTED one Lecture to the general character and situation of Abraham ; because when we have to judge upon one very remarkable act of a man, it is an advantage to have the man himself before us. An explanation popular with one school, of the act of the sacrifice of Isaac, is, that it was simply one of the class of human sacrifices which were common at that day, and especially among the Canaanitish races ; that Abraham was seized with an enthusiasm of that sanguinary type which propitiated God by human victims ; and that he made Isaac the victim. It does not appear to me that such a solution is at aU necessary, but that, on the contrary, it clashes with the whole history of Abraham, and the whole colour of his life and character; whUe at the same time it degrades and calumniates the Patriarch. That the Patriarch of that day should not meet the miraculous evidence of a Divine command to slay an innocent son, by the same counter internal evidence that we should oppose to it now, and that he was unable to feel this inward impediment, on account of the defective moral and poUtical conceptions of that day, — the inadequate sense of human individuality and human rights,— is an Human Sacrifices. 65 explanation which does not lower the Patriarch in our eyes ; because it only charges him with ideas which belonged to that age of the world, and were necessary in that stage of human progress. This explanation acknowledges a Divine command, and that the act was done in obedience to a Divine command ; and it only requires that the command was accommodated to an earlier state of ideas regarding the human being and his rights. But in attributing to Abraham such a defective- state of ideas on this subject, we are not therefore assuming him to have been under the influence of a gross and cruel superstition which sacri ficed its thousands upon inhuman altars as a propitia tion to sanguinary idols. To represent him only as without a certain class of ideas relating to humanity, which had not yet arisen in the world, is a completely different thing from regarding him as impUcated in a horrible and vUe usage, which was a lapse and a fall from the antecedent reUgion of the world ; — from making him a foUower and disciple of the Canaanites. In comparing, then, these two explanations with reference to the internal evidences of Scripture bearing upon them, and their agreement with the facts of Abra ham's life and character, I must observe fiirst, that the whole portrait which Scripture gives us of Abraham, and which formed the subject of the first Lecture, is altogether in opposition to such a solution of the sacri fice of Jsaac as would make it a copy of the human sacrifices of the Canaanites. It is indeed doubtful whether the introduction of human sacrifices into the 66 Human Sacrifices. worship of these people was so early as to be contem poraneous with Abraham. This is a disputed point. Some able historical critics have arrived at a contrary conclusion, and the terms on which Abraham stood with the Canaanites and their chiefs would serve to show that the worship of the Canaanites of his day was a less advanced form of idolatry than that which prevaUed in a later age. He is told that his descend ants, and not himself, shall possess the land, because "the iniquity of the Amorites is not yet fuU;"^ and certainly, if we compare the aspect in which the Canaanites present themselves to the eyes of Moses, the character which he gives them, and the detestation with which he regards them, with the apparent rela tions of Abraham to the same people, we cannot but see a marked difference in the earUer and later feeling, such as would imply that these reUgious corruptions had not grown to such a height in Abraham's age. But even granting that the Canaanites offered human sacrifices in Abraham's time, the whole facts of the case, as recorded in Scripture, contradict the supposi tion that the sacrifice of Isaac was put into the Patriarch's mind by the sight of the superstitious worship of those idolatrous races. The whole charac ter of Abraham is in limine opposed to such a notion as that of his borrowing from the Canaanites in reh gion. For suppose a man of lofty independence of mind, who had cast off the tiaditions of his own country, rejected human authority, discarded idols, and embraced the true rational conception of a God, ^ Gen. XV. 16. Human Sacrifices. 67 to whom he appropriated a spiritual worship, adoring Him under no material form but in His own in visible essence ; supposing him standing alone in his day in maintaining this pure worship, but casting his eye forward upon a distant era in the world's future, when that worship should become universal and gain " all the families of the earth ;" suppose a man of this remarkable type, — ^this enUghtenment and perception of deep truth, — surrounded by the slaves of a grovel ling superstition, enjoining cruel and inhuman rites ; would it be the natural tendency of such a man to accept the lead of that low reUgion, to borrow from its worst rites, and aUow them to dictate a great and critical act of his reUgious Ufe to him ? Such an idea would not enter into his mind. Such a man would look down with a vast sense of superiority upon so degraded a form of reUgion, and would pass sentence on it as a judge ; but would not dream of the attitude towards it of a learner, imitating its inhuman prac tices, and permitting them to originate an act of worship for him. The very thought of bowing to such an authority would be degradation and con- tanfiination to him. But the plain narrative of Scripture forbids such a supposition as this, because it represents the act of sacrifice as commanded expressly by God — nor only as commanded by God, but as praised by God. Scripture extols it indeed as an act of the sublimest devotion and faith, and exhibits it as the ground of an additional and overflowing renewal of the Divine promise to the Patriarch, which is confirmed by an 68 Human Sacrifices. oath and is vouchsafed to him not as the reward of any former action or actions, but speciaUy and singly on account of this action ; — "Because thou hast done this thing, and hast not withheld thy son, thine only son, I have sworn that in blessing I wUl bless thee." ^ Such an account of this action is plainly in consistent with its having been done in imitation of the gross and cruel superstitions of Canaanites, and excludes that rationale of it altogether. It has indeed been observed that God's moving a man to do some action is not, in the language of Scripture, inconsistent with the motion being also at the same time a temptation of Satan ; and the case is pointed to of the two different phrases about the sin of David in numbering the people, used respectively; in the Book of Samuel ^ and the Book of Chronicles ; ^ in the fiirst of which books God is said to have moved David to do this act, and in the latter Satan is said to have moved him. But though it may be admitted that there is nothing in God moving a man to do something, regarded as a phrase, inconsistent with Satan moving him also, this remark is totaUy irrele vant in a case in which God not only moves a man to do an act, but also praises that act when done. It may be true that Satan may move a man whom God in a certain sense moves too, — amoves in the sense of permitting Satan or his own lusts to move him ; and in this sense God moved David to number Israel, whUe the same motive was also a temptation of Satan. But it is impossible that Satan should move a man ' Gen. xxii. 16. ^2 Sam. xxiv. 1. ^ I Chron. xxL 1. Human Sacrifices. 69 to do an act which God moves him to, and which God also praises after it is done. The latter is the turning point which decides definitively in the pre sent case that Satan did not move Abraham, because the act of Abraham being commended by God, was good ; and it is impossible that Satan should move a man to do a good act. In the case of Balaam it may be observed that God moved in a sense. He told Balaam " to rise up and go with the men." But the context shows that was only a direction given to Balaam upon the assumption that he chose to foUow his own wUl; for God's anger was kindled because he went. In the case of Balaam, therefore, God's moving was quite consistent with Satan's mov ing. But had the act of Balaam been praised by God instead of calling down the Divine censure, no motion from Satan could have been compatible with the Divine motion. But when, from the moral character of Abraham, we tum to the actual plan of his Ufe and trial, we find stUl stionger evidence against the hypothesis of a copy of the human sacrifices of the Canaanites ; because we find that this hypothesis is at variance with the whole plan and purpose of the life-trial of Abraham, — that that trial implies in its whole con struction a totaUy different object and purpose for the sacrifice of Isaac than that which this hypothesis requires. It is of the very essence of a propitiatory sacri fice that the offerer should contemplate the total loss of the precious victim which he surrenders into the 70 Human Sacrifices. hands of offended deity.^ The sacrifice is made as a self-inflicted punishment ; its very object is the part ing with a treasure, the final surrender of something dear and valuable which belongs to him. There has been sin, and sin must be atoned for by a voluntary act of self-deprivation. In a word, the purpose of propitiatory sacrifice is penal. And this is histori- caUy the character of human sacrifices; they are propitiatory ; they are designed to appease the anger of an offended deity, by a father's loss of a son or daughter, whom he sacrifices. Thus the angry divinities of Greece, who detained the fleet at Aulis, were supposed to be pacified by Agamemnon's loss of Iphigenia ; and Mesha, king of Moab, sacrificed his son to Chemosh, upon the idea that he should gral^. Chemosh by the total loss of his son, which he volun tarily imposed on himself. But the whole plan and purpose of the tiial of Abraham excludes the contem plation on Abraham's part of the total loss of Isaac, the heir of the promise, and requires that he should look forward to the miraculous restoration of his son after death; imposing on him indeed in this confident expectation a piercing trial of his faith, but not an ^ I am speaking here of the propitiatory sacrifice, according to the human notion of it, according to what' it has always meant as a part of - human worship, and an act of man himself offering up something in atonement for his sins. The same condition, however, attached to the mystery of the real Propitiatory Sacrifice, only with that quaMcation which was necessary to fulfil the Divine plan. For although our Lord ever foresaw His own Resurrection as immediately succeeding His death, He did not rise again for the purpose of continuing His life upon earth, which life He had sacrificed, but only to give evidence of the reality of His propitiation, and for other purposes. Human Sacrifices. 71 absolute and perpetual loss of his son. This is the interpretation which the New Testament puts upon the act of Abraham : "Abraham, when he was tried, offered up Isaac : and he that had received the pro mises offered up his only begotten son, of whom it was said. That in Isaac shall thy seed be called : axicounting that God was able to raise him up, even from the dead ; from whence also he received him in a figure." ^ We observe that the whole Ufe of Abraham tums upon one great trial — the trial, viz., of his faith in the Divine promise to him of a son to be the seed of a whole nation, and by being the seed of a whole nation be the channel of a great future blessing to the whole world. This is what he has to believe. But at first he has not got a son. The trial therefore of his faith is to beUeve that he shaU have one ; and this part of his trial lasts a long time, and the Patriarch's faith gives way under it twice. The first occasion is, when, in despair of a real heir, he substitutes his steward EUezer as an adopted one. He becomes conscious that this is only a makeshift and an expedient of his own, gives up the arrangement, supplicates God for a real heir, is promised a real heir, and beUeves that promise. "And Abram said. Lord God, what wilt thou give me, seeing I go chUdless, and the steward of my house is this EUezer of Damascus ? Behold, to me thou hast given no seed : and, lo, one born in my house is mine heir.^ And the word of the Lord came unto him, saying. This shaU not be * Heb. xi. 17-19. ^ Gen. xv. 2, 3, 4, 6. 72 Human Sacrifices. thine heir ; but he that shall come forth out of thine . own bowels shall be thine heir. And he believed in the Lord ; and He counted it to him for righteousness." The second occasion on which the Patiiarch's faith gives way is, when, at the suggestion of Sarah herself, he sets up another substitute for a true heir, in the person of a real son, but a son by a representative wife — Hagar, whom Sarah appoints in her own place. This divergence from the straight course of faith lasts some years, though the true beUef in the gift of a real heir some day, is never wholly suppressed ; and the confidence in the heirship of Ishmael never appears to exceed a kind of despondent wish that he might be accepted as the heir in case none other came. " Oh, that Ishmael might live before thee!" Again, how ever, the promise of a true heir is renewed; twice renewed. Abraham, after a short tumult of doubt in his mind, beUeves absolutely, whUe Sarah is rebuked for her unbeUef ; and then the son is born. This is the final triumph of faith in Abraham, in the matter of the birth of a son. For a long time beUef has been mixed with doubt, or been broken by intervals of doubt; but at last, just when this event is most improbable, nay, humanly speaking impossible, at the very acme of its trial faith conquers. Such then being the preceding course of trial in Abraham's life. Scripture informs us that the command to sacrifice Isaac was but a carrying out of the same plan of probation; only that whereas, before the birth of the hefr, the birth was the subject of the trial of his faith, now it is the preservation of Human Sacrifices. 73 the heir born ; — that under the most desperate circum stances, despite even of complete apparent impossi bilities, even in the extreme case of the actual natural death of that son, God would so contrive as to secure his continuance, to be the seed of the future nation and channel of the future blessing. The trial in the sacrifice of Isaac is, whether Abraham would believe that God could raise him up to life again; and the merit of Abraham in that sacrifice is the merit of rising to this belief. His trial hitherto had been to believe that Isaac would, under such great apparent improbabUities and against the order of nature, be born; his tiial now was, whUe contemplating his sacrifice, to believe that, under such great apparent improbabUities and against the order of nature, he should survive. But the one trial was a continuation of and carrying on of the other. The probation of Abraham is upon one plan and method, and one part corresponds to and foUows up another. A cloud of mystery encompassed the gift of the heir ; it first rested upon his birth ; and when that mystery was cleared up, the same cloud reappeared and rested upon his continuance in life. The great Power which so long delayed the gift now demands the surrender of it. The trial of the Patri arch is, that he has to pierce through the cloud in either case, and that faith must foresee, as in the first instance a birth, so in the second instance a restoration. Scripture then has given us an explanation of the act of Abraham in offering up Isaac ; has told us 74 Human Sacrifices. what the act was, i.e., what it was in the mind of the agent ; its scope and meaning, the pecuUarity of the expectation upon which it was based ; and we coUect with certainty from this Scriptural account of the act that it was not a propitiatory sacrifice. It is wanting in aU the essentials of such a sacrifice. The object of it was not loss or punishment, but a certain extraordinary manifestation of faith which is thereby eUcited from him, — faith in the continuance of the Ufe of Isaac, against the laws of nature, to be the heir and transmitter of the promise.^ ' No sin in deed of Abraham's is mentioned for which he has to atone, and so the notion of a propitiatory sacrifice is gratuitous ; but there is also abundant positive evi dence of another and a different purpose in the sacri fice; a purpose which actuaUy conflicted with the idea of a propitiatory sacrifice ; for the idea of the total loss of the thing offered is essential to a pro pitiatory sacrifice ; but it was essential to the trial of faith in this case that the thing offered should not be looked upon as totaUy lost, but, on the contrary, as about to be restored. It is the only merit of Abraham in the performance of this act, that he believes that the victim will survive it. As the heir of the promise ^ Heb. xi. 17-19. There is an aUusion to the same explanation of Abraham's sacrifice in Rom. iv. 16, and scg " The faith of Abraham ; who is the father of us all," because that {xaTSvani ov) he believed God " who guicheneth the dead, and calleth those things which be not as though they were." We may observe that the passage as a whole is a paraUel to the passage in Hebrews, connecting as it does the birth of Isaac with the same kind of trial of faith as that which the passage in Hebrews connects with the sacrifice of Isaac. — See Note 2. Human Sacrifices. 75 and the guaranteed link between the Patriarch and the future nation and blessing, the Divine word is pledged for the continuance of Isaac's -life upon earth. Abraham reUes upon this word. But in the very act of thus relying upon it, he does not surrender Isaac for good, he does not contemplate his final loss, he does not look forward to a permanent parting with him. He expects the restoration of the victim. His act, then, is entirely deficient in those characteristics which are necessary to the idea of a propitiatory sacrifice.^ He contemplates an issue which negatives ^ " The faith of Abraham was to pass through a more trying ordeal. He is suddenly commanded to cut off that life on which aU the splen did promises of the Almighty seemed to depend. He obeys, and sets forth with his unsuspecting child to offer the fatal sacrifice on Mount Moriah, The immolation of human sacrifices, particularly of the most precious, the favourite, the first-born child, appears as a common usage among many early nations, more especially the tribes by which Abraham was surrounded. It was the distinguishing rite among the worshippers of Moloch ; at ai later period of the Jewish history it was practised by a king of Moab ; it was undoubtedly derived by the Carthaginians from their Phoenician ancestors on the shores of Syria. The offering of Isaac bears no resemblance, either in its nature, or what may be termed its moral purport, to these horrid rites. Where it was an ordinary usage, as in the worship of Moloch, it was in unison with the character of the reUgion, and of the deity. It was the last act of a dark and sanguinary superstition, which rose by regular gradation to this complete triumph over human nature. The god who was propitiated by these offerings, had been satiated with more cheap and vulgar victims ; he had been glutted to the fuU with human suffering and with human blood. In general it was the final mark of the subjugation of the national mind to an inhuman and domineering priesthood. But the Hebrew reUgion held human sacrifices in abhorrence ; the God of the Abrahamitic family, uniformly beneficent, imposed no duties which entaUed human suffer ing, demanded no offerings which were repugnant to the better feeUngs of our nature. Where, on the other hand, these filial sacrifices were of rare and extraordinary occurrence, they were either to expiate some 76 Human Sacrifices. it as such a sacrifice : and it is his merit, and it belongs to the very nature of his probation in this matter, that he should do so. It may be objected, perhaps, that this account of the transaction does not allow that which appears to be an essential feature of the sacrifice on Mount Moriah, the real surrender on Abraham's part of the object of his deepest affections. It may be said that this sacrffice was undoubtedly an act of mortification-;:? and the surrender of a treasure, and that, as such, it has been regarded in all ages as the type of the self- denying and self-sacrificing life ; but that if Abraham all along looked, and looked with confidence, to the recovery of his treasure, there was no true surrender and no sacrifice in this act. It would, however, be a great mistake to say that, because there was the con templation of a recovery here, there was therefore no act of surrender or sacrifice. It must be considered,;i| if Abraham resigns the possession of his son by cut ting asunder the common bond of life, that that is a true resignation of him. Death is an undeniable test of the act of surrender. If the Patriarch looked be yond death, to a recovery, that did not negative the surrender which ipso facto had taken place in death. dreadful guilt, to avert the imminent vengeance of the offended deity, or to extort his blessing on some important enterprise. But the offer ing of Isaac was neither piacular nor propitiatory. ... It was a simple act of unhesitating obedience to the Divine command ; the last proof of perfect reUance on the certain accomplishment of the Divine pro mises. Isaac, so miraculously bestowed, could be as miraculously restored ; Abraham, such is the comment of the Christian Apostle, believed that God could even raise him up from the dead." — Milman's History of the Jeius, vol. i. p. 20. Human Sacrifices. 77 Such a yielding up was losing sight of him, seeing him vanish from time, from visible nature ; it was parting with him, according to physical law, for ever. Had the father clutched the prize of a son, and once got, had refused to part with him out of his sight, that would have been the denial of surrender ; but the Patriarch in this act committed him resignedly into God's hands, and trusted him beyond the borders of the material world into an invisible keeping. He contemplated without shrinking an awful chasm in the earthly Ufe of the heir ; he saw him for a moment swallowed up in the abyss, and only to be restored to him by a mysterious hand. But this was an act of true self- sacrifice, and involved a tiue surrender of a dear possession. The explanation, then, of the act of the sacrifice of Isaac by supposing it to be a copy of the human sa,crifices of the Canaanites, breaks down at every step. It faUs first by being in total disagreement with the character and mind of Abraham; it fails next by being in absolute discord with the whole plan and purpose of the life-trial of Abraham. There is nothing in the account given of the act in the slightest degree to connect it with such a worship and such a motive. The human sacrifices of the ancient world were in atonement for public crimes, and were offered up in great national emergencies, when war or pestUence threatened the very existence of the people, and there was a cry for a gt-eat deliverance. They were at any rate propitiatory, and supposed bloodshed, or sacrUege, or some heinous 78 Human Sacrifices. crime, as the occasion of them. But here there is no crime mentioned for which propitiation is wanted. On the other hand, the trial upon which the life of the Patriarch turns is clear and conspicuous ; and that demands a sacrifice which is not propitiatory, but which is simply a trial of faith. A sceptic wiU have his own explanation to give of a life turning upon such a trial ; but even he, if he takes the account as it stands, must admit that it is whoUy opposed to the idea of the Patriarch's surrender of his son as a propitiatory sacrifice : — ^that the Patriarch's act stands upon other ground, and that the motives and the prospects in the case have nothing in common with those which originate a propitiatory human sacri fice. He wiU attribute the Patiiarch's faith in the restoration of Isaac from the dead, to a visionary and wUd fanaticism ; but even he wiU not dispute, as an historical truth, that Abraham was perfectly capable of looking forward to such a solution of the difficultyj of beUeving in such a miracle : that his eye could over leap the dark chasm, and see his son standing safe on the other side of it ; and that he was of such a mind and spirit as that he could unhesitatingly beUeve - that the heir of the promise would issue alive out of the very jaws of death. This state of mind may be amazing to him — a transformation and revolutionis ing of human nature ; but that it has existed in men the most absolute infidel cannot doubt. The whole reUgion of the Bible is, from beginning to end, historicaUy founded upon this absolute faith in an absolutely omnipotent God. But such a belief, in Human Sacrifices. 79 the mind of the Patriarch, in a certain restoration of Isaac, — if we contemplate it only as a physiological fact, — excludes wholly the intention of a propitiator)^ sacrifice, i.e., a human sacrifice in the ordinary meaning of that term, and separates the motive and design of it altogether from that religious basis. Such is the preponderance of evidence against the interpretation of a human sacrifice, drawn from the whole life of Abraham, its order, course, character, and plan ; the whole internal evidence of the narrative is a protest against such a construction ; whUe, on the side of that interpretation, there is only one fact, viz. that there were such sacrifices in the ancient world. But whUe the sacrifice of Abraham was in itself, and as a commanded action, a trial of the Patriarch's faith and not a propitiatory act, it was yet designed that it should at the same time be a type and figure of the great Propitiation.^ For it is not essential to a tjrpe that it should be a complete resemblance and copy of that event of which it is the type, and should in aU respects follow the pattern of the antitype. In the sacrifice of Abraham and in the. sacrifice on the 1 " Of aU the Prophetic Types, says Mr. Davison, this one, in the commanded sacrifice of Isaac, appears to be among the most significant. It stands at the head of the dispensation of Revealed ReUgion, as reduced into Covenant with the people of God in the person of their Founder and Progenitor. Being thus displayed, as it is, in the history of the Father of the Faithful, it seems to be wrought into the foundations of Faith. In the surrender to Sacrifice of a beloved son, the Patriarchal Church begins with an adumbration of the Christian reaUty." — Inquiry into Primitive Sacrifice. Davison's Bemams, p. 150. 8o Human Sacrifices. Cross the difference of scope and design m regard to atonement leaves stUl a common extemal ground of surrender ; and the .outward action or representation contained in the former, of a father offering up his only son upon the altar of wood, fulfils all the outward requirements of a type. The lifting up of the serpent in the wUderness was not propitiatory, but there was in it and the propitiatory sacrifice on the Cross the common principle of restoration proceeding from a certain action, such action being first apprehended by faith; and the outward representation contained ia the lifting up of the serpent had the outward Ukeness required for a type. But it may be asked — ^Was it simply a curious coincidence that the surrounding nations offered up human sacrifices, and that Abraham offered up a human sacrifice ? The answer is that the external resemblance is not fortuitous, but that the two are reaUy connected by the common principle of sacrifice or surrender. First, the heathen recognised the prin ciple of sacrifice in general, or the giving up of something precious, as a mark of devotion to the deity ; and this principle is common to the heathen and to the Jewish and Patriarchal sacrifices in general Secondly, human sacrifices were a mon strous and extravagant expression, but stUl an ex pression, of this principle. They proceeded upon the assumption that human life was the most valuable of all things, and especiaUy that a child was the most precious possession of a father, ffom which it appeared to follow that such a sacrifice was in plaee in extra- Human Sacrifices. 81 ordinary emergencies. This principle of self-sacrifice then, and in the very form of the sacrifice of a son, is common to the heathen human sacrifices and to Abraham's sacrifice of Isaac. But when one common element has been admitted, the difference is such as to completely separate the two from each other as religious acts ; the one being only a trial of faith, the other the propitiation of an angry divinity. Such are the two hypotheses which have occu pied our attention with regard to the act of the sacrifice of Isaac. There is the explanation of the act, as an act of taking away the life of another, which was given in the last Lecture, and there is the explana tion of it as a human sacrifice, in agreement with the cruel superstitious custom of the day, in heathen countries. The explanation which was given in the last Lecture was, that the conceptions of the day, with respect to one man as being the property of another, — the subject of the monarch, the son of the father, — authorised the act in obedience to a miracle, inas much as, with such conceptions of human rights and human individuaUty, there was no counter internal evidence against the act to counterbalance the miracle in command of it. This explanation makes no differ ence in the personal character or prophetic rank of Abraham ; and only supposes in him the ideas of the age in which he Uved, of the poUtical order ; such as affect the independent rights and situation of the individual man. It only does not suppose in Abraham a modern estimate and a modem standard of those rights, such as in the Patriarch of that age would have G 82 Human Sacrifices. been an anachronism. But the hypothesis of the act being a human sacrifice in the ordinary sense, and a copy of the human sacrifices of the Canaanites, mis represents and libels the Patriarch ; degrades him into a foUower and disciple of an idolatious and abandoned race, and attributes to him the contamination of a sympathy with their sanguinary altars, and the foUy of having been caught by the snare of a pagan super stition. Such an hypothesis is in the plainest contra diction to his whole Ufe and the whole scope of his trial. LECTURE IV. EXTERMINATING WARS. nPHE argument of this Lecture is in substance tho -¦- same as that of the second Lecture, only applied to Divine commands for the destruction of nations and masses of men, instead of to a Divine command for taking away the life of a single person. The exter minating wars of the Israelites also, involving as they did the slaughter of whole populations, men, women, and children, on account of the sin of the nation, in volved the principle of punishing one man for the sin of another; they were instances both of punishing infants on account of their fathers' sins, posterity on account of forefathers' sins, and some adults on account of other adults. The command of Moses respecting the Canaanitish nations was, " Thou shalt save alive nothing that breatheth ; "^ and Joshua strictly fulfiUed this order. He smote aU the cities " with the edge of the sword, and utterly destroyed all the souls that were therein; he left none remaining."^ And the Divine command, through the mouth of Samuel, respecting Amalek was, " Slay both man and woman, infant and suckling, ox and sheep, camel and ass."* The judicial destruction of whole fandUes was a smaUer instance of the same principle. Such acta 1 Deut. 22. 16. 2 Josh. x. 39. = X Sam. xv. 3. 84 Exterminating Wars. done in obedience to a Divine command are strongly urged by unbelievers as objections against Old Testa ment morality. It is repUed that God is the author of life and death, and that He has the right at any time to deprive any number of His creatures of hfe, whether by the natural instrumentality of pestilence' or famine, or by the express employment of man as his instmment of destruction. And this as an abstiact defence is unquestionably true ; nor can it be denied that as soon as a Divine command to exterminate a whole people becomes known to another people, they have not only the right, but are under the strictest obUgation to execute such a command. But there is this great distinction between God destroying human lives by natural means, and using man as his executioner of a command for that pur pose — viz., that whereas natural means are the un conscious executors of the Divine wish, man as a reasonable being, with understanding and will, is bound, in the first place, to ascertain that it is the Divine wish before he executes it. In what way, then; is a Divine command for the destmction of a whole nation, innocent and guUty aUke, made known to the destroying nation ? By the evidence of miracles it is repUed, and replied with trath ; but some distinction is still wanted in dealing with this subject. For in the present day would a miracle be sufficient authority to us to do acts such as those which were done upon the true authority of miracles under the older dispensation? Would miracles be a warrant to us now to destroy a whole nation, putting to death men, women, and Exterminating Wars. 85 chUdren ; or to deprive a whole family of life on account of some sinful act committed by the father ? It wiU be acknowledged that they would not be ; we should feel it impossible that God would reaUy command us to do such acts as these now, what ever commands He may have given in former ages ; and we should put aside the authority of such miracles, as designed, even if they were real, to test our faith, not to make us do the acts in question. For a miracle is not represented in Scripture as absolute evidence of a command from God ; rather it is ex pressly represented as not being. As evidence it Ues under checks and conditions, in the absence of the fulfilment of which it is not evidence, but trial And in this Ught, in which it is thus directly contemplated in the Bible, we should regard a miracle now, which professed to be the warrant of a Divine command to perform acts of indiscriminating punishment, and wholesale slaughter of the innocent and guUty alike. But if miraculous evidence was properly proof to the IsraeUtes of a Divine command to exterminate certain nations, but would not be sufficient proof of such a command to us now, that must be occasioned by some difference of conceptions in a former age and in the present, in consequence of which such a com mand was adapted for proof by miracles in a former age, and is not adapted for that proof now ; was not an incongruous or incredible command to the people to whom it was given, but would be to us. One explanation, then, that wiU be given of this difference wiU be that the Gospel law is a law of love. 86 Exterminating Wars. and that acts of vengeance and destiuction which were appropriate in retribution of sin in a less ad vanced age, and were the natural expression of hostUity to evil in that age, are whoUy out of place under a dispensation which enjoins as its leading precepts charity and resignation, and, instead of resisting evQ, the bearing all things and the enduring aU things. When a Samaritan viUage would not receive our Lord, His disciples, James and John, when they saw this, said, " Lord, wilt thou that we command fire to come down from heaven, and consume them, even as Ehas did ? " That was the spirit of the old law. But our Lord repUed that they were now to be of another spirit. " He tumed and rebuked them, and said, Te know not what manner of spirit ye are of; for the Son of man is not come to destroy men's Uves, but to save them." ^ But though this is a most important distinction in the standard of Judaism and of Christianity, it is not the whole of the distinction between them ; for we plainly see that the acts to which we refer, — ^the destruction of whole nations, chUdren included, for the sins of the adult portion, and the infliction of death upon whole famiUes for the personal sins of thek heads, — are not only contrary to the law of love, but contiary also to our idea of justice. When we com pare the Gospel era with the condition of the human mmd antecedent to it, we find that there has been not only a revelation of the principle of love, but that there has been also a revelation of the idea of justice too ; ' Luke ix. 54, 55, 56. Exterminating Wars. 87 that that idea has been developed, sharpened, and defined in the human mind ; so that the idea of justice would be now an absolute bar to the execution of certain proceedings, against which it did not act as such an absolute barrier in a former age of the world. The defective sense of justice, then, in those early ages, arose from the defective sense of individuality. The idea Of justice could not be complete or exact before the idea of man was, for justice implies a proper estimate of the being about whom it relates, and with whom it deals. But the idea of man, the conception of human individuaUty, that each man is an independent being in himself, was only imperfectly embraced in those ages. Man was regarded as an appendage to man, to some person or some body, and therefore the idea of man being defective, the idea of justice was defective too. Hence arose, then, those monstrous forms of civil justice in the East, in which the wife and the chUdren were included in the same punish ment with the criminal himself, as being part of him. The idea was not always acted upon, nor did it form part, as far as one can judge, of the common routine of justice ; indeed it would have caused the depopulation of countries if it had ; but it was always at hand to be brought into use if wanted. The punishment of chil dren for the sins of the fathers was, we may say, incorporated into the civU justice of the East, and was part of its traditional civU code : it was not an every day process in the courts, but the principle of it existed in the law, and was resorted to on special occasions, when a great impression had to be made. Not that 88 Exterminating Wars. the offences which were selected for the examples of this mode of retribution were chosen upon any prin ciple, for they seem to have foUowed the caprice of the monarch. But they were such as, according to this irregular standard, were heinous crimes ; and the ap pUcation of this extreme penalty seems to have carried the authority and weight of law, and to have been recognised by custom and popular opinion, and not to have been a simply arbitrary and tyrannical act of the monarch. Such was the character of Nebu chadnezzar's sentence upon all the blasphemers of the true God, to whom he had, after the miraculous sal vation of the three servants of God, pronounced his adhesion ; the sentence, viz., that aU such persons should "be cut in pieces, and their houses made a dunghUl;"^ i.e., that their famiUes should perish with them. Nor, when Darius punished the maUgnant accusers of Daniel with the very death intended for the accused, and included their wives and chUdren in it, does he appear to have done anything more than what the Oriental code of justice fully sanctioned. It was the sentence of a monarch who especiaUy respected law and legal tiadition, and did not make his own will his rule ; a monarch who had evidently a strong sense of justice in his nature, a sympathy with the oppressed and UI used, a respect for holy men, a pious and devout temper. Nor are these two cases evidently more than samples of a general and estabUshed method of pumsh- ment, though it was not an ordinary but an extra ordinary act of civU justice, regarded perhaps somewhat ^ Daniel iiL 29. Exterminating Wars. 89 in the same Ught in which our forefathers regarded attainder. These were the fruits of the idea that one man belonged to another, was part of another. The human appurtenances of the man were nobodies in themselves, they had no individual existence of their own, their punishment was a shadow as it affected them, be cause their own nonentity neutralised it ; the person punished was the hateful criminal himself, who was destroyed in his chUdren. The guarantee was given in this extended form of justice that no part of him escaped. Justice got the whole of him. The victim in himself, and in aU his members, was crushed and extinguished. In the age's blindness and confusion ol ideas, people did not reaUy seem to know where the exact personality of the criminal was, and where it was to be got hold of; whether, in the locaUty of himself, was himself only, or some other person or persons also as weU. They could not hit the exact mark to their own satisfaction, so they got into their grasp both the man himself and every one connected with him, to make sure. If they did this, if they collected about the criminal everything that belonged to him — wives, chUdren, grandchildren, dependants, servants, house hold, the whole growth of human life about him, and destroyed it aU, they were certain that they punished him, and the whole of him. The total of the individual was there, and justice was consummated. But, again, this defective idea of human individu aUty had another result besides that which affected the personahty of man ; it had an effect upon the sense 90 Exterminating Wars. of justice itself, as a feeUng of nature ; it let loose exaggerated and extravagantly developed justice as a passion, an affection, and an emotion of the mind. We are accustomed to represent Justice as neutral and impartial, holding the scales. It is so in the de partment of evidence, because a criminal is not a criminal tiU he is proved to be one. But guUt once proved, and standing in its own colours before us, justice takes a side; she is a partisan and a foe; she becomes retributive justice, and cZesiresthe punishment of guilt. Justice then becomes an appetite and a pas sion, and not a discriminating principle only. We see this in the natural and eager interest which the crowd takes in the solemn proceedings of our courts, — in the reUsh with which they contemplate the judge in his chair of state ; confiding in him as the guardian of innocence and avenger of guUt; and the satisfac- , tion with which the final sentence upon crime is re ceived, resembles the satisfaction of some bodUy want — hunger, or thirst, or desire for repose. The hold which reUgion has upon mankind is due in large measure to the justice of religion. She promises one day to fulfil the vision, and reaUse the dream in every simple mind, of a general setting to rights, when every body wUl have his due. It is evident that justice is a craving of our nature, and rests in the punishment of the guilty as an end desirable in itself. It is appeased when it attains this object, and feels a tormenting void when it fails of it. But justice, as an appetite and apassion, is subject to the same extravagances and excesses to which Exterminating Wars. 91 passion in general is subject. There is in all passion an innate tendency to the unreasonable, which breaks out under peculiar excitements. Even what we caU sentiment has elements of Mwreason in its way of. fastening upon things ; — habits, which are reasonable indeed so far as they are human, but on the other hand cannot be reconciled with pure reason. What, e.g., is the whole internal influence of association but a kind of unreasonableness ? We are more than usuaUy affected by a particular event on the recurring day of the year. But why? What has happened ? The earth has roUed so many times upon its axis. And what has that to do with the event ? Nothing. We visit the plojce where some great man was born, or died, or where he did some notable act. Here Csesar landed, here Hannibal fought, here Becket died, here Charles V. retired, here Shakespeare was born. But what has place to do with the significance of the act or the suffering, the birth or the death ? Nothing. A man must be born somewhere, and die somewhere, and act in some place or other. These are accidents which do not touch the substance of these events. Are we any nearer the person or his act because we stand on the spot where he did it ? No : the person and the place are divided by an infinite interval from each other ; yet we treasure these local connections, and feel our selves placed in a kind of vicinity to an historical per sonage by entering the house where he was bom. If quiet sentiment or feeling then has constitu tional elements of ttwreason in it, what must be the case with strong passion. ? It is a known characteristic 92 Exterminating Wars. of passion that it makes objects for itself; that when natural objects are not at hand on which to expend itself, it vents itself upon others which it creates for the occasion. This is a weU-known effect in the case of anger ; a passionate man, when something has vexed him, stamps upon the ground, or tears the note which contains the bad news into shreds, or kicks away a stone at his feet, as if he would hurt something or other, even in semblance ; anything does for an object. " The soul being agitated and discomposed," says Montaigne, " is lost in itself if it has not some thing to encounter, and therefore always requires an object to aim at and keep it employed. The soul in the exercise of its passions rather deceives itseff by creating a false and fantastical subject, even contrary to its own belief, than not to have something to work upon. After this manner brute beasts spend theU fury upon the stone or weapon that has hurt them, and are ready to tear themselves to pieces for the injury they have received from another. What causes of the mis fortunes that befaU us do we not ourselves invent ? The hair which you tear off by handfuls, and that bosom which you smite with so much indignation and cruelty, are no way guilty of the unlucky stroke which has kUled your dear brother : quarrel with something else. Livy, speaking of the Eoman army in Spain, says that for the loss of two brothers, the great captains Flere omnes repente, et offensare capita; aU wept and beat their foreheads : but this is a com mon practice. And the phUosopher Bion said plea santly of the king who plucked off the hair of his Exterminating Wars. 93 head for sorrow, ' Does this man think that baldness is a remedy for grief ? ' Who has not seen gamesters bite and gnaw their cards, and swallow the dice, in revenge for the loss of their money ? Xerxes lashed the sea, and wrote a chaUenge to Mount Athos I C5rrus set a whole army several days at work to revenge himself on the river Gnidus for the fright it had put him in when he was passing over it ; and Caligula demoUshed a very beautiful palace, for the confinement his mother had there." ^ We see this spirit exhibited in the funereal cere monies of ancient times, and the tributes paid to the memory of the dead. These became in time indeed formaUties and grand shows, matters of family or regal pride rather than the heart, yet they had their origin in real feeling. One can imagine indeed how an imperious wiU that had never yet been thwarted, and ruled its own world with an absolute sway, would feel upon the sudden loss of a beloved favourite — wife, sister, or friend, — that had been all in aU to it ; when for the first time it encountered an impassable barrier, and longed for the irrecoverable. This sense of void in the sufferer's mind must be reUeved in some way : he cannot acquiesce in impotence, he must straggle ; he must reach forward somewhere to supply the room of what iS gone ; he must do something in order to hide from himself that he can do nothing. He vents himself then in a vast expenditure of bar barous and irrelevant action ; he sacrifices attendants 1 Montaigne's Essays — "How the soul discharges itself on false objects," etc., etc. 94 Exterminating Wars. and foUowers at the funeral pUe ; others are unworthy of life when the loved one has departed ; and life is the most valuable thing, and therefore a fit treasure to throw away, and send, as it were, after the dead. Such a death is to him many deaths; it ought to caust other deaths ; it ought not to be single and stand alone. He encloses one death then in a thousand ; he loads the earth with some gigantic sepulchral fabric to express the largeness of his loss. He thus grasps with outstretched hand after some object to fill the vacuum within ; he beats the air, and his baulked desire goes off into an immense waste of energy, which pleases him because it is waste ; it is expressive on that very account ; his grief indulges in aU useless things, in vast margins, in excesses, in superfluities,, and costly emptiness. Love, grief, and passion, in general being thus Uable to excesses, justice, as an appetite and passion, '\ is Uable to the same. It tends under excitement to 1 mnke objects for itself. And so Oriental justice did. It went out into margins, excesses, superfluous sur plusses of retribution ; other lives went to this ap-? petite over or above that of the criminal, and justice; used human beings as a material of expression, as one would employ a look, a gesture, a motion ; it kiUed a thousand men merely as a mode of tearing the hair, and beating the breast. It refused to be curtaUed and checked, or to stop with the criminal himself ; if went into a crowd of extras and appendages. It was this ancient notion of justice that came out on grea| occasions ; it was then poor work to punish only one Exterminating Wars. 95 man ; this grand appetite must have more food, more material ; there was something excessive in the very nature of justice, which passed beyond the person of the criminal and claimed aU his family and house ; it was essentiaUy an overflowing thing, refusing to be fixed by the boundary of its immediate object, and pressing onwards by its own force and intensity to others beyond. Connection by blood with the guUty agent was enough to reflect his crime ; the passion was too hotly engaged in the pursuit to distinguish the nature of the association, and retribution became extermination. WUd justice thus, like an over wrought passion, made objects for itself. Had a designing set of courtiers conspired foully against Daniel? Let no member of the guUty men escape; throw them and their wives and chUdren to the Uons. Has wicked Haman plotted the massacre of the Jews ? It is not enough that Haman himself should hang on a gallows fifty cubits high ; let his ten sons hang with him. Justice was anger, and gave itself all the liber ties and privileges of the angry man ; the angry man of the stage, whose idea is that his passion to be real and honest, thorough and tme, should blunder, should make mistakes, and hit the wrong man. Aristotle discusses the passion of anger with his own characteristic shrewdness and acuteness, and with as much of the humorist as of the philosopher. He is indulgent to its mistakes, and tender to its excesses, treating the affection somewhat as a comic writer would treat the character of an honest qidck-tempered man in a play. . Anger with him is the man in the 96 Exterminating Wars. farce, who is always making blunders, and mistaking one thing for another, but in a way which provokes- a smUe rather than indignation. The affection has in his view an intrinsic proneness to misunderstanding and misconception, which he pardons, though the in stances which he gives are those which we would not so easily condone. " The intemperance of anger," he says, " is not so bad as that of the appetites ; for anger appears to hear reason, but to mistake it, Uke a too quick servant, who, before he has heard out what is said, runs off, and then makes a mistake in his errand; or as a dog barks at a knock before he knows whether it is a friend's. So anger, in consequence of the heat and quickness of its nature, hearing but not hearing what is said, goes off to revenge itself; for anger reasons that this being an insult or a slight, it must punish the man; whereas appetite rushes by mere instinct to enjoyment. So that anger foUows reason in a way, whereas appetite does not ; the one is in a sort of way conquered by reason, the other by its own lust. And, moreover, anger is more constitutional than lust, as one thought who apologised for striking his father ; for, says he, this man struck his father, and he his, and this boy here — pointing to him, wUl strike me when he is grown up ; for it is our nature — avy- yevh yap r)[uv : and one who was dragged by his son up to the door of the house, bid him stop there ; for that he himself had dragged his father so far, but not farther." ^ If we extricate the philosophy of this pass age from the humour of it, we obtain a truth which ^ Ethics, 1. vu. c. 6. Exterminating Wars. 97 bears upon the present subject. Aristotle looks upon anger as following an apparent law of reason in its errors and excesses, which seems to itself only its necessary action. Justice, also, as being anger at crime, puts its excesses in the same reasonable point of view to itself; it follows the temper of the general passion of anger. Justice simply acting as a passion goes beyond its mark, carries punishment beyond the guUty person, hits right and left, and brings in a crowd that had nothing to do with the crime, under the scope of the sentence ; justice simply as anger votes blood to be crime, and impUcates a whole family in the act of its head ; it becomes a systematic blun derer and mistake-maker, making out one man to be another, and all upon a kind of plan and a show of reason to itself, by which it determines that blood composes a sort of identity, and makes a famUy one person : an idea which has as its immediate fruit wholesale judicial slaughter. But what enabled Oriental justice to run out into these extravagances as an appetite and passion, was the defective sense, to begin with, of human indi viduality. If you have the perfect idea of human individuaUty — that every man stands on his own footing, and is a separate person from anybody else, justice may be a strong passion and enthusiasm, it may desire all these margins, but it cannot have them ; it is under checks and conditions ; it cannot make objects for itself, but must take those which are made for it ; it cannot pass beyond the real criminal. It cannot slaughter a multitude of people merely as a 98 Exterminating Wars. grand piece of extravagance, a substitution for oratory, a broad margin and surplus of emotion, and a mode of tearing the hair and beating the breast. If, there fore, justice as a passion did go out into these excesses, it was because the accurate idea of human individu ality was then wanting ; because the idea of man was not tmly understood. That extravagant and mon strous form of civU justice, then — the inclusion of the children in the punishment of the father — was occa sioned by this defective idea, coupled with the circum stance that the defect gave scope for the excesses of justice, regarded as an appetite and passion of our nature. The spirit which produced this wUd justice was not a wicked, a murderous, or a cruel spirit ; it was not deUght in the infliction of pain ; it was not objectless love of destruction ; it was the undisciplined ; passion of justice working without the perception of the limit which man's individuality imposed upon it. It aimed loosely and confusedly at a high, a good, and a necessary object — the punishment of crime. This idea of justice, then, which penetrated the ancient and especially the Oriental mind, was evi dently also the idea of the Israelitish people in its earUer history. What reason, indeed, is there why the Jewish nation upon such a point, not connected with the pecuUar object of their revelation, should not partake of the defective notions of the rest of the world a;t that time ; why the defective idea of human individuality, and the judicial standard which sprang from that root, should not extend to the minds ofthe sacred people; producing exterminating wars and Exterminating Wars. 99 wholesale judicial punishments ? When the Divine command was given to destroy a whole nation, on account of the wickedness of the great mass in it, and a whole famUy on account of the sin of the head, these were in fact judicial proceedings natural to the Jewish mind, and in accordance with a received standard of justice. Justice, by means of this release from the idea of individuality and man's rights, was set at Uberty to act as a passion ; to punish wholesale, to slaughter whole nations for the sins of many of the nation, to extirpate and destroy, upon the mere ground of connection by blood. The idolatries and abominations of the Canaanites invited vengeance, and vengeance did not confine itself to accurate justice; it expanded into the extravagances of the unchecked passion of justice, moral in its hatred of evU, but without clearness, and blind and dim in its notion of persons. But there is this great distinction between the principle of punishment for the father's sins as it was held by the Jewish people, and the same principle as it was held in the pagan and general Oriental world — viz., that in the latter the judicial principle figures as a part of civU law, coming into operation whenever a sufficiently important occasion arises. The Persian monarch flings the famUies of the false accusers into the lions' den, along vnth the criminals themselves, as a judicial act of his own, and belonging of right to a regal tribunal of justice. But in Israel the principle did not exist as a part of regular law, but only as a special and extraordinary supplement to law, when God lOO Exterminating Wars. himself commanded it. The Jewish law forbade magis trates to punish the chUdren for the fathers' sins. ' ' The fathers shaU not be put to death for the chUdren, neither shaU the chUdren be put to death for the fathers ; every man shall be put to death for his own sin."^ The punish ment, then, of the famUy for the sin of the head was among the Jews extia-legal, and stood upon a religious ground as the dictation of a special revelation. But though the Jewish mind was in a higher state than the ordinary Eastem mind on this subject, as the very fact of confining this species of justice to Divine command, and excluding it from a human court and ordinary law, shows, this retributive principle had stUl a place in the Jewish mind as an extraordinary mode of justice, which a special command might rouse from a dormant state into action in a particular case. It had a suspended operation, checked by a pecuUar religious condition. It met the Divine command haff- way, no prepossession being felt against such a shape of justice as an extraordinary one ; and it had a con stant incipient action in the system, though it was powerless unless it was taken up by a special revela tion of the Divine wUl. Such was the divided and modified hold of this ruder form of justice upon the Jewish mind ; not so strong as its hold upon the Eastern world generally, in which that form of justice was a part of regular law, but still enough so to give such justice a popular naturalness, and remove aU unfittmgness when there was external evidence of a Divine command to execute it; and when it came ^ Deut. xxiv. 16. ExtermiTiating Wars. loi before them as a grand and majestic act of Him who ordereth aU things according to His own sovereign will. And this supplies an answer to a question which is asked with respect to the need of miraculous inter position for the sanction of this extraordinary species of justice. It is said that in ages in which this was the state of ideas, that is to say, when one man was in the mind of the age an appendage of another, and was identified with a parent or ruler in crime, it followed by natural reason that he should be identified with him in punishment; and that one of these extraordinary cases would be wholesale famUy, and the other whole sale national destruction. What need, therefore, to the Jews, it is- asked, of any special Divine command, and with it of miraculous evidence, to warrant such acts, when this idea of justice existed to begin with in their minds as a natural idea ? What impediment was there to their acting upon this idea, without waiting for the special authorisation ? Why require the sanction of a miracle for these acts, if the popularly received idea of justice of itself allowed and sanctioned them ? But an idea may be held, and yet, with reference to such a question as this, everjrthing may depend upon the mode and m^easure in which it is held. Among the Jews ' what was that mode and measure ? That is simply an historical question. As a matter of fact, in the Jewish mind this pecuUar principle of justice existed in a modified and limited form ; ready to be put in execution upon a special Divine call, but not before. We have not to examine the state of mind logicaUy, but to take the fact. As a matter of fact it was a I02 Exterminating Wars. special authorisation which put in force this justice in the case of Korah, Dathan, and Abiram, the family of Achan, the family of Saul, as weU as in the larger case of the extermination of the Canaanites : an authorisation through a miracle at the time, or through an inspired leader. The principle, held in definitely elsewhere in the early ages of the world, was held with this distinction by the Jew. But such a Divine sanction implied miraculous evidence to sup port it. And thus it was an essential characteristic of this extraordinary justice under the old dispensa tion, that it was executed under such miraculous warrant ; this was a fundamental feature of it, which entered into the system, and furnished a moral con dition of it. But with whatever condition this idea of justice was held in the Jewish mind, when we have the fact that it was held, we have the reason why the Divine commands, of which we have been speaking, were adapted to man as the agent for their execution then, and are not adapted now ; and were capable of proof by the evidence of miracles then, and are not capable now ; — viz., that the imperfect idea of justice which then existed in the human mind opposed no resistance to them on the moral side. Suppose a Divine command, professing to come to us now upon the evidence of a miracle, that we were to kiU one man on account of the crime of another man, a famUy of children on account of the sin of their father, aU the infants of a nation on account of the wickedness of. a nation as a whole ; it is plain that, in the first place, we should Exterminating Wars. 103 be divided in our minds between two contradictory evidences, — the evidence of the miracle that such a command came from God, and the evidence of our sense of justice that it could not. And is it not also suffi ciently plain, in the next place, that according to the Bible's own test of the validity of miraculous evidence, such evidence could not be valid proof of a command having come from God when in opposition to our moral sense ? But then these commands had no resistance from the moral sense ; they did not look unnatural to the ancient Jew, they were not foreign to his standard ; they excited no surprise or perplexity; they appealed to a genuine but rough idea of justice, which existed when the longing for retribution upon crime in the human mind was not checked by the stiict sense of human individuality. Such commands were therefore adapted then to miraculous proof; because such proof, then meeting nothing counter to it in the human conscience, possessed its natural weight not counterbalanced or neutralised. Man in the first ages was identified with some individual or body external to him, was implicated in its crimes, and exposed to their punishment; whereas now human individuaUty is understood, and society is penetrated with the tme conception of each man as an inde pendent being, with an existence and rights of his own. LECTURE V. VISITATION OF THE SINS OF THE FATHERS UPON THE CHILDREN. WHEN in a later age we have to separate one part of the Jewish Law from another, the permanent part from the temporary part, the accommodation to imperfect morality from the moral truths ; we have to argue and to lay down some position on the subject which includes the consequence we want. But in the actual dispensation of the law ; and when one part wa^ separating from another by an actual change and development, no argument was needed on the subject. The Law naturaUy and of itself sUpped off its incon gruous matter ; all that was not perfectly holy, pure, and righteous, did not, ipso facto, belong to the Law, it was rejected as something that came from another stock ; and if it had been confounded hitherto with the Law, it was time that the partition should be made, and the difference of the two materials revealed. Our Lord, e.g., was not prevented by His Divine nature from arguing and showing forth truth by a logical process ; as when He argued for the resurrection of the dead from that which was spoken by God — saying, " I Visitation ofthe Sins of Fathers. 105 am the God of Abraham, and the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob : God is not the God of the dead but of the Uving."^ But in the Sermon on the Mount, which is the great trial of the Law, — the examination which tests the purity of its different pre cepts and rules, — there is no argument ; but the alien parts drop off of themselves, and leave the residuum pure. The Law tests itself. Does the enUghtened con science condemn anything it aUows or commands ? By the simple condemnation of conscience it ceases to belong to the Law : it goes. "Ye have heard that it hath been said of old time." AU these precepts were the litera scripta of the Law ; they are there in black and white ; statute law, as good as ever was impressed on any code. But it all goes, from the original assump tion which overrules every particular statute, that now nothing but what is perfect is aUowed in morals. " Be ye therefore perfect, even as your Father which is in heaven is perfect." K there is anything which is a falling short, which goes a certain way but not the whole way — as in the imperfect law of marriage, in the imperfect law of love, in a law of retaUation — it is assumed that the essence ofthe Law is not all this, and that, on the other hand, what is perfect is the Law. We know nothing henceforth but this perfect Law commanding in the conscience. So of St. Paul. It is remarkable that with all the imperfections, the crudities, the coarse legislation which is stamped upon the Law, the Law never figures in St. Paul's moral estimate except as perfect. "The 1 Matt. xxii. 32. io6 Visitation of the Sins of Law is holy ; and the commandment holy, and just, and good." ^ How is this ? except that ipso facto the Law parts vpith everything that is imperfect. Nothing that is not holy can be part of the Law. It is an axiom which settles everything. We hear nothing now of the exceptions taken in the Sermon on the Mount against the fallings short, defects, and inequaUties of the Mosaic legislation; but that is because these have already been eliminated ; and because, on that very account, the pure residuum is constituted the Law, and everything that is imperfect has ipso facto dropped off from it'. The Law, then, which is recognised by St. Paul is the perfect law only. He knows of nothing else. An imperfect law is an absurdity. The Law entered that offence might abound ; not to let men off, and show that they were not sinners because they had a very easy rule given them. It was absolutely neces sary, then, that the Law must be pure and perfect. But how was such a law got, but by the old Law casting its skin, and coming out in a new and perfect character as the Law of God, aspiring to the full spiritual morality? It is to be observed that the only dispute which engages attention in St. Paul is no dis pute respecting the moraUty of the Law, — as if it was doubted whether that morality were quite correct, and were not clouded by mistakes and lowered by blemishes and blots, — ^but it is a question only whether that Law ean be fulfilled, whether the human conscience is able to satisfy it. The moral demands of the Law are in satiable, we cannot mount up to this height, Alps on 1 Romans vii. 12. the Fathers upon the Children. 107 Alps arise, and we are involved in an inextricable labyrinth wherever we turn ; duties and obligations beset us with impossible claims, which cannot be resisted, and yet cannot be cleared. This is the diffi culty, then, in the doctrinal scheme of St. Paul ; but he does not think that the Law has blotches and stains ; there is no apprehension in St. Paul's mind that the Law is not good enough : the Law is spiritual, but I am carnal ; for the good that I would I do not, but the evU that I would not that I do ; the Law is perfect, but, 'we do not fulfil it. The mistake St. Paul fights against is not obedience to a carnal law so full of gross imperfections ; but that of assuming that we do and can obey a law so essentiaUy insatiable in its moral claims, and which exceeds and baffles the con science ; — that we can obey a law so spiritual. We have then here the quick and summary process by Trary are but scaffolding ; the true morals are con tained in the end and in the whole. Popular critics of the morality of the Old Testa ment apply the coarsest possible arguments to this subject. They think it enough to point to a rude penal law, to a barbarous custom, to an extirpating warfare, and it at once foUows that this is the morality of the Bible ; but this is to judge the sculptor from the broken fragment of stone. It was not the moraUty of the Bible unless it was the morality of the Bible as a whole, and the whole is tested by the end and not by the beginning. Scripture was progressive : it went from lower stage to higher, and as it rose from one stage to another it blotted out the commands of an inferior standard and substituted the commands of a higher standard. This was the nature of the dis pensation as being progressive ; it was the essential operation of the Divine government as it acted in that period of the world. The dispensation, then, as a whole, did not command the extermination of the Canaanites, but a subordinate step did ; and this step passed from use and sight as a higher was attained. The fact, though instract ive as past history, became obsolete, and was left 252 The End the Test of behind as a present lesson ; and the dispensation in its own nature was represented by its end. The very lower steps led to the end, and were for the sake of leading to it. The critic adheres to a class of commands which existed for the moment, as facts of the day; but the turning point is the issue, and the whole can only be interpreted by the event. The morality of Scripture is the morality of the end of Scripture ; it is the last standard reached, and what everything else led up to. Nothing, then, can be cruder and more rude than to identify Scripture with the action of the day. In the eyes of some, the action of the day is the seff- evident morality of Scripture, and no argument is thought necessary ; but whatever the facts may be, it is a fundamental mistake to suppose that there is any conclusion to be got from them, except through the defile of an argument. In assuming a God in the dispensation, we assume a presiding mind and intention ; and of that intention not the imme diate fact, but the upshot of the dispensation is the test. We say the upshot is worth all the extraordi nary and apparently lowering accommodation, the stooping process, and humiUation of the Divine govern ment. God allowed, during all those ages, mde men to think of Him as one of themselves, acting with the rudest and dimmest idea of justice. But He conde scended at the moment, to prevail and conquer in the end. In entering into and accepting thefr con fused ideas. He grappled with them. Through what a chaos of mistakes did final light arise, and the true a Progressive Revelation. 253 idea of justice make its way in the world I And God tolerated the mistakes, and allowed His commands to go forth in that shape, but the condescension was worth the result. It is the result alone which can explain those accommodations ; but the result does explain them, and bring them out as successful Divine policy. THE MANICH^ANS AND THE JEWISH FATHERS. QT. AUGUSTINE is perhaps the most marveUous ^ controversial phenomenon which the whole history of the Church from first to last presents. One great controversy is ¦ usuaUy enough for one man ; but he conducted, or it may be said finished, three ; the Manichsean, the Pelagian, and the Donatist. But it is not so much the number of the controversies which he conducted, as the vigour and proUfic power of his pen upon each, and the extraordinary force with which he stamped his own statements permanently upon the Church, which is the remarkable fact. The language in which he summed up the Pelagian con troversy reigned in the Church and dictated her formulae ; and after moulding the schools of the Middle Ages, prescribed the Articles of our own Church. He was superlatively fitted for fulfilUng this function, as well by his defects as by his gifts and merits. Armed with superabundant facUity of ex pression, — so that he himseff observes that one who had written so much must have a good deal to answer for, — ^he was able to hammer any point of view which he wanted, and which was desirable as a counter- The Manichceans. 255 acting one to a pervading heresy, with endless repeti tion upon the ear of the Church ; at the same time varying the forms of speech sufficiently to please and enliven. In argument he was not too deep ; to have been so would have very much obstructed his access to the mind of the mass, and prevented him from getting hold of the ear of the Church at large. Nothing could have been more fatal to his infiu ence than that he should have got himself im bedded in some profound question, the solution of which must only have taken him into lower and still more difficult depths. He undoubtedly dealt with profound questions, but his mode of dealing with them was not such as to entangle him in knots and intricacies, arising from the disposition to do justice to aU sides of truth. On some subjects of contro versy, as on the Manichsean, his line was clearly laid down for him in Scripture, in the assertion of one God of infinite power and goodness, to which Mani- chaeanism was a dfrect contradiction ; though here he had perhaps in parts and branches of the controversy rather neat answers, than fuU or final answers. In the Pelagian controversy he had one side of truth, and one fundamental and conspicuous assertion of Scrip ture, to defend, of which the Pelagian doctrine was an audacious deniafl ; but he did not aUow the unity and simpUcity of his answers to be at all interfered with by large a;nd inclusive views of truth. To the extreme contradictory on the one side, he gave the extreme contradictory on the other ; and he gave it, as he did every answer he gave, with the most triumphant 256 The Manichceans and copiousness of language; with all the structure and finished mould of a consummate rhetorical style ; with the most neat and admirable adaptation of the form of answer to the form of the hostile proposition ; and with a perpetual freshness, and flexibility of shape and construction, in the composition of his argument. Augustine is indeed, with aU this, monotonous, and perhaps no writer in the whole of Church history tries the patience of his reader more than he does. The surface is elegantly varied, but the variety is thin and superficial, as compared with a monotony which is solid, bulky, and substantial. The reader feels that the discussion, under Augustine's hand, is wanting in the novelty and variety of trunk lines of thought. We travel over the ground, aware that we are not making sohd way upon the substantial point ; while the outer coating of the subject shows variety and versatUity. But this was in fact all the better for his writing, looked at in its controversial scope., It was so much the more powerful an instrument for impressing a certain class of thoughts upon the mass of men ; so much the more effective from its repetition and constancy. He was made, by this very modification of a varied monotony, — perpetually bringing in the same ideas under very slight difference of dress, — only the more nearly per fect a controversiaUst ; only the more effective an instrument for fixing particular positions, and im pressing a particular language upon the Church. Augustine's was a different thinking from modern phUosophical thought : he did not advance by regular the Jewish Fathers. 257 steps, and unfold an argument from a foundation, as a modern superior writer does ; he thought with his pen in his hand, and the great mass of his treatises were pamphlets ; many of them, latterly, hit off in the intervals of public business, and to meet particular occasions and attacks. His first controversy was the Manichsean, to which he was the more committed from having been a convert to Manichseanism himself. And it may be asked, What could have made Augustine ever turn Manichsean ? When we come across these Oriental reUgions, Gnosticism and Manichseanism, their phrase ology, whether it is about aeons, or about nations of Ught or nations of darkness, and mixtures of the two, is so extravagant and empty, that it seems the in vention of children rather than of men. In Mani chseanism (it is Augustine's description), " On the side of the bright and holy land was the deep and immense land of darkness, wherein dwelt fiery bodies, pestilent races. There were boundless darknesses emanating from the same nature, countless with thefr progeny; beyond which were muddy and turbid waters with thefr inhabitants, and within which were horrible and vehement winds with thefr princes and producers. Then again a destructive fiery region with its leaders and nations."^ The Manichseans spoke of the five caves of the nation of darkness; they " assigned to the people of darkness five elements, each of which pro duced its own chief; and these elements they caUed 1 S. Aug. contra Fpist. Maniclicei, 15. S 258 The Manichesans and vapour, darkness, fire, water, wind." ^ Both light and darkness were spoken of as Principles, Natures, Sub stances, Gods;"^ In Manichseanism, then, the king dom of darkness made an attack on the kingdom of Ught ; and the Light or Divine Nation, being in some trepidation for itseff, thought it best to make a compact with its opponent; and a certain section of the former, entering into combination with the latter, formed the composition of this world. With respect, then, to these and such like representations, it must be observed that they are only the pictorial part of the system giving a scenic effect to the theory. Though even this had its influence in proselytising ; and when Augustine says that this imagery put into marked contrast before him the " most lucid sub stance of God," and evU as having its own foul and hideous bulk, whether gross which they caUed earth, or thin and subtle like the body of the air," ^ we can imagine the winning effect of a bright and dark con trast on a boy. But all this must have been meant, by the very construction of DuaUstic theories, only as so much imagery, putting the theory into a portrait shape, and adapting it to the minds of the mass. What was represented by it, was, that there were two original substances in nature, a good and an evU one. And this has an argument of its own, which is by no means obsolete at the present day. All DuaUstic reUgions contain thefr main appeal to human reason in the circumstance of their pretension to represent ^ S. Aug. contra Epist. Maniohoei, 18 ; and de Hceres. 46, p. 35, Ei Migne. ' Gonira Faustvm, xxi. 1. " Gonfess. v. 20. the Jewish Fathers. 259 facts. This is a mixed world, and it must have a mixed Deity. That is their real basis. In what form they do this, — whether under the form of two gods, a good and an evU, or of one God who is a mixture of both good and evU, or who is devoid of either, — is a subordinate point. Hume declared it his opinion that there was a great deal in Manichseanism. That philosopher, although he could, as he said, argue ingeniously for ever against final causes, still avowed that, as a man of common sense, he could not see his way to denying that this world must have originated in a Designing Mind. But what kind of Mind ? Yes, that was the difficulty. "Look round this universe," he says. "What an immense profusion of beings, animated and organised, sensible and active ! You admfre this prodigious variety and fecundity. But inspect a little more narrowly these living existences, the only beings worth regarding. How hostUe and destructive to each other ! How insufficient aU of them for thefr own happiness ! How contemptible or odious to the spectator ! The whole presents nothing but the idea of a blind Nature, impregnated by a great vivifying principle, and pouring forth from her lap, without dis cernment or parental care, her maimed and abortive chUdren ! Here the Manichsean system occurs as a proper hypothesis to solve the difficulty : and no doubt, in some respects, it is very specious, and has more probabihty than the common hypothesis, by giving a plausible account of the strange mixture of good and UI which appears in lffe. But ff we consider, on the 26o The Manichceans and other hand, the perfect unfformity and agreement of the parts of the universe, we shall not discover in it any marks of the combat of a malevolent with a benevolent being. There is, indeed, an opposition of pains and pleasures in the feelings of sensible creatures : but are not all the operations of Nature carried on by an opposition of principles, of hot and cold, moist and dry, light and heavy ? The trae conclusion is, that the original Source of all things is entfrely indifferent to aU these principles ; and has no more regard to good above ill, than to heat above cold, or to drought above moisture, or to Ught above heavy." " There may ybur hypotheses be framed concerning the first causes of the universe : that they are endowed with perfect goodness ; that they have perfect malice ; ihat they are opposite, and have both goodness and malice ; that they have neither goodness nor maUce. Mixt phenomena can never prove the two former un- mixt principles; and the unfformity and steadiness of general laws seem to oppose the thfrd. The fourth, therefore, seems by far the most probable."^ Hume, then, regarded Dualism only as one form of that theory of theism which was based upon the actual condition of the universe. It was an inconvenient form, because there was no appearance of a straggle in the construction of the world. But so long as your God was an induction from facts, which phUosophically Hume thought He must be. He must be either two, a good and an evU, or one Deity mixed of both ; or a wholly negative and extra-moral Deity. And thus 1 Hume's Philosophical WorJcs, ed. 1826, vol. iL p. 526. the Jewish Fathers. 261 in Mr. MiU's autobiography we see a testimony paid to the merits of Manichseanism as a mode of theism doing justice to facts. MUl says of his father James Mill, that the grounds of his objection to estabUshed theism were moral more than intellectual: that he found it impossible to believe that a world so fuU of evU was the work of an Author combining infinite power with perfect goodness and righteousness ; and that his intellect spurned the subtleties by which men attempt to blind themselves to this open contradiction ; that he would not have equally condemned the Sabsean or Manichsean theory of a good and an evil principle straggling against each other for the government of the universe ; and that he had expressed surprise that no one revived that theory in our own time.^ So far, however, Manichseanism was only the ancient theistic Dualism, and stood upon the ground of the Parsee religion, and the doctrine of Zoroaster or the Magi. But Manichseanism had this notable pecuUarity, that it was a proselytising and propa gandising religion. In this respect it had parted company with the parent stock. It was Magianism, not staying at home and content with its ancestral domains, but wandering about over the whole world like a knight-errant in the cause of truth and in quest of disciples. It was the ordinary character of these Oriental religions to be stationary ; where they had grown up, there they remained as traditionary systems, and they manffested no inclination for adventure or con quest. And so Magianism was naturally a stationary ^ Autobiography nf John Stuart Mill, p. 39. 262 The Manichceans and religion : but this was a fiery offshoot of it, which had so far diverged from the character of the parent religion. Manichseanism was Zoroastrianism feeling a want and void in its own local confinement, be ginning to suspect that truth ought to be common to all the world, and so adopting the aim and the scope of a universal religion. But this could not be managed without considerable difficulty. The ancient Zoroastrianism had very small resources for a universal religion. There was little to satisfy the human heart in a twofold Deity, and in an internecine war of good and evil, in which the theory did not speak, at any rate with any trumpet voice, as to the issue. But when the Manichsean had issued forth from the precincts of his own national worship, and looked around him on open ground, he saw before him the youthful and vigorous religion of Christianity, avowedly aiming at universal empire, and considering that its lawful and natural prize. It had afready even, partially accomplished its purpose, had broken down the boundaries of nations, and shown itseff of a universal type. This was a striking phe nomenon to a religious propagandist, who aimed at the same result, but with wholly inadequate means. The idea struck him that he would use the Christian religion for the purpose of giving universality to the Magian. He had, as it were, a universality provided for him and ready at hand in the catholic Church and creed, if only it could be appended to his own religion ; but unfortunately at present it belonged to a differ ent stock and antecedents. How was the transfer to the Jewish Fathers. 263 be effected ? Obviously by a bargaUi or compact of some kind ; but what ? Magianism must of course engraft its own main doctrines upon Christianity ; that was essential, otherwise it would not be Magianism which would attain universality in Christianity ; which was the object. But, on the other hand, Magianism, i.c. the Manichsean offshoot of it, would professedly receive into itself certain portions of Christianity. There would thus be an incorporation of Magianism into Chris tianity, of Christianity into Magianism ; and the com bination would be an eternal and universal religion. Manichseanism, then, in order to fulfil its share in the compact, incorporated in a certain shape, though a whoUy spurious one, the Christian doctrines of the Trinity, the Incarnation, the Atonement. It acknowledged in words a Holy Ghost,^ but it placed His habitation in the air. It acknowledged again the Second Person in the Trinity, and gave Him the name of Logos; but it assigned to Christ the sun as His residence, and even identified Him with the vivifying power of the sun. This was a physical theory of our Lord, who thus became partly the ancient Mithra of the Magian system, and partly the source of the animating principle of the physical world. This was the office oi power ^ which belonged to the Redeemer. The patibilis Christus, the suff'er- ing Christ, consisted in the same power being detached and dehvered from the channels in which it had re sided — i.e., from the receptacles of vegetable nature ; which detachment and delivery took place by death. * Contra Faustum, xx. 2. ^ Ib. xx. 2. 264 The Manichceans and Our Lord was thus spoken of as undergoing injury, degradation, and pollution, ," in the bands of earthly materials, in the juices of herbs, and in the corrup tion of aU flesh ; " ^ and it was said that " the Saviour was crucifled in the whole world and in every soul ; " and Christ, it was said, "was daily born, suffered, and died — that He hung from every tree." ^ A more local presence of our Lord upon earth even was accepted, but no true incarnation. "The Ught," says Manes,^ " touched not the substance of the flesh, but was only shaded with a Ukeness and form of flesh." It was denied that Christ really took on Him human flesh, that He was born, or died, or rose again, or was cfr- cumcised, baptized, or tempted, or had any of the affections of a man. But the delivery which was assigned to Christ as a function was still the dehvery from error and slavery, from enmity and from death. Though these expressions too receive a Manichsean sense from the interpretation of their uses elsewhere. They seem to mean only what Christ was and did as a teacher. " We cannot be reconciled," the Manichsean said,* " save through a Master, who is Christ Jesus." " We follow the true knowledge, and that knowledge restores the mind to the memory of its former state in the kingdom of light." ® But there was another exchange to be made before the compact of Manichseanism with Chris tianity was completed. When the Manichsean turned 1 Gontra Faustimi, xx. 17. 2 JJ. xx. 2. ^ Epist. ad Zebenam ap. Fabric. Bibl. Gr. v. 284. * Gontra Fortunat. 17. ' Ib. 20. the Jewish Fathers. 265 his eye upon the spectacle of Christianity, he saw there a mighty and expansive future, but, in his view, a somewhat degraded and ignominious past. He could not tolerate the Old Testament Saints. The Patriarchs, the Judges, the Prophets, the Kings,— he regarded them aU as simply involved in one charge of im morality, barbarism, fraud, and bloodshed. Their ways and mode of lffe were odious to him, and conflicted in the most marked way with the Oriental standard of subUmity and sanctity. He could not possibly understand how a high Saint could have many chUdren, stUl less how a Patriarch could have several wives, and how a Judge, under the impulse of inspiration, could slay a thousand men with the jawbone of an ass. The freedom, the impulse, the impetus, not to say the irregularities of the Jewish saints more than perplexed him, they astounded, shocked, and disgusted him. He could not conceive how such men could stand at the root of that sacred stem which bore the Christian branches. Moses, in spite of the moral scope of his legislation, was intolerable to him; he inveighed against his cruelty, his judicial slaughters, his exter minations. Though an antagonist, upon his own Magian basis, to idolatry, Faustus, taking the part of the Canaanites against Moses, declared of him that — " humanorum nuUi unquam divinorumque peper- cerit."^ He asserted that when our Lord said that aU before Him were thieves and robbers. He referred to the Patriarchs and Prophets of the Old Testament.^ ^ GmiVra Faustum, xv. 1. "He spared nothing either human or divine." ' lb. xvi. 12. 266 The Manichceans and The Law, with its bloody rites, cfrcumcision, and sacrifices, was denounced as only a form of paganism.. Even the quiet and peaceful family lffe of the Jewish Patriarch was low m his eyes; it was enveloped in the chains of earth; it did not scale the heights of holy absorption, or mount up to the empyrean of mortifled rapture. It did not at aU embody, but seemed coarsely to contradict, the subtle Eastern type, which demanded as its first condition the separation from matter and the rejection of sense. The fiery- proud spirituaUty of the Oriental religions put to shame the simplicity, humility, and practical temper of the Jewish saintly mind. The Manichsean could not imagine that such a Ufe could be a chastised lffe. Though it is the experience of most people, when any peculiarly showy specimens of goodness have been before them in lffe, that some character less striking in outward effect has been really the best, this was not his conclusion. The Old Testament saints and prophets were not shov?y enough for him. What was to be done with such a spfritual ancestry ? The large prospect of the Christian Church, its strong and vigorous present, were objects of ambition for the Manichsean to get hold of, but he could not accom modate his stomach to its low progenitors. Could he persuade it to give them up, and in the place of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, the Patriarchs and the Pro phets, to adopt as spfritual forefathers — the Magi ! For this was vfrtually the scope of the compact. It assumed the/orm indeed of disbelieving all the accounts of the Old Testament saints, and rejecting the whole of the Jewish Fathers. 267 the Bible narrative on that head : — " Puniantur scrip tores, damnentur eorum Ubri, purgetur propheticum nomen indigna fama, gravitati atque censurse suse Patiiarcharum reddatur auctoritas." ^ But ff the actual recorded character of the Jewish saints was thus blotted out, and another substituted for it by an hypothesis; what must that substituted cha racter be ? It must of course be the one which as a Manichsean he considered was the proper character for saints to possess ; or the sanctity of his own Magi. This was in fact, then, to say : You really cannot keep these Old Testament saints ; I can assure you they do not do for you ; they reaUy are a discredit to you ; you must change them ; it wUl be a great improvement ; attach the Magi to Christianity ; they are real saints, and wUl make you forefathers of whom you need not be ashamed. Now it is certainly an advantage which belongs to hypothetical spfritual ancestors, that their merits can be exalted to the utmost point of perfection without any fear of contradiction. This undescribed and unrecorded Une of Jewish saints which was to oust the known recorded Une, would have been supposed to possess aU the highest quahfications of Eastern saints, and all the ascetic and contemplative virtues. And so to the Manichsean Faustus the exchange would have seemed a most happy one. But to us at the present day it is more than questionable whether the torpid, 1 Gontra Faustum, xxii. 3. " Let the writers be punished, let their books be condemned, let the name of the prophets be purified from the fame that degrades them, let the authority of the Patriarchs be restored to the sober and severe life that is truly theirs.'' 268 The Manichceans a'nd ascetic contemplativeness of the Eastern saint would have seemed a good exchange for the true and genuine form of character which belongs to the Old Testament saint, — its naturalness, its life, with aU its irregulari ties ; and whether it would not have appeared like a substitution of dead men for Uving ones. It was indeed one of the principal weapons which the Manichsean controversialist wielded against Chris tianity — ^the character, of the Old Testament saints ; i.e., the striking difference of moral standard in the Old Testament and the New. He made the very most of this, and threw in the face of Christians the actions of the Patriarchs, with an insolence which reminds one of the lowest ranges of modern controversy. The tone in which Faustus censures Abraham, Moses, the Judges, and David, is like that of the National Reformer. And when we meet Augustine afterwards as a champion and defender of the Jewish saint against Manichaeanism, we can easUy under stand that this difficulty would have pressed upon him strongly when that system first gained him as a convert ; and that the escape which the Manichsean offered from the moral difficulties of the Old Testa ment was among the principal attractions of his side of the argument; that it would have great influence upon youthful phUosophical minds. The objections to Old Testament morals were upon the surface, the answer was indfrect and roundabout. Putting aside, then, the substantial part of the Manichaean contioversy, that concerned with the dual- istic basis of that religion, which Augustine refuted the Jewish Fathers. 269 upon the principles of the Old Testament revelation of one God of infinite power and goodness, let us attend to this offshoot, but stUl very important offshoot, of the subject, which had to do with the difficulty of Old Testament morality. The answers of Augustine, then, to the Manichsean invectives against the Patriarchs and saints of the Old Testament, were characterised by that ingenuity which so marked his controversial treatment of subjects. "Those who raise these objections," he says, "against the actions ofthe Patriarchs, are like schoolboys, who would reprove thefr masters for some apparent grammatical mistake, which is no real mistake : for example, they know the mle that a noun singular cannot be joined with a verb plural ; and so when their teacher, who is most learned in the Latin tongue, repeats the line — * pars in frusta secant ; ' some boys would correct him, and say, ' No, not secawi ; it must be secaf .' And when he says 'i2efligione patium,' they would say, ' No : religione, not refligione.' There is an analogy between these absurd corrections and the charges of these objectors. The virtues of great minds are some times like the faults of little minds. There is as much distance between the typical acts of the Prophets and the sensual sins of the wicked, as there is between the solecisms or barbarisms of tyros and the figures and metaplasms of grammarians."^ So again . . . "They" — Manichsean objectors to Old Testament morals — " are like to men who decry the UtUity of things, when they do not know what the ^ Gantira Faustum,, xxii 25. 270 The Manichceans and things themselves are. As ff a deaf man should see the lips moving of men talking, and should blame the superfluity and deformity of the motions ; or as ff a bhnd man put into a house, which he had heard much praised, should feel round with his hand to test the smoothness of the waUs, and coming to windows, should find fault with their inconvenience, and suppose them to be ruinous holes." ^ The typical aspect of Old Testament actions is strongly pressed by Augustine. But now we come to a sohd and real defence, viz., that the Divine orders in the Old Testament to do actions which we think wrong now, are the necessary accommodation of the Divine policy, and with it of the Divine commands, to the cfrcumstances and moral standard of the day. To the contrast drawn beween Patriarchs and Apostles he replies — " Nee (valetis) discernere consuetudinem temporis UUus, quo promissio velabatur, a consue tudine temporis istius, quo promissio revelatur."' Why does FaUstus object to the spoUing of the Egyptians ? As if Moses would not have sinned had he not done it ! " Deus enim jusserat qui utique novit . . . secundum cor hominis, quid unusquisque, vel per quem pei-peti debeat. . . . Digni ergo erant et isti quibus talia juberentur, et UU qui taUa paterentur." * ' Gontra Faustum, xxii. 7. 2 lb. xxii. 23. "You are not able to discern between the custom of that tirae, when the promise was being veiled, and the custom of the present time in which the promise is revealed." ^ Ib. xxii. 71. "For God had ordered it, who really knows . . . according to the state of man's heart what each ought to suffer, and nt whose hands. . . . Therefore they were worthy for their part to receive such commands, and the others to suffer such treatment." the Jewish Fathers. 271 . . . And he adheres to the answer in spite of the objection raised that a true or good God could not have given such commands. ..." Imo vero talia recte non jubet, nisi Deus Verus et Bonus, qui et solus novit quid cuique jubendum sit . . . solus Deus Verus et Bonus novit quid, quando, quibus, per quos fieri ali quid veljubeat vel permittat."^ The extermination of the Canaanites was thus an instance of the execution, by means of human instru ments (who were qualified by the carnal stage of mind through which they were then passing to be the recipi ents of such commands), of a great Divine principle that the kingdoms of idolaters were the property of the true God: — a principle which it was speciaUy necessary to promulgate at that time : " Sed eam rerum dispensationem ac distributionem, temporum ordo poscebat, ut prius appareret etiam ipsa bona terrena . . . propter quse maxime civitas impiorum diffusa per mundum suppUcare idolis et dsemonibus solet, non nisi ad unius Dei veri potestatem atque arbi trium pertinere."^ ... Do not they understand, he says, this principle of Divine accommodation ? — " Jamne in- teUigunt quemadmodum nulla inconstantia prsecipien- ^ Contra Faustum, xxii. 72. "Nay rather, none gives such com mands rightly excepi the true and good God, who at once alone knows what commands each should receive . . . and who alone knows the nature, the time, the objects, the instruments of any command or permission that He gives." 2 n. 76. " But the order of time demanded this dispensation and distribution of things, that it should first appear that even earthly goods, for which the community of impious men diffused throughout the world is wont to make greatest supplication to idols and demons, are reaUy only in the disposition and free will of the one true God." 272 The Manichceans and tis, sed ratione dispensantis, pro temporum diversitate, ' praecepta vel consiUa, vel permissa, mutentur?"^ We are in this part of the Manichsean controversy introduced early into a difficult question, which has been a special subject of modern, and most particularly of very recent thought — I ipean the difficulty of Old Testament morality — how God could give commands to persons to do the actions, which He did command in those ages. This has been a fertUe subject of dis cussion in the present day, and it can hardly be said that any answer has even yet been arrived at in which there is general concurrence. Augustine appears to me to have struck out in a rough way what is the main answer to the difficulty, viz. that God gives commands in accommodation to the state of mind and moral standard of the recipients of them. ..." Deus Verus et Bonus solus novit quid cuique jubendum sit ... . novit secundum cor homims, quid unusquisque, vel per quem perpeti debeat. . . . Digni ergo erant et isti quibus talia juberentur, et iUi qui taUa paterentur." ^ Here is involved the principle that God could, in a former age and to people of a lower .moral standard, give commands to do actions, which we should think it wrong to do now. " Deus jubet secundum cor hominis . . . digni erant quibus talia juberentur." There was a certain inward want, an unenlightenment, a rudeness of moral conception, in 1 Contra Faustum, xxii. 77. " Do they understand at last how pre cepts, or counsels, or permissions are changed, with no ihconstancy in Him who gives them, but by the wisdom of Him who dispenses them according to the difference of the times V, 2 Ib. 71, 72. See p. 270, note .3, the Jewish Fathers. 273 those to whom such commands were given; other wise they would not have been given. God would not have given a command to slaughter a whole. nation to an enlightened people : we cannot suppose Him, e.g., giving such a command to us at the present day. " But when people were ' digni quibus talia jube rentur,' then God commanded 'secundum cor hominis.'" When thefr moral standard was such as admitted of such a command being received by them as a Divine command, then the command was given, when in the Divine course of policy it was expedient that it should be given. There is something natural in this answer ; and if any one of ordinary understanding were asked in an ordinary way his idea of the explanation of such commands, he would most likely state it in this way. But when it has come to formal judgment in theo logical w;riting, something has prevented Divines from being wiUing to admit that God can command an action whieh, according to a perfect moral standard, is wrong. In thefr account of the Divine accommoda tion, they go as far as permission ; but they stop with permission, and do not recognise the idea of God actually commanding an action below our moral standard, though on a level with the inferior moral standard of an 'early age. This element accordingly does not enter into Butler's explanation of these com mands;^ his explanation, e.g., ofthe Divine command to destroy the Canaanites does not bring in, or avaU itself at aU of, the special defence or excuse of an in- ^ See ante, p. 31. T 2 74 The Manichceans and ferior moral standard in the Jewish people of that age. His explanation rests entirely upon the Divine right to destroy lffe, and to communicate the intention to execute that right to the persons through whose instrumentality it was to be carried out. But this defence would apply as much to such a command given in the present day, as it would to a Uke com mand given in the age of Moses and Joshua. It does not . rest on or avail itself of any distinction of moral standard existing between the two ages. And though Butler would doubtless acknowledge such a distinction as Zjfact, his explanation does without it. Augustine's explanation distinctly avails itseff of this element of defence, and expressly acknowledges the moral right of the Deity not only to permit, but to command, actions of imperfect moraUty, when the moral standard of the age does not rise above that level. But whUe Augustine acknowledges the imperfect moral standard of the Patriarchal and Prophetic age, this does not in the least affect his estimate of the high sanctity and greatness of Patriarchs and Prophets themselves. Underneath the differences of special moral rules and ideas, in which they were at a dis advantage, and which were those of the age in which they lived, he sees a fundamental unity of general sanctity and greatness, and loftiness of character, which unites them with the Apostles and the highest saints of the New Testament. It is a difficult question in moral phUosophy how far any man is lowered in dividuaUy in moral character by the faults and the Jewish Fathers. 275 defective mles of his age. One sees a moral greatness in an individual which Ues underneath the growth and progress of moral ideas in the race; which greatness is the same in a Patriarch that it is in an Apostle. We rest satisfied that there is this fun damental unity, in the moral character of Patriarch and Apostle, notwithstanding the variety of particular rules under which they lived, — which unity puts them on the same basis as reUgious men. With St. Augus tine it is always — " Tantus Patriarcha, Pater Abraham, Sanctus vfr Jacob, sancti Patiiarchse — quorum se Deum appeUari voluit Deus." ^ * Contra Faustum, xxii. 46, 47, 69. APPENDIX. Lecture I, Note 1, p. 1. An inscription on the bricks of Mugheir seems to identify the god whom Terah worshipped, with the Moongod whose worship was established in the ancient Chaldsean capital (see Eawlinson's Herodotus, vol. i. p. 365). The expression, " served other gods " evidently alludes to some decided form of idolatry. Some sort of superstitious use of images appears to have adhered to the family stock which Abraham left behind him in Haran at his second and solitary migration into Canaan, even after the first migration of the whole house from the other side the flood — ^from Ur of the Chaldees. When Eachel, a daughter of the branch at Haran, fled with Jacob from her father Laban, she stole " his gods," and " put the images in the camel's furniture." i And whatever the superstition was, it seems to have gone on surreptitiously for some time even among Jacob's own household ; for on his jour ney to Bethel, he " said unto his household and to all that were with him. Put away the strange gods that are among you, and be clean, and change your garments." " But this corrupt use of images could hardly have been any formal system of idolatry ; for the worship of the one God, as the open and established worship of Jacob's household, would have precluded this ; nor, had the kindred left behiad in Haran been formal idolaters, would there have been any reason for the family of Abraham so carefully maintaining the connection with them, and its heirs taking their wives exclusively from them, religiously avoiding the daughters of the people of the land. There would have been no religious ground for keeping up this marked distinction be tween the kindred at Haran and the Canaanites, had both wor shipped false gods. This use of images is generally supposed to 1 Gen. xxxi. SO, 31 " Gen. xxx7. 2. 2/8 Appendix. have been connected with some practice of divination or some minor form of superstition, which was consistent with the regular worship of one God. But the forefathers of Abraham " served other gods," they were idolaters who paid to false gods that worship which was due to the one true God. The book of Judith follows the statement of Scripture. "This people (the Jews) are descended of the Chaldseans : and they sojourned heretofore in Mesopotamia, because they would not follow the gods of their fathers, which were in the land of Chaldsea. For they left the way of their ancestors, and worshipped the God of heaven, the God whom they knew : so they cast them out from the face of their gods, and they fled into Mesopotamia, and so journed there many days. Then their God commanded them to depart from the place where they sojourned, and to go into the land of Chanaan." ' ".Frequens et obvia est de ea re apud veteres historia ; sed vereor ut suam satis liberent fidem, qui tam constanter de rebus tam priscis sententiam proferunt. Tradunt sane Ebrsei statu- arium fuisse Tharam, atque eandem cum eo aliquandiu exercuisse artem Abrahamum. Et legitur Sacris Literis Tharam, et patres ei contemporaneos, alienos Deos coluisse, quod in Josuse cap. xxiv. com. 2 reperitur. Quod ansam forte prajbuit, ut idolatrise initia ei deberi posteri censerent. Abrahamum item in ardentem fomacem a Mmrodo conjectum, cum idolorum cultum detrectaret, scribunt. Id prseter vulgo tritos scriptores habet Chaldseus paraphrastes in Ecclesiastem cap. iv. com. 13 sed vix est ut parentaUa seu feriarum denicalium sacra tam celeri in divinos honores transitu, quam brevia sevi inter Sheruchum et Tharam intervalla proposcerint, demutarentur. At vero Chaldaica ilia paraphrasi, Uzielidi tributa, etiam locus ille Mosis, qui quartum Genesis caput claudit de idolis, capitur perinde ac si diu etiam ante diluvium coli ccepissent, circa annum nempe a mundi con- ditu ducentisimum quadragesimum." '^ " Imagines illas quas furata est Eahel, Ebrsei vocant Teraphim, Gen. cap. xxxi. comm. 19. Pro Diis esse habitas, testis est ipse Laban, Quare, inquit ilIe,/MJ-ate es Deos meos ? Jacobum adlocutus. Fictas eas ab astrologis, ut futura prsedicerent, sentit E. D. Kimchi, et humana forma factas, ita ut caelestis influentise essent ' Chap. V. 6-9. " Selden, vol. ii. p. 238. Appendix. 2 79 capaces, adnotat Abraham Aben Ezra theologus et astrologus Judseorum maximus ; atque ad eam mentem interpretatur Tera phim quae pro liberando Davide, in lecto posuit Michal uxor ejus, de qua historia est 1 Sam. cap. 19. Inter causas etiam, cur Eahel eas sustulerit, hanc unam recensent, ne scilicet Labani Ularum inspectione innotesceret, per quod iter ilia abierat. Ideo D. Augustinus Quaest. xciv. in Genesim. Qaod Laban, inquit, dicit, Quare furatm es Deos meos ? hinc est illud fortasse quod et augurari se dixerat. Imo et Aben Ezra augurium illud ad Tera phim Labanis refert. Utrum autem ut Dii colerentur Teraphim, utcunque Dii dicti, an vero divinationis tantum instrumenta haberentur; vetus est inter magistros controversia." ^ Lecture III., Note 2, p. 74. Warburton's great theory of the sacrifice of Isaac is based upon the Scriptural account of that sacrifice, as undertaken with the fuU expectation of the restoration of the victim to life ; but he raises upon this basis a bold superstructure of his own, for which it is not easy to find equal Scripture warrant, — the theory, viz., that the sacrifice was a scenical representation, a representa tion by action of the Atonement and Eesurrection of Christ, and a revelation of the Gospel scheme to Abraham. The whole sub ject of teaching by action, which prevailed in antiquity, and is adopted in Scripture, is discussed and elucidated by Warburton. To Jeremiah it is said, — " Make thee bonds and yokes, and put them upon thy neck ; " * to Hosea, — " Go, take thee a wife of whoredoms ; " ^ to Ezekiel, — " Prepare thee stuff for removing," * etc. This was information by action instead of words. The Almighty, by the first of these actions, indicating the conquest of Nebuchadnezzar over Edom, Moab, etc. ; by the second, declaring His abhorrence of the idolatries of the house of Israel ; by the third, foretelling the approaching captivity of Zedekiah. And thus Abijah rent his garment into twelve pieces, of which he gave Jeroboam ten, to signify the secession of the ten tribes." The 1 Selden, voL ii. p. 279. => Jer. xxvii. 2. ' Hos. 1. 2. * Ezek. xii. 3. « 1 Kings xi. 29, 30. 28o Appendix. sacrifice of Abrahasn then was, according to Warburton, an example of the same manner of teaching. The offering up of Isaac, in which the real death of that victim was contemplated, combined with the event of his son's restoration, revealed to the Patriarch the Atonement and the Resurrection. Substantial action was at the same time scenic representation. The information, he supposes, had been solicited by Abraham ; and " the father of the faithful must, from the nature of the thing, become very desirous of knowing the manner how this blessing \In thee shall all the fami lies of the earth be blessec^ was to be brought about. A Mystery, if we will believe the Author of our Faith, that engaged the attention of other holy men, less concerned than Abraham, and consequently less stimulated and excited by their curiosity : ' And he turned unto his disciples, and said . . . For I tell you, that many prophets and kings [and much more Abraham, must] have desired to see those things which ye see,"" etc. (Luke X. 23, 24). \ And the text, — " Your father Abraham rejoiced to see my day," is adduced as proof that the information thus solicited by Abraham beforehand bad been promised to bim, — ^the argument being that the Greek word for rejoiced — H'/aKKioigoi.ro — signifies " the tumultuous pleasure which the expectation of an actually approaching blessing occasions." So convinced, indeed, is War burton that Abraham received information by action of the great events of the Gospel, that he accounts for the knowledge not having been divulged, but having been concealed by the Patri arch. But such a theory as this encounters great and insuperable objections. Warburton explains, indeed, the total silence ofthe Old Testament about this communication to Abraham, by saying that it would have been contrary to the Divine scheme to have recorded a revelation which would have indisposed the Jewish nation to the preparatory discipline of the Law. And he answers the obiection, that the command to sacrifice Isaac is plainly described in Scripture not as the vouchsafement of a singular privilege, but as a trial and temptation, by saying that the privilege was granted upon the condition of and by means of a trial ; that Abraham having requested to know the mode in which the blessing would ^ Diirine Legation. Book vi. § 5. Appendix. 281 be accomplished, the answer was. Offer up Isaac, and it shall be revealed to you. But the fact still remains, that Scripture is altogether silent about this communication to Abraham, and that therefore the supposition is wholly gratuitous and without foun dation. The whole proof, indeed, of this supposed revelation to Abraham rests upon that single text in the New Testament, — " Your father Abraham rejoiced to see my day ; and he saw it and was glad;" but it is an extravagant strain upon this text to extort this meamng out of it. " To see my day " is an indefinite expression, which does not necessarily mean more than that Abraham looked forward to the time when the Divine promise would be fulfilled, and that sublime gift in which all the nations of the earth were interested would be actually bestowed. One consequence of Warburton's adoption of a peculiar theory of the sacrifice of Abraham was a bad one — viz., that he defended that sacrifice by the shield of his own theory, and not by the simple statement of Scripture. To confute the notion that it was a propitiatory human sacrifice, in imitation of Canaanitish worship, the statement of Scripture was enough, — ^viz., that he who had received the promise " That in Isaac shall thy seed be called," offered him up, " accounting that God was able to raise him up, even from the dead." It was of the very nature of propitiatory sacrifices that they contemplated the loss of the victim, but Abraham did not contemplate the loss of Isaac. But Warburton prefers resting the defence of Abraham's sacrifice against the charge of being a propitiatory human sacrifice, upon the ground that the sacrificial action in , it was only scenical representation to reveal to Abraham the sacrifice of Christ. " This action being mere scenery, had no moral import ; that is, it conveyed or implied none of those intentions in Him who commanded it, and in him who obeyed the command, which go along with actions that have a moral import. Consequently, the injunction and obedience, in an action which hath no such import, can no way affect the moral character of the persons concerned : and consequently, this command could occasion no mistakes concerning the Divine Attri butes, ' with regard to God's delighting in human sacrifices." ' The defence is good, were the fact of the scenical representation certain ; the latter, however, is no more than a theory, and is ' Dvvme Legaiion, vi. 5. 282 Appendix. therefore a weak substitute for a Scripture statement. But though Warburton erects a superstructure of uncertain theory on this subject, the groundwork of his view is true and Scriptural — viz. that Abraham offered up Isaac, not with the idea of losing him, but with tbe fuU expectation of the recovery of the heir of the promise. Lecture V., Note 3, p. 121. This is from a passage on tbe subject of punishment on the didactic principle. We say that punishment for the fathers' sins is pun ishment on that principle, and we call it vicarious punishment, — regarding it as being on that principle and not on the judicial principle. I bear that certain persons are selected by their relationship to others to be instances of the consequences of sin. Now this is very clear of those who are thus didactically punished on account of their fathers' .sins. But Tucker points out, and Tvith great truth, that it is not only true of those persons who are punished on account of their fathers' sins, who make this a marked and definite class; but that it is true of numbers of men everywhere who are singled out for this use and purpose of didactic punishment. Everywhere we see persons who are singled out for providential inflictions, for the purpose of im pressing others, reminding them of the consequences of connection with sin, — whether it is the sin of a father or of a gover nor, of a political or a military leader, does not signify. These men are singled out for didactic punishment. They are not worse than other men in themselves ; and therefore so far their punishment upon the didactic principle is a vicarious one — it is in fact suffered for the benefit and instruction of others, and for tbe good of society. As Tucker says : — " It is not so much actual suffering, as the terror of it, that operates upon free will ; " but there must be some actual suffering to produce this terror. And some must submit to this suffering by visitation of Providence ; constituting an indefinite and constantly seen class. We have, in fact, vicarious punishment of a didactic kind illustrated and exemplified everyvrhere, not only in tbose who suffer for their fathers' sins, but in persons who are visited by Providence gener ally. The punishment for fathers' sins is brought under a more Appendix. 283 general head, and is only one specimen of a large and compre hensive system. Now this being the case, Tucker goes off into another point as to how justice is to be satisfied with this kind of didactic vicarious punishment, some people being visited by Providence for the instruction of others, when they are not worse in them selves than others. And the general fad that it is so may be allowed, while it may be difficult to explain the rationale of its justice. And Mr. Tucker may have stated the fact rightly, and may have rather missed a rationale. When we come across the fact, indeed, a man says, I object to this fact : I object to being made an example of didactic punishment for the instruction of others. Say, I am one of the host of Pharaoh that was over thrown in the Eed Sea for an example. How is this treatment justified % Tucker then seems to admit that he has a grievance, but thinks he sees a way out of it. He teUs the man — " In this light of punishment it appears that the party undergoing it does a signal service to his fellow creatures, by exhibiting to them an example of utmost importance ; and necessary to preserve them in happiness : for which service I see nothing in our ideas of a gracious Govemor that should hinder His making him amends." ^ He then supposes some arrangements made in a future life to meet the case. But this is loose and rough speculation. Yet the fact of vicarious didactic punishmenf, it will be allowed, may be separated from the particular form of it exhibited as a visit ation for fathers' sins, and may be considered as a general law taking place here. Indeed, when we look abroad in the world, how much we see of great masses of providential visitation, which look like didactic punishment of some kind or other, — punishment meant to arrest our attention, though not judicial with respect to individuals ! A great battle arrests our attention, and we think it must be meant to be reflected on. The pride and ambition of nations produces terrible punishment. Num bers of individuals are not implicated in this public pride and ambition, — stUl we cannot help seeing that this /afe is congenial to this public vice and stain, of kings and statesmen. The whole is a lesson, and has a moral effect. ' Tucker's Idght of Nature, vol. iv. p. 396. 284 . Appendix. Lecture VL, Note 4, p. 143. Eahab's act was the saving of two believers in the true God, whereas Jael's was the destruction of an enemy of God; but deception was common to both acts.* The whole statement in answer to the Mng of Jericho's demand for the two spies was false, the two men being at the very time on the roof of the house hid with the stalks of flax. St. James, however," says that Eahab " was justified by works," and that this very conceal ment of the messengers was the work which justified her. Scott's comment is — "Various opinions have been formed con ceming Eahab's conduct on this trying occasion. Some object that her treachery to her king and country cannot be vindicated ; but it may be answered, that as she firmly believed the God of heaven had devoted the Canaanites to be utterly destroyed by the Israelites, she must either side with Israel and Israel's God against her country, or perish with it in a hopeless contest against the Almighty : so that, in her circumstances, she could not have acted otherwise, if influenced by a true and living faith. ... In respect of the falsehoods that she uttered ... if it were her indis pensable duty if possible to protect the spies, and there were no other conceivable way of obeying this, it seems not necessary to condemn her conduct altogether. Stratagems of war, and similar impositions upon determined enemies and persecutors, are not absolutely condemned in Scripture, though inconsistent with exact veracity." ' Bacon, in his tract " On Church Controversies" speaking of certain enthusiastic preachers of his day, says — " In this kind of zeal, they have pronounced generally, and without difference, all untruths unlawful; notwithstanding, that the midwives are directly reported to have been blessed for their excuse, and Eahab is said by faith to have concealed the spies." ' Lecture VIL, Note 5, p. 172. However justly Dante offends modern commentators, it is clear that he did not outrage the conscience of his own age, character- 1 Josk ii. 4, 5. " James ii. 25. ^ Scott's Bible. Joshua ii 4. * Bacon's Works, Ed. 1819, vol. ii. p. 520. Exod. i 9 ; 2 Sam. xvi. 18, 19 ; 2 Kings vi. 19. Appendix. 285 ised as it was by bitter enmities, when he treats an inmate of the Inferno as a proper subject for deception ; as having no right to truth. In the circle of traitors, who are plunged up to the head in a frozen lake, — where tears on the upturned face freeze before they fall, thus forming a crystal vizor of ice, — he is accosted by Frate Alberigo, who had murdered his, guests at a banquet. Alberigo, mistaking him and Virgil for guilty spirits on the way to their doom in the lowest circle, thus piteously accosts them: — {Inferno, Canto xxxiii. 110). " 0 anime, crudeli Tanto, che data v' h V ultima posta, Levatemi dal viso i duii veil. Si ch'io sfoghi il dolor che' 1 enor m'impregna Un poco, pria che il pianto si raggieli. " [" 0 souls so cruel that for you is sealed The doom of the lowest gulf ! " so crying prayed me One of the sad ones of the crust congealed ; " Lift from my sight the hardened veil, and aid me, To vent the sorrow through my heart extending, A little ere the frost again invade me."] Dante answers readily : — " Perch' io a lui : Se vuoi ch'io ti sowegna, Dimmi oU se' : e s' io non ti disbrigo, Al fondo della ghiaocia ir mi convegna." [Then I, " If thou would'st have me succour lending, Say who thou wast ; and if thou art deceived, ^ Down to the lowest ice he my descending."] He knew himself bound to the icy bottom under the care of his guide, and in fact plays upon the traitor's misapprehension, who accepts the conditions ; and declaring himself, — " I am the Friar Alberigo," — tells his tale, and calls for the fulfilment of the promise, — "Ma distendi oramai in qua la mano ; Aprimi gU occhi : ed io non glieli apersi, E cortesia fu lui esser villano." [" But reach me hither now thy hand, unsealing Mine eyes, I pray thee." But I left them closed ; 'Twas courtesy to him to he unfeeling.] 286 Appendix. Lecture VII., Note 6, p. 175. From this deceit of esprit de corps to benefit a clan, or tribe, or party, or cause, we go to deceit for another object, viz. in execution of justice. A man has exposed himseK to death for the crime of bloodshed, and another man has it imposed upon him, as a sacred function, to secure justice and kill him. This is the law of Goel ; it may happen that the law can only be carried out by stratagem and deceit ; and when these are necessary the avenger of blood must use them. The Arabian character, then, is described as generous and courageous, noble and frank in aU the ordinary relations, but the tactics which the law of Goel imposes on it try its fidelity to these features, and engraft upon the main stock of the character some special and occasional modes of action which are very opposite ; we find conspicuous untruthful ness, treachery, and double-dealing, but it is stUl an insertion in the general portrait of a noble-minded and magnanimous man. In the very fulfilment of tbe law of Goel be undertakes danger for tbe sake of duty, and sacrifices himself for a sacred object. It is only when killing has been imposed as a duty, that the discbarge from the obligation of truth has been considered to go with it : — ^it ought to be said the prohibition to speak the truth, the obligation to deceive. In proportion to the sanctity which attached to tbe office of avenger of blood, and to tbe obliga tion which lay upon bim to pursue the man guilty of homicide to death, was also tbe strength of the conviction in the avenger's mind, that be bad the right, or rather the duty to put aside all the ordinary rules of sincerity and truth-speaking in the means he adopted for accomplishing his end. Extreme deceit was allowed, or rather imposed on him, when it was necessary; because it was supposed that the duty of taking away life superseded the right to truth-speaking. Tbe use of such tactics in an excep tional case, then, implied no general tendency to dissimulation and treachery in the man ; they were a special instrument for a special end, and were totally different from meanness in the character. The whole moral sentiment of the East has utterly cashiered, within tbe direct sphere of the duty of slaying, the duty of veracity. The slayer, while he is under the direct obligation to kill a man, is under no obligation to truth ; but considers that as Appendix. 287 the man is the fitting object of assassination, he is the fitting victim of deceit and dissimulation. Michaelis, in his Arabic Chrestomathy, which he quotes in his Commentary on the Laws of the Hebrews, relates stories of the Arabs which show how completely, in the execution of the sacred task of avenger of blood, tbe Arab discards the whole ordinary duty of veracity, and adopts the most intricate and elaborate arts of deceit and duplicity to get bold of the manslayer whose life bas become a solemn forfeit to him which he is bound to secure. The most honourable Arab is under an obligation in this instance to use every piece of dissimulation which can promote his end, and bring the guilty man within his grasp. " Hatim, the father, and Adi, the grandfather, of Kais bad both been murdered ; but as that happened before Kais was capable of reflection, bis mother kept it a secret from him, that he might not at any future period meditate revenge, and thereby expose bis own life to danger. In order to guard against his having any suspicions, or making any inquiries as to their deaths, she collected a parcel of stones on two hillocks in the neighbourhood, that they might have tbe appearance of burial- places, and told her son, that the one was the grave of bis father, tbe other of his grandfather. Kais bad of course no other idea than that his progenitors had died natural deaths, and were there buried .... Kais had a quarrel witb another young Arab, and received from bim this bitter taunt, " You would do better to show your courage on the murderer of your father and grand father." These words spoke much and deeply to his heart ; be became melancholy; and threatened his mother with killing either her or himself, if she did not teU bim the whole trath relative to tbe deaths of bis father and grandfather. He thus extorted the secret from ber ; and immediately set out on a peregrination, to which I cannot apply a more proper phrase, than our common one, of going in quest of adventures. He went to a distant part of the country, in quest of a man named Ohidascb, a friend of his father's, and whom he knew to bave been indebted to bis father on the score of gratitude — for that too enters into an Arab's idea of honour, barbarous as it other wise is. When be found him out, he at first entered his bouse merely as a stranger, according to the Arabian laws of hospi- 288 Appendix. tality. The wife of Chidasch immediately observed something in his face, which led her to ask whether he was not going to avenge blood. Chidasch himself recognised in bim a likeness to his friend, and after a short conversation, Kais told him where fore be was come. Chidasch was somewhat perplexed ; for one of tbe murderers was his own uncle: but he told Kais, that although he would fain put the murderer into his hands, he could not do it openly, but that be had only to mark his pro cedure next night, when be would set himself down by the murderer, and give him a blow familiarly, and in jest, upon which signal be, Kais, might kill him himself, and trust to him for protection against all retaliation from the family. This was agreed upon ; Chidasch betrayed bis uncle by the preconcerted signal; Kais killed him; and when the family threatened vengeance, Chidasch apologised for him, and said he had done nothing more than put bis father's murderer to death. They then set off both together for the province of Heger, or Baharein, on the Persian Gulf, where the murderer of his grandfather dwelt. Chidasch hid himself behind a sandhill, and Kais went up to the murderer, and after complaining to bim that a robber had attacked him among the sandhills, and taken his property from him, requested that he would help him to recover it. According to the prevailing maxims of honour and valour among the Arabs, be could not refuse the stranger's request, and immediately commanded some of his people to attend him. This, however, did not suit Kais's view, whose countenance instantly betrayed the appearance of a smile j and on tbe other asking him why he laughed, replied, " With us no brave man would take so many people to his aid, but would rather come alone." The man was ashamed, and ordered his people back, which was what Kais wanted. And when they got a sight of the pretended robber among the sandhills, and tbe man was about to attack him, Kais stabbed his succourer through the body from behind. And this base and treacherous procedure is immortalised by a poem, which exactly suits the national taste of the Arabs. So completely did the, avengement of blood justify and extol, as brave and honourable, everything which we would account infamous, and characteristic of a ruffian." ^ ^ Commentary oti t'he Laios ofthe Hebrews, Book iii. art. 134. Appendix. 289 This then is another purpose for which a lawful use was assigned to treachery among rude people, viz. the execution of justice. As a means of securing justice and the capture of criminals, treachery was completely and boldly justified ; and Jael's act had a strong alliance with this form and use of treachery. Sisera was a criminal flying from the righteous justice of God; she arrests his flight by false promises, and engages him to accept hospitality within her tent. It is the same dissimulation which the law of Goel adopts, only applied to a different type of criminal. And like the deceit employed under the law of Goel, it is not a general habit of deceit so much as a local habit confined to a special set of circumstances, and justified by the previous obligation to slay. Lecture VIL, Note 7, p. 178. The comparison between an earlier and a later age is pre sented in the case of Lord Clive and bis Indian administration ; and a long contest between two rival principles received a deci sive settlement in English opinion. The great Indian statesman had been under the dominion of the false principle of retaliation, as a just mode of action under the difficulties of Indian admini stration. It seemed necessary to meet fraud by fraud, tbe gross chicanery of the Hindu by counter-trick. Simple honesty appeared but a weak instrument to bring to bear against subtle and inveterate deceit. Was it anything more on the part of an English statesman, than to do justice to himself, when he resisted one flagrant imposition by another ? " All was going well," says Lord Macaulay, " when Clive learned that Omichund was likely to play false. Tbe artful Bengalee had been promised a liberal compensation for all that he had lost at Calcutta. But this would not satisfy him. His services had been great. He held the thread of the whole intrigue. By one word breathed into the ear of Surajah Dowlah, he could undo all that he had done. The lives of Watts, of Meer Jaffier, of all the conspirators, were at his mercy ; and be determined to take advantage of bis situation, and to make bis own terms. He demanded three hun dred thousand pounds sterling as the price of his secrecy and of his assistance. The committee, incensed by the treachery and ap- U 290 Appendix. palled by the danger, knew not what course to take. But Clive was more than Omichund's match in Omichund's own arts. The man, be said, was a villain. Any artifice which would defeat such knavery was justifiable. The best course would be to promise what was asked. Omichund would soon be at their mercy ; and then they might punish him by withholding from him, not only the bribe which he now demanded, but also the compensation which all the other sufferers of Calcutta were to receive. " His advice was taken. But bow was the wary and sagacious Hindu to be deceived ? He had demanded that an article touch ing his claims should be inserted in tbe treaty between Meer Jaffier and the English, and he would not be satisfied unless he saw it with bis own eyes. Clive had an expedient ready. Two treaties were drawn up, one on white paper, the other on red, the former real, the latter fictitious. In the former Omichund's name was not mentioned ; the latter, which was to be shown to him, contained a stipulation in his favour. " But another difficulty arose. Admiral Watson had scruples about signing the red treaty. Omichund's vigilance and acuteness were such that the absence of so important a name would pro bably awaken bis suspicions. But Clive was not a man to do anything by halves. We almost blush to write it. He forged Admiral Watson's name. . . . " The new sovereign was notf called upon to fulfil the engage ments into which he had entered with his allies. A conference was held at the house of Jugget Seit, the great banker, for the purpose of making tbe necessary arrangements. Omichund came thither fully believing himself to stand high in the favour of Clive, who, with dissimulation surpassing even the dissimulation of Bengal, had up to that day treated him witb undiminished kind ness. The white treaty was produced and read. Clive then turned to Mr. Scrafton, one of the servants of the Company, and said in English, 'It is now time to undeceive Omichund.' 'Omichund,' said Mr. Scrafton in Hindostanee, 'the red treaty is a trick. You are to have nothing.' Omichund fell back insen sible into the arms of bis attendants. He revived ; but bis mind was irreparably ruined. Clive, who, though little troubled by scruples of conscience in bis dealings with Indian politicians, was not inhuman, seems to have been touched. He saw Omichund a Appendix. 291 few days later, spoke to him kindly, advised him to make a pil grimage to one of the great temples of India, in the hope that change of scene might restore his health, and was even dis posed, notwithstanding all that had passed, again to employ him in the public service. But from the moment of that sudden shock, the unhappy man sank gradually into idiocy. He, who had formerly been distinguished by the strength of bis under standing and the simplicity of his habits, now squandered tbe remains of his fortune on childish trinkets, and loved to exhibit himself dressed in rich garments, and hung with precious stones. In this abject state he languished a few months, and.then died." ^ This policy bas received a defence from the old school of statesmen, represented by the great statesman who practised it ; but it has been utterly unable to stand its ground before pub lic opinion ; and the verdict of the whole of English thought has been that no amount of Hindu dishonesty is any justification of our own. " That honesty is the best policy," says Lord Macaulay, " is a maxim which we firmly believe to be generally correct, even with respect to the temporal interests of individuals ; but, witb respect to societies, the rule is subject to stiU fewer exceptions, and that for this reason, that the Hfe of societies is longer than the Hfe of individuals. It is possible to mention men who bave owed great worldly prosperity to breaches of private faith. But we doubt whether it be possible to mention a State which has on the whole been a gainer by a breach of public faith. The entire history of British India is an illustration of the great truth that it is not prudent to oppose perfidy to perfidy, and that the most efficient weapon with which men can encounter falsehood is truth. During a long course of years, the English rulers of India, sur rounded by allies and enemies whom no engagement could bind, have generaUy acted witb sincerity and uprightness ; and the event has proved that sincerity and uprightness are wisdom. English valour and English intelligence bave done less to extend and to preserve our Oriental empire than English veracity. All that we could have gained by imitating the doublings, the evasions, tbe fictions, the perjuries which bave been employed against us, is as nothing, when compared with what we bave gained by being the one power in India on whose ,word reUance can be placed. ^ Macaulay's Article on Lord Olive. 292 Appendix. No oath which superstition can devise, no hostage, however precious, inspires a hundredth part of the confidence which is pro duced by the ' yea, yea,' and 'nay, nay,' of a British envoy." ^ Lecture IX., Note 8, p. 201. " I MUST now speak (says Michaelis) of a person quite unknown in our law, but very conspicuous in the Hebrew law, and in regard to whom Moses has left us, I might almost say, an unexampled proof of legislative wisdom. In German, we may call him by the name which Luther so happily employs, in bis version of the Bible, Der Blutracher, the blood-avenger ; and by this name we must here understand ' tbe nearest relation of a person murdered, whose right and duty it was to seek after and kiU the murderer with his own hand ; so much so, indeed, that tbe neglect thereof drew after it the greatest possible infamy, and subjected the man who avenged not the death of bis relation to unceasing reproaches of cowardice or avarice.' If, instead of this description, the reader prefer a short definition, it may be to this effect ; ' the nearest relation of a person murdered, whose right and duty it was to avenge his kinsman's death with his own band.' Among the Hebrews this person was called ?NJ, Goel, according, at least, to the pronunciation adopted from the pointed Bibles. The etymology of this word, like most forensic terms, is as yet unknown. Yet we camiot but be curious to find out whence the Hebrews had derived the name, which tbey appUed to a person so peculiar to their own law, and so totally unknown to ours. Unquestionably the verb fiW, Gaal, means to bwy off, ransom, redeem; but this signification it has derived from tbe noun ; for origin ally it meant to pollute or stain. " If I might here mention a conjecture of my own, Goel of blood (for that is the term at full length) implies blood-stained; and the nearest kinsman of a murdered person was considered as stained with his blood, until he had, as it were, washed away the stain, and revenged the death of his relation. The name, therefore, indicates a person who continued in a state of dishonour, until he again rendered himself honourable, by the exercise and accom- pUshment of revenge ; and in this very light do the Arabs regard ^ Macaulay's Article on Lord Cline. Appendix. 293 the kinsman of a person murdered. It was no doubt afterwards used, in a more extensive sepise, to signify the nearest relation in general, and although there was no murder in the case ; just as in aU languages words are gradually extended far beyond their etymological meaning. ... In Arabic writings, this word occurs ten times for once that we meet witb Goel in Hebrew ; for the Arabs, among whom the point of honour and heroic celebrity consists entirely in the revenge of blood, have much more to say of their blood-avenger than the Hebrews ; among whom, Moses, by the wisdom of bis laws, brought this character, in a great measure, into obUvion " Moses found the Goel already instituted, and speaks of him in his laws as a character perfectly known, and therefore unneces sary to be described; at the same time that be expresses bis fear of bis frequently shedding innocent blood. But long before he has occasion to mention bim as the avenger of murder, he intro duces his name in his laws relative to land, as in Lev. xxv. 25, where he gives him the right of redeeming a mortgaged field. . . " The only book that is possibly more ancient than the Mosaic law, namely the book of Job, compares God, who will re-demand our ashes from the earth, with the Goel, chap. xix. 25. From this term the verb ^JW, which otherwise signifies properly to pollute, had already acquired the significations of redeeming, setting free, vindicating, in which we find Moses often using it, before he ever speaks of tbe blood-avenger, as in Gen. xlviii. 1 5 ; Exod. vi. 6 . . . ; and even re-purchase itself, is, in Lev. xxv. 31, 32, thence termed n?KJ geulla. Derivatives in any language follow their primatives, but very slowly ; and when verba denominativa descend from terms of law, the law itself must be ancient. " . . . . Mahomet endeavoured to mitigate this law, which was often dangerous to innocence ; but unfortunately he began at the wrong end. For, instead of enjoining a previous investigation, that an innocent person might not suffer instead of the guilty, he recommended as an act of mercy, pleasing in the sight of God, the acceptance of a pecuniary compensation from the actual murderer, in lieu of revenge. His words are : ' In cases of murder, retaliation is prescribed to tbe faithful, so that freeman must die for freeman, slave for slave, wife for wife. But when a man's nearest kinsman departs from that right, he has a just 294 Appendix. claim against the murderer for a moderate compensation in money, tbe acceptance of which is an alleviation of the crime in the sight of God, and an act of mercy. But if he afterwards oversteps this rale,' (that is by kiUing the person to whom he has remitted the murder), ' God will punish him severely. For the security of your Uves rests on the right of retaliation.' — (See chap. ii. ofthe Koran, v. 173-176.) " In this strange law, which, in fact, makes the right of retalia tion quite ineffectual to the security of a man's life, because it can be compounded for by the payment of money to his kinsman, Mahomet manifests a much greater opposition to the national maxims of honour than a wise legislator would have done, by representing as merciful, and pleasing to God, a practice which to be sure was not uncommon, but still was deemed base and selfish. . . . But on the principles of sound philosophy, such a transaction is by no means acceptable in the sight of God, who commands murderers to be punished without mercy, that men's lives may be secure ; and an Arab, bred up in the national ideas of honour, must always bave had a stronger inclination to trespass a precept of his religion, thus half left to his option, than to forfeit his honour. I remember a passage of an Arabian poet, who Uved before Mahomet, which describes cowards in the following terms : ' Those who injure tbem they forgive, and to the wicked they repay good for evil : men so pious as they are, God has not created among all the human race besides. But give me the man who, when he mounts his horse or camel, is furious in attacking his enemy.' . . . Now where poems of such a nature express the sentiments of a nation, a precept of false moraUty, recommending mercy and forgiveness in tbe wrong place, could scarcely have much influence, except with a few enthusiasts, who might happen to be among the people, and whose beUef of religion was very ardent. " No doubt, in those countries without the bounds of Arabia, where the people had not the same ideas of honour in avenging blood, and where the Mahomedan religion, which its victorious adherents propagated by the sword, was adopted only from terror, as in Persia for instance, such an admonition might have an influence on the law. Chardin, in his Travels, relates that in that country, when a person is murdered, Ma relations go before Appendix. 295 a court of justice, making a great outcry, and demanding that the murderer be delivered up to them, that they may satiate their revenge ; and that he is accordingly delivered up to tbem by the judge, in these words : ' I give this murderer into your bands ; take satisfaction yourselves for the blood he has shed ; but remember that God is just and merciful ; ' wMch manifestly aUude to tbe two passages above-quoted from the Koran, — the relations may then, if they please, put bim to death, and that in whatever way they think fit. A rich murderer, on the other hand, endeavours to accommodate matters with the relations of the murdered person, and to prevail on them to accept a pecuniary compensation ; and the judge, to whom he also gives money, exhorts them to mercy, that is to be satisfied with such a compensation, although he cannot compel them to accept it." ' ' Michaelis' Commevia/ries on the Lmis of Moses, Book iii. Arts. 131, 184, 136 Printed by R. '& R. Clark, Editiiurgk,