.' ..-.'. ¦.'..' ¦ '¦'•-' ¦ y.':!.'''\ '¦¦¦'¦'¦ ¦ ¦]':} ¦. :" ¦;'->VjVy..-.'i4-)^ . .^— '$99 THE LIBRARY OF BIBLICAL AND THEOLOGICAL LITERATURE. EDITED BY REV. GEORGE R: CROOKS, D.D., LL.D., AND BISHOP JOHN F. HURST, D.D., LL.D. VOL. I. INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURES. By Rev. Henry M. Harman, D.D. $4 00 II. BIBLICAL HERMENEUTICS. By Rev. Milton S. Terry, D.D., LL.D 3 00 III. THEOLOGICAL ENCYCLOPAEDIA AND METH ODOLOGY. By Rev. George R. Crooks, D.D., LL.D., and Bishop John F. Hurst, D.D., LL.D., . 3 50 IV. CHRISTIAN ARCHAEOLOGY. By Rev. Charles W. Bennett, D.D. With an Introductory Notice by Dr. Ferdinand Piper. Revised by Rev. Amos William Patton, D.D., V. SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Vol. I. By Rev. John Miley, D.D., LL.D., 3 00 VI. SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Vol. II. By Rev. John Miley, D.D., LL.D., 3 00 " VII. HISTORY OF THE CHRISTIAN GHURCH. Vol. I. By Bishop John F. Hurst, D.D., LL.D 5 00 " VIII. HISTORY OF THE CHRISTIAN CHURCH. Vol. II. By Bishop John F. Hurst, D.D., LL.D 5 00 IX. THE FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. By Rev. Charles W. Rishell, Ph.D., . 3 50 LIBRARY OF BIBLICAL AND THEOLOGICAL LITERATURE. EDITED BY GEOEGE K. CKOOKS, D.D., AND JOHN F. HUEST, D.D. VOL. IX.-THE FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. NEW YORK: EA TON &• MAINS. CINCINNATI. ¦ CURTS &» JENNINGS. PUBLISHERS' ANNOUNCEMENT. The design of the Publishers and Editors of the Biblical and Theological Ld3rary was declared, before either volume of the series had appeared, to be the furnishing of ministers and laymen with a series of works which should constitute a compen dious apparatus for advanced study on the great fundamental themes of Christian Theology. "While the doctrinal spirit of the separate works was pledged to be in harmony with the accepted standards of the Methodist Episcopal Church, it was promised that the aim should be to make the entire Library acceptable to Chris tians of all evangelical Churches. The following works have already appeared : Harman — Introduction to the Study of the Holy Scrip tures. Terry — Biblical Heemeneutics. Bennett — Christian Archaeology. Miley — Systematic Theology. 2 vols. Crooks and Hurst — Theological Encyclopedia and Meth odology. Hurst — History of the Christian Church. 2 vols. Eishell — Foundations of the Christian Faith. A few other works will follow these, in order to complete the circle of fundamental theological science as originally contem plated by the Publishers and Editors. The reception which has been accorded these works has been so prompt, cordial, and sympathetic that the Publishers are led to beHeve that the Christian public is satisfied that the pledges made at the outset have been faithfully kept. In every treatise in the future, as in those of the past, the latest literature will be recognized and its results incorporated. May we not hope that the same generous favor with which mem bers of all evangelical denominations have regarded the undertak ing from the beginning will be continued throughout the series? THE FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. BY CHARLES W. RISHELL, A.M., Ph.D. Professor of Historical Theology in Boston University School of Theology. NEW YORK : EATON & MAINS. CINCINNATI : CURTS & JENNINGS. Copyright by EATON & MAINS, J899. Eaton & Mains Press, ISO Fifth Avenue, New York. PREFACE. Intelligent adherents of the Christian faith agree that the grounds upon which they accept the teachings of Jesus as fundamental are sat isfactory. On the other hand unbelievers affirm that these basal ele ments of Christian doctrine are untenable and therefore incapable of sustaining the superstructure reared upon them. They deny that God is, or at least that he is what Christians hold him to be ; and also that he is related to man as Christianity represents. They further deny that man is, either in his nature or his destiny, what the Chris tian system assumes. Revelation they regard as delusion, and all the rich record of supposed reUgious truth contained in the Bible as false, and therefore unable to satisfy the normal human heart. They assume that their opinions on the questions in dispute between themselves and us are so well established as to admit of no further argument. It becomes necessary, therefore, to examine the foundations upon which our faith rests, in order to discover whether we are the victims of delusion, or they who reject teachings to us so sacred and true. We owe this examination, not to ourselves alone, but also to the multitude of those who implicitly follow our instructions in the firm belief that we are not blind guides. I have striven to keep in view the fundamentals, that is, those posi tions which, if securely held, provide for the maintenance of the whole Christian contention. By the fundamentals I do not mean what are sometimes figuratively called the citadels of the faith. When all is lost but the citadels these will scarcely be worth defending. It is be lieved that the defense here conducted saves to Christianity its whole domain by holding all the strategic frontier posts the capture of which would result in the devastation of our entire territory. My purpose has not been to give the complete hterature of Christian evidences ; nor to mention all the best books on the subject ; nor all even of those which I consulted in the preparation of this work. Yet in the main my indebtedness to the work of others has been indi cated, and I am not aware of having omitted the mention of any work upon which I depended for information. This opportunity is gladly seized for the expression of my profound sense of obhgation to President Warren, of Boston University, who, at x Preface. various times, gave me valuable suggestions, especially with reference to the books consulted on the general subject of religion, also to Wil liam Marshall Warren, Ph.D., Professor of Philosophy in Boston Uni versity, and to the Rev. George Arthur Wilson, Ph.D., Instructor in Philosophy in Syracuse University. The former went over a part of those chapters which deal with the philosophic assault upon Chris tianity ; the latter read the entire manuscript. To both I am indebted for counsel, the results of which can but render my work at once more complete and useful. My dependence upon the philosophy of Professor Bowne will be apparent from the numerous references to his writings. Throughout this entire work my aim has been to treat thoroughly, yet clearly and helpfully, the questions at issue between faith and un belief. In order to be perfectly just to our opponents I have stated their views and arguments with considerable fullness and as much as possible in their own language. This method enabled me to avoid much abstract discussion and to give concrete instances of all the principles in dispute. At the same time by pursuing this course I have not been prevented from giving a systematic presentation of the subjects under consideration, individually, and in their mutual rela tions as parts of the general scheme. The scope of the work will also be found rather more comprehensive than that attempted in most works on the evidences of Christianity. My hope is that my efforts to refute the arguments of our critics, to confirm the faith of the wavering, and to lead unbelievers to a glad acceptance of the benefits and duties of the Gospel of Christ, may prove helpful in the establishment of the kingdom of God on earth. Boston, Sept. 1, 1899. Charles W. Rishell. TABLE OF CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. PAGE. I. Knowledge, Belief, Faith, and Unbelief 1 1. Knowledge. — Knowing and knowledge defined— Methods of ascertaining reality — Revelation as a mode of ascertaining reality. 2. Belief.— Diffi culty of distinguishing sharply between knowing and believing— Belief defined — Both knowledge and beliefs received on authority — Authority less dangerous to religious than to scientific knowledge and belief. 3. Faith. — Distinction between belief and faith. 4. Unbelief.— Ambiguity In the terms faith, belief, and unbelief. II. Faith and Unbelief as Related to Religion 6 Intellectual character of religious faith — Distinction between unbelief and rejection of Christianity — So-called emotional unbelief is in fact emotional rejection of Christianity — "The will to believe" — Criticism of Professor Clifford's position — Value of a practical decision in the absence of conviction. III. Idea and Method of Evidences. Definition and Discrimination of Terms 12 1. Apology. — Aggressive character of apology. 2. Evidences.— Purpose of evi dences different from apology. 3. Apologetics. — The science of apology. IV. Limitations and Scope of the Subject 13 1. Not to defend any creed. 2. Includes facts essential to proof of a revela tion. 3. Demonstration not required. 4. Must furnish rational basis of belief. 5. Must prevent alienation from Christianity. 6. Must command respect of thoughtful unbelievers. 7. Must aim to lead men to acceptance of Christ as their Saviour. V. Value of Christian Evidences 15 Effectiveness of arguments on the subject of religion — Their design — Evi dences comprehensible by the majority — Seasons why they should be provided. DIVISION I. The Relations of Philosophy and Christianity. Section L — Atheism. CHAPTER I. The Atheism of the Physical Senses 20 First argument of atheism — Philosophers and scientists who believed in the existence of God — The search conducted by Inadequate means — False dis tinction between the natural and the supernatural— Folly of the atheistic argument from the regularity of nature. XI xii Table of Contents. chapter II. PAGE The Materialistic Denial of the Soul 24 The second argument of atheism — Strecker's definition of materialism — Buchner's evasion of the question of matter— Damaging admissions of materialists — Views of Du Bois-Reymond. CHAPTER III. The Dispute Between Du Bois-Retmond and Haeckbl 28 Supposed astronomical knowledge of the brain — No causal connection be tween brain-movements and consciousness — Haeckel's reply to Du Bois- Reymond — Haeckel's scornful language no argument. CHAPTER IV. Refutation op the Materialistic Pstchologt 33 Chasm between mental and material phenomena — Haeckel's identification of thought and energy — Man as a conscious automaton — Uselessness of thought in materialistic theory — Materialistic denial of freedom — Con fusion of thought arising from materialism — Materialism destroys the validity of thought— And also its significance. CHAPTER V. The Materialistic Denial of God 39 Difficulty of materialism with matter and motion — Supposition of matter eternally in motion — Difficulty of Intelligence In the world — Human think ing demands a God. CHAPTER VI. The Alleged Imperfections op the World and Intelligence nf Crea tion 45 Third argument of atheism— Presupposes a finished world — Argument from analogy — Martineau's answer — Value of alleged useless provisions of nature — Helmholtz on the human eye — Darwin on the sting of the bee — Excessive fecundity of animals— Proved to be untrue— Lange's criticism of the birth-law of species answered — The law of death defended — Atheistic argument from imperfections popular but without force. Section IL,— Agnosticism. CHAPTER I. The Agnosticism of Huxlet as a Practical System 53 Huxley's definition of the word — Slight difference between agnostic and atheistic position — Agnosticism a method of investigation — Based on a creed — Further characterization of agnosticism — Agnosticism not content to remain in Ignorance — Results reached by agnostic method — Closely re semble a creed negative of Christianity— Fallibility of the individual reason — Agnostic principle unscientific. CHAPTER II. Huxley's Deceptive Terminology 60 Huxley on faith and ratiocination— His denial of " pressure " in religion — We act in common life without pressure of a mercenary kind — Suggestion of a more accurate nomenclature — Agnosticism based on a false philos ophy. Table of Contents. xiii chapter iii. PAGE The Philosophic Basis of Huxleyan Agnosticism — The Philosophy of Hume 64 Ideas and impressions distinguished — The representational theory — Inference from cause and effect. CHAPTER IV. Criticism of Hume's Agnostic Principles 68 Complexity of Hume's so-called impressions — The activity of the mind in con nection with them — The mind's activity examined — Ideas not reducible to Humian impressions — Origin of ideas — The mind's contribution to knowl edge — Origin of the Idea of God according to Hume. CHAPTER V. Hume's Theory of Knowledge and of the Causal Relation 74 The representational theory no solution of the problem of knowledge — Origin of the idea of causal relation— The idea of force not a deception — Further answer to Hume's skepticism — Relation of the discussion to doctrine of creation — Hume's doctrine of mental limitation refuted — Conclusion. CHAPTER VI. The Philosophy of Kant as a Basis for Agnosticism - 80 Knowledge as related to experience — Kant's three transcendental ideas — Cannot be proved either real or unreal — Reaction from this extreme skepti cism — Findings of the Critiques of Practical Reason and of the Judgment — No philosophic basis for Huxleyan agnosticism. CHAPTER VII. The Agnosticism of Herbert Spencer as a Practical System 85 Primary purpose of Spencer's philosophy — Validity of religious belief — Inade quacy of symbolic conceptions of religion — The existence of the absolute a necessary assumption — Prevailing religious beliefs should not be too sud denly changed — Spencer's divergence from Huxley. CHAPTER VIII. Spencer's Philosophy of the Unknowable 90 Unknowableness of the reality behind appearances— Spencer's confusion of two distinct propositions — His faith sufficient for action — What is meant by the established limits of our intelligence f CHAPTER IX. Spencer on the Divine Personality 94 Denial of God's personality— Argument for something higher than personality in God— Why we attribute personality to God— What God may be besides personal we do not know — No certainty that Spencer's idea of God is the most definite possible — Spencer's recoil from the consequences of his argu ment — His unreasonable demand — Universal skepticism. Section HL. — Pantheism (Monism). CHAPTER I. Pantheism in its Older Forms 99 Pantheism of Averroes and Spinoza distinguished— Spinoza on the finite and the infinite mind— Denial of personality to the infinite— Suspicious source of this idea of God— Objections to pantheistic view— Confusion arising from pantheistic theory. xrv Table of Contents. CHAPTER II. PAGE Pantheism in the Form op Monism 104 In what sense monism is pantheistic — Prevalence of monism in Christian thought— Reason for its rejection of dualism— Romanes's argument against mind as a cause of motion in matter — One form of his argument examined— Hoffding on change of direction in physical movement— The real difficulty not stated by Romanes— His assertion of the impossibility of intervention from without— Romanes turned against himself — Would intervention from without destroy the order of nature ? — The answer depends upon the mean ing of the term " order of nature." CHAPTER III. The Idealistic-Monistic Psychology 112 Two classes of monists— HSffding's reasons for holding to monism in psychol ogy—First reason— Second reason — Third reason — Dualism a better explana tion than monism of the concomitant brain and mental activity — Heading's illustration examined — Physiology opposes dualism. CHAPTER IV. The Materialistic-Monistic Psychology 116 Forel and Haeckel as materialistic monists — Atom and cell souls — Forel on con sciousness and soul — The soul as a function of the brain — Forel' s description of sensation and other mental phenomena — Criticism of the above account — Relation of brain condition to mental activity. CHAPTER V. The Monistic Psychology op Haeckel 121 Haeckel not a philosopher — Hoffding the philosopher versus Haeckel the sci entist — Further evidence of their disagreement — Monism fails to provide for consciousness of personal unity — For freedom of the will — For freedom of thought — And for immortality of the individual — Failure of monism to escape dualism. CHAPTER VI. Monistic Theology 126 Three chief characteristics of monistic theology — Monistic proof of God's ex istence — The sole attribute of the God of monism — Feelings necessarily ex cluded from monistic piety — The feelings it allows not distinctively religious — Theological inconsistency of monism — Wider range of feelings in theistic belief — Failure of monism in aesthetics. CHAPTER VII. Monism as a Cosmological Theory 132 Double misunderstanding of Christianity by monists — Monistic cosmology — The world a numerical unit — And involves also qualitative unity — Qualita tive oneness admits of no grades — No distinction in kind between man and animal — Our mental faculties our only means for construing the world — Dualism regards the world as an aggregate— In the world of matter also there is multiplicity, not unity— Qualitative diversity in the physical world. CHAPTER VIII. The Monistic Negation of God's Personality 140 Monism metaphysics, not science— Grounds for monistic denial of personality of God— Defense of Christianity against Imputations of monists— Haeckel' s objection to the doctrine of personality in God — His scientific dogmatism — And profound ignorance of the teachings of Christianity. XABLE OF CONTENTS. XV CHAPTER IX. PAGE Concluding Criticism of Monism 145 Real doctrine as to God and man in Christian teaching — Further statement of the difference — Inconsistency of monism in attempting to define God — Also its absurdity — Practical abandonment of monism by monists— Inadequacy of the dualism of monism — Are this ether-spirit and the atom-soul the same in kind f Section IV. — Deism. CHAPTER I. Deism Versus Religion 149 Deism, pantheism, and Christianity — Deism in modern thought — Evidence of deistic tendency in apologetic literature — Effect is to destroy prayer— Equally dangerous to the ethical side of religion — Frohschammer's doctrine of res ignation — Steude's reply. CHAPTER II. The Christian and Deistic Conceptions op God's Relation to the World 154 Wallace on the exalted character of the deistic conception of God — Wallace's assertions denied — His own admissions — Deism makes God content with the world — And gives him nothing to do — Deism and evolution incapable of being united in thought. DIVISION II. Scientists and Theologians in Conflict. Section L — Scientific Agnosticism. CHAPTER I. Christianity and Scientific Research 158 Valuelessness of the argument from the opinion of scientific men — The re lation of the clergy to scientific thought — Christians should not oppose or fear scientific research — True attitude of the clergy toward science — Scien tists' confession of their own faults — Language of Mr. Spencer. CHAPTER II. The Method op Acquiring Theological Knowledge 163 Haeckel's doctrine that all science is physical — The study of history refutes his view — Diverse phenomena demand diverse methods of investigation — Conflict between theology and scientists unnecessary — Diverse methods may be equally valuable — Wrong methods sometimes employed by theologians- Exactness of modern theological methods. CHAPTER III. Belief in Miracle is Evidence of a Wrong Method 168 Scientists who affect the role of philosophy — Andresen and Dahl cited— Bowne on the subject of method — Unscientific procedure of some scientists. xvi Table of Contents. CHAPTER IV. PAGE The Objects op Theological Knowledge 172 False assumptions of certain scientists — Monism and Christianity as supersti tion — Assumptions of theologians and scientists — Dispute between theolo gians and scientists as to ownership of facts — Faith employed both in sci ence and theology — Parallel between scientific and theological practical procedure — The parallel carried further — Strecker on scientific articles of faith — Also Huxley and Haeckel. CHAPTER V. Articles op Faith in Theology and Science 179 Haeckel's assertion against religious dogmas — First part of his argument for belief in God — Second part — Biichner on articles of religious faith — Spencer on limitations of scientific knowledge— Wagner and Rosanes— Articles of faith justifiable in science and theology. Section IL — Scientific and Theological Theories of the Relation of God to Creation and Providence. CHAPTER I. God and Creation 185 Creation not a problem for science — Scientists do not generally deny the agen cy of God in creation — Darwin's position — Why they have been understood to deny the divine agency — Conclusions of natural philosophy not war ranted by science — Can the teachings of modern science and of Genesis be reconciled ? CHAPTER II. The Science op the Bible 190 Are the scientific utterances of the Bible of fundamental importance » — The essence of the Scripture account of creation to be found in its religious as pect; — Haeckel's concession as to the science of Genesis — Horton on the superiority of the Mosaic cosmogony — Necessity of observing the true lim its of science — The evolutionary method of creation not unworthy — Distinc tion between man and beast as noted in the Bible. CHAPTER HI. Necessity of Miracle to Religion 198 The assault of science directed against miracle — Disadvantages connected with giving up belief in miraculous interventions — First disadvantage — Second disadvantage. CHAPTER TV. The Inadequacy of the Mechanical Theory 202 Mechanical theory inadequate to the explanation of phenomena known to sci ence—Summary of the argument by Wallace. CHAPTER V. Breaks in the Progress op Material Development 206 President Schurman on the survival of the fittest— Evolutionists Ignore, minify, or invent facts— Life a break in the continuity of development — Wallace's theory of the nature of the intelligence which guided man's development examined. AAUi,*; vss CONTENTS. XVII CHAPTER VI. PAGE SCIENCE AND THE MIRACLES OP THE NEW TESTAMENT 212 The New Testament idea of a miracle— Do the New Testament writers regard miracles as violations of the laws of nature ? — Errors arising from the at tempt to define too exactly the relation of each miracle to natural law — Re lation of our knowledge of nature to the fact of miracle — Alleged unknown or higher laws according to which miracles might be performed. CHAPTER VH. Laws of Nature and Divine Intervention 219 Human analogies to divine interventions — Lack of uniformity in certain de partments of nature— Relation of the doctrine of conservation of energy to the possibility of miracle — Can an unembodied spirit affect matter ? — Professor Bowne's criticism of realism. division m. Christianity and Modern Historical Science. Section L — The Opposition to Miracles. CHAPTER I. Modern Exclusion of the Supernatural prom History 226 Denial of miracle by modern historians — The excessive credulity of many rela tive to miracles — Chief difficulty relates to evidence — Hume's statement crit icised — Testimony sufficient to establish the New Testament miracles might be possible — And such testimony is furnished by Jesus Christ. CHAPTER II. The Alleged Thaumaturgic Element in the Miracles of Christ 231 Wellhausen, Renan, and Strauss — Renan's falsification of the record — The proof that Jesus was not a thaumaturgist — Renan's theory makes Jesus dis honest. CHAPTER III. Renan's Attempted Degradation of the Miracles of Jesus 235 The delusion of Renan— Renan's unhistorical procedure— His degradation of the character and of the works of Jesus— His estimate of the record by Mark— Contrast between the miracles of the apocryphal and those of the canonical gospels— Conclusion. CHAPTER IV. Miracles as Unusual Events 34° The unusual character of the miracles as a cause of doubt— Hume's misstate ment of the law of evidence— Unusual and solitary events in the natural world— Their significance for the claims of Jesus. CHAPTER V. Credulity as a Ground for the Rejection op Miracles 243 The tendency to the belief of the marvelous as an occasion of doubt— The love of the marvelous checked by the love of truth— Hume's apparent concep tion of the spirit of religion inapplicable even if true— The caution of the writers of the gospels in accepting accounts of miracles. 2 xvm Table of Contents. CHAPTER VI. PAGE The Prevalence op Miracle Stories 249 Doubts arising from the alleged ignorance and barbarism of the nations among whom miracles are said to have occurred — Because the miracle stories of the New Testament were written by unschooled men they must be received as true — Argument from the presence of miracle stories in all religions— Christian miracles introduced a new order into the world— Argu ment from the frequent violations of truth considered— And in particular its application to testimony concerning religious miracles. CHAPTER VII. Christian and Skeptical Requisites to Faith in Miracles 254 Renan' s requisites for the belief of miracle— These requisites not as rigid as those demanded by the Christian— Points which the Christian would add to Renan's requirements. CHAPTER VIII. Biblical and Nonbiblical Miracles 259 Limits as to the acceptance of miracles recorded in the New Testament — The superior dignity of the New Testament miracles — Examples of nonscrip- tural miracles— Superior motives of the New Testament miracles — Also their superior attestation. SecMon LL— The Criticism of the New Testament Records. CHAPTER I. Strauss's Mythical Theory op the Gospel Records 265 Many who still accept the theory — Strauss's rejection of the miraculous in history considered — Why the miracles of Jesus were not more frequently alluded to, in apostolic preaching and teaching — The mythical theory stated. CHAPTER II. Criticism of the Mythical Theory 270 The identification of Jesus as the Messiah unaccountable on the theory of Strauss — Our knowledge of the character of Jesus largely dependent upon the miracle stories — Further difficulties connected with the mythical theory. CHAPTER III. Trustworthiness of the Gospel Records 273 Harnack on the New Testament Records— Dates given by Jalicher and Weiss —Harnack on the credibility of the gospels — Difference between the criticism of the literary critic and that of the historian — Julicher on the trustworthi ness of the synoptic gospels. Section ILL — Christianity as a Factor in Human Progress. The growth of Christianity in numbers — And in its influence upon public opinion and private life — Why Christianity has not been more effective in transforming the world — Effect of unbelief in checking the uplifting influ ence of Christianity — History shows that Christianity has advanced science and material progress 278 Table of Contents. xix DIVISION IV. The Struggle of Christianity with Antichristian Ethics. Section I. — Proposed Substitutes for Christian Ethics. CHAPTER I. PAGE Atheistic Egoism 283 Strecker's statement of this ethics — Its practical eflect — Strecker not misun derstood nor misrepresented — Relation of this view to the social organism — This system compared with the teachings of Jesus. CHAPTER II. The German Ethical Culturists 287 Gizycki's statement of the ethics of ethical culture — Its principal fault the denial of the value of an external authority — The impracticability of the common weal as a means of determining what is right — The sole content of the moral law not self-imposed. CHAPTER III. The Ethics op Monism 291 Hoffding admits the profound historical significance of external authority — But denies that it is the complete foundation of ethics— The monistic ethics also based on external authority — But its authority is Inadequate — What does Hoffding mean by relative authority ? CHAPTER IV. Criticism op Antichristian Ethical Systems 296 The fatalism of antichristian systems of ethics— Obliteration of the distinction between good and evil — Carneri and other monists on truthfulness — Advan tages of a fixed ideal standard — Morality a means, not a goal, in evolution ary ethics — Inconsistent and inadequate motives of non-Christian systems —Conclusion. Section IL — Objections to Christian Ethics. CHAPTER I. Christian Ethics and External Authority 304 Nature of ethical authority in Christianity — The relations of love and faith in the Christian system— Hoffding's misconceptions of Christianity — The ne cessity of positive as distinguished from ethical requirements. CHAPTER II. The Ascertainability op God's Will 309 Gizycki on the difficulty of ascertaining the will of God— His difficulty imagi nary — Is the knowledge of revealed morality dependent upon a previous knowledge of the ethically good ?— Not knowledge merely, but also motives needed. xx Table of Contents. CHAPTER HI. page Originality op Christ's Law of Love— Rewards and Punishments 312 Testimony to the originality of Jesus— Love as taught by Christ and by others— Nature of the love required by Christ^-His law not comprehended by its critics— Rewards and punishments in Christian ethics. CHAPTER IV. Need of Divine Aid— Practicability of Christian Ethics 316 Divine aid needed in right living— Its benefits proved by history— Are the de mands of Christ impracticable ?— Are they incomplete ?— Jesus's method with intellectual honesty, slavery, and political economy. CHAPTER V. Incidental Objections to Christian Morals 322 Necessity for caution among Christian writers — Alleged immorality of the Christian doctrine of atonement— Is forgiveness of sins dangerous ?— Prayer — Providence — Nearness to God and nearness to men — Christianity and the suffering classes. DIVISION V. Christianity and Opposing Religious Theories. Importance of treating such systems as Theosophy, Christian Science, etc. Section L — Proposed Substitutes for Christianity. CHAPTER I. Positivism, or the Religion op Humanity 328 Comte's misunderstanding of Christianity — Rigidity of Positive religion — Pos itivism and the priestly class — The Supreme Being of Positivism — Positivism an atheistic system — Superiority of Jesus, as an ideal, to the ideal of Posi tivism. CHAPTER H. Worship in Positivism 335 Comte's alleged three stages of theoretical conceptions — Absurdity of the Pos- itivist object of worship — Positivism and prayer — The religion of deception —Artificiality of Positivism. CHAPTER III. Ethical Culture— Its Misrepresentations op Christianity 339 Relation of ethical culture to Christianity — Salter's first misrepresentation of Christianity — His second misrepresentation — Third misrepresentation — Fourth misrepresentation— Fifth misrepresentation. CHAPTER IV. Inadequacy of Ethical Culture to the Purposes op a Religion 346 Narrowness of application of ethical culture— Severity of the righteousness inculcated by ethical culture — Attractiveness of righteousness — Lack of an external standard of authority — Ethical culture offers no adequate check to human selfishness. Table of Contents. xxi chapter v. PAGE Theosophy — Exhibition of its Speculative Character 351 Relation of Theosophy to Christianity — Exoteric and esoteric doctrines — Plan of theosophic salvation— Unpractical character of Theosophy— Citations from the Epitome. CHAPTER VI. Theosophy — Its Inferiority to Christianity 356 The doctrine of Karma and the Christian doctrine of retribution — Aim of The osophy — Its demands upon our credulity— Its fatalism — The miracles of Jesus and the alleged marvels of Theosophy compared. CHAPTER VII. Christian Science— Statement and Criticism 360 Scant use of the words and deeds of Jesus by Christian Scientists — The prom inence it gives to bodily healing— Its false metaphysics— Citations from Mrs. Eddy — Her anthropology — Her doctrine of evil — Her philosophy of the plan of salvation. CHAPTER VIII. Christian Science Contrasted with Christianity 367 First contrast between Christianity and Christian Science — Second contrast — Third contrast — Fourth contrast — Inapplicability to life as a whole — Its neg ative ethics. Section IL — Objections to Christianity Drawn from Religious Considerations. First theological objection — Second theological objection— First practical ob jection — Second practical objection — Objection to the Christian doctrine of sin 370 Review op Results to this Point 372 Great value of the indirect evidences — Necessity and nature of the positive evi dences. DIVISION VI. The Doctrines Concerning Man. Section L — The Spiritual Nature of Man. CHAPTER I. Reasons for the Christian Belief 375 The meagerness of New Testament psychology— Obligations growing out of our faith — The Christian doctrine alone explains the phenomena of the men tal life — The universality of the belief in the soul. CHAPTER II. Validity op the Christian Idea of the Soul -. 380 Tylor's theory of animism examined — Capacities of primitive men — Thought must be the product of something immaterial— Consideration of Paulsen's views — Nature of the soul no more indefinable than matter. xxn Table of Contents. CHAPTER III. PAGE The Personality op Man and his Superiority to the Brutes. 384 The Christian position— Haeckel's denial of distinction between man and beast criticised — Romanes on mind in man and beast — Sameness of origin com patible with difference in kind — His error here vitiates his reasoning. CHAPTER IV. Man's Personal Superiority to the Brute — Romanes 389 Estimate placed on self-consciousness — Romanes's incorrect definition of self- consciousness — Perceptual, receptual, and conceptual faculties — His sub sidiary considerations— He makes the distinction while denying it. Section IL — The Immortality of the Soul. CHAPTER I. Man's Capacity for Immortality 394 The question of conditional immortality left to polemics — The capability of the soul for immortality — The soul-life independent of the brain — Weakness of argument against immortality. CHAPTER n. Grounds for the Belief in Human Immortality 399 Man's rank in creation as an argument for immortality — John Fiske on man as the chief of God's creatures — Ascription of folly to the Creator — George Eliot's impersonal immortality immortality only in name. CHAPTER III. Presumptions in Favor of Immortality 404 The argument from the insufficiency of time for man's development — The same applied to the moral nature — The argument from the demands of jus tice—The presumptions all in favor of immortality, and they are very pow erful. Section HI.— The Origin of Human Sin. CHAPTER I. Examination of the non-Christian View 408 Man, not God, responsible for sin— John Fiske's statement of the evolutionary origin of sin — The doctrine of the brute origin of man challenged — The alleged great antiquity of man— Lack of existing remains to prove man's brute origin. CHAPTER II. The Fall of Man 413 The argument from analogy is against the brute origin of man— Facts show ing the great improbability that man sprang from the brutes — The evidence as to man's primitive condition — Man's present moral sentiments as proving the fact of a fall. Table of Contents. xxiii division vn. The Doctrines Concerning God. Section L — The Existence of God. CHAPTER I. PAGE Necessity, Universality, and Persistence of the Belief 420 First reason for believing in the existence of God — Herbert Spencer quoted — Second reason for the belief — Moral and intellectual superiority of those who believe — The only valuable form of the ontological argument. CHAPTER II. The Argument prom Design 424 The source of the idea as augmenting the force of the ontological argument — The argument from design stated — Romanes's argument against design examined — At most his argument proves only a process by fixed laws. CHAPTER III. Inadequacy op the Process of Natural Selection 438 The fatal flaw in his reasoning concerning the eye — Natural selection works destructively, not constructively— Four points to be considered — Impos sibility of stating the doctrine of natural selection except in terms of tele ology — Citation from Professor Bowne. Section IL — The Personality of God. CHAPTER I. The Personality op God Ascertainable 433 Unity of God conceded — Trinity left to systematic theology — Our knowledge of God partial — Treatment of the first obstacle to belief In God's personal ity — Fallacy of Hamilton's reasoning pointed out — Spencer's criticism of Hamilton's position. CHAPTER n. False Assumptions of Denial 437 Mansel and the second obstacle — Mansel's erroneous definition of terms — The third obstacle — The denial is based on a material conception of God — Bearing of the doctrine of the Trinity on the question. CHAPTER III. Erroneous Conceptions of Personality — The Theories of Schopenhauer and Von Hartmann 442 Mansel's denial of our right, in thought, to regard God as personal— Professor Bowne on the objections to the personality of God — The positions of Schop enhauer and Von Hartmann— Martineau's criticism— Intrinsic absurdity of their views — Their denial of freedom. CHAPTER IV. The Argument for Personality 447 Naturalness of the belief in the personality of God— Is the belief legitimate also ? — Justifiability of our spontaneous thinking— Our personality carries with it the personality of God — Our religious natures demand that God be personal— So also our intellects— Parallel between creative and human in telligence. xxiv Table of Contents. DIVISION Vffl. Revelation. Section L— The Nature and Fact of Supernatural Revelation. CHAPTER I. PAGE The Possibility op a Revelation 453 God not the only object of revelation — Revelation not given in propositions alone — The allegation that God cannot reveal himself — Special revelation to a single people — Doctrine of a purposed as distinguished from an inci dental revelation. CHAPTER II. Human Capacity and Need 457 Is man capable of receiving a revelation from God ? — Purpose of revelation — Man's need of a divine revelation — Perplexity of the primitive man as to his religious feeling and its gratification. CHAPTER HI. Primitive Revelation 461 Improbability that God would leave man uninstructed — Probability in pro portion to the necessity and possibility — The insignificance of the earth as an objection to a purposed revelation — Why a further revelation was neces sary. CHAPTER IV. Natural Revelation 465 Revelatory significance of nature — Further reasons for the belief that man needed a special revelation — Agreement of theologians as to the principal teachings of the Bible — The perversity of nature and of history forbids that it should reveal God. CHAPTER V. The Biblical Revelation 469 The real purpose of the revelation contained in the Bible — The Bible the record of a revelation progressively bestowed — Human misunderstandings of revealed facts — At each stage of progress the revelation was in advance of human attainment. CHAPTER VI. Limitations and Effect op the Old Testament Revelation 473 The superior claims of the biblical revelation— Mill on the apparent partiality of God for the Jews — The Jews well adapted to become the recipients of a reve lation from God— Preparation of other nations for the reception of the Gospel— Incompleteness of the revelation of the Old Testament— Its falli bility asserted in the New Testament— To the Christian the truth of Christ is the criterion— The Old Testament accomplished its purpose — Superiority, in some respects, of the Old Testament. Section n.—Christ the Chief Source of Revelation. CHAPTER I. The Doctrine op Inspiration 480 The men, not the writings, inspired— Summary of Bishop Butler's views as to a priori estimates of inspiration— The obligation of caution— The infalibility of the New Testament not essential to faith in the truth It contains— The real advantages of inspiration. Table of Consents. xxv chapter II. PAGE The Fact op Inspiration 486 First reason for believing that the writers of the New Testament were in spired — The desirability of such inspiration — Some New Testament writers claimed inspiration — Superiority of the New Testament to all other religious literature. CHAPTER III. The Claims of Christ— His Premundane Existence 490 His premundane existence claimed — John's gospel furnishes most of the alleged utterances of Jesus regarding himself — The objection that preexist- ence was attributed to all important objects — Examination of passages upon which the doctrine of Christ's premundane existence depends. CHAPTER IV. Other Claims Made by Christ 495 The right to forgive sins — Jesus's unique power over the consciences of men — His relation to the kingdom of God — His claim of equality, if not of identity, with the Father. Section ILL — The Validity of Christ's Claims.— The Evidence from His Character. CHAPTER I. His Humility and Sinlessness 498 The humility and unselfishness of Jesus — Argumentative importance of Christ's assertion of sinlessness — His conception of sinlessness — Agree ment between the synoptists and John — The opinions of his friends. CHAPTER II. Alleged Sins of Jesus 502 First argument against his sinlessness considered— Examination of specific sins charged by the Jews — Alleged record of sinful deeds and words in vestigated. CHAPTER III. Objections to the Doctrine of Sinlessness 509 Did Jesus deny moral goodness of himself ? — The objection that perfect sinlessness is impossible to man — Relation of temptation to sin — The allegation that he must have been imperfect in his childhood— Moral de velopment does not necessarily imply previous sinfulness — Significance of the fact. Section IV. — The Miracles as Evidence of the Validity of Christ's Claims. CHAPTER I. The Evidential Value of the Gospel Miracles 514 Are the miracles a burden to our faith ? — Reasons not discoverable for deny ing the reports of Jesus's miracles — The attempt to explain the miracles of Jesus without the supposition of special divine aid— Miracles involving control over forces of nature. xxvi Table* of Contents. CHAPTER II. PAGE Special Divine Aid in the Miracles of Jesus 518 The superiority of Jesus's miracles an argument for the divine aid in their performance— Other considerations— The question of a sufficient occasion for the divine intervention— Order of nature properly interfered with for such results— Conclusion. Section V.— The Resurrection of Jesus and the Validity of His Claims. CHAPTER I. The Theory of apparent Death 523 Miracles wrought upon Jesus — Distinction between his resurrection and his raisings from the dead— Rationalistic denial of the actual death of Jesus — A second theory. CHAPTER II. Untenability op the Theory op Apparent Death 527 Inherent improbabilities of the theory — Strauss's and Keim's criticisms — A principal basis of the theory is mere assertion — No reason for questioning the fact of his death — Jews and Romans combined to prevent mistake as to his death. CHAPTER III. The Vision Hypothesis — Strauss 531 Something took place to alter the feelings of the disciples — Strauss's earlier theory — Theory of reflection and consequent vision — The theory criticised — Its abandonment by Strauss. CHAPTER TV. The Theory of Renan 535 Summary of Renan's hypotheses— Weakness of his position — Impossibility that his suppositions should be real — His violation of the record — Renan's theory fails to account for the faith of the early Christians. CHAPTER V. General Defects op the Vision Hypothesis 540 The dreams of Mohammed and the resurrection of Jesus as springs of reli gious action— Examination of alleged parallels to the supposed visions of the early disciples — Blindness of the theorists to the defects of their argumenta tion — If an illusion it was one both of sight and hearing. CHAPTER VI. The Theory of a Divinely Wrought Vision 544 Keim's plausible statement — The theory preserves the supernatural — The ques tion one of fact, not of faith— First difficulty — Second difficulty. CHAPTER VII. Paul and the Resurrection of Jesus — Other Considerations 548 Did Paul see Jesus as the primitive apostles saw him f — Significance of 1 Cor. xv, 3-8— The argument from the empty grave— Keim's attempted reply. Table of Contents. xxvii chapter VIII. PAGE Alleged Contradictions in the Records — Recapitulation 555 Universal belief of the early Church— Modern instances of discrepant reports in which the main fact is not denied— The fact of the resurrection a necessity to Christian faith — Recapitulation of the argument for a genuine divine revelation. Section VL— The Superiority of the Christian Revelation. CHAPTER I. Christianity and Buddhism 559 First point of comparison— Second point— The main fact in Buddhism is temporal evil — Buddhism seeks redemption from suffering ; Christianity from sin — The Buddhist and Christian saint compared. CHAPTER II. Christianity and Mohammedanism 566 The idea of God in Mohammedanism and in Christianity — Mohammedanism and polygamy — Mohammedan theory and practice of divorce — Total absti nence from intoxicants — Practical results of the Christian system. Section VO. — Christianity the Final Revelation. CHAPTER I. Its Satisfactory Conception of God and of Man 572 The exalted religious conceptions of Christianity prove it the final religion — The needs of the human heart perfectly met by the Christian doctrine of God. CHAPTER II. The Threefold Satisfaction of the Conscience 577 The conscience demands a perfect moral standard — Release from the burden ing sense of guilt — Pardon cannot be safely bestowed as the act of a sover eign will — Christian system does not minify sin — The human condition of pardon. CHAPTER III. Christianity and the Problem of Temporal Evil 582 Its doctrine of a future life as affecting earthly happiness— Its emphasis on the joys of the soul — All Christians incited to labor for the betterment of human conditions on earth— Its doctrine of the future life as satisfying human longings. CHAPTER IV. Christianity and Human Progress 585 Material progress most advanced in Christian lands — Limits to the demands upon religion — Christianity makes men successful in business — Encourages the study of nature — Impels to the pursuit of education and culture— Its spirit of freedom. xxviii Table of Contents. Section VuX— The Experimental Test. CHAPTER I. PAGE The Discoveries Reached by this Test 589 The facts of Christian experience capable of classification and examination— To decline the experimental method with Christianity is to proceed unscien tifically — Christianity capable of scientific verification — What God's will is— And what is meant by willing to do it — The conditions of the experiment within the reach of all — The first effect of the experiment is to convince us that we are sinful— The second discovery is that by faith we are saved. CHAPTER II. Christian Experiences Divinely Wrought 595 The suggestion that all the foregoing is true, but naturally, not divinely wrought — Four reasons for rejecting the suggestion just mentioned — Experiences which increase the certainty gained by the earlier experiments — Improba bility that so many intelligent persons should misread the source of their experience. CHAPTER III. The Experimental Test and the Future Life — Final Summary and Ap- pbal to Unbelievers 600 The limitations of this method — The experimental method lends additional support even to the doctrine of the future life — Summary of the entire result of the study now concluded — Appeal to unbelievers to cease opposition and to lend their aid. INTRODUCTION. As long as human hearts are sinful and human intellects liable to deception the difficulties in the way of the universal acceptance of Christianity arising from passive and active unbelief will continue. It is the design of this work to remove, as far as possible, these obstacles from the path of Christian progress. A study of them must, therefore, first engage our attention. This can be best conducted by a comparison of certain phases of faith and unbelief. We shall endeavor, first of all, to differentiate a number of words which, though in constant use, are frequently misemployed. I. KNOWLEDGE, BELIEF, FAITH, AND UNBELIEF. 1. Knowledge. In general, knowledge may be described as the sum of our cogni tions. In knowledge each cognition must be of something real, and the reality must be correctly conceived. Denned in terms Knowing and knowledge of the mental acts involved, knowing is the double mental defined. process of determining what is real and forming correct conceptions of the real. These two processes, however, while logically distinguished, are so interwoven, in the act of knowing that they may be said to go forward together, and mutually to aid each other. The process need not be wholly performed by the possessor of knowledge, since others may determine for us what is real ; but in order to know we must at least correctly conceive the real. The result of the process is knowl edge, which may be defined as the correct conception of that which has been determined to be real. Since we know only that which has been found real, it follows that to ascertain what is real is the first important element in the process of knowing. It is this which distinguishes knowledge from Methods o f SLSCsrtniii- surmise. But the ascertainment of the real may proceed ing reality. by several different methods : (1) by intuition ; (2) by demonstration ; (3) by revelation ; (4) by experience ; (5) by combinations of the pre ceding methods. Intuition gives us self-evident truths; demonstra tion furnishes us secondary truths ; revelation includes all communi cated truth, of which a divine communication would be but a single 2 Introduction. item ; experience is the result of voluntary or involuntary experiment, and furnishes us with many of our primary cognitions ; while as an illustration of the combinations possible we may mention the testing by personal experiment of facts revealed to us by others, thereby affording a double assurance of reality. Each of these modes of putting the mind into possession of correct concepts of reality has its own specific advantages in the various fields of research. For example, intuition and demonstration are peculiarly valuable in mathematics; experience (experiment) in the physical sciences, psychology, and religion ; revelation in religion and history. It is customary to think of revelation as an inferior mode of ascer taining reality. But it should be remembered that none of the modes Revelation as mentioned above can be employed without challenge. ascertain- While we cannot demonstrate an axiom, we still put to ing rea y. pgj^^ tesjg every proposition offered to us as self-evident. We do not accept as demonstration everything that passes under that name. We test alleged demonstrations even in mathematics, and even then we confirm our faith by the fact that thousands of others have tested them also, and that all agree to their soundness. Experi ences, physical or mental, have to be examined with critical care to avoid deception. No more can be said of revelation, the principal caution in connection with which is that it be tested by those who are skilled in the methods of preventing such deceptions as may arise in its employment. We are just as well assured that the American Revolution is a fact as we are that the sum of the angles of any tri angle is equal to two right angles, though the one fact is given us solely by revelation and the other by mathematical demonstration. Indeed, much of our knowledge would at once disappear should we lose all that has come to us by revelation. All the history of the re moter past would be gone from every mind, as also most of what the students in our schools and colleges and the masses of the people know about science and other departments of learning. The question is thus seen to concern not the value of revelation as a means of putting us into possession of conceptions of reality, but the possibility and actuality of divine revelation. This it is no part of our plan to discuss here. Our only purpose at present is to show that revelation is a reli able method of ascertaining reality. 2. Belief. There is no well-defined line of demarcation between knowing and believing. This is true whether we consider the use of the words, even INTRODUCTION. 3 by careful writers,1 or the nature of that which the words are intended to express. We often use the term belief to designate matters of knowledge. The realm of that which we may indiscrimi- Difficulty of nately describe as the known or as the believed is very ing sharply he twe e n large. For example, if one should ask, Do you know that knowing r J and believ- Napoleon was defeated at Waterloo ? we should unhesita- ing. tingly answer, I do. On the other hand, were we asked, Do you believe that Napoleon was defeated at Waterloo? we might be surprised that the questioner should imply a doubt, but we should feel no sense of inadequacy in the reply, I do. Of almost all historical events the same is true. But, further, if there is anything we know, it is the truths stated in the propositions of geometry. Yet we do not hesitate to say that we believe those truths. On the other hand, we often say we know that which is, perhaps, strictly speaking, incapable of being known. Do we know the factors composing the so-called Copernican theory to be true, or do we believe them ? In all matters of knowledge there is an element of belief also. The revelations of the spectroscope as to the composition of the stars give us knowledge. But we accept the data as knowledge on the basis of faith in the uniformity of the action of the instrument and of the re actions of the primary elements upon it. We do not trust even the demonstrations of mathematics as such, but rather we believe in our own powers of reasoning or in those of others, many or few. When skepticism has questioned everything else it must at last trust the powers of the human mind or land in denial of all knowledge.' Thus underlying all our knowledge is belief in the power of the mind to know. Still, there are some things of which it would be absurd to say that we believe them, for they are matters of knowledge; and there are others of which it would be equally absurd to say that we know them, although we may have every reason to believe them. There are some things which lie altogether without the range of human knowledge, and others lie as certainly within that range. To put it in another form, there are some things of which it is possible, and others of which it is impossible to ascertam the reality. In general, all propositions the validity of which cannot be established by intuition, demonstra tion, experience, revelation, or by combinations of these, must be ac cepted, if accepted at all, as beliefs, and not as knowledge; for in- 1 Professor James uses the term belief to signify " every degree of assurance, including the highest possible certainty and conviction."— The Principles of Psychology, New York, 1890, vol. ii, p. 283. aComp. Shoup's Mechanism and Personality, Boston, 1891, chap. 1. 4 Introduction. stance, many of the hypotheses of science and many wholly justifi able inferences from scientific data. Of course the degree of support which such propositions have in their favor will vary in fact, and also in the judgment of different minds. Some of the hypotheses of science have much in their favor and but little against them, while others account for many facts, but fail to account for many others. So also the weight of testimony will be differently estimated by different minds. For credibility and incredibihty are purely subjective con cepts with reference to objects of thought. Things are credible or in credible to minds only. When it is asserted that anything is incredi ble the question at once suggests itself, To whom is it incredible? There are but few minds capable of determining accurately the credi bility of alleged facts, and it is only within the limits of their own departments of learning that even the best thinkers can be trusted to give a correct opinion. Even then their general philosophy may warp their judgments as to what is credible. A skilled historian might be supposed capable of giving an authoritative opinion as to the credi bility of miracles. And such an opinion he could give if he confined himself wholly to the realm of historical evidence. But if he allows his Christian or non-Christian philosophy to affect his judgment, his opinion as an historian might be at once invalidated. Belief is affirmative opinion, more or less well supported with refer ence to matters which lie beyond the possibility of true knowledge. It Belief is exceedingly common. All the results of metaphysical 6 ne " and other speculation, most verdicts given in our courts of law, and all expectations with reference to the future, whether of the actions of man or the events of the natural world, are beliefs, in the sense now described. In the same sense even the denial of the truth of many of the doctrines of Christianity is but the expression of a belief. For, so far as they lie outside the realm of ascertainable reality, any assertion concerning them, whether positive or negative, must, in the nature of the case, be based on belief. The distinguishing feature of belief as compared with knowledge is not that the former is received on authority — that is, on the word of Both knowi- one who is supposed to know ; ' for many of our beliefs do edge and rr ' J beliefs re- not so arise, but are the results of our own reflection. On ceived on authority, the other hand, much of our knowledge is received on au thority. If such were not the case, none but original investigators in the realm of physical nature would have any scientific knowledge, 1 On the compatibility of authority with reason in religion, see Moberly's Reason and Religion, London and New York, 1896, particularly pp. 1-87. AJSiiiui^uCTION. O and they would have only what they had acquired independently of all others. Strictly it cannot be said that either knowledge or belief is received on authority. Facts may be made known to the mind which, if properly conceived, result in knowledge for the mind to which they are made known. Our knowledge is based on authority more frequently than our belief. For when anything is given us as an opinion or belief the mind must not only properly conceive what is intended to be expressed, but it must weigh its reasons for making the opinion or belief its own. Neither as to matters of knowledge or belief does the mind accept the authority of another without at least a measure of reasoned con fidence in the authority accepted. And men are either credulous or incredulous with regard to that which is presented as fact ; but the very nature of belief is such as to involve a measure of incredulity. Were some fantastic opinion presented to us as fact by one whom we recognized as authority, we should accept it as fact and think we had knowledge ; but if it were presented to us by the same authority as a matter of belief, we should, possibly, reject it. The truth is, there fore, that so far as the action of the mind is concerned it is more liable to deception when receiving supposed knowledge on authority than when receiving items to be believed. For, while we are at lib erty to reject a suggested belief, our loyalty to truth forbids our re jection of the imparted fact. Intelligence is no more shocked when a theological dogma is received on authority than it would be were a deliverance of science so received. If both are given out as facts by the same »uthoritv person, or by persons recognized by the mind as of equal less daP" authority, both will be received without regard to the thantoscE diverse realms to which they belong. If both are given ence- out as matters to be beheved the mind will accept them only after having applied the proper tests. The danger in either case is that the authority will give out for fact what is merely a matter of belief. But this danger is slighter in religion than in science, since religion does not generally dignify its facts as knowledge, but as beliefs ; while sci ence says very little about its beliefs, but speaks much of its knowl edge. Dogmatism is not confined to theology.1 lWe know of no more dogmatic utterances than those of Haeckel. This is true whether we consider his disdainful language concerning articles of religious faith or his unwarranted assertions concerning the results of scientific investigation. On page 44 of his Monismus he says that we know that " the soul is a sum of plasma movements in the ganglia cells," and on page 45, that we know " that man developed from pithecoid mam mals late in the tertiary period." It is perhaps needless to say that neither he nor anyone else knows anything of the kind. Even Huxley will not make such assertions, 3 6 Introduction. 3. Faith. The words faith and belief are commonly employed interchange ably. This practice is misleading and should be abandoned, since the Distinction two words connote different, if not radically diverse, con- beiieT and cepts. BeUef emphasizes the intellectual, faith the emo tional elements of our nature, as brought into exercise when an object is presented to us. We believe a proposition ; we have faith in a person or in a plan or in a process, and the like. The former is almost, if not quite, wholly intellectual; the latter, while involving the intellect, takes the form of practical trust. Religious belief is acceptance by the intellect of propositions connected with re ligion. Religious faith is the heart's trust in the objects of worship and in the methods offered by any religion for the accomplishment of its proposed results. In the Christian system religious faith is often termed saving faith. 4. Unbelief. As here used, the word unbelief is not so much the negative of sav ing faith as of belief. It may be defined as negative opinion, more or Ambiguity less well supported, with reference to matters which he n erms. Devon(j the possibility of absolute knowledge. Still, there is an ambiguity both in the words faith and belief, and in the word unbelief, which must be guarded against by every reader. In refer ence to unbelief the ambiguity arises from the fact that we have no one word which distinctly notes the contrast between saving faith and the lack of it. Hence we are obliged to use the word unbelief for the intellectual and also for the emotional condition which eventuates in the rejection of Christ and Christianity. n. faith and unbelief as related to religion. When opponents of Christianity speak of religious faith as though it were superstitious or purely emotional, and condemn it accordingly, intellectual they forget or suppress the fact that unbelief has no bet- ch&rflctipi* of religious ter claim to an intellectual character than has faith. Since the judgment is always at least so far involved in every act of faith as to assent, faith is in the nature of the case intel- though he evidently believes (not knows) them to be true. See his prefatory notes in Haeckel's Freedom in Science and Teaching, London, 1879, p. 14 ff. Compare some excellent remarks on this dogmatizing spirit of Haeckel, in Semper's Der HaeckeUsmus in der Zoologie, Hamburg, 1876, pp. 28, 32 ft., 34. Introduction. 7 lectual as well as emotional. The intellectual is one of its constant and constitutive factors, though often unconsciously, and though the contents of our creed may not, by everyone, be put into the form of propositions which the intellect can grasp. Faith is, indeed, always accompanied by emotion ; but that its basal element is intellectual is clear, first, from the conditions under which it originates, and, second, from the conditions in which alone it can continue to exist. It orig inates under the influence of facts made evident to the intellect ; the facts, namely, that we are dealt with honestly and benevolently by those whom we learn to know, and uniformly by the natural order in which we live. Did we as commonly meet with deception and self ishness, from the cradle onward, as we do with constancy, honesty, and love, we should have no faith ; but unbelief would be the rule be tween man and man and between man and God. Faith is not an instinct with which we are born. The child learns but gradually that every movement of its mother is one of tender ness. We do indeed inherit a capacity which has to do with our at titude of trust or distrust in reference to those about us, but it is because the preponderance of influence is in favor of faith that this faculty takes the direction it does. So also the conditions of its con tinuance are withdrawn the instant an intellectual doubt arises ; and only when this is removed can faith reenter. The traditional acceptance of Christianity at the hands of our par ents or of other associates of our childhood life is no exception ; for it is based on the intellectual acknowledgment of their good judgment and veracity. In childhood this process is, of course, not clearly per ceived, and it might be truthfully said that in all such cases religious faith arises in a state of ignorance. The fact remains, nevertheless, that it is the intellect, not the heart, that first accepts. Indeed, it is psychologically impossible to exercise faith prior to or unaccompanied by intellectual cognition. Faith in God includes assent to the propo sition that God is. Of unbelief it is equally true that its fundamental element is always intellectual. But while faith always includes the accep- Distinction tance of the Christian system, there is a clear distinction unbelief between unbelief and the rejection of the Christian sys- tion of tem. That these statements are true will appear from an ty. examination of the following tabulated statement, which considers chiefly the emotional side, and which is confined in form to the situ ation in Christian lands. It would vary in form, though not in prin ciple, for non-Christian countries. 8 Introduction. A. Emotions which work for the acceptance of the Christian system. 1. The interests which from childhood have been bound up with it in our thought, amounting to an unconscious bias. 2. Party pride. (Church, parents, etc.) 3. The intelligent recognition, by means either of experience or of testimony, of the value of Christianity. 4. The sense of the truth of the Christian system, for instance, that it explains otherwise inexplicable problems. B. Emotions which work for the rejection of the Christian system. 1. Prejudices instilled in childhood, unconscious bias. 2. Party pride. (Often not so much against Christianity as against the Church — for instance, socialism.) 3. Intelligent recognition of the antagonism of Christianity to in terests chosen as supreme — perhaps always sin in some form, though often subtle. 4. The feeling connected with the conviction that the Christian sys tem is false. Under A, case 2 is not identical with faith, and is thus an apparent exception to the statement that faith and the intellectual acceptance of Christianity are always practically coincident. The case is given for the sake of completeness, since it is conceivable that such an emotion might aid in producing faith, for example, by preparing the way for case 3. It is no exception for the reason that it supposes a relation to a party, and not to the objects of faith themselves. Case 1 furnishes instances of intellectual but comparatively unintelligent acceptance. Under B, case 1 is intellectual, though relatively unintelligent, un belief, while case 4 furnishes instances of undoubted intellectual and intelligent unbelief. Where cases 2 and 3 are unattended by cases 1 or 4 they involve unbelief ; but the rejection they imply may coexist with a suppressed, though more or less clearly conscious, conviction of the truth of the Christian system. The result confirms the statement that both faith and unbelief al ways have an intellectual basis, and shows that they are always ac companied by prompting or sustaining emotions. But it also shows that while the rejection of the Christian system is sometimes based on unbelief, it is in other instances, perhaps generally, the result of emotion, and may be accompanied by real intellectual belief. It shows, further, that the acceptance of the Christian system is always intellectual, and that it is more often both intellectual and intelligent than is rejection. INTRODUCTION. 9 On the other hand, it shows that it is incorrect to speak of unbelief as emotional, and that what we call emotional unbelief is in reality not unbelief, but emotional rejection of the Christian system. These conclusions explain our abhorrence of much of the infi- so- called delity of every age, and enable us to comprehend its un- unbelief1 Is reasoning and unfair character. Its turpitude consists tionai re in the fact that it is not unbelief, but belief crushed in ^hr is ti the interest of some emotion. They also furnish the clew to am y' our respect for a certain class of rejecters of Christianity. There is no moral dishonor in their attitude. Belief fails them just where it must exist, if at all, namely, in the intellect. The necessity of break ing away from the demands of the heart may sadden those who do it, as in the case of Romanes, ' and even of the late Professor W. K. Clifford.2 And as the emotional rejection of Christianity, where real intellectual belief exists, is culpable and base, so would be an attempt to force the conviction of the intellect in the interests of emotional acceptance. Our hope for the honest skeptic is that he is accessible to reason, while our despair for the willful or emotional rejecter of Christianity lies in the fact that he cannot be reached by argument. The moral excellence of an intelligent believer, or the changes wrought in lives by conversion, or the testimony of intelUgent Christians to their reUgious experiences, will always command the respect of the inteUectual and inteUigent unbeliever, and may lead him to reexamine the ground of his unbelief, or, as scientific facts, even create a presumption in his mind in favor of the Christian system. It is rarely the case in instances of emotional rejection that the difficulty can be removed by positive evidences, for these do not appeal to the emotions. Such cases need practical rather than literary treatment. They are amenable to revulsions of feeling, such as the appeal to the nobility of a mother's or a wife's Christian character, the death of a loved friend, the scenes at a stirring relig ious revival, and, occasionaUy, appeals to the conscience.3 The views just expressed as to the presence of an intellectual element in all faith seem to conflict with those which prevail in many quar- 1 See his Thoughts on Religion, Chicago, 1895, p. 27 ; also his Candid Examination of Theism (by " Physicus "), pp. 51, 130. Romanes began and ended his Ufe as a Christian believer, though for a period he was an atheist. 3 President Noah Porter quotes Clifford as saying, " We have seen the spring sun shine out of an empty heaven to light up a soulless earth ; we have felt with utter loneliness that the Great Compaion is dead."— Science and Sentiment, with other papers, chiefly philosophical, New York, 1882, p. 371. 3 For good suggestions of a practical kind see Theodor Christlieb's The Best Methods of Counteracting Modern Infidelity, New York, 1874, pp. 18-27. 10 Introduction. ters to-day. We hear much of the wish or the will to beUeve, and there are those who do not hesitate to declare that faith is a function " The will to of the will. ' This can never be the case when propositions believe." ax& offered for our acceptance or rejection. Here the judgment must decide, and to speak of volitional beUef would be ab surd. It is true that our judgments are often warped by our charac ter. But these same judgments appear in consciousness as the result of a purely intellectual process. Did we in any given case recognize the influence of our character upon a judgment we should at once lose confidence in its validity. There are other cases in which our choice between the affirmative and the negative of a proposition is governed by our wish. We can come to no conclusion. There is a degree of satisfaction in beUev- ing one way or the other, and by an act of will we end aU further reflection and decide for that which we desire should be true. This is done by everybody in aU departments of Ufe. There is nothing dishonest about it, -but to do it exhibits good, practical common sense. It would be as legitimate in reUgion as elsewhere. But there should be no misunderstanding as to what has taken place. There is in reality no more belief than there was before. The wfll has Criticism of no* performed the impossible task of coercing the inteUect. Clifford's7 We Uave simply quit debating the question and determined position. henceforth to assume that what we wish to be true is true. The idea promulgated by Clifford ' and others, that we dare not, at the peril of moral dishonor, choose sides in cases like those just men tioned, but must wait until the mind is compeUed to accept one side or the other, is absurd from every point of view. Let us suppose the proposition in question. to be, There is a God. According to Clifford we should have to withhold judgment until the argument for one side or the other is convincing. The heart's preference can have no rights until the mind reaches a conclusion. Now, this is to ignore the right of any portion of our being except the intellect to have a word in de ciding our destiny or happiness. If the inteUect leaves us in the dark, we must remain without a guide, however miserable that may make us. Such a course is, to say the least, high-handed outrage upon aU the other elements of our being. But, further, in such a case as that which we have supposed we may be doing both ourselves and others 1 See, for example, the delightful book of Professor James, on The WiU to Believe, New York, 1897 ; also his Principles of Psychology, vol. ii, pp. 320 ff. » Lectures and Essays, London, 1886, p. 339. Precisely opposite Is the position of the school of Albrecht Ritschl in Germany. See Otto Ritschl's Ueber Werthurthelle, Freiburg 1. B., and Leipzig, 1895, particularly p. 34 f. Introduction. 11 a great wrong. The simple fact that we cannot settle a proposition does not make it untrue. Yet by going only as far as our inteUects guide us we act as though it were untrue. The practical.concerns of Ufe do not admit of such handling. We may with perfect propriety hold our judgment in reserve when no practical interests of our own or others demand action ; but when a proposition contains in it the obUgation of duty we cannot long wait for further Ught, but must act one way or another. Again, in the case of all unsettled reUgious propositions Clifford's principle would involve action on the side of infidelity, though the heart's sympathies might be on the side of reUgion. There are many cases in which the judgment is unconvinced, when to act on the negative of the proposition would be to act the part of the infidel. On the other hand, to act on the affirmative would be to act the part of the religionist. There is no more of hypocrisy in one than in the other. It is impossible not to act, for in aU such cases we act by not acting. Why should our wishes or our interests be sacrificed when the judgment has nothing to say ? Our only true course under such circumstances is to act in accordance with what we think wiU best further our own and other men's welfare. The agnostic ought to be governed by this principle, if he is an agnostic and not an atheist. For, being an agnostic, he does not know whether there is a God or not. All he knows is that he does not know. If he has any prefer ences, he has a perfect right to indulge them, provided only that he does not thereby do injury to his feUow-men. Why should, the ag nostic act as though he were an atheist ? He repudiates atheism, but persistently acts the atheist's part. It must be either that he does simply follow his preferences, or else he is governed by the pernicious principle that when the affirmative of a proposition is unproved we must assume that the negative of it is true. While it is justifiable, therefore, to give our wishes consideration when our judgments are undetermined, it needs again to be pointed out that the act is not one of faith, unless we use the term value of a faith in the sense of a venture, which would be a misuse, cision in the Nevertheless, it does not f oUow that those who, under such conviction. circumstances, act on the supposition of the truth of Christianity wfll not be as firm Christians as those who act on conviction. A practi cal decision may, as easily as belief, lead to the consistent practice of reUgion. The steadfastness of one who makes such a choice will be in proportion to the strength of the inclinations which lead him to choose, to the completeness with which those inclinations are subse- 12 Introduction. sequently gratified, and to the sense of the importance of the interests involved. Furthermore, by such action the conditions wiU be pro duced by which intellectual conviction may be reached. By willing to believe, then, can be meant only the determination to give our inclinations and apparent interest, and our sense of obliga tion to our fellow-men, the right to decide our conduct when our judgments can reach no conclusion. In order to guard against run ning into fanaticism, however, these incUnations and interests must have been subjected to the criticism of reason. Only then may we break the bands which have hitherto restrained us. in. IDEA AND METHOD OF EVIDENCES. DEFINITION AND DISCRIMINATION OF TERMS. 1. Christian Apology (from a-Kofaryia, a defense or a speech in de fense) is the Uterary defense of the Christian reUgion against its op- Aggressive ponents. It is either general or special, according as it ClJ.ci'T^CLCr ot apology. includes aU or but specific phases of unbeUef . In Uterary defense it is sometimes necessary to overthrow assumptions on which objections to the Christian system are based, and hence apology has an aggressive as weU as a defensive aspect. Since, however, even in its more aggressive forms, the object of apology is defense against assault, it must adapt itself both to the character of the assailant and to his method of attack. If the weapons and methods employed against Christianity be those of philosophy, science, history, and ethics, the apologist must meet the assailant with corresponding weapons and methods. Any other form of defense would be ineffec tual, because irrelevant. Apology, therefore, cannot choose its ground. It must meet the assault where it is made and in the form in which it is made.1 Hence there is an element of variabiUty in apology which is unavoidable, and which is the sure mark of its Uving character. On the other hand, the apologist need do no more than show that, judged by facts which both parties to the contest accept, either from conviction or for the sake of the argument, the difficulty in question affords no substantial hindrance to the acceptance of Christianity; and he may concede for argument's sake as much as he pleases, since his duty is not to convince of the truth of Christianity, nor to eluci date its tenets, but to repulse its assailants. 2. Christian Evidences, or the Evidences of Christianity, includes apology as argument in rebuttal ; but its peculiar province Ues beyond apology, whose function is merely to clear away objections, while > " Die Apologie ist der Anwalt des Chrlstenthums vor verschledenen Instanzen '* — Chr. A. Bugge, In Die Christliche Welt, 1897, No. 17, Col. 387. Introduction. IS evidences should aim to produce conviction. Apology prepares the mind for belief ; evidences should induce beUef . Apology p . is addressed chiefly to the intelligence or reason, and |Tflder1e1e| deals only with the intellectual aspects of unbelief ; evi- fr°m aP0l~ dences should appeal to reason, emotion, and will, and deal both with the inteUectual and the emotional causes of rejection of Christianity. Apology says to its opponents, "Your contention is untenable, or irrelevant ; " by evidences we show that the Christian position is inteUectually and moraUy obligatory. Apology takes form and method from the attacks made upon Christianity. Evi dences wiU exhibit Christianity as superior to aU other systems, actual or conceivable. From these remarks it will be seen that evidences should, so far as they are vaUd, have an abiding character. As a matter of fact, how ever, evidences have suffered in the past, and probably wiU suffer in the future, in the permanency of their value, by being falsely reasoned, or else based upon false conceptions of science or of phi losophy. For evidences, like apology, must undergo both formal and material modifications in order to the proper employment of the changing views of scientific and phflosophic fact, even though the champion of Christianity may not be persuaded of the truth of the new views. 3. Apologetics is a term for a treatise on apology. It includes with apology proper the discussion of the nature of faith and unbeUef , the consideration of methods, the history of apology and evidences, and the Uke. It is the science of apology. In its ordinary use the term is made to include the whole treatment of faith, unbelief, and rejec tion of Christianity, as these stand related to the propagation of the Gospel. rv. limitations and scope of the subject. 1. The apologist is under no obligation to defend or enforce the articles of any particular creed, or any particular form of faith. This would lead him into the domain of polemics. Nor is he bound to de fend the acts of the visible Church.1 2. His duty is to defend and enforce the facts essential to the proof of revelation. There may be room for difference of opinion as to what these essentials are ; but when he has settled this question for himself his only duty is in reference to them. All the rest may be safely left to polemics for adjustment. But the apologist has no right to abate anything of these essentials, once he has determined 'Comp. A. B. Bruce's Apologetics, New York, 1892, p. 503. 14 Introduction. what they are, in order to make them more acceptable ; rather must he strive to change the mental and emotional attitude of the objector.1 3. Demonstration is seldom, if ever, to be required.3 If a fair de gree of probability in favor of a truth of Christianity is established, it should, in most cases, satisfy aU demands. By such a degree of probability we mean one which at least preponderates over the prob abilities on the other side. 4. Evidences should satisfy the Christian demand for a consciously rational foundation of beUef . It is designed, therefore, primarily, for those who are already Christians, and who require that there should be no controversy between their inner experience and their scientific conceptions, or between their inteUigence and their wiU. 5. Evidences should counteract the influence of those arguments against Christianity which tend to aUenate men from Christian faith and life. For example, one who is an admirer of natural science, if persuaded that Christianity is either intrinsicaUy or historicaUy in imical to it, would be alienated from the faith by that beUef . So, too, many of the ethical culturists are alienated from the faith by the feel ing that Christianity, at any rate in its present form, lays too much stress on devotion and dogma, and not enough on moraUty. Hence it is the duty of the apologist to point out the fallacy of aU such arguments. 6. Evidences should be so constructed as to command the respect, if not to win the adherence, of sincere and scholarly unbeUevers. In order to this it is necessary that the apologist should know his antag onist's position, appreciate the weight of the arguments in its support, and in aU references to the same be entirely fair and just. Further, he must be thoroughly loyal to his own convictions, and prove by the force of his reasoning, both against his opponent and in favor of his own position, that he is worthy of inteUectual respect. He must be able to give a reason for the faith that is in him. In addition to aU this he must speak or write in the spirit of Christ. Lacking any of these qualifications he is liable to stimulate prejudice against his cause and against all in whose name he speaks. The fact that aU men feel the need of religion should prompt the apologist to his best endeavor.3 1 See Crooks and Hurst's Theological Encyclopaedia and Methodology, on the Basis of Hagenbach, New York and Cincinnati, under The Task of Apologetics, and Steude's Beitrage zur Apologetik, Gotha, 1884, p. 75. » Bowne asserts that demonstration is no longer expected in any department of ob jective knowledge.— Philosophy of Theism, New York, 1887, pp. 10, 30, and elsewhere. 8 That such is the case is clear from the many attempts of soientlflo men to pave the way for a reconciliation between science as they conceive it and religion. For examples Introduction. 15 7. Evidences should aim to lead men to a humble acceptance of Christ as their Saviour. If the results were merely inteUectual, some thing would be gained, but not all that the Christian apologist desires. The conflict is not intended merely to end in belief, but also in saving faith. V. VALUE OF CHRISTIAN EVIDENCES. That the evidences of Christianity, rightly conducted, are effectual need scarcely be affirmed. The large number of works, designed to set forth these evidences, which have been written and the eagerness with which they are read by thoughtful ness ofVar- people sufficiently evince their value. Men are convinced IS Subject by argument on reUgious as on other subjects ; and they ° re lglou' are persuaded to action here as elsewhere by the due presentation of weighty considerations. True it is that the most valuable evidence anyone can have of the existence of God is the power of God exerted in the individual's own salvation ; and hence the evidences of Chris tianity fafl of their purpose if they do not lead the reader of them to submit himself to that power. It is necessary to repeat that the evi dences are not addressed to the judgment alone. They are designed to produce not merely opinions, but convictions. He who * J * ' Their design. has only the former may remain inactive; not so he who is possessed of the latter. The evidences of Christianity must not only be presented ; they must be weighed by him to whom they are offered. If this cooperation is not accorded by the reader, he wiU, of course, receive no benefit. If, on the other hand, he furnishes his part, he must of necessity be led to the participation of the benefits of the Gospel. If anyone refuses this cooperation, evidences cannot be accused of uselessness because they do such a reader no good. Nor can it be urged against the value of Christian evidences that the vast majority of people neither understand nor need them. There are few who do not at times raise the question why Evidences they beUeve in the doctrines of Christianity, and, whether siwi'by'the false or true, many are drawn away from the faith of the ma;lorl y- Gospel by the arguments of our enemies. To all such the evidences of Christianity may prove valuable.1 If some do not understand or feel their force, it still remains true that vast numbers do both under stand and need them. By all means we shaU thus save some. Haeckel's Der Monisums als Band zwichen Religion und Wissenschaft, Bonn, 1892, and Spencer in First Principles of a New System of Philosophy, second edition, New York, 1868, to say nothing of many lesser lights. Says Spencer: "Of all antagonisms of belief, the oldest, the widest, the most profound, and the most important is that between Re ligion and Science," p. 10. 1 Comp. G. F. Wright's The Logic of Christian Evidences, Andover, 1880, p. 4. 16 Introduction. Furthermore, in a time when infideUty is exerting its utmost efforts to overthrow Christianity sflence would be regarded by many as a Reasons why sign of conscious insecurity against the assaults of the ad- fa e* pSr o v i - versary, and as a virtual confession that it has no reasons to offer why men should accept it. Here, again, it is neces sary to remind the objector that Christianity does not exist simply for its own sake, but for the benefits it can confer. And although it be true that Christianity contains the truth, whether men are con vinced of that fact or not, yet only as men recognize the truth that is in Christianity do they place themselves under its sway. We may not stand stiU and see thousands swept away from the influence of the Gospel simply because we know that Christianity is true. We must make other men see that it is true, and that its truth imposes obligation. FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. DIVISION I. THE RELATIONS OF PHILOSOPHY AND CHRISTIANITY. The manifold assault upon the Christian system is reducible to five forms : the philosophical, the scientific, the historical, the ethical, and the religious. In order to thoroughness it will be neces- Five forms of If each brain atom had its own consciousness how could we account for the existence cf a single harmonious consciousness of the entire brain ? 3In Die Perigenesis der Plastidule, Berlin, 1876, pp. 38, 39. Dispute Between Du Bois-Keymond and Haeckel. 31 we attribute to them sensibility and will .... That the wiU of man and of the higher animals appears free in contrast with the fixed will of the atoms, results from a delusion elicited by the highly complex voli tions of the former in comparison with the exceedingly simple voU- tions of the latter." To this Du Bois-Reymond retorts 1 that such a method of argumen tation is a disdainful forsaking of the inductive method of treating the question as to the conditions under which consciousness origi nates. Well does he make this charge against Haeckel. For, so far as this quotation from him goes, it in nowise adds to our information concerning the origin of consciousness, but simply attributes mental states to atoms. Indeed, Haeckel does not pretend to explain con sciousness by the arrangement and movement of atoms — though he censures Du Bois-Reymond for saying these cannot explain it 2 — but simply postulates consciousness as an attribute of atoms. Du Bois-Reymond further answers Haeckel by saying that the lat ter sins against the first rule of philosophy : Entia non sunt creanda sine necessitate. (Existences are not to be created without neces sity) . For why should there be consciousness where mechanics explain everything ? And if atoms are capable of receiving sensations, what is the need of organs of sense ? And he calls attention to the fact that Haeckel passes over the difficulty mentioned by Du Bois-Rey mond : that the numberless atom-souls of the human brain cannot ex plain the single harmonious consciousness of the human being. s Other objectors to Du Bois-Reymond undertook to explain the influ ence of one body upon another at a distance through empty space by the supposition of a will inherent in the atoms, to which he replies that this is indeed a wonderful will which is shared by two, and re minds them that such a man as Newton gave up all hope of explain ing the problem they would make clear.* In a scornful passage Haeckel 6 speaks of the outworn notion that the human consciousness is an insoluble problem, a transcendental phenomenon in contrast to all other phenomena of nature. Haeckel's scornful And he declares that it is on just this notion that men language no argu- base their belief in the specificaUy distinct quality of man ment. and the doctrine of the immortaUty of the soul. He also intimates that Du Bois-Reymond's lecture is distinguished for its rhetorical grace rather than for its contents, and that the fair sex are Ukely to be most partial to so " fair " a sermon. That all this offers no shadow 1 Vortrage, p. 83. a See Du Bois-Reymond, Vortrage, p. 84. 8 Vortrage, p. 83 f . * Ibid, p. 84 f . 6 Der Monismus als Band, p. 44. 32 Foundations of the Christian Faith. of argument he probably feels, for he refers to his work on Freedom in Science and Teaching for a defense of his views as against his ad versary. But turning to that work we find 1 that his treatment of the subject in hand furnishes no facts upon which to base a conclu sion which could not be admitted by Du Bois-Reymond. Theories and opinions there are which beg the whole question, to which he would not consent. Between the two men, therefore, the dispute is one of interpretation of facts; Haeckel interpreting them in accord ance with his preconceived opinions and reaching the conclusion that there is no such thing as mind, Du Bois-Reymond interpreting them inductively and reaching the conclusion that all we know, and in the nature of the case can know, of the brain must forever fail to explain all the phenomena of mind. Haeckel goes beyond the warrant of the facts; this Du Bois-Reymond refuses to do. The outcome of the whole dispute can be summed up in a few words. Haeckel has failed to show how material causes can produce nonmaterial effects, and he has failed to show how the many supposedly conscious atoms of the human brain can, combined, result in the individual consciousness of the human mind. In closing this part of the discussion we wish to caU attention to the fact that it is by the unreserved appUcation of the principles of materialism that these results have been reached. MateriaUsm, fol lowed as far as it has ever been carried, has failed to explain the fun damental facts of the human consciousness. Where Haeckel fails, even with the aid of his atom-souls, it is useless for others to try.2 1 Chapter vii. 5 Clifford thinks it may some time be established that there is no mind without brain. He does not pretend that such a conclusion is now established.— Lectures and Essays, p. 269. Refutation of the Materialistic Psychology. 33 CHAPTER TV. refutation of the materialistic psychology. The history just given of the dispute between Du Bois-Reymond and Haeckel furnishes arguments sufficient to restrain any unpreju diced mind from adopting the materiaUstic view of the mental life. But our case against materialism is not complete. Many of Du Bois- Reymond's utterances are so brief as to lose somewhat of their real force except for those who are familiar with the points in dispute. We emphasize therefore, first of all, the immense and impassable chasm between thought and the phenomena of matter. "The state of a man's brain and the actions which go along with it Chasm be- tweenmen- are things which every other man can perceive, observe, taiandma- tcri&l piiG- measure, and tabulate ; but the state of a man's own con- nomena. Sciousness is known to him only, and not to any other person. Things which appear to us and which we can observe are caUed objects, or phenomena. Facts in a man's consciousness are not objects or phe nomena to any other man ; they are capable of being observed only by him.1 We have no possible ground, therefore, for speaking of an other man's consciousness as in any sense a part of the physical world of objects or phenomena. It is a thing entirely separate from it ; and aU the evidence that we have goes to show that the physical world gets along entirely by itself." 2 There is no point at which the distinction between mental and physical phenomena is more marked than in connection with physical and mental pain. We are perfectly able to distinguish them, and to trace the former to the body, while the latter appears to have no relation to bodily condi tions. Laughter may be caused either by tickling or by a ludicrous idea ; but these causes differ totally from each other. Because of this significant fact most investigators are disposed to admit that, though brain processes and thought proc- Haeckel's . identifica- esses always appear together, there is no evidence that tion of their relation is that of cause and effect. 3 Even Haeckel and energy. is able to make the leap from brain processes as conditions of 1 Those who believe in mind reading object to this; but even for them it does not in validate Professor Clifford's conclusion. 3 Clifford, Lectures and Essays, p. 260. ?So Tyndall: see British Association Report, 1868. 34 Foundations of the Christian Faith. mental action to brain processes as causes of mental action only by denying the distinction between thought and energy, and asserting that the mysteries of matter and force are exactly identical with those of consciousness.1 This he gives, of course, only as his opinion. The opinions of the majority of those as able as himself are against him. Aside from opinion, however, the identity of thought with motion involves a contradiction ; for motion and space are the neces sary concomitants of each other, but thought gets on without space. To identify thought and energy leads to a similar difficulty, since it violates the law of the conservation of energy. This law demands that for every footpound of energy lost to one body there shaU be stored an additional footpound in some other body. But if energy be transformed into thought, energy is lost to the physical world, since thought is not physical energy.2 Moreover, as Romanes points out, we have no gauge for the quantity or the quaUty of thought pro duced other than the effects of the thought. But a stupid fellow might expend vast quantities of brain energy and yet produce no valuable thought. It is an admitted fact that it is not all brain energy, but energy of a brain of a certain quaUty which returns re sults worth the effort. Hence there is no equivalency between the physical causes and the psychical effects. In fact, there is no demon strable connection between neurosis and psychosis but that of simul taneity. This is practicaUy admitted by those who attribute mentality to atoms. For if there can be mentaUty without brain, then why is a brain necessary ? And if the movements of atoms in their infinitely varied combinations are to be attributed to mentality, it must be a much higher type of mentaUty than that of the human brain, for it is very certain that this could never have produced a thought as infi nitely varied and intricate as this world is. If it be replied that the world is not the product of designing thought, then we are compeUed to say that blind thought is superior to conscious thought. This is not to be overcome by giving different names to different kinds of human movements, as vegetative, reflex, etc., for none the less those 1 " The problem of the origin and nature of consciousness is only a special case of the general problem of the connection of matter and force."— Freedom in Science and Teach ing, p. 102. Clifford declares that if we accept the doctrine of evolution we must believe that along with every motion of matter there is some fact which corresponds to the mental fact in ourselves, since we cannot suppose that so enormous a jump from one creature to another should have occurred at any point in the process of evolution as the introduction of a fact entirely different and absolutely separate from the physical fact. —Lectures and Essays, pp. 265, 266. He does not pretend, like Haeckel, that there is any. thing In the action of the atoms themselves to indicate mentality even In the lowest de. gree. a Comp. Romanes' Mind and Motion and Monism, p. C6. Refutation of the Materialistic Psychology. 35 actions which are performed by atoms and even by plants afford us a variety, deUcacy, and exactness unknown to the volitional acts of man. Besides, this would leave human thought, which is teleological and conscious, to be accounted for. So that materialism would fail again in the realm of psychology. Another insuperable difficulty in the way of the materialistic theory, to which many have called attention, is that it makes of men con scious automata.1 If it were not for consciousness, mate- Manasacon- . scious au- rialism could get on very well. But consciousness is the tomaton. one great terror of materialistic thought, continuaUy heading it off, whichever way it turns. Unconscious automata are perhaps conceiv able, but conscious automata defy all our powers of conception. In the first place, if aU the changes in the brain are determined by phys ical causes, and if these changes in turn determine our thinking, our mental states, then thought, which is not physical, can have no func tion, since it cannot, by hypothesis, influence either the brain on the one hand or further thought on the other. Thought is a product of brain activity, but itself has nothing to do. This is a serious difficulty from the standpoint of materiaUsm, which claims to be the special champion of the doctrine of natural selection, according to which every thing that is has some function to perform. Let the reader consider what it means when it is declared that thought has never in any way affected the welfare of the world nor modified human action in the sUghtest degree, as it most surely has not if the contention of the materiaUsts be true, that every condition of the brain is directly deter mined by physical causes, and that thought is merely the product of brain conditions. If this be true, and we could suppose no one ever to have been conscious of any of his deeds, the world would be in exactly the same state in which we find it to-day. A world of unconscious actors would have done precisely the things which the world of con scious actors has done, and would, therefore, have reached just the state we have reached. This supposition is an enormous tax upon our creduUty, since it contradicts thought itseU. And it also emphasizes the uselessness of consciousness, and thus contradicts one of the first princi- uselessness pies of natural selection. If, in order to escape from this m materfai- difficulty, we suppose thought to have a place in tho prog- ls 10 * e0ly* ress of the world by regarding it as a mode of motion or a kind of energy, then, since it is at least not physical energy, we have destroyed 1 Says Clifford, "We are more than automata, because we are conscious."— Lectures and Essays, p. 263. 36 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the doctrine of the conservation of energy. But this doctrine is the principal barrier erected by materiaUsts against the theory that mind may influence matter. There is no place left to which materialistic thought may escape for safety. We come next to consider the inadequacy of the materialistic theory for the explanation of one of the greatest and most persistent facts of Materialistic our self -consciousness, namely, our sense of freedom. We denial of ,,,.,,- m. , freedom. have seen that Haeckel regards this as a delusion. Strecker says that a materialism which undertakes to explain mental processes by means of laws which are vaUd in the entire world cannot recognize the freedom of the wfll ; a that the freedom of the wiU is a deception. There is and can be no such thing. Not independent self-determina tion, but iron necessity, rules aU the thoughts and actions of man, and what has been regarded as free will is but a link in the chain of causes which has existed from all eternity and wiU continue eternaUy ; in which every member is the effect of what went before and will become the cause of what foUows.2 " The man of honor and the malefactor are made of the same material, and not free will, but the force of cir cumstances, has made them what they are." 3 Such a view of the wfll is the only consistent one for materialists to take. We shaU not attempt to follow here aU the subterfuges to which they resort in order to make it appear that their doctrine is not dan gerous to morals. It is vain for them to point to those who have denied freedom as among the most upright of men, for this is not a fact in any instance where the denial has been consistent. Where it is a fact it is to be accounted for on the ground that the denial has been made for purely theoretical reasons, while in practice the deniers have held themselves and others responsible. This is confessed by Strecker.4 So that if this doctrine of materiaUstic determinism does not affect men for evil, it is because of the force of the opinion that, in spite of the theory, the persistent old notion is true that we are free, and hence responsible. The only consistent view for materiaUsts to take is the one held by some of their number, that repentance is both needless and futile, since by hypothesis the act repented of was una voidable, and since repentance can neither undo the deed nor affect future conduct and destiny. No mental act can affect the brain, from which alone all thought and action spring. B If now we undertake to limit ourselves to the consistent material istic conception, we find our mechanical brains, which work according 1 Welt und Menschheit, p. 83. a Ibid., p. 6 ff. » Ibid., p. 92. « Ibid., p. 90 f. s As Lamettrie, see Lange's History of MateriaUsm, Boston, 1880, vol. ii, p. 85 f. REFUTATION OF THE MATERIALISTIC PSYCHOLOGY. 37 to fixed and unchangeable physical laws, producing the strangest series of contradictions. First, they have produced the delusion that we are free and responsible, and made it so persistent a conviction that it cannot be eradicated from our thinking. Second, they have pro duced the opinion, in contradiction to that delusion, that we are not free. Third, they make those who beUeve that aU actions are necessi tated honor the benefactors of the race, praise virtue, condemn vice, and pursue and punish the disturbers of our peace and of the social order.1 And, fourth, they make us wear ourselves out trying to find some way to reconcile aU these mental facts to this materiaUstic theory. The charge we bring against materiaUsm, then, is that by denying the freedom of our thinking and willing, and at the same time their power to influence conduct, it fails to explain our sense Confusion of of freedom and introduces confusion into aU our think- aristagfrom • ni itprinl- mg. When we remember that aU this results from an ism. attempt to deduce everything in the realm of matter and of mind from the application of the law of causality, and then recaU that this law of causaUty is itself an article of faith, it does seem as though it were better to adhere to the old faith which teaches us that we are free. For it is, after aU, a question of which faith we shaU accept. The preference should be given to the faith in freedom, since it is native and spontaneous as weU as capable of giving consistency to our thinking and conduct, while the faith of determinism is deduced from an hypothesis and ends in moral disaster if consistently held, and in confusion of thought and action if inconsistently held.2 This brings us to the final consideration which we shaU mention in the argument against materiaUsm drawn from psychology. On mate riaUstic principles, there is no trusting thought. We have Materialism seen what dire confusion it introduces into the world of thevaUdity ethics. No less confusion is there in the realm of abstract oftnougnt- thinking, and that necessarily, if materialism be true. We cannot control our thoughts. From simple perception to the highest forms of mathematical reasoning, everything is predetermined by the pre ceding physical conditions, upon which thought itself never reacts. 1 Welt und Menschheit, p. 90. 8 At this point we call attention to the evil practical effects of materiaUsm. The argu ment is one we do not like, and we should not mention it but for the fact thatmaterialists never grow weary of asserting the immense ethical superiority of their system to that of Christianity. Suffice it to say that it is not Christian thinkers alone who affirm the evil practical effects of materialism. See, for example, ForePsGehirn und Seele, p. 30; Paul Cams' The Soul of Man, an investigation of the facts of Physiological and Experimental Psychology, Chicago, 1891, p. 382; and Huxley's Lay Sermons, Addresses, and Reviews, New York, 1871, p. 127, and elsewhere. 5 38 Foundations of the Christian Faith. No effort of ours can render our thinking more correct, for this is sim ply one form of the delusion of free will. Now, however it may be with the correctness of our sense impressions, whether they be true or false, we can do nothing to correct them if we suspect them erroneous. This suspicion itself is a result of precedent physical conditions, and if our errors are to be corrected this result wfll be brought about by phys ical conditions also. In fact, thinking is useless. If we try to think, the effort springs from physical conditions ; if, knowing the useless ness of the effort, we no longer try, our subsequent stupidity as weU as the despair which led to it are all produced by this endless chain of physical causes. Thus the conflict of thought is a conflict of physical conditions. The man who sets himself up as a judge of another man's thinking is simply foUowing a necessity of his physical nature. His assurance that he is right and his opponent wrong is the result of the same kind of causes. If one grows skeptical in consequence, and says that on this princi ple we cannot be sure of anything, even this is a product of physical And also its conditions. Whichever way we "turn, we find no escape sign cance. £rom ^ne jaws 0f physics. Thought has no significance. The only consistent thing to do is to cease to think. We have no cri terion except our own brain, which determines for each individual what his thinking shaU be like, both as to substance and quaUty. If we undertake, with Herbert Spencer, to introduce a saving element into our thinking, not, indeed, for the present, but for the future, on the theory that by natural selection those who think truly wfll sur vive and those who think falsely wfll perish, we find ourselves con fronted with the fact that, according to materiaUsm, right thinking can only affect those who survive, but they and their offspring are the ones who have already thought correctly. But even here right thinking must mean right brain action, and, as Professor Bowne' says, even this " would provide for valid thoughts only so far as they are related to survival; whereas the bulk of our thoughts have no bearing on survival. A mistake in our theory of double stars or in solar physics would not be attended by any physical disaster. " " What warrant, then, have we for trusting the report of thought on these things ? " Thus it is that thought is reduced to chaos by the material istic hypothesis which gives itself out for so superior a way of looking at the facts of Ufe. For all these reasons we must reject materialism and assert that it is not a sufficient basis for the denial of the reality of the soul. > Metaphysics, New York, 1882, p. 390; revised edition, 1898, p. 323. The Materialistic Denial of God. 39 CHAPTER V. THE MATERIALISTIC DENIAL OF GOD. So far, then, atheism fails to satisfy the demands of thought. We raise the question whether in its denial of God it can satisfy us any better. In reaUty, we are entitled to deny atheism the right to expect any further attention. It undertakes to prove that there is no super sensuous existence. It has had a fair hearing and has completely broken down in reference to the soul. What right have we to sup pose that it can do any better with reference to its denial of God ? Nevertheless, we shall not employ our advantage. If the materialistic hypothesis can get on without God, let it prove its ability so to do. Here again it is necessary to call attention to the inadequacy of the materialistic view as confessed by its most pronounced advocates. Strecker says that those who believe that matter never Difflcult„ ot began to be must assume that motion is not as eternal as ™jt^ matte? matter, but had a beginning. The question is, how mo- and motion- tion was first imparted to matter. The supposition that motion arose in the hitherto motionless matter as a result of a potential energy which the latter possessed is untenable, since no explanation is thus afforded. Without some external cause, however small, this poten tial energy could not be transformed into kinetic. Idealism cannot aid the materiaUst, since, contrary to the former, he holds that the sensuous is the real world and admits no mysterious second world, and confesses that our means of information are insufficient for a clear and thorough understanding of the world. ¦ We must not won der that so frank an avowal of the inadequacy of materiaUsm does not turn its adherents away from it. They hold to the beUef that it is not the inexpUcability of things on their hypothesis which causes the trouble, but the limitations of the human understanding. Their faith in the truth of their view is, therefore, without sufficient foundation. In effect they say we cannot, by reason of the Umitations of the hu man mind, demonstrate our theory ; but we maintain it nevertheless. It is strange that Strecker does not recall his other confession, that the articles of faith of materiaUsm, added to the knowledge we possess of the world, are still not sufficient for its explanation.2 1 Welt und Menschheit, pp. 25-29. a Ibid, p. 14. 40 Foundations of the Christian Faith. But as in the case of the materiaUstic psychology, so in reference to the materialistic cosmogony, the confessed inadequacy of material ism must not be the main reason for its rejection. The confession is merely adapted to prevent those from taking such a step who have not already given themselves up to it. Supposition Materialism denies the need of any God to explain the eternaiiyin existence of the universe in which we Uve, and asserts 111 that all that exists is matter with its forces. It is of necessity assumed that matter has always existed, otherwise it must have had a creator. Now, let us suppose that matter existed from aU eternity in motion, or matter possessed of any and all the forces necessary to the development of such a universe as ours, without a mind to direct these forces. This is assuredly a most generous sup position. Then the question arises, why we can reckon a period of time in which, beginning with a rotating mass, the present universe might have come to be. For, give as many billions of years as we may to this process, no one pretends that it is eternal. What is the reason this process is not further along ? The only answer that can be given is again purely hypothetical, namely, that we do not know but that our present universe is one of an eternal series which have been coming into existence, and dissolving again into their original elemental condition, and that this process will repeat itself eternaUy. Now, when one is hard pressed in argument he can make any sup position that wfll extricate him from immediate danger of annihila tion, and this supposition is exactly of that sort. The idea' that there will come in the course of ages such changes in physical condi tions as will cause the heavenly bodies to coUide? thus generating such heat as to reduce them to the original condition supposed in the nebular hypothesis, has no foundation on which to rest, and would never have been thought of but for the exigencies of the materiaUstic argument. To support the hypothesis that there is nothing but matter and its forces, such an hypothesis might be framed. But to support an hy pothesis by an hypothesis which has no fact to support it, is certainly a most unphilosophic and unscientific procedure, and has not been much employed, be it said to their credit, even by materiaUsts them selves. But if this heaping up of hypotheses must be disapproved, we have on our hands the difficulty that matter, supposed to have had eternally the potencies in operation necessary to the production of such a world as ours, has produced it only in time. But let us suppose the difficulties just mentioned to be not insoluble. ' Welt und Menschheit, p. 6. The Materialistic Denial of God. 41 We should then have, instead of an inteUigent creator, eternal, un created matter possessed of certain powers or capabilities as a result of which a world is evolved, or a series of worlds. Now, we may ad mit that, as we must posit something eternal, something without be ginning, it is as conceivable that matter possessed of the assumed potencies might be eternal as it is that an inteUigent creator is eternal. Or, to put it in language more commensurate with the power of hu man thought, we can as easily think of the former as existing prior to everything else, or, as Herbert Spencer designates it,1 as self -existent, as we can of God. If we must ask, Whence this matter ? we must also ask, Whence this God?2 If anyone is inclined to doubt this, let him reflect that it is because he has been accustomed to think of God as the author of all things, himself being uncreated, and not be cause of any inherent difficulty in the thought.3 When we come, however, to apply the hypothesis of this supposed matter to the expla nation of our present world, we find it inadequate. There Difficulty is intelhgence in the world, and for this nonintelligent 2enceelin matter cannot account. If it be said that intelhgence is world. one of the quaUties of matter, the result is pantheism, with which we shall deal later. But this pantheistic hypothesis is a yielding of the 'First Principles, p. 31. 3WissenschaftUche Vortrage uber relioglose Fragen, Zweite Sammlung, Frankfurt-am- Main, 1878, p. 31. 3 We cannot agree with Professor Flint in complaining of the materialist for not prov ing the eternity of matter. It is pertinent to question the arguments offered in its proof; but the materialistic atheist has as good a right, though not as good reason, to assume eternal matter as the theist has to assume an eternal God. His criticism of the argu ment in favor of eternal matter is, we think, absolutely unanswerable. The argument in question is that of the German materialist, L6wenthal, author of a widely read work en titled System und Geschichte des Materialimus, Leipzig, 1862, and founder of a religious community called " Cogitants ; " "a society which, on the one hand, makes thinking and knowledge themselves the object of cultus, but, on the other hand, is based on the cultivation of human dignity and human affection" (comp. Lange, History of Material ism, vol. iii, p. 295), and is stated thus : " What has no end can have no beginning. What cannot be destroyed can also not be created. Matter cannot be destroyed and conse quently cannot be created ; it is without end, and therefore likewise without beginning— is eternal." Thrown into syllogistic form we have two distinct arguments : first, "What has no end can have no beginning ; matter has no end ; therefore it had no beginning." The major premise is, to say the least, a pure assumption, in the nature of the case ut* terly incapable of demonstration, and as a general proposition there is reason to believe it false ; for instance, influences once set in motion as a result of mental action will prob ably never end, yet we can mark their historical beginnings. But, aside from this, the minor premise is also unproved. No one knows whether matter will have an end or not. One's theory of the nature of matter must determine one's opinion on this question. From these assumed premises it is proposed to demonstrate the eternity of matter. The second argument runs : " What cannot be destroyed can also not be created ; matter cannot be destroyed, therefore it was not created." What, we ask, has the indestructi bility of a thing, once called into being, to do with the possibility of its creation? Again, it is unproved that matter cannot be destroyed. Only as an hypothesis, therefore, is the materialist justified in speaking of the eternity of matter. On the foregoing compare Zollmann's Bibel und Natur in der Harmonie ihrer Offenbarung, GekrOnte Preisschrift, Zweite Auflage, Hamburg, 1869, p. 52 ff. 42 Foundations of the Christian Faith. doctrine of materialistic atheism, and is therefore fatal. Yet on no other hypothesis can materiaUsm account for intelligence. Human thought, to say nothing of animal intelligence, is the crushing weight under which materialistic atheism, as an explanation of the world, groans. But there is evidence that inteUigence was employed also in the production of the nonintelUgent creation. However we may regard the doctrine of design in nature, there can be no question that the world does leave upon the human mind the impression of an adjust ment for which it cannot account except on the hypothesis of an intelligent somewhat in action. In order to get rid of this impression we are obliged to think contrary to the laws of our own being. Our only means of estimating possibiUties is ourselves. It is as human beings that we are endeavoring to understand the world. Our whole idea of causality, motive, and purpose springs from what we know of ourselves. We are obliged by the Umitations of our own minds to anthropomorphize everything which is not ourselves, whether it be God or the world. We know full weU that in our own Uves results are the outcome either of purpose or of what we are obUged to regard as accident ; and that the inteUigent results — that is, those results which are inteUigible to other beings like ourselves — are the outcome of a more or less intelligent purpose. When we look at the world, which is not the product of our own action, we are obliged to read into it either purpose or accident. We have no other way of account ing for things, whether within or without ourselves. And as we can not account, on the ground of accident, for some results which we know to be the work of man, so we cannot account, on the ground of accident, for some things which we know to be not the work of man. It is not so much particular results in nature which leave this im pression as the whole scheme. When the world as a mechanism is offered in explanation of things, we cannot, without dehumanizing ourselves, refrain from the feeling that somehow inteUigence has to do with the mechanism. The mechanical view of nature is as old as scientific thought, to which, indeed, it has always been serviceable, though only as united with dynamism. It appeals to us because of its apparent simplicity. Matter, motion, and force, with space and time as conditions,. are its only fundamental assumptions. All the infinitely varied products of nature result from the interactions of these elements. To be sure, certain laws of activity, as Newton's laws of motion, are also assumed, but these follow as a matter of course from the nature of the elements. When we consider, how- J.HE MATERIALISTIC DENIAL OF GoD. 43 ever, that these general conceptions and laws are entirely inadequate to the explanation of any single event in nature, and that for such an explanation a particular assumption must be made for each particular condition, "-he complexity of the theory becomes evident. For in stance, why does water boil ? The fundamental assumptions furnish the general conditions, but for the adequate answer we must supply every specification that enters into the problem. Thus the mechani cal theory leaves us just where we were before — it is itself as com plex and as much in need of explanation as the facts it would explain. It does not give us the faintest suggestion of an answer to the onto logical question in which we are interested. Atheism fails to satisfy our thinking as human beings. We must posit a somewhat in which inteUigence plays a part. We must be come either pantheists, or deists, or theists, even though Human think- we say with the agnostic that we know nothing further of ing demands this intelhgence than that it is. If anyone says that this is to narrow the world down to our small way of thinking, we repeat that we can judge of things only by what we know. If the world is to be intelligible to us, it must be interpreted by means at our com mand ; and all our philosophic and scientific thought is really an at tempt to understand the world. Therefore it is supreme folly to cast away the only criteria by which we can estimate what is about us. 1 If it be replied that judging the world in this way is to render our knowledge of it insecure, since we may be totally wrong owing to our acknowledged mental limitations, we answer that the only means we have of knowing that we are limited in our power to know is the application of our own judgment to that question. Should we carry out the argument we are trying to answer, we might say that per haps we are totally wrong in thinking our minds are limited. As soon as we distrust our means and powers of knowing we re duce all thinking to hopeless chaos. Hence, no argument can be based on what we possibly do not know. All arguments must be based on what we do know ; and we know that in the realm of hu man activity we are compelled to attribute intelligence to many of its results. Our criteria for judging nonhuman activities are the same as those we apply to human. On this principle the conception of eternal matter, possessed of any forces one may be pleased to bestow upon it, cannot account to the human mind for the mechanism of the 1 Paulsen, though in the interest of idealistic pantheism, follows most other thinkers in applying this method in the interpretation of the world. See his Einleitung in die Phi losophic, Berlin, 1892, p. 242 ff. 44 Foundations of the Christian Faith. world. We f uUy recognize that this argument does not prove intelli gence in the conduct of the world. StiU, it does render such inteUi gence probable, and it shows that the materiaUstic theory is not a suf ficient basis for the denial of a God, and this is aU that we have endeavored to demonstrate here.1 1 Romanes has some excellent remarks along this line. He takes up Herbert Spen cer's doctrine of the persistence of force as rendering uniformity of law inevitable, and shows that, even though it were admitted, It is nevertheless true that " the mere persist ence of force, even if it were conceded to account for particular cases of physical se quence, can give us no account of the ubiquitous and eternal direction of force in the construction and maintenance of universal order." See Thoughts on Religion, p. 67 ff. The Alleged Imperfections of the World. 45 CHAPTER VI. the alleged imperfections of the world and intelligence in creation. We next take up the argument of atheism as drawn from the suposed evfls and imperfections of the world. In fact, the evfls to which we are subject, the reaUty of which we have , . . . TWrd argu- no disposition to underrate, do not militate against the ment of atheism. existence and intelhgence but against the goodness of God, which is a Christian doctrine to be stated and defended when the proper time arrives.1 It is not so with the alleged imperfections of the world. They furnish an argument which the atheist may legiti mately employ against the beUef in any God, since chance is more likely to result in imperfection than is the act of creative inteUigence. We point out here that this argument, however, presupposes a finished world. From the point of view of those who hold to a sud den creation the argument would be difficult to overcome Presupposes if the facts of imperfection be substantiated. But if we a finished .... world. view the world as in process of evolution, as science, which modern atheists affect so much to revere, teaches us to do, then we should not expect perfection, but imperfection. A partiaUy devel oped world must appear imperfect from the ideal standpoint. God himself would so adjudge it. The only resource left for the atheist, then, is to assert that God would have created the world outright and perfect, and since the world has not so come into existence God has had nothing to do with it ; that the only use we have for a God is to create a perfect world. But no finite being can predict what infinite wisdom would elect to do ; and atheists themselves do not pretend to say that God would have done as we have supposed. Hence the ar gument of atheism from the imperfection of the world is valueless. But even on the supposition that the world is complete, the imper fections which it is supposed to exhibit do not necessarily rr Argument prove that infinite inteUigence did not produce it. Where from anal- there is so much that appears like intelUgent action as it is admitted the world affords, the argument from analogy would re- 'See division Iv, section ii, chapter v; and division viii, section vii, chapter ii and chapter iii. 46 Foundations of the Christian Faith. quire us to suppose that what does not appear such is nevertheless like all the rest. As the knowledge of nature increases, the realm which seems to human judgment unmeaning becomes constantly nar rower ; and this fact should lend force to the analogical argument just mentioned. It should also make us cautious about calling anything unmeaning or imperfect, since if our knowledge were more compre hensive and exact our estimates might be reversed. And we caU at tention once more to the fact that this supposition is not arbitrary, but founded upon the history of man's acquaintance with the world. So, then, although these aUeged imperfections might arouse in us a suspicion that they evince chance rather than design, they cannot possibly prove that it is so ; while in reaUty the preponderance of evi dence is on the other side. But we raise the question whether these alleged imperfections are imperfections in fact. Martineau in his Study of ReUgion ¦ takes up Martineau's this question and negatives it ki an exhaustive consider- ation of the facts. He classifies them as (1) those caUed useless and unmeaning, and (2) those regarded as positively hurtful. Under the former he mentions faults found in the inorganic world, such as the ice of the poles and the parching heat of the equatorial regions ; the vast deserts and seas uninhabitable by man ; the desola tion wrought by earthquakes, volcanoes, and hurricanes ; the absence of atmosphere and water in the moon, one side of which alone is ever turned toward the earth and whose periodic time gives us such scanty glimpses of its face ; the great gap between Mars and Jupiter with its insignificant asteroids ; the excessive heat of Mercury and cold of Neptune ; the fifteen years of alternate night and day near Saturn's poles ; the progressive cooUng, contraction, and resistance which must reduce the whole to a dead mass; and the enormous waste of space, unfilled by worlds, and of light, diluting itself through vacancy. Turning to the organic kingdom he mentions organs, such as the spleen and some glandular bodies, to which we can assign no function ; the wings of the ostrich, the feet of the sloth, and the ant lers of the deer, which but ill perform their function ; and organs never developed in the animal that bears them, as the teeth of the embryonic whale and bird ; the pretense of wings in numerous in sects that never fly ; the muscle under the skin used by the horse for throwing off flies, but which, though traceable in man, he has no power to use, and the functionless mammae on the breast of most mammalian males. 1 New York, 1888, vol. I, pp. 352-398. The Alleged Imperfections of the World. 47 We cannot even condense here his reply to these criticisms of creation ; but we cite one sentence which gives the clew to it. He says: " Facts of this kind may fairly enough be caUed Value of al leged use- unmeaning, if no more is intended by the phrase than less provi- si ons of that we do not know their raison d'etre ; and useless, if, nature. in order to try them, a purpose is assumed which they fail to serve.'' The fact is that whereas men call these things useless and unmeaning, they ought only to say they appear to us unmeaning and useless. Nor is this astonishing. We must judge according to our capacities if we judge at all ; though perhaps modesty would suggest that we refrain from judging concerning that of which we know so little. We have absolutely no way of knowing what the effects would be were things in nature different from what they are. Speculation on that question is useless, even if nothing in nature is useless. Though we should aUow that man's happiness only is to be consulted, still it is evident that there is ^precious little, if anything, which is useless and unmeaning even to our minds. We must consider that for man's interest in nature variety is needful, and some of the things above mentioned contribute to variety if to no other end. Man needs beauty, and what is more beautiful than the waxing and the waning moon? To this must be added that the moon is earth's timepiece for some of man's larger periods of time. The vast spaces of the sky develop a sense of awe ; and to this end even earthquakes, volcanoes, and hurricanes contribute. Undeveloped organs give us hints of the laws of development in the organic world. Deserts and oceans de velop the energy and the spirit of enterprise in man, and have pre vented the too wide dispersion of men over the face of the earth, to say nothing of other uses. We do not say that these are the ends which the things mentioned were intended to secure. We do say that they serve these, with many other ends, and that it is folly to assert that there is anything in the world which is useless and unmeaning to man. There is nothing that the atheist enjoys more than to charge believ ers in God with anthropomorphism. This word is frequently hurled at us also by those who profess to be unusuaUy objective in their thinking. But in maintaining that there are meaningless products in nature the theorist either assumes the strictly human standpoint according to which all that does not in some way minister to man is held to be without significance, or he presumes to judge the mean ing of each particular product in its relation to the whole purpose of the universe. If he is not anthropomorphic he must be omniscient. 48 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Under those provisions of nature which have been complained of as positively hurtful Martineau discusses three classes. His treatment is so exceUent that, though we cannot quote at length on the hu- his splendid rhetoric, we condense his argument for the 1113.11 6V© benefit of the reader. The first class is that comprising supposed faulty single organs of the animal economy. For example, the human eye has been charged by Helmholtz and others with serious imperfections, concerning some of which Helmholtz says: "Now, it is not too much to say that if an optician wanted to seU me an instrument which had all these defects, I should think myself quite justified in blaming his carelessness in the strongest terms."1 In view of Helmholtz's high standing in the scientific world this appears serious, though few of us are aware that the normal human eye is so imperfect and none of us know it except by scientific study ; so that for practical purposes the eye does its work in a satisfactory manner. No criticism on the theoretical imperfections of the eye can weigh against creative wisdom if, after all, it perfectly answers its ends. And this Helmholtz himself admits. "The eye has every possible defect that can be found in an optical instrument, and even some which are peculiar to itseU. " 2 " AU these imperfections would be exceedingly troublesome in an artificial camera obscura and in the photographic picture it produced. But they are not so in the eye." ' After further discussion he adds the foUowing refutation of himself : " The adaptation of the eye to its function is therefore most com plete, and is seen in the very limits which are set to its defects. Here the result which may be reached by innumerable generations work ing under the Darwinian law of inheritance coincides with what the wisest wisdom may have devised beforehand.'''' * Another instance of alleged unskUUulness in nature is cited from Darwin," as follows: "Can we consider the sting of the wasp or of the bee as perfect, which, when used against many attack- Darwin on ° •> the sting of ing animals, cannot be withdrawn, owing to the backward serratures, and so inevitably causes the death of the insect by tearing out its viscera?" But Darwin himself suggests that this is a case of a misapplied tool. Originally intended for cutting grooves in wood, which purpose it answered weU, it is sometimes employed as a bayonet. Hence it is the misuse, not the use, of the sting which is 1 Popular Lectures on Scientific Subjects, translated by E. Atkinson, with an introduc tion by Professor Tyndall, 1873, vi ; and Recent Progress of the Theory of Vision, trans lated by Dr. Pye Smith, p. 219. « Popular Lectures, p. 227. s Ibid., p. 224. * Ibid., p. 228. * Origin of Species, chapter vi, p. 202. The Alleged Imperfections of the World. 49 fatal. Besides, if the bee or wasp confined the use of its sting to war with its own kind it would receive no harm, as observation proves. And we add to what Martineau has said the consideration that the death of the insect in attacks upon men or domestic animals is really to be regarded as a benign and wise provision, tending to teach it better morals and to spare the human race from needless pain ; for aU its attacks upon others than its own kind are unnatural and un necessary. The second class of supposed hurtful phenomena has to do with the law of birth which regulates the arrival of new beings ; whether (a) of individuals, or (fi) of species. (a) The fecundity of animals, for instance, especiaUy of the lowest types, apparently amounts to a frightful excess. The herring's roe, the duck which wfll lay nearly one hundred, and the goose Exccssiv© which wfll lay about thirty eggs per year, are illustra- fecundity of animals. tions. Even among quadrupeds the provision for succes sors is profuse, the annual offspring of the rabbit, for example, amounting to upward of thirty. Of aU these preparations for life only a smaU proportion can fulfill its apparent end. In such dispro portion between preparation for and realization of the ends of Ufe is there any trace of wisdom ? In seeking an answer to this question it is necessary first of all to consider that, unlike ourselves, nature has no occasion for parsimony. Says Madame Dudevant : " Do we say that the exuberance of shrubbery and fruit is an error of nature ? Nature is prodigal because she is rich, not because she is foolish." • But, again, though a grain of wheat, for example, may miss its own intended end by finding its way into a loaf of bread, does it thereby fail of at least one of its natural purposes ? Nearly every- pr0ved to thing has an evident end in relation to something outside e un ue- of itseU. We can say that anything misses its end, then, only in case it misses every end it is adapted to subserve ; and Martineau might have added that in nature there is at least the hint of the Christian doctrine that nothing exists for itself alone, but that its highest reason for existence is its serviceableness to its neighbors. If its defeat, so far as itself is concerned, is better for its neighbors than its own perseverance, has it then added nothing to the general good? Is there then no sign of wisdom? "Whatever may be said, from considerations of humanity, against the system of prey, . . . it thus escapes the charge of breach of promise." Even the death of so many human infants is no evidence of unwisdom, and the con- 1 Nouvelles Lettres d'un Voyageur, Paris, 1877, referred to by Martineau in loc. 50 Foundations of the Christian Faith. trary opinion springs from an unwarranted expectation of long life. An infant has its right of existence not alone in view of an adult state that is to be, but also in view of what it is as an infant. If we con sider our own instead of the infant's claim to its right to continued life, we are in no better position to find fault with the wisdom which provides for early deaths. For to no parent can the value of child hood be estimated, even though the parent's farther expectation be not realized. (b) StiU sharper criticism is apphed to the birth-law of new species, on the assumption that it is correctly defined in the Dar- LicfsmofCthe winian hypothesis. Of the numerous "accidental" vari- of1 spelefes ations which hving organs may spontaneously take myri- answered. ^ ^^ ^ ^.^ ^ only thoge wm gtand which aid the animal in holding its footing in the world. The copartners in these happy changes find each other out and start the successful famines, thus founding fresh species. In the process nature destroys infinitely more of her own work than she preserves ; makes many failures for one hit. " If," says Lange,1 " a man, in order to shoot a hare, fired off milUons of gun barrels in aU random directions upon a great moor ; if, in order to get into a shut room, he brought ten thousand keys at haphazard and tried them aU ; if, in order to obtain a house, he built a city, and abandoned the superfluous houses to wind and weather," no one would " suppose that in this procedure there lay a higher wis dom, recondite reasons, and superior skill." In answer Martineau premises that the shot hare, the fitted key, the occupied house, stand for any new species which nature sets up, or a new organ that had been wrought out. The random discharges, wrong keys, empty tum ble-down houses, represent the aimless, fumbling, wasteful activity of nature on her way to the new species, the disappearance, without trace, of innumerable abortions from the world. But, allowing the Darwinian hypothesis, where are the millions of failures from the midst of which success has emerged ? Are the real steps of evo lution that have now advanced to man, the intermediaries between the ascidian and Shakespeare, to be regarded as missing shots ? That can hardly be, since they are the very means that have conducted to the end, and have not failed. Nor can we treat as failures those lines of variation which have resulted in something else than the human species. Unless everything is to be condemned as abortive which, in leading to an ulterior nature, at present stops short of it though car rying in it its own minor end, there is not the slightest resemblance 1 Gesohlchte des Materialismus, Zweltes Buch, 2ter Abschnit, p. 264. The Alleged Imperfections of the World. 51 between the real process of the organic world and the senseless actions with which Lange compares it. The third class has to do with the law of death, which provides for the dismissal, from the world, of superseded beings. While the struc ture of sentient creatures might suggest intelligence, it is said that a contemplation of the brevity of their existence indicates that nature sets no value on her own work, and hence leaves no room for the hypothesis of intelligence. But, says Martineau, whatever ends are pursued in nature must be temporary ends, admitting of The law of reahzation within a Umited term of existence, and the fended. vanishing of that existence affords no evidence that its purpose has broken short or failed. We can think of no better means of ren ovation than by the substitution of new organisms for old. Even the instinctive dread of death, if not checked by other facts, would produce ruin. Such a fact is the beneficence of death. In the case of human death also there is at least good reason to see inteUigence, to say nothing of beneficence. There may be advantages in a longer term of life, but the question is, How long should the term be ? Indi- viduaUy we should never, probably, be willing to die, nor to have our friends die, if our powers and theirs did not decay. Were the term prolonged so as to give us the centuries of Methuselah there would be no gain to man unless maturity were reached as early as with us ; in which case the world would be soon filled, and with but a limited number of families. If childhood, youth, manhood, and old age were long in proportion to the entire life, the effect would simply be to make progress slower. Under the former supposition society would exist on the principle of immense clans, and the fathers would possess an undue preponderance of influence as compared with youth. Under the latter supposition children would be born late in the life of their parents and far apart, so that to newcomers in the world the old would be older, and companions few. Besides, if great minds, such as that of Newton, continued among men for centuries, the general knowledge would be increased, but a few minds would do aU the work, thus discouraging effort with its consequent mental development. And if it were still regarded advantageous to have our benefactors live long, it must be remembered that the tyrants and wicked men would have a similar lease of life. These considerations relative to the supposed blemishes in nature show that after all there is no adequate ground, for calling them blem ishes. If there is no such ground then there is no reason to be drawn from them which would warrant the denial of inteUigence in the 52 Foundations of the Christian Faith. ordering of the world, as the atheist does. We have given a large space to this entire third argument of atheism because it is the pop- Atheistic ar- ular one; the people employ it or are staggered by it. g u m e n t from im- It now seems evident that, although there are some inex- popular but plicable mysteries in the world, they are not sufficient w 1 tho ut , , ¦,,.-, ¦ * r force. to overthrow the preponderant evidences m favor of inteUigence; so that the atheistic view has no basis here on which to rest. In our whole treatment of the subject of atheism we have endeav ored to observe the Christian law of thinking no evil. We have striven to attribute to thoughtful atheists an unaffected sincerity. We ask them to give our remarks an equaUy fair consideration. Their difficulties wfll not all be removed. But we think that enough has been said to accomplish our purpose, namely, to show that, whether there be any other and better way of accounting for the world, at least the atheistic theory does not account for it. -ri-tuNObiiuisM uu ij_u.vi.jiji jvs a Practical System. 53 SECTION II.-AGNOSTICISM. CHAPTER I. THE AGNOSTICISM OF HUXLEY AS A PRACTICAL SYSTEM. Agnosticism is a word of recent origin, invented by Professor Thomas H. Huxley, as an epithet by which to designate Huxley's his intellectual attitude toward conclusions of atheism, oV^tVe1 theism, pantheism, materialism, idealism, and Christianity. word- Most people had, in their own judgment, more or less successfully solved the problem of existence by one means or another, while Pro fessor Huxley felt sure that he had not solved it, and, moreover, was pretty strongly convinced that the problem was insoluble ; that is, that all the others were deceived in thinking they had solved it. In this conviction he was conscious of having Hume and Kant on his side. Yet he could find no term by which to designate this mental attitude, until, in the reflection that the gnostics of Church history professed to know so much about the very things of which he was ignorant, he hit upon the term agnostic' This account of the origin of the epithet agnostic, given by its inventor, relieves him of the charge of attempting, by the adoption of the term, to shift the issue in relation to the Church and Christianity,2 though the affirmation connected with the charge that the term ' ' involves a mere evasion" is, we think, in practice, true. So, then, agnosticism was not intended to be a mere cowardly name for atheism, since it originally designated an ignorance as to matters of fact which the atheist does not profess. Nevertheless, the agnostic position is one that troubles the atheist very little. He is quite content with those who, though gngnt differ- they will not say they know or are certain that there is no twcen *a|- God, take up the position that they do not know, or have Sthel s't'ic no evidence sufficient to convince them, that there is a position. God. For in fact this is exactly the position maintained by most ] Huxley's Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, New York, 1892, p. 27. The ety mology of the word has been criticised and its needlessness pointed out by President Schurman's Belief in God, New York, 1893, Lecture I. 2 This charge was made by Dr. Wace, Principal of King's College, London, in a paper read at the Manchester Church Congress, 1888. See Christianity and Agnosticism, New York, 1889, p. 6. 6 54 Foundations of the Christian Faith. atheists, and there can be no doubt that, whether by intention or not, agnosticism has greatly strengthened theoretical and practical athe ism. That it has also served and wfll yet serve to moderate the excess ive dogmatism of some theologians is one of the proofs that, as we have our treasure in earthen vessels, we need those who, by their extremes of denial, lead us to inquire whether we have not ventured to be wise above that which is written. The genuine agnostic, in the sense indi cated by Professor Huxley's history of the origin of the term, may find fault when we assert, as knowledge, details concerning things un seen, though he can find no fault if we assert them as beliefs, even though he may not regard our beUefs weU founded with respect ta those things. But agnosticism, as denned by Huxley himself, is something more than a conditon of ignorance. "Agnosticism, in fact, is not a creed but a method, the essence of which lies in the rigorous appUcation of a single principle." ' " Positively the principle may be expressed : In matters of the intellect foUow your reason as far as it will take you without regard to any other consideration. And negatively : In mat ters of the inteUect do not pretend that conclusions are certain which are not demonstrated or demonstrable." If we rightly understand Agnosticism this description of agnosticism it is a method of investiga- of^nves°tf- tion in matters with which the inteUect concerns itself. gation. It insists that when the inteUect is at work it shall employ reason only, pushing aside any and all other considerations. The em ployment of this method may lead us, as Professor Huxley says it led him,2 " nowhere else but into the dark depths of a wild and tangled forest ;" but this discovery should not deter us from foUowing our rea son " as far as it wfll take us." We are concerned just now, not to attempt a refutation, but a statement of agnosticism ; stiU, we cannot refrain from declaring that, if in foUowing reason alone we are led in our thinking nowhere but " into the dark depths of a wild and tangled forest," we certainly have just cause to suspect, either that we have misread the signboard and have been following some other than the path of reason, or else that, after all, reason may be a good path to follow, part but not all of the way, through the continent of thought. This, not that we should shrink from foUowing reason into those dark depths because they are unpleasant or frightful to us, but because when we see that any road, be it reason or any other, takes us nowhere, but constantly plunges us further into intellectual confu sion, we should suspect the sufficiency of the road we have chosen. 1 Essays upou Some Controverted Questions, p. 281. > Ibid, p. 276. Agnosticism of Huxley as a Practical System. 55 We must do this, unless we have deliberately decided that the uni verse is unintelligible, and this the agnostic cannot know. If he has the slightest suspicion that it is inteUigible, and discovers that reason, followed alone, makes it wholly unintelligible, it would be an evi dence of nothing but dogmatic stubbornness of the most antiagnos- tic kind to be minded, as Professor Huxley says,1 "to go straight on until I either come out on the other side of the wood or find there is no other side to it, at least, none attainable by me." This discussion has not been intended to afford any argument against agnosticism as such, but merely to bring to hght this method of foUowing to its last consequences the lead of reason alone, in mat ters of inteUect, and not aUowing ourselves to be deterred by any consequences of any kind whatever. And we have now reached a point where it has become plain that if agnosticism, as Based 0n a Huxley adheres to it, is not a creed, it is a method based creed- on a creed whose principal article is the exclusive right of reason to guide us in matters of inteUectual activity ; and that Professor Hux ley holds fast to this creed with a grim determination not surpassed by any theological dogmatist of any age.* In order to exhibit further the Huxleyan agnosticism we turn to his negative expression of the principle which underlies agnosticism as a method. It might be pertinent to show that in following reason so faithfully Professor Huxley has acted at least as though the wisdom of such foUowing were demonstrated or demonstrable. But, whether pertinent or impertinent, to call attention to the fact has the merit of bringing us to see that in this negative expression of his principle he has said nothing new nor to the point. For all will admit it as it stands, but each will reserve the right to determine what has been demon strated or is demonstrable. Professor Huxley regards the F u r t h e r cbaraeteri- sufficiency of reason as so demonstrable that he would fol- z at ion of agn osti- low it, which he did, his life long, though intellectually it cism. led him through (and kept him in) the dark depths of a wild and tan gled forest. The majority of us would consider that very result as sufficient demonstration that reason, or at least Professor Huxley's use of it, was not a sufficient guide in intellectual concerns. But not only is there difficulty in determining when any proposition is demonstrated or demonstrable ; it is to be observed also that it touches only the regarding of conclusions as certain without demon- 1 Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 277. 2 That Huxley continued to the end this adherence to the agnostic creed is made clear by E. Clodd, in his Pioneers of Evolution, New York, 1897, pp. 201-266. Comp. also an article on Professor Huxley's Creed, in the Quarterly Review, vol. clxxx, pp. 160 ff. 56 Foundations of the Christian Faith. stration. If we regard them as probable, in other words, the princi ple of agnosticism as here laid down does not affect them. Again, this exposition of agnosticism as a method would not be even relatively complete did we not call attention to the significance of the word method itself. A method is a process for reaching results. Professor Huxley has described agnosticism as a method for reaching intellectual results ; that is, conclusions. He has made reason the sole instrument employed in the process. That, hovever, is not the point here. The point is that agnosticism, as interpreted by Huxley, is not content to remain in a condition of ignorance concerning the problems of existence, but has its own methods of investigating those problems. In other words, it proposes, not to aUow atheists, theists, pantheists, etc., to do all the work of investigation, but to enter upon that work itself, in its own way. It is not content with Agnosticism the role of a mere spectator ; much less to ignore the to remain questions at issue. Hence we must expect it to reach con- rance. elusions. From this point of view, even though we had none of the conclusions of agnostics before us, we should be compeUed to look at it with a profound degree of interest, if not of anxiety. For, to change the figure, it enters the field with the assertion that aU of us have failed to find the solution we have claimed, and, further, it has an exclusive method by which such investigations should be con ducted. Thus Christians are compelled to see in agnosticism, not a state of mental ignorance relative to God and the soul, but, at least in some respects, an antagonist. In order that we may stiU more completely understand the nature of Huxleyan agnosticism, we must take a further statement from the great scientist. " Agnosticism," he says,1 "is not properly described as a ' negative ' creed, nor indeed as a creed of any kind, except in so far as it expresses absolute faith in the validity of a principle which is as much ethical as inteUectual." This principle is the one just discussed, as stated in its intellectual aspects. As to its ethical aspects he says : " This principle may be stated in various ways, but they all amount to this : that it is wrong for a man to say that he is certain of the objective truth of any proposition unless he can produce evidence which logically justifies that certainty." Further: "The ap- Results plication of that principle results in the denial of or the reached by .... agnostic suspension of judgment concerning, a number of Dronosi- method. ,. , . , r r tions respecting which our contemporary ecclesiastical ' gnostics ' profess entire certainty." All this is intended as an ethical 1 Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, pp. 350,351. LUItUO IILHOIU \JJ* XJ- UAiifJ 1 as a Practical System. 57 justification of the denial of, or the suspension of judgment concern ing, a number of propositions connected with the Christian system. As he does not limit the ecclesiastical gnostics by any other word than contemporary, and as the controversy which occasioned his re marks was with Protestant theologians, we may presume that he had in mind Protestant doctrines or propositions. Perhaps he has gone too far in attributing to these "gnostics" entire certainty. But, whether this be the case or not, at least we see that agnosticism of the Huxleyan type leads to the denial of these propositions — or at least to suspension of judgment concerning them ; and not only as an intellectual necessity, but also as an ethical. The denial of a proposition certainly bears a strong resemblance to what is ordinarily called a negative creed ; and the same closely re- may be said, though in a lower degree, of suspension of creed 6neg^ judgment concerning it. Both of them are unqualifiedly chrisUani- negative when compared with the assertions made by Jesus y' Christ. In response to Christ's positive assertion the Huxleyan agnos tic says, "Surely not," or at least, " Perhaps not." When Professor Huxley appeals to his conscience, and declares that it forbids him to do otherwise because he can produce no "evidence which logically justifies " certainty, he plainly refuses all evidence whatever, and de nies or suspends judgment simply because he has assigned these propo sitions a purely intellectual significance and because he has followed reason alone, "without regard to any other consideration." Thus each agnostic judges all, or at any rate some, of the essentials of the Christian system by the light of reason alone, putting aside all other considerations such as the effects of Christianity on the individual Christian life. And each makes reason coequal with his own individ ual reason. He will not aUow the judgments of others any weight. This would be to give up the agnostic principle as interpreted by Huxley. If it is proper to speak of the pride of reason, surely it is proper to do so here. For while we may trust reason implicitly, ab stractly considered, it is very certain that experience teaches us that reason as used in almost every concrete instance has led men more or less astray. We point out then here some of the fatal defects of agnosticism so far as we have already studied it. It establishes the individual reason as the sole guide in inteUectual concerns. It makes a virtue of standing by the findings of the individual reason, regardless of what they are. All this sounds exceedingly plausible. For who is not wflling to praise the power of reason ? and who does not recognize the courage of 58 Foundations of the Christian .faith. the man who wfll follow so infaUible a guide to any length, even to the martyrdom of being led into the " dark depths of a wild and tan gled forest to which there is no other side ? " The man who wfll do that must be a truth-seeker indeed. But, alas ! the infaUibflity of the Fallibility of individual reason is not demonstrated nor demonstrable, uai reasom though its frequent falUbility is. So then the Huxleyan agnostic is, to say the least, inconsistent when he accepts as so very secure the guidance of reason. He is obliged to do as other mortals, accepting some guide and trusting in its leadings to the end. Only he is doubly credulous ; for he accepts the abstract thing caUed rea son, and also his own appUcation of it, without regard to any other consideration whatever. Furthermore, this principle, so far from being "the fundamental axiom of modern science," as Professor Huxley assures us it is,' vio lates the principles of scientific investigation at every point. True science does not follow reason even though it leads into the " dark depths of a wild and tangled forest." When any principle, whatever it be, fails to lead the investigator into clearer knowledge, he rejects it. When, in the use of reason, men are led into intellectual dark ness in any realm of thought, science teUs them that either they are not using reason or they are making an inadequate or otherwise im- Agnostic ProPer use °f it. Science advances on the principle of re- u nVci en*- Jectmg a:nJ method which affords no clear and harmonious tific. view of all known facts in a given realm ; and it will rea son on all facts, refusing to declare alleged facts no facts because apparently out of harmony with the reasoner's reason. Science em ploys reason to account for the fact, not as a universal means by which to determine whether alleged facts be real facts. In determin ing facts reason is indeed employed ; but so is observation. We do not need reason, in the sense in which Professor Huxley uses the term, to determine whether we have a headache, or experience happiness, or anticipate disaster. These are facts to be explained, and in the process of explanation reason is employed ; but if it fail to explain them we should call in some other aid, refusing to follow reason, even though it confused our minds with reference to the facts. Huxley is not alone in his appreciation of reason. In this all intel- lectuaUy earnest thinkers would foUow him. But he forgets what some others remember, namely, that reason is but a logical apparatus for the attainment of insight. Granting that one employs his reason correctly, the outcome may still be intellectual confusion, owing to 1 Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 281. Agnosticism of Huxley as a Practical System. 59 wrong or inadequate data and presuppositions. The fact that Huxley remained to the end in the "wfld and tangled forest " indicates that his data or his presuppositions, or both, should have been subjected to a thoroughgoing criticism and revision. Had this been done he would have found, as so many others have found, that to this tangled forest there is "another side." 60 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. HUXLEY'S deceptive terminology. The history of the word agnosticism which Professor Huxley gives shows that it was coined for the purpose of expressing an attitude or condition of mind with reference to the great problems of religion. We have seen also that the principle which underlies the agnostic method is, according to Huxley, that reason is a safe and the only proper guide, no matter where it brings us ; and that the appUcation of the principle ' ' results in the denial of, or the suspension of judgment concerning, a number of propositions respecting which our contem porary ecclesiastical ' gnostics' profess entire certainty." Did agnosticism do nothing more than this last it would not be so very dangerous. But it does not stop with the suspension of judg ment concerning these propositions ; it acts as though they were not true. "In the business of life," says Professor Huxley,1 " we constantly take the most serious action upon evidence of an utterly insufficient Huxley on character. But it is surely plain that faith is not entitled ratiocfna- to dispense with ratiocination, because ratiocination can not dispense with faith as a starting point; and that, because we are often obhged by the pressure of events to act on very bad evidence, it does not follow that it is proper to act on such evi dence when the pressure is absent." Several things must be noted in connection with these statements. First, they are made in order to illustrate the use of faith in "the business of life," on the one hand, and in religion on the other. Second, it is assumed that the evidence upon which religious action depends is "very bad," " utterly insuffi cient." Third, that while we act on such evidence in "the business of Ufe," we need not act upon it in matters of reUgion, because, in the former, pressure is brought to bear which requires action, whfle in the latter there is no such pressure. Now, we shall pass over the as sumption that the evidence for religious action is utterly insufficient. This is not the place for the display of the evidence. We confine ourselves to the third point noted. While, according to the agnostic principle, in matters of intellect we must follow reason alone, no 1 Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 280. Huxley's Deceptive Terminology. 61 matter where it leads us, it appears that the considerations which should govern us in the business of life are not applicable in religion, because the pressure is present in the one and absent in the other. These two agnostic principles completely destroy all religious belief and all religious activity ; that is to say, according to Professor Hux ley, they leave nothing of religion. Now, we all admit that we act in many cases on very insufficient evidence, because action is demanded. The evidence that one can earn a Uvelihood in a given line of business may be very inadequate, but if this is the only line open to him he is '.' pressure" ^ J r in religion. obliged to follow it or go hungry. The pressure of need is upon him. But we judge that Professor Huxley feels no pressure of religious need, and that he attributes his own state to all others. If not, he ought to have made it clear that all who feel such need are as properly within limits when they act on the bad evidence of reUgion as when they act on bad evidence in any other practical concern. For religion is not merely, nor chiefly, a series of propo sitions. Even the credal propositions we possess are all designed to bear on the practical side of religion, though some of them may be confessed to bear very remotely upon it. Religious action grows out of the needs of the heart as truly as business action springs from the needs of the body. The pressure does not arise from the same source, but it is as great in one realm as in the other. That it appears otherwise is owing to the fact that we have as the basis of life a physical being to which we have given far more attention than we have to our spiritual nature. But even if one were dis posed to deny that the pressure is as great in reference to religion as it is in reference to food, still it is false to assume that it is whoUy absent in any considerable number of cases with reference to the former. We cannot help asking what is meant by evidence of an utterly insufficient character. Insufficient for what ? For the estabhsh- ment of a proposition? If that is what is meant, would we act in Professor Huxley teU us that where pressure is absent £& without we must not act? If it is irrational to act in the absence a^merce- „ ., ' * i. nary kind. of certainty except where there is a pressure of events, even science itself will make slow progress. For science acts on many a hypothesis the evidence for which is, at first, utterly insuffi cient for its confirmation ; and it acts on it in the hope of finding the confirmatory evidence, which hope is often realized. There is no particular pressure in the mercenary nor in the physical sense of the '62 Foundations of the Christian Faith. word. There is a pressure which arises from the desire for knowl edge, or perhaps from the benevolent desire to confer some benefit on mankind. Such a pressure is on most of us for religious action. There is in most of us a desire to know, in the sense of experiencing for ourselves, the truth, for example, of the proposition that we can be saved from the power which certain of our pecuUarly offensive propensities exercise over us. Many a one has started on the search for this knowledge scarcely believing that it was possible to attain it; at least, the evidence he had was in nowise convincing. He acted in order to test this particular religious hypothesis ; not, indeed, for the sake of establishing merely an inteUectual proposition, but for the sake of the benefit he would derive if the proposition were found true. If Huxley's agnostic principles were to be adopted, not only would scientific investigation lose one of its main methods for the ¦establishment of fact, but morality would be deprived of one of its principal means of advancement. Thus, in the course of our investigation, we have discovered that agnosticism has completely changed its form. It quietly substitutes Suggestion "I do not believe" for "I do not know," and yet calls accurate itself agnosticism to distinguish itself from gnosticism. nomencla- . ture. What rights has agnosticism in the realm of belief ? But it draws the practical conclusion from its "I do not beUeve," and says, " I wfll not act." If it had remained agnosticism it might have acted, in spite of its lack of knowledge. But its "I do not beUeve " is a complete annihilation of all impulse to action. The difference be tween agnosticism in this form and atheism is almost, if not whoUy, in name. Let the adherents of this phase of, irreUgion caU them selves, not agnostics, signifying their lack of knowledge, but apistics, signifying their lack of beUef ; and let them caU their system, not agnosticism, but apisticism. The mongrel character of the word is no more marked in the one case than in the other, and the name we propose has the merit of describing the fact. Translated into English, for those who do not care to hide the real facts from the English reader by the use of a Greek form, we should have for apistics, un believers, and for apisticism, unbeUef . To designate his inaction the agnostic might call himseU an aergist and his system of inaction aergisticism. Agnosticism comes to us in the garb of modest reserve and intel lectual honesty. As an inteUectual attitude or condition it presents no alarming features. Every honest man, in his reflecting moments, has felt the necessity of caution in statement, however he may have Huxley's Deceptive Terminology. 63 transgressed in this respect under the influence of emotion. AU our admiration and confidence disappear, however, when we discover that it is a method and a creed, or at any rate a method based on a creed, both of which are fundamentaUy antireligious, impracticable, and unscientific. We now proceed, to show that it is based on a false philosophy. That philosophy, so far as the Huxleyan form of agnosticism is concerned, is weU stated by Professor Huxley as foUows:1 "The results of the working out of the agnostic princi ple will vary according to individual knowledge and capacity, and according to the general condition of science. That which is unproved to-day may be proved by the help of new discoveries to-morrow. The only negative fixed points will be those negations which flow from the demonstrable Umitation of our faculties." It is the last of these sentences which contains the kernel of the agnostic phflosophy. In the nature of the case we never can prove by any discoveries what by reason of the limitations of Agnosticism our faculties we could not know. In order to ascertain a af|i|e pn° the limits of our knowledge, therefore, we must discover osop y' what are the limitations of our faculties. The distinguishing feature in the philosophies of Hume and Kant was just this attempt to dis cover these limitations, and Professor Huxley professedly adheres to their philosophic views. He says:2 "The reader . . . wfll now see why my mind steadily gravitated toward the conclusions of Hume and Kant." He quotes approvingly from Kant the following: "The greatest and perhaps the sole use of all phflosophy of pure reason is, after aU, merely negative, since it serves, not as an organon for the enlargement (of knowledge), but as a discipline for its delimitation." And again: "With Hume and Kant on my side I could not think myself presumptuous in holding fast by that opinion," that is, the opinion that the problem of existence was insoluble. a Hume and Kant were not caUed agnostics ; but, since their philosophy with reference to the limitations of our faculties is made the basis of the agnostic system of practice, our next task must be to consider their phflosophy, which, so far at least as Hume is concerned, it ought to be remarked, is in such discredit among philosophers of to-day that it almost looks as though Huxley had read philosophy until he came to something bearing the impress of two strong names— something also exactly suited to his agnostic purposes— and had then refused to go further. » Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 282. » Ibid., p. 275 f. •Comp. his Hume, New York, 1879, pp. 55-58. 64 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF HUXLEYAN AGNOSTICISM— THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUME. For our present purposes Hume's philosophy is sufficiently por trayed in his Inquiry Concerning the Human Understanding. 1 His somewhat ambiguous use of words makes it difficult to ascertain exactly his meaning. Nevertheless, on the main points it is not easy to misunderstand his positions. His philosophy is in fact a theory of knowledge relating (1) To the Methods of Its Acquisition, and (2) To Its Limits. (1) The Methods of Acquiring Knowledge. We mention three methods which Hume seems to distinguish : A. Intuition and Demonstration. He says:2 " AU the objects of human reason or inquiry may naturaUy be divided into two kinds ; to wit, Relations of Ideas, and Matters of Fact. Of the first kind are the sciences of Geometry, Algebra, and Arithmetic, and, in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstrably cer tain." B. Sensations and Other Impressions. "Everyone will readily al low that there is a considerable difference between the perceptions of the mind when a man feels the pain of excessive heat or the pleasure of moderate warmth, and when he afterward recaUs to his memory this sensation, or anticipates it by his imagination. These faculties may mimic or copy the perceptions of the senses, but they never can entirely reach the force and vivacity of the original sentiment. The utmost we say of them, even when they operate with great est vigor, is that they represent their object in so lively a man ner that we could almost say we feel or see it." 8 " We may observe a like distinction to run through aU the perceptions of the mind. ideas and A man m a nt of anger is actuated in a very different sioiisdis- manner from one who only thinks of that emotion. If tmguished. you tell m0 tnat any person is in lov6) j g^jjy understand your meaning and form a just conception of his situation, but never 1 The Philosophical Works of David Hume, four vols., Boston, 1S54, vol. iv. Our ref erences will be to the " Inquiry" as found in the volume just mentioned. » Ibid., p. 30. » Ibid., p. 16. Philosophic Bksis of Huxleyan Agnosticism. 65 can mistake that conception for the real disorders and agitations of the passion." " Here, therefore, we may divide all the perceptions of the mind into two classes, or species, which are distinguished by their different degrees of force and vivacity. The less forcible and lively are commonly denominated thoughts or ideas. The other species want a name. . . . Let us, therefore, use a little freedom and call them impressions. ... By the term impression, then, I mean all our more Uvely perceptions, when we hear, or see, or feel, or love, or hate, or desire, or wfll." ¦ Thus sensations and impressions not only furnish us knowledge, but by the action of memory and imagination we have ideas or thoughts. C. Inference from Cause and Effect. "By means of that relation (of cause and effect) alone we can go beyond the evidence of our memory and senses." "A man, finding a watch or any other ma chine in a desert island, would conclude that there had once been men in that island. All our reasonings concerning fact are of the same nature. And here it is constantly supposed that there is a con nection between the present fact and that which is inferred from it. Were there nothing to bind them together, the inference would be entirely precarious. The hearing of an articulate voice and rational discourse in the dark assures us of the presence of some person; why ? because these are the effects of the human make and fabric, and closely connected with it. " 2 These, in brief, are the three methods by which we acquire knowl edge. But we have given them place rather for the sake of complete ness of outline and for purposes of definition than because they bear upon the agnostic philosophy. The real point we now attempt to por tray. (2) The Limits of Human Knowledge. These are determined in three ways. A. By Its Sources. Among these he ranks intuition and demon stration,3 together with impressions as the source of ideas.4 B. By Its Means. It is here that the much-discussed Bepresenta- tional theory of perception makes its appearance in Hume's system. "It seems evident," he says," "that men are carried TheKe re_ by a natural instinct or prepossession to repose faith in sentationai their senses. ... It seems also evident that, when men follow this blind and powerful instinct of nature, they always sup pose the very images presented by the senses to be the external ob- 1 Hume, Inquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, p. 15 f. 2 Ibid., p. 31 f. 3Ibid., p. 188. i Ibid., pp. 183 ff. 6 Ibid., p. 172 ff. 66 Foundations of the Christian Faith. jects, and never entertain any suspicion that the one are nothing but representations of the other. . . . But this universal and primary opinion of aU men is soon destroyed by the slightest touch of philos ophy, which teaches us that nothing can ever be present to the mind but an image or perception, and that the senses are only the inlets through which these images are conveyed, without being able to pro duce any immediate intercourse between the mind and the object. No man who reflects ever doubted that the existences which we consider when we say this house, and that tree, are nothing but perceptions in the mind, and fleeting copies or representations of other existences which remain uniform and independent." Note the practical bearing of aU this. "By what argument can it be proved that the perceptions of the mind must be caused by external objects entirely different from them, though resembling them (if that be pos sible), and could not arise either from the energy of the mind itseff, or from the suggestion of some invisible and unknown spirit, or from some other cause still more unknown to us ? ... It is a question of fact whether the perceptions of the senses be produced by external objects resembling them. How shaU this question be determined? By experience, surely, as aU other questions of a like nature. But here experience is, and must be, entirely silent. The mind has never anything present to it but the perceptions, and cannot possibly reach any experience of their connection with objects. The supposition of such a connection is, therefore, without any foundation in reasoning." The second of the two principal means of knowledge upon which Hume depends for the proof of the limitations of our knowledge is the inference from cause and effect, before mentioned as Inference . . from cause a method of knowing. It is, says Hume, in effect, a and effect. method of knowing, but it is a method which iUustrates how little we can go beyond the evidence of sense and memory. " If we would satisfy ourselves, therefore, concerning the nature of that evidence which assures us of matters of fact (that is, apparently, of that which lies beyond the evidence of the senses and memory), we must inquire how we arrive at the knowledge of cause and effect." " The knowledge of this relation (cause and effect) is not, in any in stance, attained by reasoning a priori; but arises entirely from expe rience when we find that any particular objects are constantly con joined with each other." 1 " Every effect is a distinct event from its cause." "It could not, therefore, be discovered in the cause ; and the first invention or conception of it a priori must be entirely arbi- 1 Hume, Inquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, p. 32. r hilosophic Basis of Huxleyan Agnosticism. 67' trary." "In vain, therefore, should we pretend to determine any sin gle event, or infer any cause or effect, without the assistance of obser vation and experience." " All inferences from experience, therefore, are effects of custom, not of reasoning." "Having found in many instances that any two kinds of objects, flame and heat, snow and cold, have always been conjoined together : if flame or snow be pre sented anew to the senses, the mind is carried by custom to expect heat or cold, and to believe that such a quality does exist and wfll dis cover itself upon nearer approach." As the conclusion of the whole matter, he says that if we go into a Ubrary and take up any volume, we should ask, " Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number ? No. Does it contain any experimental rea soning concerning matter of fact and existence ? No. Commit it then to the flames ; for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illu sion." 1 C. By Our Capacities. " They (the philosophically disposed) will. never be tempted," says Hume,2 "to go beyond common life so long as they consider the imperfection of those faculties which they em ploy, their narrow reach, and their inaccurate operations. While we cannot give a satisfactory reason why we believe, after a thousand experiments, that a stone will fall, or fire burn, can we ever satisfy ourselves concerning any determination which we may form with regard to the origin of worlds, and the situation of nature from, and. to, eternity ? " 1 Hume, Inquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, p. 188. a Ibid., p. 184 f . 68 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. criticism of hume's agnostic principles. After reading this outline of Hume's philosophy we shall be con vinced that, though without the name, Hume was an agnostic. The sources and means of knowledge and the limits of our capacities combine to prevent our knowing anything but mathematical truth, and, perhaps, somewhat of the ordinary course of nature. But even in the practical concerns of life we are not sure that we know what to do. We can at most believe that the future will be as the past. And we do not wonder that Huxley says that he had Hume on his side in entertain ing a pretty strong conviction that the problem of existence is insoluble. ' For our purposes it wfll not be necessary to consider this whole out lined scheme, but only so much of it as relates to the determination of the limits of our knowledge ; and of this we shall take into account only a part. Nor can we give a fuU discussion of a truer theoiy of knowledge than that of Hume. For such theory we must refer the reader to works especially devoted to the subject.2 We shaU confine ourselves to some hints that may suffice to show the inadequacy and falsity of Hume's theory, which is all that is needed in the overthrow of agnosticism. Under the limits of knowledge as determined by its sources we shaU examine his theory of impressions as the source of ideas. We are not anxious to emphasize, what has often been pointed out, that the distinction which Hume makes between impressions and ideas is su perficial, artificial, and valueless. It is more to the purpose that his definition of these terms is false, and the relation which he makes them sustain to each other, at least in part, inverted. Hume's notion seems to be (1) that an impression is itself a simple, Complexity uncompounded thing, and (2) that the mind is the passive of Hume's . . , . . s o-c -,i 1 1 e d recipient ol it. JLet us examine a couple of the impressions Impressions. . . . , . . mentioned by him ; for example, that of loving. It is cer tainly very complex, including the consciousness of seU, of the loved 1 Essays upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 276. 2 One of the best is Theory of Thought and Knowledge, by Borden P. Bowne, professor of philosophy In Boston University, New York, issi7. Another excellent work is Philoso phy of Knowledge, by George T. Ladd, professor of philosophy in Yale University, New York, 1897. uriticism of Hume's Agnostic Principles. 69 one, and of love itseU more or less clearly differentiated from friend ship, indifference, and iU-will. And even these necessary elements of consciousness in loving do not exist simple and alone. Self is in some measure distinguished from aU that is not self, the object of my love from others toward whom I feel no such affection, and love itself is in part admiration and in part an indefinable attraction. It is perfectly evident that in loving the impression is not uncom- pounded. But it is far more important to note that the mind is not passive. The activity of the mind is even more apparent The activity ,. ... ,, . . „ „ of the mind in connection with the impression of suffering from excess- in connec- ive heat. This impression is exceedingly complex, and in them. connection with it the mind is of necessity active. The mind need not emphasize but it must be conscious of the self ; it must conceive of suffering; of these two as connected; of heat and of the degree of heat. Each of these elements of the complex impression is itself com plex to a degree, and the mind with incredible swiftness takes cogni zance of each of the absolutely simple elements, compounds them into higher units, and then compounds these units into the unit which Hume calls the impression of suffering from excessive heat. Itnow becomes necessary to define more exactly the activity of the mind in connection with any impression, or, as the modern psycholo gist would say, perception. A piece of hot metal is brought T^tiv?tind^ into contact with the tip of my finger. What is the proc- amined. ess by which I become aware of the fact? First, there is the con sciousness that I am being touched ; second, that I experience pain ; third, I discern that the pain is of a definite kind ; and fourth, I locate it in a definite portion of my body. These are not all the steps in the process, but the other steps do not differ in kind. In each case the mind does all that is done. This is true even in the simplest percep tion of an object. For example, we say that we see a book on the table. It is a psychological commonplace that all the eye receives from the book is the beating of the ether waves upon the retina. When the effects of these waves are carried to the brain, what have we as a result ? Nothing but a form of motion in the physical ele ments. We have as yet not even a sensation. The age-long efforts of materialists have only served to emphasize the fact that in the brain we have physical movements alone. AU beyond this is mental activity, strictly so-called. Without stopping to be overnice in our analysis, we point out that, instead of an indefinite series of move ments, we have the one sensation. Each variety of physical movement results in a specific sensation unrelated to aU others. Then foUows 10 Foundations of the Christian jjaith. the relating activity, and the objectifying of the whole under the form of space, and the application of the various other categories, such as time, substance, causality. The fact that this process is in the main automatic does not in the least invaUdate the conclusion that it is strictly the product of mental activity as distinguished from the physical. As soon as the nervous changes have taken place the mind begins to operate. On the one side we have nervous change, on the other mental activity. But the mind has not noted the nervous changes; the mental process would be the same in a person who did not know that he had nerves. How mental activity and nervous 'changes are connected it is impossible to determine. Certain it is that the nervous changes are not the impression (perception) nor any part of it, and that impressions are not the ready-made things Hume thought them to be. It must follow inevitably that the mind forms its own im pressions, instead of their being formed for it and stamped upon it or thrust into it. Figuratively we may speak of the mind as containing thoughts, or as having impressions made upon it, as though it were a piece of hoUow ware or a waxen tablet into which things called per ceptions can be put or upon which they can be stamped ; but it is mis leading to take these figures for facts. We do not know the whole process by which we gain impressions, but we do know that they are not injected into nor imposed upon the mind by external objects ; for we have discovered by analysis how the mind constructs and defines its own perceptions in response to the physical stimulus. So when Hume tells us that all our ideas are feeble copies of impres sions we are able to perceive more exactly the amount of truth there is in what he says. If impressions are not altogether nor chiefly the re sult of the power of external objects over us, but rather the product of our own mental action under given conditions, then the copying of impressions or perceptions for the purpose of obtaining ideas must mean simply the mind's copying of its own activities, that is, remem bering what it has done. ' The analysis of Hume's impressions further betrays the fact that the mind is in possession of ideas which cannot be reduced to Humian ideas not re- impressions, nor any compound, transposition, augmenta- Humiau im- tion, or diminution of them. Such is the idea of seU. It pi ess ons. jg nQ^ jn an^ sense a feeble copy of a lively impression which preceded it. It is indeed difficult to get at the origin of the idea 1 The immense significance of this conclusion for the theistic argument need not be pointed out here. Criticism of Hume's Agnostic Principles. 71 of seK, but we know that it is not a copy of an impression. It is the primary fact and presupposition of the mental life.1 At the earliest dawn of knowledge it is there, however vague its form, as a part of our mental outfit. Nor is it the result of the analysis (division, dimi nution), nor of a compound, nor of an augmentation, nor of a transpo sition of any impression or set of impressions. It is a fundamental element in every impression. We have no impression of seU in the same sense in which we have an impression of chill, or warmth, or pressure, or sorrow, or joy. But prior to and entering into aU Humian impressions is the idea of self ; for not only must there be a seU in order to such an impression, but there must be the idea of self. Without this the impression is impossible.2 So far, then, from aU ideas being copies of impressions, every impression is in part a syn thesis of ideas ; that is, some ideas at least are prior to impressions and necessary to them. We are not particular to answer aU the questions that might be asked concerning the origin of ideas. From one aspect they all appear innate, in the sense that they are potentially in the mind origin of and are called into consciousness under the appropriate * eas' stimulus. Especially is this true of certain ideas which, when formu lated, are caUed axioms ; as, that a thing cannot both be and not be at the same time. It is sufficient for our purposes to point out that even on the confession of Huxley himseK there are ideas of relation which are not given in sense experience,3 such as succession and coexistence. These may, as Huxley says,4 require at least two impressions (simple sensations) as a condition of their appearing in consciousness. But as they are not furnished, but only brought to our attention by these sensations, they must have been a part of our mental outfit, ready for use when the purposes of knowledge demanded them. It is not true, then, that the "creative power of the mind amounts to no more than the faculty of compounding, transposing, augmenting, or diminishing the materials afforded us by the senses and experience. " The mind is in possession of ideas or constructive principles which, though they may appear in consciousness in connection with sense 1 Comp. J. F. Ferrier's Institutes of Metaphysic, second edition, Edinburgh and London, 1856, pp. 79-96. 2 For a discussion of the idea of self in its relation to thought, see Bowne, Theory of Thought and Knowledge, pp. 21-29. Comp. Morell's An Historical and Critical View of the Speculative Philosophy of Europe in the Nineteenth Century, New York, 1862, pp. 51-55. Schurman holds to the three primary ideas of the self, the noiVself, or the external world, and God.-Agnosticism and Religion, p. 104f. Comp. also, Ladd's Philos ophy of Knowledge, pp. 193-227 ; Lotze, Microcosmus, translated by Hamilton and Jones. New York, 1886, pp. 143-167 ; and Ferrier, as noted above. 3 See his Hume, p. 85. 4 Hume, p. 66 f. 72 Foundations of the Christian Faith. experiences, are not copies of such experiences, but are, nevertheless, the fundamental elements in aU impressions. In other words, the na- The mind's ture of the mind is such that it furnishes aU that is most ti0onnribtUo necessary in knowledge. If from this the conclusion knowledge. were drawn that we have then no way of testing knowl edge, and must be forever in doubt about its vaUdity, we reply that for the mind itself, at least, there is valid knowledge, and as knowl edge has no uses or interests apart from minds we need not trouble ourselves about it any further. He who would undertake to go behind the laws of thought must cease to think. The vast significance of the question under discussion wfll be seen in the statement of Hume that the "idea of God, as meaning an infi nitely inteUigent, wise, and good Being, arises from reflecting on the operations of our own minds, and augmenting, without Umit, these qualities of goodness and wisdom. " • He gives this as an example of an idea which is a copy of an impression. By the process of augmen tation, however, the original has been clearly distorted beyond recog nition. It is purely the work of the constructive activity of the mind rather than of the memory. It is the creation of the mind, and that without the checks employed in the definition of our sensations, and hence has no claim to reality.2 It must be said that Hume's is not the true account of the origin either of the idea of God, or of God as infinitely intelUgent, wise, and Origin of the good. His view is not borne out by the later investiga- according tions of those who have devoted their talents to the study to Hume. of religions. s We might rest our case against Hume on this point, with a reminder to the reader that we have shown that ideas are not "copies of im pressions," but that "impressions" involve ideation, and that as the theory is false, aU applications of it to matters of religion are discred ited. But we prefer to investigate this special appUcation briefly by itself. According to the theory, the impression goodness, or the lively perception of goodness in ourselves, is augmented until it is infinite, and then attributed to God. So also of wisdom. But while aU men have the idea of God, not aU are "impressed" with human goodness, 1 Inquiry, p. 18. 'Hume has had successors In his account of the origin of the idea of God, as he had predecessors. An example of the latter Is Leibnitz, in Principes de la Nature et de la Grace, § 9 ; and of the former, F. W . Newman, in A Defense of the Eclipse of Faith, by Henry Rogers, Boston, 1854. » Comp. Lectures on the Origin and Growth of the Conception of God as Illustrated by Anthropology and History, by Count Goblet d'Alviella, second edition, London, Edin burgh, and Oxford, 1897, especially Lectures ii and v. Criticism of Hume's Agnostic Principles. 73 but rather with human depravity; not with human wisdom, but rather with human ignorance and folly. That we do attribute a de gree of goodness to certain individuals is true, but the idea of good ness did not spring from seeing goodness in men. For if the idea were not in the mind, we could not possibly recognize it when we saw it. At least there must have been some innate capacity by which it could be recognized in its true nature. The same is true of the infiniteness of the goodness of God. Were the idea of infinity not in the mind, it could not be joined with the idea of goodness and ascribed to any being. So, too, the idea of God must exist before any infinite attri butes can be ascribed to him. The idea of God with his attributes is impressive, but man has no attributes impressive enough to suggest, or to leave as a copy in the mind, the idea of God. Thus this example breaks down upon analysis just as aU the rest of them did, and we are doubly warranted in rejecting his account of the origin of the idea of God as infinitely intelligent, wise, and good. The elements of truth in his position wfll aU be dwelt upon in another connection. 74: Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER V. HUME'S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND OF THE CAUSAL RELATION Under the limits of knowledge as determined by its means we take up, first, Hume's representational theory. There is, however, the less need for lengthy discussion here, since the result of the theory is doubt, not alone of the things peculiar to religious thought, but also of the things of sense. StiU, as it is a part of the phflosophical basis of agnosticism, we cannot altogether pass it by. The theory supposes rightly that it is not the external objects themselves which are present in perception. It is wrong, however, in affirming that the images of these external objects are admitted to the mind through inlets caUed senses, and that these images are immediately perceived by the mind. It is impossible to give any clear account of these images. Confessedly they are neither material nor mental. Differing from both matter and mind, it is difficult to see how matter could throw them off, as the figure has it, or how mind could know them any more than it can know immediately any other substance differmg from itself — as, for instance, matter. So then we cannot help asking, The repre- What is that which is neither mental nor material ? And sentational . -, . , . . ,, , ., -, , . . theory no we cannot desist from saying that the explanation does the prob- not explain. The solution of the problem of knowledge knowledge, gained in perception may seem hopeless. The representa tional theory certainly does not solve it. The fact of knowledge no one can seriously doubt. How it is possible and what it imphes we leave to the metaphysicians to explain. 1 For all the practical con cerns of life we must act on the theory that there is an external world. Doubts raised by the representational theory are at most speculative, and, as we have seen, the speculation is itself inconsistent and unclear. Hence we must go on with what is needful for practical life, entertaining no doubts arising from the representational theory. We consider, second, the limits of knowledge as determined by in ference from cause and effect. Hume is right in saying that the 1 The Immense reinforcement which the theistic argument receives from this deepest of all philosophical investigations is one of the surprises revealed in the more thorough going methods of post-Kantian studies. The present-day theory of knowledge Is theistic In spite of the most searching adverse criticism. We must be theists or give up all hope of explaining the problem of knowledge. Hume's Theory of Knowledge. 75 knowledge of the relation of cause and effect is not in any instance attained a priori. But when he says that it arises entirely from ex perience he is in error. Even according to his own development of the subject the knowledge of that relation does not arise out of ex perience, for none emphasizes more than himself the fact that we experience no causal relation. Indeed, the very end of his discussion of the subject is to prove that we go beyond experience Origin of the when we do more than assert the conjunction of what we ai re°ation!~ call the cause and the effect. That they are conjoined we know ; that they are connected he says we do not know. Or, to put it another way, we have, in experience, knowledge of the conjunction of things in time and space, but not of any relation between them except that of the conjunction described. If, then, the external world does not furnish us any knowledge of the causal relation, have we any other means of knowledge concern ing it ? Hume answers in the negative. Is he right ? It wfll be ad mitted by all that we have the idea of cause, and Hume has made it clear enough that sense experience did not furnish us the idea. It must, then, have been furnished by the mind itself. The analysis of the idea shows that it is essentially an idea of force or power ; so that we may admit with Hume that we perceive no power in the conjunc tions we call causal, and yet we know we have the idea of power in those conjunctions. That we do not attain the idea by a priori reasoning, and that we do not attain it by sense experience, does not destroy the fact that we have it. Nor would that fact be destroyed if we should fail to show under what conditions the idea arises in the mind. In any event the idea is there, and it does not come to us apriori nor in sense experience. But may it not be that the idea arises, as Hume teUs us, from custom or habit ? Do we not have the idea of causal connection from the observation of constant conjunction ? Hume says that we are led by custom to expect heat or cold when we perceive flame or snow, and the movement of one billiard ball when struck by another. This is true, but the causal relation is not expressed alone in terms of change or sequence, but also in terms of force or power. And there is nothing in ten thousand effects to suggest power which is not equaUy resident in a single effect. Custom would account only for our expec tation of change upon the conjunction of two objects in given ways. a 1 On Hume's theory it is absurd to speak of impressions or of any form of influence, or even of explanation, since all these imply the causal relation. On the difficulties con nected with Hume's theory of causation and related conceptions, see Works of Thomas Hill Green, vol. i, pp. 172 ff, London, 1885. 76 Foundations of the Christian Faith. It remains, however, to be determined whether this idea of force is not itself a deception. To raise this doubt is, indeed, to raise a doubt The idea of about our profoundest convictions, and yet it is impossi- decTption3, ble to prove that we are not deceived. But we hasten to say that there is no reason to believe that we are deceived, and he who raises the doubt as to the reality of force has upon him the burden of proof. It is possible to raise a doubt of anything. It is not possible always to give good reason for our doubt. This is such a case. But while we cannot demonstrate the existence of force, there is every reason to beUeve in its reality aside from the mind's assertion of the fact, which is itself a reason for behev- ing in it. Now, though we know so httle of the nature of force as distinct from its effects, there are certain facts which compel us to beUeve in its existence. Primary among these is our own con sciousness of resistance and counter-resistance. The impression of our being resisted by external objects is as lively as that of our being affected in any other way by them. To say that there is nothing con nected with an external object to occasion that impression is as absurd as to say that there is nothing in a piece of heated metal to occasion the impression of pain. But there is something in the action we take in connection with the two impressions that helps us to beUeve in the reality of force more than in the reality of heat. When we have the impression of pain as arising from heated metal we withdraw our fingers, or other parts affected, and we might almost think we were deluded if no perma nent injury were wrought. In the case of the impression of being resisted, on the contrary, we are conscious of a counter-resistance, not by the bodily organs, indeed, but by the mind. And this conscious ness of mental resistance is accompanied by an impression of mus cular exertion. Besides, our judgment and volition come to our aid under such circumstances, the one suggesting a change in the position of the body according to the laws of physics, the other stimulating us to perseverance. We can time both the beginning and the end of the resistance and counter-resistance. We are very sure that if there is sufficient counter-resistance we need not yield when we are resisted. There is something by which we resist. We have that something at our command. Universal consent terms it power. Whatever it is we can employ it in different degrees up to a certain limit, which is not the same in all persons. When we see another person doing as we do under like circumstances of stress we attribute to him both volitional and muscular power. There is the same reason for doing Hume's Theory of Knowledge. 77; this that there is for supposing him to be constituted in other respects.; like ourselves. AU other things being equal, we should attribute both a voUtional and muscular power to animals. Of the muscular power - we are sure. When we come to unintelligent objects there can be no voUtional and no muscular power, but muscular power being but one form of physical power we can attribute other kinds of physical power to inanimate objects. This is, probably, the account of the origin of the idea of power in the material world. It is irresistible to the thinking mind. Besides, we have tests which we can apply here. As we accomplish more when we are conscious of the exertion of a greater degree of power, so we expect those objects which give evidence of great physical power to accomplish much, and we are never disappointed. That we can not explain the whole process of physical causation does not affect . the certainty that there is such a thing as force, whether in the realm of practice or of thought. Only he who overlooks or ignores the facts while he gives exclusive attention to certain unanswerable questions can be skeptical here. My consciousness of volitional energy would in nowise decrease in case those parts of my body which Further have hitherto been under my control were removed from if u^m e *s that control by paralysis or excision. I should simply s ePtlclsm- lack the means of expression. That some parts of my body are under- my control and others are not arises solely from the fact that some are constructed to that end and that others are not. This, and no de fect in the nature of supposed force, as Hume intimates to be the case, ! is the explanation of our inability to move some of the organs of the body. Hume further strives to make it appear that our idea of power is not connected with its conscious exercise by the wiU. He says that , if we were conscious of power in ourselves we should be fully ac quainted with it, and so could explain why it would move some of our organs and not others. But we have just seen that it is not in the nature of the power that the failure lies, but in the construction of the organ. Besides, it is not true that if we are conscious of the power we must be fully acquainted with it and all its limits and capa bilities. This, in the nature of the case, could not be known unless we knew that we had tried our power on every possible object. Hence we conclude that Hume has not succeeded in destroying the fact of causality, and thus in establishing the atheistic, or at any rate, the> agnostic denial of the necessity for a first cause. 1 Inquiry, vol. i, p. 75 f. 78 Foundations of the Christian Faith. There is, however, one special application of his doctrine of infer- enee from cause and effect which we must here notice. It is that Relation of the cause can never be concluded to be greater than the '"doc3: known effect demands; and that as the world is not infinite ci^tion.0* the cause of it cannot be infinite, or at least cannot be known to be. This is in reality the old idea that the world has im pressed us as of a certain magnitude, and our idea of its cause must be a copy of that impression Umited by the magnitude of the original. Even if we suppose the argument vaUd from every other standpoint, it is invalid from that of our knowledge of the limits of the world; for we have no knowledge of any such limits, and to limit the cause of the world because we suspect limits to the world would be a gross violation of thought. The more the world is studied the more it ap proaches to our idea of the infinite, whether in its extent, its variety, or its power. The idea suggested by what we know of the world is not that of a limited, but of an infinite cause, in point of wisdom, power, and goodness. Correct reasoning from the nature of the effect to the nature of the cause, in this case, leads to the postulate of a cause great enough to be equal to aU we know and aU we can ever learn as to the world. Were we to say that such a being is Umited we should have to go outside the universe to define the limitation. Only inexperienced investigators would pretend to Umit the cause to what they know of the effect, for the experienced have discovered that their conception of the world is constantly enlarging. After this relatively brief discussion it wfll not be necessary to give much space to the supposed Umits of our knowledge as determined Hume's doc: by our capacities. That they are limited none can deny. mental lim- But that they are as Umited as Hume asserts has, we futed. ' think, been disproved ; and also that they are Umited in the way described by Hume. It might be sufficient to caU atten tion to the fact that the limitations of our faculties asserted by Hume are discovered only by the use of the very faculties which, it is de clared, cannot be trusted beyond the realm of practice and experience. It is most clear that no one ever found either in practice or experi ence the limitations supposed ; but they are deductions from facts dis covered by practice and experience. As, then, in order to discover the alleged fact of limitation, Hume has gone beyond the realm fixed for our mental activity, what right have we to believe that the deduc tion is not erroneous ? It is true that the direct appUcation of his language, as cited above, is rather to philosophy than to religion, and would completely destroy our belief in any external reaUty. Yet he Hume's Theory of Knowledge. 79 evidently means to cut us off from any kind of religious thought which rises above "common life" to causes and to our relations with God. We are exhorted to reflect only on "common life" and to avoid thought concerning the origin of worlds. The " more sublime topics" are to be left "to the embellishment of poets and orators, or to the arts of priests and pohticians." 1 " The imagination of man is naturally sublime, delighted with whatever is remote and extraordi nary, and running without control into the most distant parts of space and time." ... "A correct judgment observes a contrary method, and, avoiding aU distant and high inquiries, confines itself to common life, and to such subjects as faU under daily practice and ex perience."2 All this would be true if our faculties were turned only earthward by their very nature and limited by their observations of earthly things. But this, we have seen, is not the case. We cannot here discuss the significance of conscience for something aside from what he calls "common life ; " but in its appropriate place it will be made clear that that which is highest in us looks away from earth, however much one part of us may be of the earth, earthy. This survey of Hume's philosophy has not only served, as we be Ueve, to show its falsity, but also to exhibit the intimate connection between it and Huxleyan agnosticism. Huxley has simply applied Hume's fundamentaUy agnostic principles. Were they Conclusion correct we must come to Huxley's conclusions. As they have been proved incorrect we are released from the bonds which would hold us down and in, and are permitted, not, indeed, to roam at wiU, but to take a wider range than agnosticism allows. We are bound to exercise caution in all our thinking and assertions of knowledge ; but we are not indebted to the agnosticism of any age of the world for the sense of that necessity. » Inquiry, vol. i, p. 184. 2 Ibid., p. 184. 80 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VI. THE PHILOSOPHY OF KANT AS A BASIS FOR AGNOSTICISM. This, like the philosophy of Hume, is an attempt to define the. lim its of knowledge, but it is much more elaborate and critical than Hume's. The mere skeleton or bony structure of Kant's works would occupy more space than we can here afford. We shall be obliged to refer those who desire fuller information concerning it to his published works in the original or in translation. We must con tent ourselves with brief summaries of his arguments and conclu sions and such points in their discussion as wfll serve to show the source and nature of the fallacies they contain. We need to consider his three principal works, the Critique of Pure Eeason, the Critique of Practical Reason, and the Cri tique of the Judgment. The first is a study of the powers and processes of the mind in the acquisition of knowledge ; the last two a study of those things which for practical reasons we may accept, though we cannot know, as true. If we fail to take into account the last two treatises we must of necessity misunderstand him. And we wish to point out here that, so far as the agnosticism of Huxley is true to its name, it is guilty of exactly this fault of considering only the Critique of Pure Reason ; and so far as it transforms itseff into apisticism it has no foundation in the Kantian system. Kant holds that all our knowledge begins with experience; that is, that " in respect to time," "no knowledge of ours is antecedent to Knowledge experience, but begins with it." "But, though all our to expert knowledge begins with experience, it by no means foUows ence. that all arises out of experience." • Here Kant denies the Humian theory of knowledge, and by no one has it been more suc cessfully combated. But it will be distinctly noted that he does not deny that our knowledge is limited by experience. On the contrary, he holds that knowledge is so limited. This he discusses at length in Part First of the Critique of Pure Reason. Summing up in section. 1 Critique of Fure Reason, translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn, London, 1869, p. 1. A standard German edition of Kant's works is that edited by G. Hartensteiu. I. Kant's silmmtliche Werke, In chronologischen Relhenfolge, 8 Bde. Leipzig, 1867-69. All our references are to Melklejohn's translation. Philosophy of Kant as a Basis for Agnosticism. 81 10 he says:1 "We have shown that we are in possession of pure ¦a priori intuitions, namely, space and time, in which we find, when in a judgment a priori we pass out beyond the given conception, something which is not discoverable in that conception, but is cer tainly found a priori in the intuition which corresponds to the con ception, and can be united synthetically with it. But the judgments which these pure intuitions enable us to make never reach farther than to objects of the senses, and are valid only for objects of possible experience. " The last sentence is the one which proves that Kant limits our knowledge as above stated. In further illustration of his position we quote as foUows : 2 " Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind ; the first of which is the faculty or power of receiving rep resentations (receptivity for impressions), the second is the power of cog nizing by means of these representations (spontaneity in the production of conceptions) . Through the first an object is given to us ; through the second it is, in relation to the representation (which is a mere deter mination of the mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions consti tute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither con ceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can afford us a cognition." "We apply the term sensibility to the receptivity of the mind for impres sions, in so far as it is in some way affected ; and, on the other hand, we call the faculty of spontaneously producing representations, or the spontaneity of cognition, under -standing. Our nature is so con stituted that intuition with us can never be other than sensuous ; that is, it contains only the mode in which we are affected by objects. On the other hand, the faculty of thinking the object of sensuous in tuition is the understanding. Neither of these faculties has any pref erence over the other. Without the sensuous faculty no object would be given to us, and without the understanding no object would be thought. Thoughts without content are void ; intuitions without conceptions, blind. Hence it is as necessary for the mind to make its conceptions sensuous (that is, to join to them the object in intuition) as to make its intuitions intelligible (that is, to bring them under con ceptions). Neither of these faculties can exchange its proper func tion. Understanding cannot intuite, and the sensuous faculty cannot think. In no other way than from the united operation of both can knowledge arise." It is clear from this that Kant thinks of knowledge in its twofold aspect of matter and form. This embarrasses him continuaUy 1 Critique of Pure Reason, part i, p. 44. * Ibid., p. 45 f. 82 Foundations of the Christian Faith. throughout the Critique of Pure Reason, and is the source of many a faulty conclusion. The distinction is so far correct that the senses do furnish the impressions while the mind, not merely the under standing, supplies all the constructive or organizing principles. The discussion of the sensibility and understanding is, however, but a sort of introduction to the treatment of the Pure Reason, which "contains in itself the source of certain conceptions and prin ciples which it does not borrow either from the senses or the under standing." ' Speaking of the nature of these conceptions he says:" "The term conception of reason, or rational conception, itself indi cates that it does not confine itself within the Umits of experience." "The pure conceptions of reason at present under consideration are transcendental ideas."" "AU transcendental ideas arrange them selves in three classes, the first of which contains the absolute (uncon ditioned) unity of the thinking subject, the second the absolute unity Kant's three of the series of the conditions of a phenomenon, the third transcen- . . dentaiideas. the absolute unity of the condition of all objects of thought in general. The thinking subject is the object-matter of Psy chology; the sum total of all phenomena (the world) is the object- matter of Cosmology; and the thing which contains the highest con dition of the possibihty of aU that is cogitable (the Being of aU be ings) is the object-matter of aU Theology. Thus Pure Reason pre sents us with the idea of a transcendental doctrine of the soul (psy- chologia rationalis), of a transcendental science of the world (cos- mologia rationalis), and, finaUy, of a transcendental doctrine of God (theologia transcendentalis) ." "They are . . . pure and genuine products, or problems, of pure reason."4 In a very lengthy, elaborate, and profound discussion in the re mainder of the Critique of Pure Reason he reaches the conclusion that, while the reason cannot do otherwise than entertain these ideas of the existence of the soul, the world, and God, yet all arguments in favor of them as realities are sophistical. Thus, though these ideas are present in the reason yet there is no way of proving that there is any reaUty corresponding to them. According to this we have a faculty for receiving impressions of objects in the physical world and a faculty for transforming these impressions into thoughts, thus giv ing us a knowledge of external objects, at least so far as phenomena are concerned; but we have no faculty by which a nonphysical be ing, as God, can make himself felt in the soul. It is true we have 1 Critique of Pure Reason, part i, p. 212 ' Ibid., p. 219. » Ibid., p. 228. « Ibid., p. 233. j. jcuu-uou-t-ni: OF 1\.ANT AS A BASIS FOR AGNOSTICISM. 83 the idea of God as we have the idea of marble, but the latter is the product of sensibility and understanding, while the former is the product of pure reason, and there is no way by which to cannot be prove that it is anything but an idea. So of the soul, t^/reiiOT and so of the world. However, as it is impossible to prove "ureal. that these ideas correspond to external or objective reality, so it is impossible to prove that they do not. The possibility of such sup posed realities cannot be denied, since they are transcendental. Knowledge is confined to the world of sensuous experience. It would seem that such a system of thought is exactly suited to that agnosticism which professes to be a condition of inevitable igno rance concerning the problem of existence, arising from the natural Umitations of our powers. And on the supposition that there is no fatal flaw in Kant's system, as presented in the Critique of Pure Reason, Huxleyan agnosticism, as just defined, is so strongly en trenched that it can never be dislodged. It is wholly unnecessary for our purpose to undertake to show that this part of Kant's system does exhibit any such fatal flaw. In the first place we do not seriously object to agnosticism as long as it con fines itself to the realm of knowledge in the Kantian sense. For Kant only that was knowledge, strictly so caUed, which either Reaction from depended on the necessary laws of thought, and hence skepticism. was demonstrative, or which the senses give in conjunction with the forms of the understanding. Religious truth is neither demonstrative nor sensuous knowledge. It is the knowledge of belief based on such evidence as our nature, considered in. its entirety, furnishes. And when any system includes in its sweep a denial of aU knowledge ex cept of phenomena, and affirms that not only do we not know the existence of the soul and God, but also of the world, the result is to make men act on the principles of common sense and to disregard phflosophy. And when philosophy, after it has done its worst, can not affirm that there is neither soul, nor world, nor God, men of practical sense will assume, along with the reality of the world, the reality of the soul and of God ; especially as we have the express permission of this mighty champion of agnosticism for such an assumption. Besides, this philosophy strongly insists that these ideas are neces sarily in every mind and come to consciousness on occasion ; that of the soul and of God as truly as of the world. All that it says is that we can neither prove nor disprove them because of the fact that the mind has no powers by which it can reach them. The ideas are 81 Foundations of the Christian Faith. there, and that is all we can say of them. They are aU there, and it would be unfounded discrimination to act upon the reality of one and the unreality of the others. Agnosticism as a scheme of action belies its name, and proves that it is not agnosticism. But as a scheme of action it has no support in the Critique of Pure Reason. But to the Critique of Pure Reason Kant added the Critique of the Practical Reason and the Critique of the Judgment. In the latter works he found, not indeed a basis for knowledge, in the Kant ian sense, of the three ideas of Pure Reason, but a necessity for belief in them. With belief agnosticism has absolutely nothing to do. As soon as it touches this realm it becomes apisticism. The man who calls himself agnostic may also be an apistic ; but what we require is that he shall not include both of these attitudes under one name Findings of and then define his attitude merely according to its ety- of Practical mology. If he wfll insist on being both an agnostic and ofthe Judgd- an apistic let him make his definition of his attitudes ment' such that everyone will understand that he neither knows nor believes that there is a God, and then everyone wfll see at a glance in what class to rank him. Kant's philosophy as a whole, then, is unfitted to become the basis of agnosticism with apistic annexes. There is nothing in it to prevent our believing in the soul, the world and God ; but it affords us much that must lead us to believe in them as realities. It bears hard on certain systems of theology ; but it leaves room for Christ and the apostles. When, therefore, Huxley bases his apisticism on Hume and Kant he bases it upon an insecure foundation. For so far as Hume afforded it a basis Kant has refuted him ; and Kant makes it impossible to doubt the soul, the world, and God. Huxleyan agnos ticism is harmless ; the attempt to make the term cover belief and the activities appropriate thereto would be contemptible were it not No p h i 1 o- for the probability that the so-called agnostics are blind sophic basis ° for Huxley- to their own method of procedure. So that whfle we an agnosti- cism. condemn their methods we may possibly excuse or paUi- ate them in view of their infatuation. Nevertheless we cannot resist the feeling that those who set themselves up for oracles should not allow themselves to be blinded. • But to proceed. Huxleyan agnosti cism is, as we have seen, an impracticable system when applied to the methods of scientific investigation ; and it has no secure basis in the philosophy of Hume and Kant. So much our investigation of its claims has clearly revealed. The Agnosticism of Herbert Spencer. 85 CHAPTER VII. THE AGNOSTICISM OF HERBERT SPENCER AS A PRACTICAL SYSTEM. When we turn from Huxley to Spencer we discover that the latter, like the former, professedly bases his system upon a philosophy which had been in a large measure developed before him. While Huxley depended upon Hume and Kant, Spencer starts from Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy of the Unconditioned, and Henry Longueville Mansel's Limits of Religious Thought.1 But, as Huxley takes only so much of Hume and Kant as suits his purposes, so Spencer modifies and extends the doctrines of Hamilton and Mansel. Spencer's philosophy as embodied in Part I (The Unknowable) of his First Principles of a New System of Phflosophy " is really an at tempt to show on what basis a reconciliation may be primary pur- brought about between religion and science. He regards cer't°ph?ios- the conflict as one which has been in existence ever since op y' " the recognition of the simplest uniformities in surrounding things set a limit to the previously universal fetichism," and as being the most important of all antagonisms of belief.3 His sense of the impor tance of the conflict is at the same time his consciousness of the impor tance of bringing it to an end. The method by which he seeks to effect the reconciliation is to show that the ultimate ideas of religion and science are identical, and may be summed up in the recognition of the mystery behind all things. * ' 'If religion and science are to be reconciled, " says Spencer, "the basis of reconcihation must be this deepest, widest, and most certain of all facts : that the Power which the universe mani fests to us is utterly inscrutable." It will be noted that we have here the admission that there is a Power which the universe manifests to us. So, then, we have gotten from a mystery which we cannot ex plain to a Power to which this mystery is attributed. It is the high merit of Religion that " from the beginning it has dimly discerned the ultimate verity and has never ceased to insist upon it. " 6 ' After criti- i The Bampton Lectures for 1858. Boston, 1860. In reality Jacobi had previously de veloped the ideas emphasized by Hamilton and Mansel in this respect, asserting that Kant labored under the error that it is not in the nature of the ideas, but in the nature of our knowledge, that these ideas cannot be proved realities. See Schwegier on Jacobi, in History of Philosophy. * New York, 1868. s First Principles, p. 11. * Ibid., chaps. 2 and 3. 6 Ibid., p. 99. 8 86 Foundations of the Christian Faith. cism has abolished aU its arguments and reduced it to silence there has still remained with it the indestructible consciousness of a truth Validity of re- which, however faulty the mode in which it had been ex- ligious belief. pressedi was yet a truth beyond cavil." ' And this inde structible consciousness of a truth in the mind's possession is to be trusted. Speaking of the diverse forms of reUgious beUefs he says:3 " To suppose that these multiform conceptions should be one and aU absolutely groundless discredits too profoundly that average human intelligence from which aU our individual inteUigences are inherited." Further, " To the presumption that a number of diverse beliefs of the same class have some common foundation in fact must, in this case, be added a further presumption derived from the omnipresence of the beliefs. Religious ideas of one kind or another are almost, if not quite, universal." "The implication is practically the same," even though in some races these ideas arise only when "a certain phase of inteUi gence is reached." Again,3 "A candid examination of the evidence quite negatives the doctrine maintained by some, that creeds are priestly inventions." Even the hypothesis that reUgious ideas are the products of the religious sentiment admits that this sentiment is a "constituent in man's nature,'' and this "cannot be denied by those who prefer other hypotheses." 4 "And if the reUgious sentiment . . . must be classed among human emotions we cannot rationaUy ignore it. We are bound to ask its origin and function." "Any theory of things which takes no account of this attribute must, then, be ex tremely defective." We are " obUged to admit that it is as normal as any other faculty," and that it " is in some way conducive to human welfare." Furthermore, "Throughout aU future time, as now, the human mind may occupy itself, not only with ascertained phenomena and their relations, but also with that unascertained something which phenomena and their relations imply. Hence if knowledge cannot monopolize consciousness— if it must always continue possible for the mind to dwell upon that which transcends knowledge— then there can never cease to be a place for something of the nature of religion."6 Thus we have a defense both of a Power as existing, though inscru table, and a religious sentiment in man which cUngs to the fact of such a Power, with science on the side of religion here if nowhere else. Nor is this wrung from Spencer's occasional utterances, but it is the very thing for which he contends. So far, then, there is nothing in the system to alarm the most timid soul. We must next note, however, that, according to Spencer, theology ¦First Principles, p. 100. » Ibid., p. 13. 'Ibid., p. 14. * Ibid., p 15. » Ibid., pp. 16, 17. The Agnosticism of Herbert Spencer. 87 has gone too far in asserting anything except the existence and in scrutability of this Power. This is developed under the ideas of " sym- boUc conceptions" and the "relativity of knowledge." inadequacy The doctrine of symbolic conceptions is summed up as conceptions5 follows:' "When, instead of things whose attributes of religion. can be tolerably well united in a single state of consciousness, we have to deal with things whose attributes are too vast or numerous to be so united, we must either drop in thought part of their attributes or else not think of them (the things) at aU ; either form a more or less sym bolic conception or no conception. We must predicate nothing of ob jects too great or too multitudinous to be mentally represented, or we must make our predications by the help of extremely inadequate rep resentations of such objects — mere symbols of them." As iUustrations of symbolic conceptions he gives, along with others, the foUowing:'' "Should something be remarked of the class, say farmers, . . . we neither enumerate in thought all the individuals contained in the class nor believe that we could do so if required ; but we are content with taking some few samples of it and remembering that these could be indefinitely multiplied. Supposing the subject of which something is predicated be EngUshmen, the answering state of consciousness is a still more inadequate representation of the reaUty. Yet more remote is the likeness of the thought to the thing if reference be made to Europeans or to human beings." But the use of these symbolic conceptions is liable to lead us into error. "We are led to deal with our symbolic conceptions as though they were actual ones, not only because we cannot clearly separate the two, but also because, in the great majority of cases, the first serve our purposes nearly or quite as well as the last- are simply the abbreviated signs we substi tute for those more elaborate signs which are our equivalents for real objects."3 "Thus we open the door to some which profess to stand for known things but which reaUy stand for things that cannot be known in any way." 4 With one swoop he includes ultimate religious and ultimate scientific ideas in the illegitimate symboUc conceptions, saying that they are not cognitions but mere symbols of the actual.6 He next proceeds to show by an analysis, both of the product and the process of thought, that the reality existing behind all appearances is and must ever be unknown ; thus aiming to establish the relativity of thought, that is, the fact that thought can never reach the reaUty behind phenomena. The reUgious significance of this doctrine is that God, just because he is the First Cause, the Infinite, the Absolute, i First Principles, p. 27. a Ibid., p. 26 f. 'Ibid., p. 28. ? Ibid., p. 29. « Ibid., p. 68. 88 Foundations of the Christian Faith. cannot be known. We need not elaborate this here because Mr. Spen cer does not draw the conclusions which the argument seems to war rant. He shows that the teachings of Hamilton and Mansel lead to the impossibility of affirming the positive existence of anything be yond phenomena, and then states that to his mind such a conclusion involves a grave error. He says: "Observe . . . that every one of the arguments by which the relativity of our knowledge is demon strated distinctly postulates the positive existence of something be yond the relative. To say that we cannot know the Absolute is, by implication, to affirm that there is an Absolute." " Clearly, then, the very demonstration that a definite consciousness of the Absolute is impossible to us unavoidably presupposes an indefinite consciousness of it." 1 Hence, when he comes to the final act of reconciliation, he says that "though the Absolute cannot in any manner or degree be The existence known, in the strict sense of knowing, yet we find that oftheAbso- ' D J luteaneces- its positive existence is a necessary datum of conscious- sary assump tion, ness ; that so long as consciousness continues we cannot for an instant rid it of this datum, and that thus the belief which this datum constitutes has a higher warrant than any other whatever."2 Thus we discover that Spencerian agnosticism does not transform itself into apisticism, but aUows us to beUeve what in the strict sense we cannot know, and that this belief has a warrant so high that it is preeminently respectable. We turn now to the final element in the agnosticism of Spencer in its practical aspects. As he does not draw the most radical conclu sions relative to the existence of the inscrutable Power, so he is less radical than we might anticipate concerning the use to be made of the illegitimate symbolic conceptions of that Power. "The imperfections of Religion, at first great but gradually diminishing, have been imper fections only as measured by an absolute standard." "Speaking gen erally, the religion current in each age and among each people has been as near an approximation of the truth as it was then and there possible for men to receive." The concrete forms "have, for the time being, served to increase its impressiveness." Were these concrete Prevailing re- conceptions taken from men, "and the attempt made to iiefsUshouid Sive them comparatively abstract conceptions, the result s Sa dlnYy would be to leave their minds with none at all, since the changed. substituted ones could not be mentaUy represented." "At the present time the refusal to abandon a relatively concrete notion for a relatively abstract one implies the inabihty to frame the rela- 1 First Principles, p. 85 f. a Ibid., p. 98. The Agnosticism of Herbert Spencer. 89 tively abstract one, and so proves that the change would be premature and injurious." "Few, if any, are as yet fitted whoUy to dispense with such conceptions as are current. The highest abstractions take so great a mental power to realize with any vividness, and are so in operative upon conduct unless they are vividly realized, that their regulative effects must, for a long period to come, be appreciable in but a smaU minority." "Those who relinquish the faith in which they have been brought up for this most abstract faith in which Science and ReUgion unite may not uncommonly fail to act up to their convic tions." "We must, therefore, recognize the resistance to a change of theological opinion as in a great measure salutary." " These various beliefs are parts of the constituted order of things, and not accidental but necessary parts. Seeing how one or other of them is everywhere present, is of perennial growth, and when cut down redevelops in a form but slightly modified, we cannot avoid the inference that they are needful accompaniments of human life severaUy fitted to the soci eties in which they are indigenous. From the highest point of view we must recognize them as elements in that great evolution of which the beginning and end are beyond our knowledge or conception — as modes of manifestation of the Unknowable, and as having this for their warrant." 1 Here again we see that if the principles of Spencer were lived up to aU faiths would be tolerated ; each thinker would have a right, and indeed be in duty bound to speak out his best thought, Spe??^r's„ &- and no one should be censured for being conservative any fromHuxiey. more than for being progressive. In other words, as distinguished from Huxley, Spencer would have some regard to practical conse quences. His theory would allow the matter to be determined by force of the better argument, not by malicious thrusts at the opposi tion from either side. Whatever his phflosophy may imply which he does not hold, it is clear that as a practical system the outcome of his teaching is that there should be perfect toleration ; since whatever one believes, that belief is best for him, as it is the only one possible to him. The dangerous elements are therefore in the phflosophy of Spencer, not in his application of it. 1 The foregoing citations are from pp. 116-122 of the First Principles. 90 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VIII. spencer's philosophy of the unknowable. The agnosticism of Spencer differs from that of Huxley, not alone in its practical consequences, but in that while the latter dweUs chiefly on the limitations of our faculties the former emphasizes the trans- scendent nature of the great Object of reUgious thought. Neverthe less, the difference in this respect between the two systems is not im portant, for they come to the same conclusion, namely, that it is im possible for the human mind to know God. In both systems this con clusion is reached by a study of the attempts of the mind to see behind phenomena. And although in Part I of the First Principles Spencer appears to present a new philosophy as taught by Hamilton and Man sel and modified by himself, in Part II, it is evident that he is far more a follower of Hume than would be at first supposed. Hence we may confine ourselves to the philosophy of the Unknowable. But it is not necessary to take up the whole of that phflosophy, since our purpose is merely to show that such positions as are destruc tive of Christianity in its practical operations are either untenable or otherwise ineffectual. Indeed, were aU to draw the inferences that Spencer draws and then live up to them in practice there would be little need to attempt an answer to his philosophy. It is only be cause there are those who hide behind the philosophy and do not make Spencer's application of it, thus excusing their practical athe ism, that we need discuss this phflosophy here. The one burden of Spencer's phflosophy is, " that the reaUty exist- Unknowabie- ing behind all appearances is, and must ever be, un- Q6SS 01 L 11 © Reality be- known." 1 " AU possible conceptions have been, one by ances. one, tried and found wanting ; and so the entire field of speculation has been gradually exhausted without positive result."2 The same idea is found in many forms of statement throughout this entire philosophy. All knowledge is relative; never reaching the finality of things, but only the relations between tilings. This is as true for the things with which science is conversant as for those with which religion deals; and Spencer displays his fair-minded ness by boldly showing up the unscientific character of science in pro- 1 First Principles, p. 69. a Ibid., p. 68 f . Spencers Philosophy of the Unknowable. 91 f essing to know that about which nothing can be known. Neverthe less, it is only with the religious aspects of this Unknowable that we have to do. There can be no doubt that many have so spoken of God in theo logical treatises as to leave the impression of a knowledge of him far more comprehensive than they possess ; and in so far they have been forgetful of the silence of Jesus and the apostles on the very points in which they have seemed so wise. And the documents from which we, as Christians, draw our knowledge of God, are entirely clear in their utterance on the question of his inscrutable nature. We did not need a Hamilton, or a Mansel, or a Spencer to teach us this truth. Paul exclaims : " O the depth of the riches both of the wisdom and knowl edge of God ! how unsearchable are his judgments and his ways past finding out ! " 1 The nearest approach that Jesus ever made by direct statement to a characterization of the nature of God was when he said, " God is a Spirit," 2 though he tried to convey to the minds of men much concerning the character of God, and his relation to the world and to men. It is not, therefore, antichristian in Mr. Spencer to affirm that we know very little of God's nature, ontologically consid- Spen(.er>Seon- ered; and especially when he declares that all human ^fnetprop" thought is inadequate to such a discovery. Mr. Spencer's osltlons- error appears to consist in the identification of two quite separate and distinguishable propositions, the first of which is that we do not know aU about God, and the second of which is that we do not know anything about God. The first is undeniable, but the latter is not to be quietly and without protest substituted for it. The first is a Christian doctrine, the second is hardly different from atheism. Though we do not and cannot know all about God, we may know something about him ; or if it suit the agnostic mind any better, we may and must believe something concerning him. Mr. Spencer believes in the existence of a something which he so far defines as to call it a Power, the First Cause, absolute, infinite, and capable of manifesting itself . s Of the certainty of these things Mr. Spencer says : "Though the Absolute cannot in any man ner or degree be known, hi the strict sense of knowing, yet we find that its positive existence is a necessary datum of consciousness ; that so long as consciousness continues we cannot for an instant rid it of this datum ; and that thus the belief which this datum constitutes has a higher warrant than any other whatever."4 1 Rom. xi, 33. 2 John iv, 24. 3 First Principles, pp. 38, 46, 87, 98, 99, 108, and throughout. 4 Ibid., p. 98. 92 Foundations of the Christian Faith. This sounds marvelously like the utterances of theistic writers. For example, Bowne says:1 "The infinite is the most certain factor in objective knowledge." Whoever wiU take the pains to recaU the fact, made clear in the Introduction to this work, that there is no well-defined line of demarkation between knowledge and belief, since all knowledge is dependent on beliefs, wiU not think it worth while to dispute as to the antitheistic or the theistic form of statement. The one emphasizes the high warrant of the belief, the other the certainty of knowledge, in reference to the infinite. Both agree as to the cer tainty. Mr. Spencer was probably not conscious of quibbling when he insisted that we know nothing of the Absolute, and yet that we must believe in the positive existence of the Absolute with aU the at- His faith suffl- tributes, which as we have seen, he admits it to possess. cient for ac tion. And his agnosticism amounts to nothing, so far as the confessed attributes of the Power are concerned. For men do not act on knowledge alone, nor chiefly. And a beUef with so high a war rant as Spencer affirms the beUef in the positive existence of the Abso lute to have, a warrant "higher than any other belief whatever" — for example, higher than that for our own existence or for the existence of matter — is one on which men can and wfll act. By what right, we ask, does Mr. Spencer Umit our belief in the Abso lute to the list of attributes mentioned on the preceding page ? And be it noted that it is belief that he is here talking about, not knowledge ; yet a belief that has for it a higher warrant than any other beUef whatever. The principal limit he sets to our beUef is in refer ence to the personality of the inscrutable Power. Criticising the statement of Mr. Mansel, that " it is our duty, then, to think of God as personal," he says2 : " Duty requires us neither to affirm nor deny personahty. Our duty is to submit ourselves with all humility to the established limits of our inteUigence, and not perversely to rebel against them." Here he is protesting against Mr. Mansel's affirma tion of duty. We wish, however, to waive the question of duty with reference to this matter, except to agree with Mr. Spencer that it is our duty to submit ourselves with all humility to the estabhshed limits of our intelligence. The question as to what he means by the ^byfhe estai> established limits of our intelligence is, however, still an ofSilr intern- open one- What does he mean »y intelligence? He gence. certainly does not mean knowledge, for he repeatedly declares that we must believe things which we cannot know, in the strict sense of the word. But since knowledge and belief exhaust ' Metaphysics, p. 479. a First Principles, p. 108. Spencer's Jf hilosophy of the Unknowable. 93 the possibilities of inteUigence he must mean by the established limits of intelUgence the established Umits of belief. There is also an ambiguity in the term " estabhshed limits," which needs to be cleared up. In what sense are these limits established : by the nature of things, or by Mr. Spencer's argument ? If by the na ture of tilings it would certainly be our duty to submit with all humil ity. But even then we could not refrain from constant effort to dis cover whether the limits we suppose established in the nature of things are the real limits ; and if we were convinced that they were the real, there would still be the possibility that they are not both real and final. So we ought in duty not to submit to the established limits unless we know them to be both real and final. In those limits as es tablished by the nature of things there is, then, at present, nothing to submit to. If he means the limits established by his argument, then he means to say that it is our duty to submit to his estimate of the limits of belief. We suspect that only those will submit to his judg ment, as such, who do not venture to think for themselves. All are at liberty to submit to the limits of belief he thinks he has estabhshed if they are convinced by his argument. To that number we do not belong. Qi Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IX. spencer on the divine personality. What are the limits of beUef , then, with reference to the personal ity of the inscrutable Power ? It is evident that Mr. Spencer has no Denial of positive beUef in the personality of God, and that he be- God's per- r sonality. lieves that God is not personal. It seems," he says,1 " somewhat strange that men should suppose the highest worship to lie in assimilating the object of worship to themselves. Not in assert ing a transcendent difference, but in asserting a certain likeness, con sists the element of their creed which they think essential." These words refer entirely to the fact that personality is attributed to God, and hence they can only mean that, whatever he beUeves, he does not believe that God is personal, but that he is, in this respect, transcend- ently different from men. So much in fact he says. " Is it not just possible that there is a mode of being as much transcending inteUigence and will as these transcend mechanical motion ? It is true that we are totaUy unable to conceive any such higher mode of being. But that is not a reason for questioning its existence ; it is rather the re verse."2 This fairly commits him. to the belief that in denying per sonality to God he does not necessarily assert of him something lower, but rather something higher. He says in support of his position : "Have we not seen how utterly incompetent our minds are to form even an approach to a conception of that which underlies aU phenom ena ? . . . Does it not follow that the Ultimate Cause cannot in any respect be conceived by us because it is in every respect greater than can be conceived ? " 3 Putting it aU together it means that there is more reason for asserting of God something higher than personality than there is for attributing personality to him. Let us then test the arguments, first for something higher than per sonality in God, and then for personality. The only argument Spen- Argument for cer gives on his side is our inability to conceive of this something , higher than higher mode of being. Our total inabflity to conceive personal!- , . J ty in God. any such higher mode of being "is not a reason for ques tioning its existence ; it is rather the reverse." This is absolutely the only scrap of support he offers for his belief. All the rest is directed 1 First Principles, p. 109. a Ibid. ' Ibid. Spencer on the Divine Personality. 95 against belief in personaUty. We are asked, then, to believe in the higher mode of being because we cannot conceive it. This is to make inconceivability a test of reaUty. Against assigning personality to God, or, as Mr. Spencer prefers, the Unconditioned, the Ultimate Cause, the Absolute, the Infinite, he mentions that this attribute must be derived from our own natures, and hence is not an elevation but a degradation. This, together with the foregoing, sounds very much as though Mr. Spencer, besides all the other attributes he assigns to the inscrutable Power, would assert of it that it is higher than we, since he fears lest we may degrade it by attributing to it inteUigence and wfll ; that is to say, personaUty, which is an attribute of man. Here he is in agreement with theists, especially Christian theists, who firmly beUeve that God is infinitely more exalted than ourselves. This is not the place to discuss the source from which we derive our ideas of the personality of God. We are engaged now, not in testing Christian theism, but in testing Mr. Spencer's doctrine of the Un knowable. Nevertheless, we suggest that it is just possible that we do not derive those ideas from ourselves primarily, but from a reve lation of himself which God made to men. This statement will be a great grief to the deniers of the need or the possibility of revelation, we know, but it will be no greater grief to them than it is to us to have Mr. Spencer make inconceivability a test of reaUty. But let us see briefly what it is in us men which has so persistently caused us to attribute intelligence and will to God. If we, aside from revelation, assert anything concerning God we must do it on the ground of reasoning from the known to the unknown. This kind of reasoning is adopted by all who reason. Now, we know in the products of the human cause that intelligence and will are involved. When we see any product of a nonhuman cause that looks like what we would call intelUgence in the product of a human cause Wbyweattrib- we inevitably attribute it to intelligence and will in the aiity?o God. nonhuman cause. We may be wrong in so doing ; but to do this is inevitable if we think. So that only those thinkers who deny evi dence of intelligence in the world can escape from attributing in telligence to the Ultimate Cause, and no cry of "Anthropomor phism ! " wfll ever induce the human mind to shrink back from acting according to its own laws. But when we have done this we do not necessarily believe that this intelUgence is only equal to ours, but, on the contrary, we think it in finitely greater. The exaltation of God in our thought consists, in 96 Foundations of the Christian Faith. part, in making that intelligence infinitely more perfect than our own, as the products of his intelligence are infinitely more perfect than What God our own. Nor when, by the necessities of our thought, sufves,epei> we attribute personality to God, rather than, with Spen- not know. ° cer, some alleged unknown thing higher than person ality, do we mean to say that we have conceived of God as he is in all respects. It is possible, though not probable, that God is not personal in our conception of the word ; since our idea of personaUty may be erroneous. Or it is possible that he is personal in our sense of the term, and more than personal. When we foUow the example of Spencer and begin to make conjectures there is no saying where we shall end. But when we think according to the laws of our mind and according to all the ordinary modes of thought we are obhged to think of God as personal, and in no other way. It may be said in reply that we should not construct any definite idea of God at aU. A Spencerian agnostic cannot consistently make such a demand. For Mr. Spencer, while leaving his idea of the in scrutable Power very indefinite, has, as we have seen, given it at least a small degree of definiteness. In discussing Mr. Spencer's de mands that we should submit to the established limits of our inteUi gence we saw that it is impossible for the human mind to be sure that it has reached those limits. Hence, though we may be very cer- No certainty tain that we shaU never fuUy comprehend the infinite, it that Spen- J r . , . cer's idea of foUows that we cannot be sure that Mr. Spencer's idea is God is the most den- as definite as it can be made. Thus there remains, not nite possi ble, only the right, but the duty to seek ever to know more of the inscrutable Power, just as the scientist seeks ever to penetrate more deeply into the mysteries of nature. No one is more ready than Herbert Spencer to confess and even to emphasize the present limits of scientific knowledge ; and yet he does not conclude that the scientist should not try to add definiteness to the indefinite concep tions of science. Why should he blame the theologian for striving for the same end ? He admits frankly the errors of science in the course of its history. We as frankly admit those of theology, espe cially of natural theology. But because mistakes have been made in the past we do not feel disposed to cease effort. And if the apostle of the indefinite in religious thought finds some degree of definiteness we champion the right of those who by proper methods seek to know more of God than Mr. Spencer has told us. All we ask is that the Spencerian agnostics shall not insist on fixing the limits of our intelU gence this side of our utmost possibility, and that they shall be as Spencer on the Divine Personality. 97 loyal in adhering to the estabhshed constitution of our minds as they expect their opponents to be to the limits of intelligence when once they are reaUy discovered. And in fact, in this instance, as so often, Mr. Spencer recoils from the logical consequences of his own argument, and says: "Very likely there wfll ever remain a need to give shape to that spencer's re- indefinite sense of an ultimate existence which forms consequen-C6s of (lis the basis of our intelligence. We shaU always be under argument. the necessity of contemplating it as some mode of being ; that is, of representing it to ourselves in some form of thought, however vague. And we shall not err in doing this so long as we treat every notion we thus frame as merely a symbol, utterly without resemblance to that for which it stands." Thus he gives up his case against those who believe in giving definiteness to an indefinite idea. He thinks this not only right now, but suspects that there will always remain a need for doing so. This necessity, which will always be upon us, arises, as we have pointed out, from the constitution of the human mind and, indeed, from the entire spiritual nature. What that form of thought or mode of being is which we shall always necessarily frame he does not say. If our argument is correct it will always be the personal mode of being which we shaU attribute to the inscru table Power. There is, however, one point in the statement of Mr. Spencer's con cession to the Christian theists to which we must take exception. He says that we shall not err in giving definite form to His unreason- the indefinite " so long as we treat every notion we thus a e eman ' frame as merely a symbol, utterly without resemblance to that for which it stands." We have no objection to regarding all our notions merely as symbols. This is in fact what the Church has done from the beginning. But we do object to the requirement that we shall treat these symbols as utterly without resemblance to that for which they stand. It is impossible for man, without self -stultification, to treat the attribute of personality in God as utterly without resem blance to the fact. If we represent the inscrutable Power as any mode of being it must be the personal mode. To override this ne cessity and say that it compels us to think of God as entirely differ ent from what he is would be to turn all human thinking into hope less chaos. For there is nothing about which we think deeply whose correspondence to our thought we could not equally and with equal positiveness deny. So far as there is any probability in the case it is all on the side of the belief that when we attribute personaUty to God 98 Foundations of the Christian Faith. we are so far correct, though it is not impossible that this does not wholly describe him. There is only one other form of agnosticism which needs to be no ticed here, and that can be briefly dismissed. It is that rare kind which assails aU knowledge. It exists in two forms : first, a nega tive, which is not sure of anything ; and, second, a positive, which Universal asserts that nothing can be known. The first simply de- skepticism. nieg ^^ there is a basis for any conclusion, and consist ently maintains a purely skeptical attitude. It arises from a defect of wfll. Both forms contradict their fundamental principles ; for the first knows at least something, namely, that there is no basis for any conclusion, while the second knows that nothing can be known, which is knowledge of the most comprehensive kind. l After a reasonably full and a thoroughly impartial consideration of agnosticism in aU its principal forms we are led to the conclusion that it is fll founded and deceptive, and that, as far as it contradicts Chris tian thought, it is entirely without claim upon us as thinking beings. Much less should it be permitted to rob us of our faith in God as knowable, at least to the extent of our practical needs. 1 It is interesting to note that Augustine handled universal skepticism with rare skill, so early did Christianity attempt the defense of knowledge. See his De vera religlone, 39, 72. Comp. Windelband's History of Philosophy, translated by J. H. Tufts, New York and London, 1895, pp. 277-279. Pantheism in its Older Forms. 99* SECTION HI-PANTHEISM (MONISM). One of the most striking features of modern anti-Christian thought is the prevalence therein of the pantheistic element. Atheism has had a new lease of life in recent times, and the general tendency of agnosticism has been to lend it aid and respectability. But there are many anti-Christian thinkers who are not atheists, and pantheistic who resent being classed with them. l Nevertheless, their m6™!"! r'n idea of God is so vague as to be destructive of everything tnought- valuable in Christianity. In this vagueness they strongly resemble Mr. Spencer; and in fact agnosticism lends its assistance to anti- Christian thought through Professor Huxley to atheism, on the one hand, and, on the other, through Mr. Spencer to pantheism. Or per haps it would be more correct to say that Mr. Spencer borrowed from pantheism in the construction of his agnosticism, whfle Professor Huxley borrowed more from atheism. CHAPTER I. PANTHEISM IN ITS OLDER FORMS. It is our purpose to consider pantheism, as every other form of anti-Christian phflosophy, chiefly in its more recent forms. But ' in order to do this to advantage it wfll be necessary to look briefly at pantheism as a general doctrine of God, the world, and man, without reference to any special period of time. Broadly speaking, panthe ism identifies God and the world. According to Averroes * the world is an emanation sustained by an anima mundi, or world soul, as which the Deity was conceived. Spinoza took the view that every thing was God, who, or which, is a substance with two modes of man ifestation, one being thought, the other extension. Both modes he regarded as acts of Deity, thought being his subjective, extension his 1 We cheerfully acknowledge tho sturdy blows struck by pantheists in recent times at materialism ; but we cannot escape the conviction that the dread of materialistic opinion which they ascribe to others has been the principal influence holding them back from carrying their arguments to the conclusion for a personal God. For illustrations sec Paulsen's Einleitung in die Philosophie, pp. 242-248, and Forel, Gehirn, und Seele, pp. 6, 8, 31, 32. 2 Deberweg, History of Philosophy, translated by G. S. Morris, New York, 1874, pp. 406, 415-417. 100 Foundations of the Christian Faith. objective act. The difference between Averroes and Spinoza might Pantheism of be stated thus : The former regarded God as the aU ; the .A. vcrrocs and Spinoza latter regarded the all as God.1 Since in popular ed. " thought God is regarded as spirit and the universe as matter it might be supposed that to call God the aU would be to make the all spiritual, while to caU the all God would be to make God ma terial. But such a distinction would be erroneous. Only the gross materialists think of matter in such a way as to assert that it ex cludes spirit. Rather is the tendency toward a refusal to define mat ter, thus making it possible to leave vague the answer to the question whether God is material or spiritual. It is claimed that we know nothing of the nature either of spirit or matter, and that, hence, it is better to speak of one substance with the two attributes of thought and extension. With reference to the doctrine of God and the world the two forms of pantheism just mentioned give us the only possibiUties, although there are all shades of these forms represented in philosophy. But we have yet to state the main points in the pantheistic psychology. It is evident that to the pantheist the human soul can have no real indi viduality. Whether we regard God as aU, or all as God, the human soul, as a distinct entity, is blotted out of existence. Taking Aver roes and Spinoza as the two great historical types of the genus pan theist we find that the former regarded the individual mind as but a manifestation of the impersonal mind — the anima mundi. Spinoza expressed himseU in other language, but the essential idea was the same. Morell 2 thus sums up Spinoza's views as to the relation of the finite to the infinite soul: "The mind of man . . . must be essen- Spinoza on tiaUy and substantially a portion of the divine thinking; andetheninfi- regarded individually or phenomenally it must be a sitc- nite mind. cession 0f different modes of the infinite thought:' " The body is the object of the mind, the mind the idea of the body ; and they are united to each other through life, not because there is any direct connection between them, but because there is a fundamental unity." Thus pantheism, by making God all, or all God, and our ' minds or spirits merely modes of the divine, destroys the hope of in dividual immortaUty along with our real personality. Not only so. Besides the denial of human personality and individual immortality pantheism denies our freedom. We are but modes of the divine. To 'Comp. Farrar's Critical History of Free Thought, pp. 109, 415; Martineau, A Study of Religion, vol. ii, pp. 159-166; Ueberweg's History of Philosophy, vol. ii, p. 56; Morell's History of Modern Philosophy, pp. 124-128. a History of Modern Philosophy, p. 128. l'ANTHEISM IN ITS OLDER FORMS. 101 admit our freedom would be to admit that there is something besides God. Because Spinoza thus took up aU things into the being of God, and apparently made everything divine, Novalis described him as "the God-intoxicated man," and Schleiermacher says of him that " the infi nite was his Alpha and Omega," and that "he was full of religion and holy spirit." 1 It is unnecessary to deny the purity of Spinoza's life in order to prove the antichristian character of his doctrine. But we are chiefly concerned here to show that, being antichristian, it is at the same time false. We may admit without hesitation that pan theism is not, in theory, atheism, and also that as a theory of the rela tion of God to the world it is in some respects preferable to that held by many uninstructed Christians — preferable as a system of thought and also as to its practical results when carried to the logical conclu sions. But viewed in its fundamental principles pantheism is hardly more satisfactory to thought than materialism, and scarcely less dan gerous to morals. One of the chief difficulties connected with pantheism as a system of thought is its necessary denial of personality to the infinite. His only freedom is a freedom from external constraint. Denial of per- J sonality to And since pantheism denies anything external to the the infinite. Deity he must be in this sense absolutely free. But freedom to choose this rather than that is denied him. He is free only to unfold his essential being, and this not freely, but according to his essential nature. What he is he does ; but he does it because he is, not because he will; because compeUed by an inner necessity, not as of free choice. This denies to the Deity inteUigence in any sense of the word known to us by our own experience or observation. The intelligence known to us by the observation of ourselves is not bound, or at least does not appear bound, by an inner necessity, though often hindered in the execution of its designs by external obstacles. The God of pantheism, contrary to this, is not hindered by anything external to himself, for there is no such thing ; but he is, on the other hand, if conscious at all, conscious of his inability to unfold in any way other than he does. He is a helplecs God. What, now, is the source of this notion of a necessitated infinite ? It arises solely from the purpose to make aU being suspicious consist in substance, and to make that substance one. thjVTdea of These postulates are taken for fact in the very funda- ° ' mental definitions and propositions of Spinoza's system. Given cer- 1 Eeden iiber die ReUgion, 4te Auflage, 1831, p. 47 f. y 102 Foundations of the Christian i^aith. tain definitions, certain propositions necessarily follow. But take these propositions, which are logicaUy connected with certain of Spinoza's definitions, and see if there be any reason for holding them. "There cannot be, and we cannot conceive, any other substance than God. " " Whatever is is in God ; and nothing can be, nor be conceived, without God." • These are mere assertions, based on nothing but the definitions which involved them. If one defines everything as God then, of course, we can conceive of nothing except as in God. But there is no reason for saying that everything is God. That is, the assertion is an hypothesis, not a fact. On the other hand, there is the best of reason for attributing free inteUigence to the Deity.2 Here we are engaged simply in testing pantheism, which involves certain consequences so serious as to prevent its acceptance. Thus, not only because it is unfounded, but because it is inconsistent with established fact we reject it. But what are these consequences 1 How is it inconsistent with established fact ? First, very much in the Objections to same way as was found to be the case with materialism. view. el'L" The world, says pantheism, is but an unfolding of God according to his inner necessity. There is, therefore, no purpose, but only impulse. The world, or God, or both as one, is an automaton. We are a part of that great machine, or rather we are modes of it. Our thoughts, feelings and purposes, are also a part of it. The fundamental conviction of our being is thus contradicted, and aU for the purpose of maintaining that there is but one substance. Admit as fact the con viction from which we cannot free ourselves in point either of feeling or of practice, the conviction, namely, that we are free personal agents, and the pantheistic doctrine that God is aU is at once swept away. And what is the argument by which it is sought to destroy that conviction ? Simply this, so far as pantheism is concerned, that God is all, and therefore our freedom and personaUty are delusive sentiments. The consciousness of our freedom and personaUty is in destructible, and yet we are asked to annihilate that consciousness i It has often been pointed out that the pantheism of Spinoza is, in essence, little more than a logical fallacy— the fallacy of the universal. How did he come by his notion of a universal substance? The facts from which he started are, on the one hand, the infi nite manifold of nature, and on the other the individual minds that think. By a process ot dropping characteristic features he advances along each line until he arrives at what he considers the essential nature of each in the pure abstractions, thought (or conscious ness) ana extension. The suggestion lies near at hand, Why have two substances? Would it not be far better In the Interest of unity to posit one substance with two attri butes ? Thus his pantheism is triumphant. But as soon as we ask for such a definition of terms as will give them some intelligible content all the diversity and manifoldness of the original reappear. Thought and extension are abstractions existing only In the mind that thinks them. The actualities to be explained are things and thinkers. ¦' See infra. Pantheism in its Older Forms. 103 in the interest of the theory that God is aU in such a sense as to make us but modes of himself. That theory has no foundation in any fact known to us. It is a theory, pure and simple. Why should we let it destroy our firmest convictions ? Further, pantheism as surely as materiaUsm, would, if carried out to its logical results, destroy all thought. It begins with the contra diction of the fundamental facts of consciousness. If we do not know that we exist as personal and free agents we know nothing. For to deny this is to deny the ego, in contradistinction from which alone we know the non-ego. So that both the seU and the not-self are struck down at a single blow. But if we are so grossly deceived in the pri mary facts of consciousness, in those things which are most accessible to thought, how can we trust our conclusions with reference to mat ters more remote from us ? And here we are talking as though we were at least free to think, while by hypothesis we do not exist and we do not think, but God is the existent thinker. But if God is the only existent thinker, and each of us is but a mode of him and each one's thoughts but his thoughts, then God thinks uninteUigently, erroneously, partially, as weU as in some, correctly. And since it takes aU the Confusion aris- thoughts of all of us, and more, to make up the sum total tneistic^eo- of the thoughts of the infinite we have as a result the ry- greatest conceivable intellectual muddle in God. Besides, with the knowledge of the self and not-self gone there is nothing left to consti tute God. This whole system, therefore, is destructive of all thought and all knowledge. And, as Professor Bowne says, "Any theory which shakes the mind's trust in itself is speculatively untenable ; and for the reason that the theory can be established only by trusting our faculties, while the moment it is established it undermines itself ; " that is, by shaking the mind's trust in the very faculties by which the the ory was established. It is not too much to say, therefore, that pan theism is a system built out of nothing, upon nothing, by nothing. 104 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. PANTHEISM IN THE FORM OF MONISM. But we do not wish to give further attention to pantheism in its older forms, although so much seemed to be necessary to an under- In what sense standing of the newer. The newest form of pantheism is monism is a . . ., . . pantheistic, known as monism. It is, however, only pantheism in so far as it includes a doctrine of God. It may be, and often is practi cally atheistic. Judged etymologicaUy monism is the doctrine which proposes to explain all existence on the supposition of a single sub stance. This substance might be regarded as spirit, thus annihilating matter except as a phenomenon, or as an activity of spirit. In this case it would be spirituaUstic monism. Or the one substance might be regarded as gross matter, in which case we should have materialis tic monism, with mind as mere phenomenon. In either case monism would be primarily a doctrine as to substance rather than as to theol ogy or psychology, though these would inevitably demand an expla nation at its hands. But, as a matter of fact, monism, as it is known at the present day, is professedly neither spirituaUstic nor materialis tic. It is an attempt to account for the phenomena of both matter and mind, and yet to avoid the dualism involved in those conceptions. It makes this attempt by postulating a substance which is neither matter as ordinarily conceived, nor spirit, but which has the attributes of both, manifesting itself now under the form of extension, now under the form of thought. According to monism the materialists, the spir itualists, and the dualists are alike in error. ' To Science, which seeks to reduce everything to the most elementary conditions, this doctrine has proved exceedingly attractive, and, except- Prevaience of ing a few ultra materiaUsts, most scientists of to-day are Christian monists. Not only so, but monism is exceedingly preva lent in the thought of many Christian writers. For all these reasons it is absolutely necessary for the apologist to examine and weigh it with all care and fairness. As a further preUminary statement it must be said that monism in the present day is scarcely distinguishable from materialism, so material is the conception of this 1 On the various types of monists comp. Ziehen's Introduction to Physiological Psychol ogy, translated by Van Liew and Beyer, second edition.London and New York, 1895, p. 300. Pantheism in the Form of Monism. 105 supposed one substance, and also that it has formulated a doctrine of psychology and theology. Before going further it wfll be necessary to give the principal argu ments by which monists support their contention. These of necessity relate to the systems which monism rejects, namely, du- Reason for its alism, spiritualism, and materialism. Dualism is rejected dualism. on the ground that there is no way of explaining how spirit and mat ter, which are so exceedingly diverse, can affect each other as, on the supposition that both exist, it appears that they do. Of dualism there are two forms ; the first emphasizing mind as the cause of motion, the second mind as the effect of motion. Such is the distinction made by Romanes,1 himself a monist, and it is probably the best possible put ting of it, though we enter our caveat when, without further ado, he identifies spiritualism with that form of dualism which makes mind the cause of motion. The elements of the problem, then, are mind, matter, motion. We have already discussed the materialistic theory and need give it no further attention here. But when, in the effort to sustain monism, it is proposed to show that mind cannot be the cause of motion we are obhged to examine the process of reasoning. The one argument which Romanes employs is the supposition that motion in matter considered as an effect of mind violates the scientific doctrine of conservation of energy. We condense his argument. 2 He begins by ad- Romanes's mitting that the view he combats has the advantage of agalnstmind supposing causaUty to proceed from the mind, which is moatCiaoUnei°n the source of our idea of causaUty, and not from that into mattei- which that idea has been read by the mind. "Hence," he says, " it is so far less difficult to imagine that mental changes are the cause of bodily changes than vice versd; for upon this hypothesis we are start ing at least from the substance of immediate knowledge and not from the reflection of that knowledge in what we call the external world." Nevertheless, this does not overcome his difficulty with the doctrine of the conservation of energy. "If the mind of man is capable of breaking in as an independent cause upon the otherwise uniform sys tem of natural causation the only way in which it could do so would be by either destroying or creating certain quanta of either matter or energy. But to suppose the mind capable of doing any of these things would be to suppose that the mind is a cause in some other sense than a physical or a natural cause ; it would be to suppose that the mind is 1 Mind and Motion and Monism, pp. 47, 50. Romanes experienced many changes of opinion, but finally died a theist and a Christian. a Ibid., pp. 50-54. 106 Foundations of the Christian Faith. a supernatural cause, or, more plainly, that aU mental activity, so far as it is an efficient cause of bodfly movement, is of the nature of a miracle." This conclusion he designates as per se improbable. Its impossibility he considers further on. In order to avoid confusion let us pause here and examine the argument as far as it has been carried. We begin with that part of his objection to mind as the cause of motion in matter which says this would be to make the mind a cause One form of jn some other sense than a physical or a natural cause ; his argument r J ' examined. that is, it would make it a supernatural cause, and aU movements of body by mind miraculous. In this objection, physical and natural are taken to mean the same thing. A physical cause is a natural cause and vice versd. The mind is neither to be designated as physical nor natural, but as supernatural, and its power to affect the movements of the body as miraculous. It appears, then, that the force of the objection lies in the difficulty which the monist feels in admitting the existence of anything besides the natural, that is, the physical, or, in other words, the monist objects because he will not consent to the supernatural, or, to use his alternative word, the super- physical. He stumbles at the supernatural (superphysical) and at the miraculous. This objection is of force, therefore, only when one has reached the conclusion beforehand that the supernatural (superphysi cal) and the miraculous are incredible. But, since the mind is regarded as supernatural, if the supernatural is incredible the mind is incredi ble ; that is, there is nothing corresponding to our ordinary ideas of mind. This reductio ad absurdum is perhaps sufficient to show the futility of the argument in question. Let us try the former part of the argument, which asserts that if the mind breaks in as an independent cause upon the otherwise uni form system of natural (physical) causation it must be either by de stroying or creating certain quanta of either matter or energy, or both.1 Let us think of physical causes at work, the sum total of matter and force being always the same though changing as to locality and form. Now, is it true that the only ways in which an outside cause could break into this kind of a system would be by destroying or creating; that is, subtracting from or adding to the matter or the energy of the system, or both ? It is not true. There is yet a third possibility ; that is, that the external agent might merely manipulate i The reader's attention Is called to the fact that our purpose here Is not to prove that an independent cause can break into the system, but that, if it can, it can do so without the consequences which Romanes says would follow. Pantheism in the Form of Monism. 107 the matter, or force, or both, as they would not be manipulated were they left to themselves. Hoffding in answer to this possibility says * that a physical movement does not change its direction except by the appUcation of a physical force of a given strength. But Hoffding on this affirmation is just the point in dispute, and simply rection in " physical begs the question at issue. In fact, on a preceding page, movement. he admits the possibility that a physical movement might have a nonphysical cause.2 It is true that such.an external agent would have to exert energy to change the direction of the energy of the system ; but it is not nec essary to suppose that the energy of the system would be either in creased or diminished by such interference from without. The doc trine of conservation of energy demands that if one body in motion be interfered with by another body the loss of energy in the first shall become an increase of energy in the second. It has nothing to say as to the effect of interference with body by spirit. Now, if a super- physical mind could stop a rolling ball the energy of the ball could not, according to the doctrine in question, be imparted to the mind, for the doctrine demands that the energy shall remain within the sys tem. Hence there would be no diminution in the sum of physical force. On the other hand, the mind-energy could not be imparted to the body, for the energy of the physical system cannot be augmented. So that nothing would be added. On the supposition, then, which Romanes himself makes, of the breaking in of an independent cause upon the otherwise uniform system, no energy need be added or sub tracted. The energy would simply be given a new direction.3 In truth, Romanes did not put the dualistic difficulty in its strong est form. The real difficulty is as to how two supposed entities so whoUy diverse in their attributes as mind and matter can T]le real diffl. affect each other. How can a nonphysical force in any statJd'b'y way influence a physical force? The two forces might Romanes. be supposed to be so different as to be both at work at the same time and place without interfering with each other. It does appear as though it were not difficult to conceive of mind as influencing mind or of matter as influencing matter;4 but how can mind influence matter ? In fact, however, it is impossible for us to conceive how one 1 Psychologie in Umrissen auf Grundlage der Erfahrung. German by F. Bendixen. Leipzig, 1887, p. 70. 2 Ibid., p. 38. 3 Comp. O. Kiilpe's Outlines of Psychology Based upon the Results of Experimental In vestigation, translated from the German by E. B. Titchener, p. 4 ; London and New York, 1895, and Ziehen's Introduction to Physiological Psychology, p. 305. 4 Even HSffding seems to have assumed the truth of this appearance, Psychologie, p. 69 f. 108 Foundations of the Christian Faith. particle of matter influences another particle of matter. It is agreed among scientists that matter cannot influence matter across empty space; and yet it is also agreed that no two atoms of matter touch each other; that is, there is seeming contact, yet actual distance, between them. It is one of the profoundest mysteries of science that matter seems to influence or affect other matter. Why, then, should we stagger at another mystery in the form of matter influenced by mind ? In this respect at least duahsm is as explicable as monism. Judged by the only standard known to us it is easier to think of matter as moved by mind than of matter as moved by matter. These considerations show that the assumption of matter moved by mind does not carry with it the consequences which Romanes sup poses, and that, if it did, still it would prove nothing to one not already convinced of the incredibflity of the rniraculous and of the existence of mind. They also show that the assumption is not, as Romanes asserts, improbable per se. But having attempted to show that the assumption in question is improbable, he next proceeds with the attempt to show that it is vir tually impossible. He supposes the case of a sportsman who shoots His assertion and kills a bird The sportsman's vohtion is supposed to sfbmtyoFm- have broken in upon the otherwise continuous stream of f romewVt°h" physical causes by modifying the molecular movements of the brain in a way to make the aim correct and the gun to discharge at the right instant, by converting the gunpowder into gas which propeUed the lead, which killed the bird. The first change in the material world (the brain) was very sUght ; but owing to the intricate nexus of physical causaUty throughout all nature, the introduction of so slight a disturbance is found to exert an everlast ing and ever-widening influence. The mechanical processes of the bird's body — its animal heat, its power to condition other mechanical changes in other lives, its power to propagate its kind, with all the physical changes this must have carried with it — all these have come to an end as a direct consequence of the man's volition thus suddenly breaking in upon the otherwise uniform course of nature. " Now," says Romanes, "I say that, apart from some system of preestablished harmony, it appears simply inconceivable that the order of nature could be maintained at aU if it were thus liable to be interfered with at any moment in any number of points." And he rightly says that the only difference between the doctrine of preestablished harmony and materialism as affecting freedom is that the former provides for a spiritual force which governs aU things, and the lat~ Pantheism in the Form of Monism. 109- ter a material. Hence he thinks we shall not accept preestabUshed harmony. This is the argument that is designed to show the impossibility of the assumption that mind can cause motion in matter. We wish first of all to determine whether Romanes means to deny that the will is free, and to assert that the wfll of the sportsman was a Romanes part of the chain of physical cause and effect. That this againsthim^ is what he means is evident from the fact that he is argu- self • ing against the possibility of an intervention by an independent cause. In other words, he here maintains that the physical system is a closed circle into which a mind from without could not break except at the risk of introducing the utmost confusion into the system. Now, this is identicaUy the position of materialism ; and vso monism is thus far materiaUsm. But one of the strongest arguments against material ism is just the consequences of this denial of the place of thought in the system. And indeed it is an argument employed by Romanes himseU. In the same work from which we have condensed this argu ment he sums up the materialistic position thus : ' " Nowhere can we (according to materiaUsm) suppose the physical process to be inter rupted or diverted by the psychical process ; and therefore we must conclude that thought and volition really play no part whatever in determining action." Such a conclusion he declares to be opposed at once to common sense and methodical reasoning ; and he shows the truth of this judgment by a sound argument of some length. We simply turn Romanes loose against himself. The sportsman's thought and vohtion did or did not play some part in determining his action in taking aim and pulling the trigger. If they did not, as Romanes argues on pages 52 and 53, then materialism is right, and Romanes is simply a materialist calling himself by the name of monist. If they did, as Romanes argues on pages 70 ff., then the materialistic Romanes is overcome in argument and fact by the spiritualistic Romanes ; not by the monist Romanes, for the argument is that of spiritualism as against materialism. So, then, Romanes has answered himself thus far by showing the unsoundness of the position that thought and voli tion do not affect action. Hence we conclude that, whether the order of nature can or cannot be maintained if man's volition can interfere with that order, man's volition does so interfere according to Romanes himself. But is it true that the order of nature cannot be maintained under such conditions ? What is meant by the order of nature ? Let us 1 Mind and Motion and Monism, pp. 70 ff. 110 Foundations of the Christian Faith. answer the second question first. It may perhaps be safely assumed that there is nothing involved in the order of nature except the forces of nature. If they should cease to operate in their regular way the order of nature would be overthrown. If gravitation, cohesion, and Would inter- chemical affinities, for example, should prove inconstant vention from m their operation there could be no order of nature such strty the as we now have. But it does not interfere with the order ordfir oi nn- ture? 0f nature when the action of gravitation in one place is counteracted by its more forceful application in another ; as when the weight of the suspension bridge is thrown upon the towers. Nor does it interfere with the order of nature when cohesion is called in to aid in checking the local force of gravitation ; as in the cables which are employed in the supposed bridge. As a whole the system of nature is not interfered with. The forces of nature are simply manipulated. It cannot even be said that the force of gravitation is suspended in the span of the bridge. It acts just as before ; but other forces have been caUed into exercise by which gravitation in the span does not produce its ordinary effects. But the order of nature is larger than this diminutive earth on which we live, and as yet no human voUtion has been able to affect this larger order. It goes on in a perfectly uniform way, uninfluenced by human action. We are beginning to reach the point where we can answer the ques tion of the possibility of niaintaining the natural order if interfered with by the human wfll. The human will cannot reach beyond the earth and its atmosphere, hence the order of nature in that realm be yond is in no danger from the mind of man. Nor can the human will affect the fundamental order even upon the earth. It cannot make nor unmake gravitation, nor any of the other forces of the natural world. The most it can do is to change the direction of these forces. And this it can do only by a law of compensation. If it checks gravi tation in one place it must do it by increase of gravitation elsewhere. Thus the order of nature is maintainable on the supposition that human volition can interfere, for that interference is limited. But, if by the order of nature is meant that which would be were The answer man not on the earth, then it is plain that man has changed on the meaiv the order. He does it every time he destroys or plants a term " order tree, or cultivates a wild plant until it is fit for the flower Of Tl 3.^111* A " garden, or dams a stream and turns a water course, or builds a house, or weaves a web of cloth and makes a garment. With the order of nature in this sense man's voUtion is constantly in- Pantheism in the Form of Monism. Ill terf ering ; sometimes for the better — that is for its greater beauty and utility in the sight of man — and sometimes for the worse. Nay, more ; even from beyond our earth and its atmosphere come additions to its quantum of matter and force without any perceptible change in the fundamental order. Numberless meteors fall into our atmosphere. Those which reach the earth's surface and those which do not add alike to the earth matter and force which did not originaUy belong to it ; but the earth swings in its orbit and rotates upon its axis just as before, and the action of none of the laws of nature is interrupted in any serious way.1 We conclude, therefore, that the monistic argu ment against dualism is altogether inconclusive. Our object has not been to establish the fact of duaUsm, but to show that monism has failed to prove its impossibility. So far as monists consistently object to pure materiaUsm we accept their arguments and conclusions, which indeed were not theirs before they were ours, but ours before they were theirs. We also grant their right to claim that there is some thing in the world besides spirit, though we reserve the right to say in the proper place what we must hold that something to be. For the further test of monism it will be better to take up the monistic psy chology and theology, including, of course, its cosmology. In these we must find its strength or weakness. 1 The above criticism of Romanes's views Is applicable to all statements similar to his ; for example, that of A. Riehl, Introduction to the Theory of Science and Metaphysics, 1894, p. 231. 112 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. THE IDEALISTIC-MONISTIC PSYCHOLOGY. We are met at the very threshold of this branch of the subject by the fact that there are two distinct tendencies in monistic circles, the Two classes of first being represented by those who are inclined to ideal- monists. igm> the secon(j by tnose wn0 incline toward materiaUsm. In English, Romanes is a fair representative of the former, and Paul Carus ¦ of the latter. Because the continental thinkers have studied the subject more profoundly and originaUy we prefer to take them as the standard monists, though their works are in a foreign language. As the representative of the idealistic or spiritual monists we choose Hoffding as he has presented his views in his "Psychology," already several times referred to. But we must guard against thinking of Hoffding as a confessed idealist. He says that he does not enter on the question whether it is spirit or matter which lies at the foundation of being.2 "As to the inner relationship of spirit and matter we teach nothing ; we assume that one substance (Wesen) works in both. What kind of a substance (Wesen) is this ? Why does it reveal itsefl in a twofold form? Why is not a single one sufficient ? These are ques tions which lie beyond the realm of our knowledge. Spirit and matter appear to us as an irreducible twofoldness, just as do subject and ob ject. We remove the question farther back, therefore. And this is not only justifiable, but even necessary, since it is plain that in reality it lies deeper than is generally believed." s Why, then, does he insist on thinking that one substance works both in spirit and matter ? He gives us several reasons. * (1) Because, Hi"asons gfoSr according to the doctrine of the conservation of energy, mmiYsm in We cannot beUeve the dual theory of interaction between psychology, spirit and matter. Let us consider this. According to Hoffding himself the doctrine in question is one purely of physics." Ho makes this declaration the basis of an argument against any causal relation between spirit and matter. But, in reality, when he limits it to physios ho limits it to the brain, so far as psychology is concerned, 1 See in his The Soul of Man, an Investigation of the Facts of Physiological and Exper imental Psychology, the section on " The Reaction against Materialism," pp. 380-388. a Psychologic, p. 84. s Ibid., p. 83 f. * Ibid., p. 80. 'Ibid., p. 69. 1HE JLDEALISTIC-XV10NISTIC PSYCHOLOGY. 113 and thus the doctrine says nothing about the possibflity of an influence from without the system. We think this is made clear in a preceding discussion.1 (2) Because of a series of par allels between the activity of consciousness and the functions of the nervous system.2 He thinks it would be a wonderful accident if these parallels existed without any fundamental innerconnec- * Second reason. tion. But it would be easy to account for these parallels without the theory of accident on the hypothesis that mind and brain mutually influence each other. And, as we have seen, there is noth ing to hinder us from holding this theory, since its only support is the doctrine of the conservation of energy, which we have proved to be no support. (3) Not only the parallelisms between the activity of consciousness and that of brain but the equivalency be- m, . . ^ J Third reason. tween them he holds to be a proof of the inner connec tion, or, in other words, of the theory that it is one and the same sub stance giving a twofold expression to itseU. But in fact there is no such equivalence. This Romanes has clearly demonstrated,3 though, as he supposed, in the interest of monism. Hoffding seems to have confused the fact that there is a proportion between brain develop ment and the degree or grade of consciousness with the thought of a proportion of brain activity and activity of consciousness.4 Hoffding also discusses the question whether there are not some mental processes which are not in any way connected with brain action, and comes to the conclusion that there are no such mental proc esses. We are not particular as to the settlement of this question, since if we may suppose all mental processes connected with brain action the question is not thereby answered as to which is cause and which is effect. And in no case is it necessary, with monism, to deny caus aUty in the relation, and to make both effects. For, as we have repeat edly pointed out, dualism as well accounts for the facts Dualism abet- as does monism. And perhaps this is as good a place as tion than ... monism of we shall find to show that dualism is a better explanation concomitant of the twofold activity than is monism. This will un- mental ac- J , , tivity. questionably appear to be the case when once we have conquered the inveterate prejudice against the idea of interaction be tween mind and body. For, as Hoffding says,B with all frankness, monism is not a complete solution of the problem of the relation be tween soul and body, and this supposed inner connection is inexplica- ' See pp. 106,107, above. » These parallels may be found in his Psychologie, pp. 62-65. •Mind and Motion and Monism, p. 68 f. 4 Psychologie, pp. 75 and 80 compared. 6 Ibid., pp. 83, 84. 114 Foundations of the Christian Faith. ble, lying beyond the limits of our knowledge. Now, we do not pretend that dualism is a complete explanation of the relation of soul and body. That there can be any effective relation whatever between the two is a mystery— a part of the broader mystery of effective rela tion between things in general. But dualism explains what monism fails to explain, while it can explain everything that monism can explain. We can best make this clear by reference to an expression em ployed by Hoffding. He says that the thoughts, feelings, and pur poses of which we are conscious in inner experience have their Heff ding's counterpart in the physical world in certain processes examined!1 of the brain. " It is as though one and the same content were expressed in two languages."1 Now, we ask, is it likely that two languages would be needed to express the same content or fact ? Is it not more Ukely that the two languages give expression to two distinct facts f Besides, the monistic theory supposes that it is one and the same substance which speaks these two languages. It is, indeed, not unusual for one person to speak two languages ; but it is an unheard-of thing for the same person to have two native lan guages. Yet here is a supposed substance which expresses the same fact in two languages both of which are native to it. We affirm, that it is much more natural to suppose that there are two entities cor responding to these two languages. Particularly is it more natural since, according to Hoffding himself, these languages have nothing in common. They differ, not as two different human languages differ, but as the languages of two beings might be supposed to differ whose attributes are mutuaUy exclusive of each other. Hoffding's figure of speech is misleading in that it attempts to minify the actual difference. This difference is not simply such as exists between two languages, but rather such as obtains between the letters in the words of a printed page (so much color, form, etc.), and the thought conveyed by them to the reader. The one is material, the other mental.2 But recurring once more to his figure we say again that such differ ences of language point to the thought of different entities which employ them. We fully recognize that it is figurative language which Hoffding uses, but we have kept to the thought which his 1 Psychologie, p. 81. On Hoffding's theory comp. the excellent discussion in Ladd's Philosophy of Mind, pp. 319-355. * The same remarks apply to the illustrations of the convexity and concavity of the same arc of a circle, and of the solar system as Copemlcan and Ptolemaic when viewed respectively from the sun and the earth. See Fechner's Elemeute der Psychophysik, Leip zig, 1889. Erster Theil, p. 2 ff. The Idealistic-Monistic Psychology. 115 figure sought to express, and have shown thereby the improbabflity of monism and the probability of dualism. There is but one more point made by Hoffding which need be here noticed. He thinks that physiology will never admit that the physi ological processes in the brain suffer any interruption at Physiology op- the hands of psychological processes. For, aside from fimfs the doctrine of the conservation of energy, physiology must regard the nervous reactions as proceeding in an articulated circle of a self-dependent character. The fundamental thought of physiological science is the complete inner connection of the organic life. There is no place in the process where physiology can find any trace of cessation.1 As an argument this amounts to absolutely nothing, as Hoffding would doubtless confess. It does nothing but record the fact that the science of physiology is bent upon maintaining its position. And from the standpoint of physiology alone we certainly have no fault to find with either the theory or the purpose. It is only when certain physiologists assert that there is nothing in man but physiological processes that we object. One may, from the physi ological standpoint, insist that there is no interruption of physical processes in the human brain without denying, from a wider stand point, that for other than physiological results there may be some sort of cooperation between brain and mind. For according to mon ism itself there is mind as truly as there is matter, both of which, however, monism regards as abstractions.2 The use of the fact that physiology cannot allow any external science to dictate its limits is, then, merely to warn us off and prevent our trespassing ; or at most it serves to tell us that, right or wrong, some physiologists are deter mined to deny interaction between mind and brain. 1 Psychologie, p. 71 f. 2 Carus, The Soul of Man, pp. 23 f. 383. 116 Foundations of the Christian jaith. CHAPTER IV. THE MATERIALISTIC-MONISTIC PSYCHOLOGY. We turn our attention next to that class of monists who lean to ward materiaUsm, and we take for the representatives of this class Forel and August Forel, professor in the University of Zurich, and materialistic Emst Haeckel, professor in the University of Jena. monists Forel has defined and defended the monistic position with great ingenuity, in a small work of recent date, ' and Haeckel has published what he calls his confession of faith,2 in which he sounds the high praises of monism as a bond of unity between reUgion and science. It is a striking illustration of the fact that our daily occupa tions predispose our tendencies, to find Hoffding, the philosopher, tending toward idealism, and Forel and Haeckel, the men of natural science, tending toward materiaUsm, yet all professing to deal with the same data and to represent the same system. Both parties have a right on the field, since monism professes to be a philosophical con ception which is the outcome and result of science in its maturest shape.3 Of course aU monists repudiate materiaUsm in its baldest form — Carus, Forel, Haeckel, and all the rest — and we do not question their honesty. That they work into the hands of a purely material istic view of the soul is nevertheless true. We shall attempt to state in brief the principal doctrines of the more materialistic monistic psychology. According to Forel, brain and soul are one ; ' each phenomenon of soul has its material aspect, and each material phenomenon has its psychical, though in the main more elementary, aspect ; there is no brain without soul, and no complex soul, analogous to our own, with out brain ; psychology and brain physiology are but two different ways of looking at the same thing. Consequently, according to both Forel and Haeckel, the investiga tion of the phenomena of soul belongs within the domain of the de scriptive, experimental sciences of nature ; the soul must be studied, 1 Gehirn und Seele, Bonn, 1894. 2 Der Monismus als Band zwischen Religion und Wissenschaft. Glaubensbekenntniss eines Naturforschers. Bonn, 1892. 3 Carus, Monism, Its Scope and Import, Chicago, 1891-92, p. 6. 4 Gehirn und Seele, pp. 13, 14, 18, 27. 1HE IVIATERIALISTIC-IVLONISTIC PSYCHOLOGY. 117 not as an immaterial thing, but in the organ of the soul, the brain, since scientific psychology is a part of physiology.' It should be noted here that by the brain as the organ of the soul these men do not mean an instrument which the soul employs for its purposes, but that which produces the soul. Again, they teach that the human being is not the only existence which has a soul, but that there is a soul in everything — in each atom, in each living cell of plant and animal, in the lowest, the Atom and cell highest and the intermediate forms of life.2 But they sous' claim that the higher forms of soul life are connected only with brain. In fact, Forel warns vigorously against what he calls humanizing the ideas ceU-soul and atom-soul, which he postulates on logical grounds, but which have not the slightest resemblance to the human soul.3 For, as he says in the same connection, we have difficult and but partial access to the souls even of the higher mammalia ; the souls of insects we can construe but hypotheticaUy and fragmentarily ; while every soul becomes more and more difficult of access and investiga tion as it recedes in the scale of life. As to consciousness in relation to the soul, Forel is unclear as possi ble. He says that the essence of the idea of soul lies in the idea of consciousness, which he defines as the faculty of inner vision, and of reflecting external objects in this inner vision.4 Yet he Forel on con- . sciousness says that it would be impossible to prove that any activity and soul. in the world is unconscious, and seems to identify consciousness with attention.6 On page 13 he says that human consciousness, soul, the content of consciousness, activity of the brain and brain matter, are but forms in which one and the same thing appears, and not separa ble from each other though logicaUy distinguishable by our faculty of abstraction. Haeckel is rather more clear. He says 8 that the soul is a function of the brain, and that what we caU human soul is but the sum of our sensibilities, volitions, and thoughts, the sum of thephysi- The soul as a ' function of ological functions whose elementary organs the micro- the brain. scopic ganglia cells of our brain constitute. And he confesses that we > Gehirn und Seele, p. 14, 18, 19; Der Monismus, p. 21 f. On the other hand Professor Scripture, who is an ardent advocate of the experimental method in psychology, ad mits the right of the introspectionists to attempt the maintenance of a true science ot mind apart from physiology, and says that no physiological experiments or methods can ever reveal a mental act. The New Psychology, London and New York, 1897, p. 14. a Ibid., p. 26 f. ; Der Monisms als Band, p. 21. 8 Ibid., p. 27. 4 Ibid., p. 11. 5 Ibid., p. 12. 8 Der Monisms, p. 21 f. His use of the word function is similar to that which Professor James distinguishes as productive function. Human Immortality, Boston and New York, 1898, p. 13. 10 118 Foundations of the Christian Faith. can definitely prove the existence of consciousness only in the highest animals. In a note on page 44 he asserts that the soul is a sum of plasma-movements in the ganglia ceUs. Thus the soul is, from one aspect, the sum of sensibihty, volition, thought ; and from another,. movement in matter organized in a certain way. Now, in accordance with the theory that brain and soul are one, Forel attempts to explain sensation and other mental phenomena physiologically. He first- explains that the peculiar property of the Forei's de- nervous system is the power to convey an excitation sensation swiftly by a sort of wavelike movement.1 For the sake mental phe- o£ brevity we shall caU the wavehke movement wave. nomena. Explaining sensation he says 2 that it occurs in the cere brum plainly at the point of arrival of the wave which started from that portion of the periphery of the nervous system which was the subject of the excitation. Here it meets with other coordinated waves and wakens countless other associated waves which, in an infinitesi- mally weakened form, or as one might say in a state of slumber, con tinue to swing on as a sort of memory of their original vigor, or which stand ready in some other mysterious way to be aroused. These traces of memory exist together in the most multitudinous though orderly and harmonious union, or in so-caUed association. The wave which wakes these slumbering or weakly swinging waves, these mem ories of former sensations, strengthens and changes in part the whole associated complex. The result of this is to affect other series of complexes, partly checking them, partly strengthening them. Some of these strengthening waves result in impulses of the wfll and pro duce movements. Having given us this powerful effort he admits that though we must approximately represent the process of thought as just given we must not forget that there are many other forms of waves which are whoUy unclear; for example, how the brainwaves which result in emotion are conditioned ; also that there are processes which are accompanied by an effort which we caU attention. This, then, is the monistic account of sensation, accompanied by the confession that it is but approximate, and that the profounder contents of consciousness are not explicable. Now we call attention to the fact that this is not a description of the process of thought at Cthec above1 a11, but only of certain movements in the brain which account. have been arbitrarily identified with thought. The monist takes such a material view of things that he cannot see that 1 Gehlrn und Seele, p. 15. a n,^ p. 19. The Materialistic-Monistic Psychology. 119 the brain movements are one thing and the thought another. Forel could have learned from Hoffding that it is purely a figure when memory is attributed to any phenomenon of the physical world.1 And it is a purely hypothetical account even of the connection of these hypothetical waves. It is pure assumption that waves which reached the brain went to sleep there but continued to exist, ready to wake up when called upon. The figure of speech has, so far as we know, nothing to correspond to it. It is another pure assumption that these original waves continue to be waves though in a weaker meas ure. And it is a pure assumption that new waves have the power to strengthen weakened waves. So that even from the physiological standpoint we have learned nothing to the purpose. Yet we are told that we must not any longer study the mind in its own phenomena, but in the phenomena of brain movement. Then, too, why make this demand and at the same time admit its impossibility ? — as we see that Forel has done in the confession noted above. Another thing that Forel insists upon as proving the physiological character of thought is the relation of brain conditions to mental activity. He declares2 that the study of the brain and of mental dis eases shows that when the cerebrum is injured the result is at once seen in psychical changes, though he admits that not every such in jury results in serious mental impairment. The point as to how much injury the brain can suffer without loss of mental power is not altogether settled. Carus gives ' a number of instances of injured brains which resulted in loss of Eeiation of i ... ,-, £ , . . brain condi- bodfly movement in various members, but m all oi wnicn tion to men- -. j, ,1 • , tal activity. the mental power remained intact. One ot the instances was that of a general whose mental activity and professional judg ment were left unimpaired, but who wearied easily when engaged in intellectual pursuits. Carus says that if one hemisphere of the brain remains sound the loss of sensory and other centers in the other hemi sphere wfll be marked only by tiring more easily than when both hemi spheres are intact. But, if the theory of monism as given by Forel be true, loss of brain matter in considerable quantities ought to result in loss of mental activity in variety and intensity. That instead of this the result, in cases like those mentioned by Carus, is quicker weariness in inteUectual labor, shows that the inteUectual worker, the mind, is in possession of an instrument which, by reason of its injuries, cannot serve as long as it once did without fatigue. The in teUect must give the relatively small amount of brain more work to i Psychologie, p. 59. 2 Gehirn und Seele, p. 18. s The Soul of Man, p. 172 f. 120 Foundations of the Christian Faith. do. The inteUect remains the same; but the servant is weakened. Besides, Forel quietly assumes the facts to prove his theory, whereas, they are as capable of explanation on duaUstic as on monistic grounds. Let us suppose that aU he says is true ; still the question would be, Is the alleged difference in mental power real or only apparent ? Does the injury to the brain really decrease mental power, or does it only decrease the facility with which the inteUect expresses itseU ? Forel assumes the former, and then draws the conclusion that brain action and mental action are practicaUy identical. This is a circle in reason ing as perfect in its kind as the famous circle of Giotto. In fact, brain injury does limit bodily movement in some cases ; but that does not prove that there is any loss of wfll power. The disturbance in the physiological functions is admitted, but not the disturbance in mental functions. As we have seen, the fact of weariness indicates that the power of the mind remains the same, but that the power to express itself is reduced.1 1 The doctrine we have here maintained is that of Professor James, published since the above was written, called by him the permissive or transmissive function ofthe brain, as distinguished from the productive function, which he rejects. Human Immortality, p. 15. XJtUJJ J.Y10N1STIC rSYCHOLOGY OF HAECKEL. 121 CHAPTER V. THE MONISTIC PSYCHOLOGY OF HAECKEL. It is time to turn our attention to Haeckel. His wide reputation, arising in part from his real services to science in some of its depart ments and in part from the natural vigor of his mind, which leads him to give forcible expression to whatever position he holds, lends to his above-mentioned work an importance far beyond its ability. As a compendium of assumptions and assertions in the interest of monism it probably has no equal. But as Haeckel is a scientist, and scientists are popularly supposed to be very exact in statement and rigid in their demands for proof before they wfll accept anything as fact, his words will carry immense weight with a certain class of readers. We desire to call attention, then, to the fact that, whatever may be Haeckel's merits when dealing with biological phenomena, the philo- Haeckel not a sophical interpretation of these phenomena is more likely p osop ei" to be conducted properly by one whose life is devoted to philosophy than by one whose field of research has been the material realm. On this point David Friedrich Strauss, whom Haeckel calls the greatest theologian of our century,1 is correct when he says:2 "Phflosophy alone, considered as metaphysics, is able to furnish the ideas of energy and matter, substance and phenomena, cause and effect, those finest instruments with which the student of nature hourly operates; it alone can teach us how to- apply them with logical correctness. The scientist can receive from the hand of philosophy alone the Ariadne clew to the labyrinth of the daily increasing mass of observed facts ; and phflosophy alone can furnish the scientist with the only possible information in the regions which contain the questions of beginning and end, Umitation or Umitlessness, purpose or accident, in the world." Had Haeckel heeded this suggestion his attempt to construe the world from a philosophical point of view would have been, to say the least, more modest. Let the reader, therefore, not be prejudiced in favor of Haeckel's philosophy ; for Haeckel is not a philosopher but a scientist. Let Haeckel furnish the facts, and let phflosophers inter- > Der Monismus, p. 23. a Der alte und der neue Glaube, Siebente Auflage, p. 215. 122 Foundations of the Christian j^aith. pret them. As we have already said, Hoffding, the philosopher, in terprets these facts quite differently from Forel and Haeckel, the sci entists. We have given Haeckel's description of the soul. We now give Hoffding, the Hoffding's estimate of Haeckel's view.1 "One some- S^Hafei, times meets, in the utterances of physiologists who have the scientist: gome philosophical education, the statement that the ac tivity of consciousness is a function of the brain. It appears, how ever, as though the strictly physiological use of the expression ' func tion ' must contradict such a statement. That, for example, contrac tion is the function of muscle, says nothing but that it (contraction) is a given form and condition of muscle in movement. . . . Muscle in function is as material as muscle in rest, and what does not possess the attributes of matter cannot be the form of activity of anything mate rial. The idea of function, in the physiological sense, points as truly as the idea of matter or product to something which meets us in the form of space as an object of perception. Thoughts and feelings can not be represented as objects in space or as movements. We learn them (thoughts and feelings), not by external perception, but by the sensibility of the self and by self -consciousness. ... By many round about ways it is finaUy discovered that certain phenomena of con sciousness are connected with the functions of certain definite parts of the brain. And there is no doubt that the highest activities of con sciousness have their corresponding brain functions. . . . But the ac tion of consciousness and the functions of the brain we constantly learn to know by means of different experimental sources. Material ism overreaches itself by obliterating this essential distinction. By giving to brain the power of consciousness (that is, by making con sciousness a function of brain), or perhaps even making the brain the subject of the manifestation of consciousness, the materialist returns to the mythological-fantastic standpoint." These words were written to oppose materialism. But in this respect there is no difference be tween materialism and Haeckel's monism. Both make the soul a func tion of brain. That Hoffding and Haeckel, the philosopher and scientist, disagree Further evi- *s further evident from additional remarks by the former, theirCdis°a- which we here quote and compare with remarks of the greemen . ]atter. Says Hoffding," commenting on the preceding quotation from his Psychologie : "We have in mind here more es pecially empirical or phenomenological materialism, that is, that view ' Psychologie, p. 75 f. a Ibid., pp. 76 ff. J- JUIj JYIUWIOJJU XD TOHGLOGY OF HAECKEL. 123 which makes it a result of experimental science that the phenomena of consciousness are forms or effects of material phenomena, so that all reality may be reduced to motion in space." We pause in the quota tion to show that this is just what Haeckel does. He says : a " The neurological problem of consciousness (note that he assumes that con sciousness is a neurological problem) is only a special one contained in the all-comprehensive cosmological problem, the problem of substance. If we had an understanding of the nature of matter and force we should also understand how the substance which forms their basis could, under given conditions, feel, desire, and think." And on page 44 of the same work he says : " The facts of consciousness and its rela tion to the brain are not less and not more puzzling than the facts of seeing, hearing, gravitation, and the connection of matter and force." As quoted before, Haeckel declares that the soul is a sum of plasma- movements in the gangha ceUs. Here he plainly speaks, not merely of equal degrees of mystery ; on the contrary, he identifies the mysteries of consciousness and the mysteries in the physical world. Now hear what Hoffding has to say concerning the view in question : "Even if he (the empirical materialist) were right in all his assertions, Still he constantly overlooks something which raises a new and, to him, an alarming problem — the fact, namely, that motion in space is known to us only as an object of our consciousness. From the Standpoint of the theory of knowledge, therefore, such ideas as con sciousness, representation, and perception lie deeper than the ideas of matter and motion. . . . What we have here tried to do is, how ever, not to point out the inconsequence, from the standpoint of the theory of knowledge, which (empirical) materialism is guilty of by the demand that consciousness shall recognize as the absolutely original and only real that which is given only as an object of consciousness, and which can only be represented and known by the activity of con sciousness itself. Our object here, on the other hand, is only to de termine what view the given compels us to take ; and the result of our criticism of materiaUsm is that it sins against the very ideas we gain from experience." We must now briefly note several other points which may be dis missed the more promptly because they have already been considered in other connections. For example, Haeckel's description Monism fans of the soul as a sum of mental states or of physical move- for conscious- HcSS OI ^JtrA- ments makes no provision for our consciousness of per- sonal unity. sonal unity. It denies the existence of a unitary soul, and so fails to i Der Monismus, p. 23. 124 Foundations of the Christian ±'aith. explain how we have a sense of unity or can be aware of a multiphc- ity. This is possible only to an individual. For example, it would be logicaUy possible to an atom-soul but not to a complex brain-soul. Again, monism denies the freedom of the wfll. Says Hoffding,1 "Psychology, like every other science, must be deterministic, that is, For freedom of it must proceed on the supposition that the law of causal- the will. ity deludes tne action of the wfll just as it is assumed that it includes other phenomena of consciousness and material nature." Such, indeed, is the doctrine of all monists. It is true they do in some cases speak of the freedom of the wfll, but by that they mean freedom to do what one wills, not to wfll freely, even within- narrow limits. And some of them, Uke the materiaUsts, claim that the doctrine of freedom in its usual form is incompatible with the preaching of morahty. But in fact if our choices are necessitated, in any true sense of the word, then we aU labor under a tremendous delusion. But the quotation we have just given from Hoffding contains an al lusion to a third point which we cannot leave unnoticed. It is the For freedom of expression about each and every phenomenon of con- oug ' sciousness as included along with material nature under the law of causality. This is the old materiaUstic doctrine which de nies freedom even to our thought. And here, as there, it cannot be allowed without destroying the vaUdity of aU thought. For if one thought is necessitated, every thought is also. Hence when we think differently from others their thoughts and ours have equal value for truth, that is, reaUy no thought can be said to be either true or false. Again, monism, as truly as materiaUsm, finds no place for individ ual immortality. Carus" discusses at length the question, Is death a a n d f o r i m- finaUty ? and gives it a negative answer. He even speaks ttier fnaivid- of the immortaUty of the soul. v But the careful reader wfll see that it is not the irnmortahty of the individual, but of the father and mother, who though they die, Uve on in their children. It is remarkable that he did not recall those numerous human beings who are destined to live ceUbate lives, and those other numerous husbands and wives who have no "life after death in the coming generations," because nature affords them no offspring;3 or whose progeny become extinct. Had he reflected on these facts he i Psychologie, p. 439. a The Soul of Man, pp. 398 ff . a There seems something almost dishonest in his language about the immortality of the soul on p. 407 f, when we see in his discussion of the Psychological Problem and Religion (pp. 429 ff.) bow vigorously he denies any true immortality. But we prefer the more char itable view that he is deceived by his preconceived theory. xujts, jnuiUSTIU JTSYCHOLOGY OF HAECKEL. 125 would not have been betrayed into ascribing immortaUty to man in the sense in which he uses the word. In due time we shall see how unscientific is the denial of immortaUty.1 Here we can only use the denial to point out how many conclusions materiaUsm and monism have in common. Monists are loud in their professed renunciation of materialism. And no doubt they are honest. But it is strange they do not see that their path is the same in aU essential respects as that of their declared foe, and that at the end of the journey they therefore reach the same goal. And finaUy, monism does not do away with the fact that there is a dualism between mentality and matter. It only Fa,iure of changes the relation they sustain to each other. Seapeduai- Thought and extension have the same mutuaUy exclu- lsm- sive character as in dualism, only these mutually exclusive some things are regarded as two ways of looking at one self-consistent sub stance. We have seen that it is more natural to suppose that two such wholly unlike phenomena are the aspects of two wholly differ ent substances. As between dualism and monism in psychology, the former has taken up the more tenable position.2 1 See division vi, section ii, chaps. 1-3. 2 See Ladd, Philosophy of Mind, chap. x. 126 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VI. monistic theology. Monism, judged by its etymology, distinguishes itself as a stand ing protest against dualism. Nevertheless, it is much given to theol ogy, and its adherents do not distinguish it theologicaUy from pan theism, but apply that name to its conception of God and his relation to the world. The first peculiarity of monistic theology is its proof of the exist ence of God, which is not moral but cosmological. In this connec tion it is to be noted that monism is very sure of the existence of God, • although its only use for him (or should we say " it ? ") is as the up holder of the world, and the like. Another striking feature of monistic theology is its negative char acter. Particularly does the monist negate certain attributes which Christianity has cherished as most precious, especiaUy personaUty. Three chief A third characteristic of monistic theology is its vague- tics of mon- ness. This is necessarily the case, since to the monist istic theol- ... ogy. it is impossible to liken God to anything in heaven above, nor in the earth beneath, nor in the waters under the earth. Theism strives to make God in some degree comprehensible to thought, though it recognizes the impossibility of giving more than a few practical hints in this direction. Pantheism, or monism, pur posely avoids all descriptions of God which can be grasped by the logical understanding. Let us take up these points in the order of their statement. We find Forel defining God as that which makes out or constitutes the unsearchable, metaphysical Omnipotence,1 and he declares that while we cannot understand this infinite power we have no right to deny its existence, which is proved by the phenomena of the universe.2 Ben- Mon i stic Jamin Vetter says: "With the progress of the knowl es0 exisiv edS© of the causal connection of nature arose . . . ever clearer the suspicion, and at length the certainty, that there is one unchangeable Somewhat (Wesen) which is far above all human limitations, the source and preserver of aU finite things.'" 1 Gehirn und Seele, p. 6. a pjid. p 31 0 Die moderne Weltanschauung und der Meusch, Zweite Auflage, Jena, 1896, p. 145 f. -i-ViONISTIO XHEOLOGY. 127 When we turn to Strauss we find no attempt to prove the existence of God. He identifies God and the universe. We feel ourselves depend ent, and it matters not whether we say we are dependent on God or on the universe. • Haeckel, who has taken the trouble to give us a so-caUed " Confession of Faith of a Natural Scientist," also gives no proof. Why should he ? The universe and God are simply names for one and the same thing. There is as much evidence for the exist ence of one as for the other. Of course there remains the question as to the right to identify God and the world ; but that is the presup position of monism, so far as it is a theology. Nevertheless, it is plain that even in Strauss and Haeckel we have the proof of the existence of God in the existence of the world, so that they fall into Une in this respect with other monists. Now, what are the consequences for rehgion of this doctrine that God is, or is known only as the source and upholder of the world ? This question receives the suggestion of an answer in the considera tion that the one idea in connection with the God of the monists is Power. This is his sole attribute. In the New Testament we are taught that God is Love. In the scriptures of the monists God is de clared to be Power. It is true that Strauss, the great The sole at- prophet of monism, rebukes Schopenhauer for hitting the the™God of monistic conception of God in the face ; and says that momsm- such conduct affects the religious feeling of the monist as blasphemy, and that the monist demands for his Universe-God the same rev erence demanded by the pious soul of the old style for his God.2 But even he would not venture to assert that the God of the monists should be loved, or that we should feel grateful to the universe. He demands only that such feelings as he possesses should not be wounded by unbelievers, and he does not like to think that anyone should annihilate his feeling of dependence which is, to him, the sub stance of the reUgious feeling. " We call attention to the fact that certain of the most important of the religious feelings have no place in the attitude of the monist to his God. Love is out of the question ; for we never love Feelings nec essarily ex- the merely powerful. Some of the forms in which this eluded from ,. , , j i, monistic pl- power manifests itself we may love, but not the power ety. itself. The same is true of the feeling of gratitude. There is nothing to be grateful to. We may indeed congratulate ourselves when we are situated according to our own wishes, but gratitude is a feeling toward a person, and is clearly distinguishable from self-compla- 1 Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 142. 3 Ibid., p. 147. 3 Idem. 128 Foundations of the Christian Faith. cency. So, too, communion with this God is impossible. We may meditate all we will in the presence of nature. It may, in a poetical sense of the word, speak to us, or commune with us. But of com munion such as we have with a person there can be none. Again, toward this power it is impossible to feel any sense of duty, though such a sense may be experienced toward some of its manifestations. Thus while love, gratitude, and duty would not be absent between man and man, their manifestation would be social rather than reU gious ; that is, limited to our relations with our feUow-men. Strauss speaks indeed of reverence (Pietat) toward this monistic deity. But this, too, is a feeling impossible of entertainment in reference to a mere power. One can reverence a person only, and that because rev erence is a sentiment elicited by character, which we can attribute only to a person. When we turn to those feelings which we could experience in our relations to this mighty power which the monist calls God we find that not one of them is, strictly speaking, distinctively reUgious, The feelings though aU of them attend upon religious feeling to a distinctively greater or less extent. We mention, first, admiration ; religious. jor we can jyjjjjjpg p0weri and especiaUy when it assumes forms of expression harmless to our interests and adapted to awaken our aesthetic emotions. Closely akin to this is wonder; a feeling which we may experience toward any power which is to us mysteri ous because of its evident reserve of what we conceive to be its vast or unknown possibilities. This emotion may be heightened to awe when the sense of the vastness of the power becomes overwhelming, or to sublimity when it is mixed with admiration rather than fear. This awe-inspiring power may also elicit fear and terror, which it often does in timid souls, or when it appears inimical to some or aU of our present interests. Any of these sentiments— admiration, won der, awe, sublimity, fear, terror— might lead to adoration, which is a religious state and a reUgious act, if the object of adoration were per sonal. When it is impersonal the thoughtful man wfll refrain, be cause he would not commit the folly of adoring that which has no intelUgence to perceive his emotion. We may be incited to hope, also, by the contemplation of power, and it is possible even to exer cise faith in power. But the hope and faith here mentioned are not the religious sentiments known by those names, and are as possible to the atheist, whom the monist condemns, as to the monist himseU. In fact, the vociferations of monism are well adapted to deceive only the unobservant, among whom we are obliged to place all mon- JMonistio Theology. 129 ist theologians. Forel, for example, repels the charge of atheism placed against monism. He says : ' "We often meet with the saying, Pantheism is the same as Atheism. A hundred times, Theological No ! " But we chaUenge the monist to show us one single encyof mon- sentiment which his God can eUcit which is not equaUy lsm" called for by what the atheist calls power. In fact, the atheist and the monist hold exactly the same notion of the power that is in the world. The monist simply becomes inconsistent by naming this power God. The monist says, "A spirit in everything ; " or " God in everything." But it is only as he unconsciously or surreptitiously in troduces the theistic idea, which denies that God and the world are identical, that he gains anything over the atheist, who says merely that there is power in everything. Let the monist rid himself of every vestige of theism and the difference between himself and the atheist wfll be one of nomenclature only. Admiration, wonder, awe, sublimity, fear, and terror are felt by the atheist in his contemplation of the world — the universe. The monist makes it a matter of indif ference whether we say God or universe ; if he makes any distinction rather preferring the latter to the former word.2 We do not make this point against the monist theology in order to arouse prejudice, but to call attention to the unclear thinking of mon ism. If they take their doctrine earnestly there is nothing which monists can feel toward their universe-god that the atheist cannot feel toward the universe. As soon as they rise above this atheistic condition of the feelings it is evident that there is something in their thought that is other than the universe ; or, in other words, that they have forsaken the monistic standpoint. But, it may be asked, can it not also be truthfully said of theism that it knows no emotions except those which atheists and aU men have in common ? We answer that such a proposition would be false. Neither monist nor atheist experiences any sense of love, gratitude, or duty toward the All, because these are sentiments which exist be tween persons, and the AU is impersonal. But the theist can love his personal God, feel grateful to him, and recognize the relation of obli gation. So, too, the theist, unlike the monist and atheist, can rever ence the personal God. And, furthermore, as we have seen, com munion in the true sense of the word is possible only on wider range ...,,,. of feelings in the theistic hypothesis. It may be said that the person- theistic be- ality of God is a fiction, and hence aU this sentiment is sentimentality. But that is not the question here. The point is not i Gehirn und Seele, p. 30. ' Strauss, Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 144. 130 FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. the justifiabiUty of these feelmgs, but the possibility of them in the one case and the impossibility of them in the other. So, too, of the other class of feelings which the AU induces in every heart, such as admiration and the like. They become religious only when they are joined with the idea of God as distinct from, not as wholly identical with, the world. Unless we are willing to admit that the social feel ings of love, and the like, are religious when experienced toward men, and hence that a God is unnecessary to religion, and that an aesthetic feeling, such as admiration, is religious in every instance of its exer cise without reference to the cause which produces it, we shaU have to confess that theism knows religious feelings unknown to other forms of faith. Besides, hope and faith in a system such as the uni verse are very different feelings from hope and faith in a person. We cannot, therefore, accept the results of the monistic theology as a sub stitute for the theistic. For the purposes of a religion which shaU satisfy aU the needs of the human heart monism is a failure. It leaves us love, but with no object such as the heart demands. It robs us of the "Great Compan ion " as truly as atheism. It limits faith and hope to man or to the mechanical universe. For the purposes of aesthetics, so far as it can be separated from the other elements of our nature, monism wfll an swer. But even in this respect it would prove a failure, since the aesthetic feelings, while distinguishable, blend with aU our other feel ings, and would suffer numbness as a result of the deadening of the religious emotions. As a matter of fact aU high art has been the product of theism or polytheism. There is no single instance of the F5i!lLrJ! °„£ antireligious contemplation of nature which has resulted JlHMl 1SII1 in aesthetics, in the permanent artistic satisfaction of the mind. Nor has pantheism, consistently held, which it but seldom is, ever pro duced a poet, orator, musician, painter, or sculptor of note. Haeckel, with his usual wealth of assertion and poverty of proof, declares that Strauss has proved that monism does not destroy poetry nor fail to satisfy the emotional needs of man.1 But Strauss has neither done nor attempted any such thing. He has simply shown that the monist must turn from religion, as ordinarily conceived, to the great masters of poetry and art." Here Haeckel fails to distinguish things which are different, as he so often does. Of this failure we have another in stance in the same connection. He affirms that every increase in our knowledge of nature's secrets warms the feelings, nourishes the fancy, ' Der Monismus, p. 34. » See his development of this subject In Der alte und der neue Glaube, pp. 303-376. Monistic Theology. 131- and enlarges our sense of beauty. Of this he mentions Goethe as an example. Who denies this? Assuredly not the theist. What we deny is that the increase in knowledge above mentioned would have produced the alleged results in Goethe, with aU his genius, had he been a consistent pantheist. That one needs to be an orthodox Chris tian to be a poet is not asserted ; although we do assert that the more truly Christian the poet is, in the primitive and essential sense, the richer and warmer his fancy and feeling wfll be. The history of lit erature proves this assertion, Goethe not excepted. As a sustainer, therefore, of either religious or aesthetic emotions, monism is a fail ure ; and without the emotions reUgion and art would disappear. We are compeUed, as a consequence, to reject the monistic religion. 132 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VH. MONISM AS A COSMOLOGICAL THEORY. We note, as the second characteristic of monistic theology, its nega tive character. It consists chiefly in a negation of Christianity, espe ciaUy of the personality of God. Here it takes common ground with Spencerian agnosticism, though generaUy for less philosophical rea sons. In respect of its denial of personality monism rests in part upon a double misunderstanding of the Christian doctrine. In the first place the monists appear, generally, to think that Christianity regards God's relation to the world as an external one, and when they re ject a personal God who intervenes in the affairs of the world, a deus ex machina, they appear to think they are rejecting the Christian doctrine of the relation of God to the world. That many Christians have inconsistently held that doctrine is unfortunately true. But that it is the Christian doctrine is not true. Rather is it the deistic idea with the addition of what deists deny, namely, intervention in the world's affairs. In the second place, monists appear to think that, be cause Christianity asserts personaUty therefore it must deny or for get his immanence, or his omnipresence. ¦ Given the Christian idea Double mis- of God, as a personal being present in aU the phenomena understan d- ing of Chris- of the world, yet as not identical with the world, the tianity by monists. monists might save themselves much needless trouble. They need not try (1) to prove to Christians that God is not external to the world in a spatial sense, for that Christians do not deny. He is not, in the Christian view, external to the world in any sense except that he is not the world. If anyone can think of no kind of exter nality except spatial externaUty it is doubtful whether anything can be done for him unless we could somehow impart a Uttle mental abil ity to him. StiU, we shaU try ; and we try by stating that neither our thoughts nor our spirits are spatially external to our bodies, yet they are external in the sense that they are not our bodies. Nor need monists try (2) to prove to Christians that God is in everything, that 1 See Forel s Gehirn und Seele, pp. 22, 80 ; Strauss's Der alte und derneue Glaube, p. 109. Spencer falls also to take any account of the real Christian position in what he evidently regards as an exhaustive classification of the various doctrines of the relation of God to the world. See First Principles, pp. 30 ff. Monism as a Oosmological Theory. 133 he is everywhere present, that he is in all and through ah. But in as serting his omnipresence Christians do not assert that he is all in the sense that there is no other being except him. The two points of dif ference, then, between monists and theists in their doctrine of God and his relation to the world are, first, whether God and the world are one and the same, so that whether we take God or the world mat ters not ; and, second, whether God is personal or impersonal. The first of these questions we have discussed from the standpoint of reUgion. We must now consider it as a question of cosmological fact. In order that we may have a basis of operation let us take up a definition of monism. Carus says:1 "Monism (that is, Monistlc Cos- the word monism) means that the whole of reality, that mol°sy- is, everything that is, constitutes one inseparable and indivisible en tirety. Monism accordingly is a unitary conception of the world." "The AU being one interconnected whole, everything in it, every fea ture of it, every relation among its parts, has sense and meaning and reality only if considered with reference to the rest of the world and to the whole itself. In this sense we say that monism is a view of the world as a unity." We have here two somewhat diverse aspects of monism. The first relates to the asserted fact that " everything that is constitutes one in separable and indivisible entirety," and the second is this fact as con ceived by the mind with all its implications. StiU, the essential thing is the assertion that the world is a unity ; the word world meaning everything that is — the whole of reality. The language of the defini tion leaves the impression that the unity spoken of is numerical. It is a "whole," an "inseparable and indivisible entirety." Nevertheless, this "whole," this "entirety," has "parts" which are so intercon nected as to make one whole and which also have their relations with one another. The inseparability and indivisibility of this entirety cannot, however, we suppose, exist for thought, since the parts are thought of separately by monists, as by others. But these parts, when thought of as such, are not "things in themselves," "ab- The world a D ' numerical solute existences," but abstractions. They have their unit. "sense," "meaning, and reaUty only if considered with reference to the rest of the world and to the whole itself." Hence the inseparabil ity and indivisibility, which are not impossible for our abstract think ing, must pertain to the existing whole. Thus we have reached a numerical unit. There is but one existence, and that is the world. We think of it as having parts, but these parts are not realities, they i Monism : Its Scope and Import, p. 7. 134 Foundations of the Christian .faith. are simply abstractions of the mind to enable us to think the more easily. Now, this numerical unity involves also a qualitative unity. That And involves cannot be a numerical unit which has within it differ- tativequn!ty" ences in kind. A duality or a pluraUty of different kinds of things, did they exist in combination, would be an aggregation, not a numerical unit. This doctrine of quahtative unity is much insisted upon by monists when speaking of the relation between a supposed soul and a supposed body. It is made very clear that when we see phenomena of extension we merely think of a body, and when we see phenomena of thought we merely think of mind ; but we are taught that in fact there is but one kind of substance, and this substance has the quality of impressing us as possessing the wholly diverse attributes of extension and thought. Says Forel : ' " Our human brain-soul is not at all to be considered as something different from the world-all, but as a partial phenomenon of it. It is in our (monistic) sense divine, but not in and of itself higher than the other phenomena of the world." Here we see that the denial of the difference in kind includes the dif ference of higher and lower kinds. The qualitative oneness admits of Qualitative n0 grades. Gravitation and cohesion are as exalted as mHsfof no love- Haeckel even says this in so many words. "As grades. an essential, fundamental ingredient in this pure monism we may, in a certain sense, consider the supposition of ' besouled (be- seelte) atoms ' — an early idea to which Empedocles gave expression more than two thousand years ago in his doctrine of the hate and love of the elements. Our present-day physics and chemistry have uni versally accepted the atomic theory first proposed by Democritus, in asmuch as they regard all bodies as composed of atoms, and trace all changes to the movements of these discrete particles. All these changes, alike in organic and inorganic nature, appear to us in reality comprehensible only when we represent the atoms to ourselves, not as dead masses, but as living particles, invested with the power of at traction and repulsion. Like and dislike, love and hate, are but other expressions for this power of attraction and repulsion." 2 We do not regard Haeckel as capable of saying, except by happy chance, exactly what he means when outside of the realm of science. But, if we are to judge from what he says, he does not mean that attraction and repulsion are to atoms what love and hate are to con scious being, but that attraction, physically and chemicaUy considered, is love, and love is but physical and chemical attraction. If he does 1 G ehirn und Seele, p. 14. » Der Monlsmus, p. 14. MONISM AS A COSMOLOGICAL THEORY. 135 not mean what he says, we do not know what he does mean ; and since he is trying to make us see that atoms are never dead, but always Uv- ing, we see no way out but to take him as meaning just what he says. Psychologically, then, monism teaches that there is no difference in grade, between what we call soul and what we call matter ; and also that the forces of nature are identical in kind with the moral forces which unite mankind. Strange as all this seems it is perfectly con sistent with the doctrine that everything that is constitutes one insep arable and indivisible whole ; and, in fact, from this latter position no other conclusion could be logically deduced. We have seen that Strauss makes no distinction between the ideas God and universe. So that the denial of the distinction in kind in relation to psychology, theology, and cosmology is complete. Anthropologically also the distinction in kind is obhterated. Says Haeckel:' "The first beginnings of those higher brain functions which we designate as reason and consciousness, religion, and morality, are undeniably present in the most highly developed domestic animals, especially dogs, horses and elephants ; they differ only in grade, not in quality, from the corresponding soul-activities of the lowest races of men. Had apes, particularly the anthropoids, been, No distincti0I1 like dogs, domesticated for thousands of years, the ap- tween dman proach to the soul-activities of man would undoubtedly and ammal- have been still more striking. The apparently deep gulf which sepa rates man from the most highly developed mammals has for its par ticular ground the fact that man unites in himself several prominent qualities which appear in the other animals only one by one, namely, 1, the higher differentiation of the larynx (speech) ; 2, of the brain (soul) ; and, 3, of the extremities ; 4, finally, the upright position in walking. Solely the fortunate combination of a higher grade of de velopment of these important animal organs and functions lifts the majority of men so high above all animals." So that there is no qualitative difference between animals and men. Fdrel sums up the monistic position as follows:2 " The knowledge thus gained compels us to the supposition of a truly divine monistic world-potentiality (Weltpotenz) which hides itself behind our abstract artificial con cepts, and this world-potentiality must be at once consciousness, mat ter, and force, and that which brings forth the progressive evolution of the world and especially of inorganic and organic nature on our earth. This world-potentiality evidently possesses the possibility of a plastic expansion necessary to the infinite, evolutionary diversity in 1 Der Monismus, p. 38. " Gehirn und Seele, p. 13. 136 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the details of its phenomena, together with the cyclic repetition of the individual series of phenomena ruled by harmonious laws, aU of which we with our weak brain power, in our partial human conscious ness, but relatively and partiaUy divine or cognize, and then construe in our own way." We pause to take our bearings. The reference to the weakness of the human brain power is very impressive. Who that has ever thought but has all too painfuUy felt its truth? And when first re minded of it we incline to say that, after all, our dualistic or pluralis tic explanations of things are probably wrong. Recovering our selves, however, we remember that monists as a class are probably as brain weak as dualists ; and that though the human brain is weak it has undertaken the task of construing the world according to its Our mental phenomena, and it, or, as we should prefer to say, the only 'means mind, is the only power we have with which to perform for constru- tnat task. We should certainly feel commiseration for world. the man who claimed that he had solved aU problems. But it is plain that we cannot rest until we have reached a solution which is at least relatively satisfactory. If there be several such solutions each must choose that which to his own judgment best an swers aU questions. Now, the dualist says it is more Ukely that there are two entities corresponding to the two phenomena of thought and extension than that these wholly incommensurable attributes should inhere in one entity. And this we must argue because aU analogy is on our side. For diverse chemical reactions we seek diverse chemi cal elements. It would be impossible to make the physician beheve that a poison is at the same time not a poison, however innocent or even helpful it might be when adininistered under certain conditions. The duaUst furthermore maintains that the supposed difficulty of in teraction between mind and matter is no whit greater than that of interaction between material units. Yet all admit interaction in the latter case, inexpUcable though it be. So, then, the duaUst thinks his interpretation more satisfactory than that of the monist, while he frankly admits that both dualist and monist may be, though he sees no reason to think that the former, is wrong ; and thus far he cannot admit the qualitative and quantitative unity of the AU or the sum total. Within this higher realm of mind (and the duaUst insists that mind is higher than matter) there is, if we may judge from aU we know of it, a multitude of individuals. I cannot get rid of the feeling that I have an independent personality, nor can I believe that the idea of Monism as a Cosmologioal Theory. 137 self is a mere abstraction with no reaUty to correspond to it ; though I am perfectly wflling to concede, as the monist demands, that my self has significance only when viewed in its relation to the whole. The whole, however, as the dualist conceives it, is not a nu- Dualism re- merical unit but an aggregate. If I am a person, in the world Sas' an sense in which it seems to me I am a person, then it is aggre8ate- very sure that the whole is not a numerical unit, unless I have erred in attributing personality to others. Now, if I give up the idea of my personality I must have a better reason than the mere desire to re duce all things to unity in the numerical sense. I cannot avoid the conviction of personaUty, but I can avoid the conviction of numerical unity in the universe. I yield the less fundamental to the more fun damental conviction. Just here is one of the chief weaknesses of monism. It holds to the doctrine of numerical unity, but it cannot act on the supposition of its truth. To hold a doctrine as scientific which must be contradicted in practice is absurd. The theory and practice of chemistry and physics must be harmonious. We cannot hold the Newtonian doctrine of gravitation and act as though it were false. We practice what we preach in these respects. But monism holds a doctrine of individuality which it forbids us to put into practice. But within the lower realm, the realm of what we all caU matter, we find what we are bound to treat as a multiphcity instead of a unity. Take, for example, the atoms. The very scientists who so vigorously assert the unity of the universe, numerically and qualita tively, are those who insist on the atomic theory of the composition of matter. Carus consistently regards the atoms and molecules as abstractions also.1 And for a view of the world, an opinion of the nature of things, it may be proper to call them abstractions ; since a view of the world held by the mind need not correspond to the facts. The monist view of the world, which considers atoms and molecules as abstractions, certainly does not cor- in the world ' of matte r respond to the facts unless we are now to be taught that also there is r multiplicity, molecules as weU as atoms are fictions. For the chemist not unity. has hitherto been unable to get on without his molecules, and to him they are not abstractions, but substantial realities, whatever they may be for thought. If we may say that atoms and molecules are abstrac tions we may say also that matter is an abstraction ; and that all chemical reactions and processes of the physical world are abstrac tions. If they are not abstractions they are realities ; and, in practi- 1 Monism : Its Scope and Import, p. 7. 138 Foundations of the Christian Faith. cal life, we are obliged to treat them as such. This is true even of the monists, whose philosophical creed must be abandoned for the pur poses of science and art. But if each molecule is a reality we have a multiplicity, and not a numerical unity, in our world. Each molecule might be of the same quaUty as every other, but it would not be every other molecule. Again, the numerical unity of the physical world breaks down when we consider that the universe is made up of a number of solar systems. Our own solar system has a sort of identity for itself which it preserves side by side with other solar systems within the one great whole. But, more important still, within the physical world there is every evidence of qualitative diversity instead of unity. Things are not all Qualitative di- alike. We leave out of the count here the apparent the physical difference between the organic and the inorganic and the A living and the dead. The chemical elements, so called, have their individual characteristics, no two of them being alike. The theory that there is one kind of substance out of which aU these elements are constructed has almost no scientific evidence in its sup port, and, even if speculatively tenable, cannot be appUed in practice. For even should we suppose that there is one simple matter of which the so-called elements are constituted still it would be true that this simple matter exists in different states, which is essentially the same thing as different kinds of matter, by which we mean matter with different kinds of properties. There might be homogeneity in matter considered as having no properties, if such a thing were thinkable, but as soon as we think of matter with properties we find diversity, or heterogeneity. And should we at length reduce the properties of matter to a minimum there would have to be at least two in order that the law of cause and effect might operate. For perfectly homo geneous matter in one perfectly homogeneous state could not result in anything different from itseU.1 So that qualitative unity is, in human thought, an impossibflity. It never could satisfy our need of causal explanation. But, as a matter of fact, the progress of science is not, except speculatively, in the direction of belief in the homoge neity of matter, but rather favors its heterogeneity. For the number of chemical elements which are irreducible by any means known to chemical science is constantly increasing. Modern scientific thought, with its atoms and molecules in a real space, is monistic only in name. The quantitative and qualitative dif- 1 Compare Spencer, especially his assertion that one cause produces many effects. Illustrations of Universal Progress, New Vork, 1866, p. 32. Monism as a Cosmolqgical Theory. 139 ferences among things must be explained, and as long as they are referred for explanation to an impersonal power their own complexity must be carried back into their source. Thus the unitary ground breaks up into a plurality as manifold as its products.1 On the other hand, the dualistic position must be transcended, and hence we are aU monists in some fashion. But the true monist re fuses to assert unity where none is possible. He can affirm no proper unity of spatial objects since they are indefinitely divisible, and con sist of aggregates of parts. Nor can he think of a unitary cause of a variety of products, except as the entire cause is active in each. These axioms of a true monism are violated by all so-called monists who view the fundamental reaUty as impersonal. With both these ax ioms Haeckel plays havoc, and as a result his unity is one of words. The actual manifoldness has not been in the least reduced. Only as we advance to the conception of a personal intelligence who remains seU-identical whfle thinking and wflling into existence the manifold, can the notion of the manifold be combined with that of unity. 1 For further evidence of the dualism of monism see p. 147 f ., infra. 140 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VIII. THE MONISTIC NEGATION OF GOD'S PERSONALITY. The estabhshed facts of science point, then, to heterogeneity in matter as psychology points to a multitude of personalities. Neither in the one nor in the other realm do we find the numerical unity which monism teaches. We are perfectly wflling to foUow all facts where they lead us, but we are not willing to have the scientist turn metaphysician, and then claim dominion over us for his speculations Monism meta- as weU as for his facts. The course of our study must. science.' have revealed to the reader the fact that monism is far more metaphysics than science. Disclaiming, in the name of science, any knowledge of the reality behind phenomena it surreptitiously posits, in that reality, absolute unity. This is a metaphysical theory ; and we have seen that it has less to support it than the metaphysical theory of duaUty as between mind and matter, and of multiplicity within both the realm of mind and the realm of matter. Should it be said that nevertheless we cannot escape the conviction of the unity of nature, we reply that we do not deny it in any other than in the monistic sense. Of a metaphysical unity in which aU distinctions of quality and number lose their reaUty and must be regarded as mere abstractions we know nothing. We repeat, the unity known to dualism is one which is the result of scientific investigation, not of metaphysical speculation. It begins with the simplest forms of matter and extends to the bounds of the universe. Each human body is a unit in the sense that its members cooperate with each other. Each human being is a unit in the sense that mind and body cooperate. Each planet is a unit in the sense that it has its individual orbit and plane of revolution ; and the planet and aU its parts and inhabitants are a unit, not only for thought, but in that they dweU together in harmony. In the same sense the human race is a unit, and all the planets, with the central sun, con stitute a unit ; and aU the systems united are a unit. There are many units in one unit. But the one unit is a composite thing, not a thing whose parts exist only as abstractions of the mind.1 This scientific > Paulsen, though an idealist pantheist, seems to favor this idea of a composite unity.. Einleitung in die Phllosophle, p. 245 f. Monistic Negation of God's Personality. 141 unity need not deny the scientific theory of the origin of the world, of life, of the diversity between plant and animal, between animal and man, nor yet, to put the same idea in another form, the develop ment of aU the highest forms of Ufe out of the simplest. When dual ists deny evolution they are not, if they understand themselves, moved by the desire to support duahsm as against science; for science, as such, has nothing to say about dualism or monism. As soon as these questions enter the field of discussion science becomes silent, though scientists, essaying the role of metaphysicians, may be very voluble. The conclusion is that monism, as a cosmological theory, is a fail ure, whether considered from the standpoint of science or of meta physics ; and hence its negation of the Christian cosmology has no force. But this peculiarity of monistic theology which consists in the negation of the Christian position is even more striking in its denial of the personaUty of God. It behooves us, therefore, to Grounds for , , ., . .... ... monistic de- see on what grounds monism denies his personality, mai of per- Monism is anxious to have a God, but it is also anxious God. ' y to make it clear that he is not a God fitted out with human at tributes and weaknesses, nor one who is " exteriorized " or re garded as personal. It opposes aU compulsory worship accorded to such outworn, untenable, puerile, and legendary dogmatic repre sentations, as well as all supposed interventions of God in nature.1 We Christians are often reproached for worshiping an absentee God. We suspect that an absentee God, if weU employed, would be prefer able to a present God of the do-nothing kind held by monism. But we beg the pardon of the reader for this descent to the plane of argumentation employed by our opponents. We rise again to the Christian level. The God of the Christian is neither an absentee nor a do-nothing; but one who is ever present and ever engaged in a manner which must be considered worthy by all who do not regard inaction as the proof of perfection. We call attention to the fact that the God of the Christian is not "exteriorized," nor fitted out with human weaknesses, and that such human attributes as we regard him as possessing are those which man has in common with God, rather than those which God has in common with man. They are attributes without which we could not think of him as God. They are attributes worthy of a God ; attributes which must forever make men attractive who think of themselves as men rather than as highly developed animals. They are such attributes as goodness, love, i Forel, Gehirn und Seele, p. 30. 142 Foundations of the Christian Faith. purity, strength, wisdom, inteUigence, truth, faithfulness. These are not human weaknesses, but constituents of whatever Godlike charac- D e f e n s e of ter men possess. That Christians have sometimes made ity r against of God a man somewhat magnified, a being with hu- o?monists.S man weaknesses, we do not deny, but confess with shame ; but we do deny that it is Christian to do so, and we shaU attempt in the proper place to portray the true Christian concep tion of God. As to compulsory worship, that too is unchristian; and the same may be said of so-caUed Christian dogma in the sense objected to by monists. Compulsory belief is no more Chris tian than compulsory worship, and from the Christian point of view neither is acceptable to God. So also it is unchristian to dogmatize in the sense of intolerant exclusion of aU from the kingdom of God who do not accept our definitions of Christian truth. But dogmatic representations, in the sense of efforts to state in aU humility of spirit some of the great truths of religion, are not unchristian, nor are they unscientific, nor objectionable to men of a true scientific temper. As to the alleged outworn, untenable, puerile, or legendary character of Christianity, we deny that it has in it, when correctly understood, anything of the kind. That it appears to some to be of the char acter described is not due to the facts, but to a misapprehension of the facts. Haeckel, with his usual brutal forcefulness and disregard of the facts, gives us in his "Confession of Faith," so called, his religious reason for opposing the personaUty of God. He says:1 "AU the multifarious forms of religious faith which ascribe to the personal God purely human attributes can be grouped under the one con- Haeckei's ob- cept of Homotheism or Anthropomorphism. However doctrine of diverse these anthropomorphic representations may be pci son a!- ity in God. in the dualistic and pluraUstic reUgions, there remains common to aU of them the unworthy conception that God is like man and is organized according to the same type. In the realm of poetry such personifications are to be both admired and per mitted. In the domain of science they are thoroughly inadmissi ble ; they are doubly reprehensible since we know that not until the Tertiary period was man developed, and then out of the pithecoid mammals. Every religious dogma which represents God as a spirit in human form degrades God to a ' Gaseous vertebrate ' (Gasfbrmigen Wirbelthier) ." The whole burden of this objection to personality in God Ues in the 1 Der Monlsmus, p. 45 f. JM.0NISTIC INEGATION OF (jOD's PERSONALITY. 143 i fact that personaUty makes God like man. In answer there are sev eral things to be said. First, we call attention to the dogmatism of Haeckel on the date and method of the origin of man. Nobody knows that man was developed in the latter part of the Tertiary period out of the pithecoid mammals. It is the most arrant dogmatism to make such an assertion. If Haeckel has not lost all power to H- distinguish between belief and knowledge he must know dogmatism. that, so far from our knowing what he says, the evidence for a scien tific belief in the aUeged fact is by no means complete. PersonaUy we do not care which way the dispute terminates. But a scientist ought not to speak as he has spoken on this subject. In this connec tion we wish to mention a related point. Evolutionists never tire of teUing us that, in the language of Darwin, man born of the animals is nobler than man born of the dust. But if the argument of Haeckel is not to be robbed of much of its force we must suppose that in his deepest soul he beUeves the pithecoid origin of man to be ignoble ; for he seems to say that in attributing human attributes to God, in mak ing him like man, we are in reality reducing him to the level of the brutes. It is by reminding us of our animal origin that he emphasizes the "unworthiness " of that conception of God which makes him Uke man. Closely interwoven with this is his idea of spirit as gaseous. It matters not that theologians have sometimes spoken of the soul as though it were material. Christianity teaches that the soul is spiritual, not material, and that God also is a spirit, and not material. Haeckel ought to take pains to learn what Christianity is, not merely what some people have thought it to be. Of the same kind is his representation of anthropomorphism as making God similar in organism to man (gleichartig— homotyp organ- iziert). Christianity does not think of God as organized at all. Can it be possible that Haeckel has taken his idea of God as organized Uke man from the nursery ? Or did he receive it from classic art ? These are the only sources whence he could have gotten , the notion. That we have not misunderstood his meaning is evident And profound ignorance of from the fact that his language is plain, and from the *f cnristiali- fact that others have expressed the same idea in stiU ity- more unequivocal terms. Nordheim, who is a firm Haeckelian in the doctrine of evolution and in respect of his rejection of the per sonaUty of God, says : "The God of the First Book of Moses (Genesis) is an old man with a long beard."1 It is a remarkable thing that a 1 Die Erfullung des Christenthums auf ;Gundlage der Entwickelungslehre, Berlin, 1894, p. 309. 144 Foundations of the Christian Faith. man who undertook to write a book designed to bring about har mony between Christianity and scientists (there never was and never will be any conflict between Christianity and science) should so grossly misunderstand the God of the Bible. The God of Genesis an old man with a long beard ! The God of Christianity organized like man I Very evident is it that men who have gotten their idea of the God of the Christians from the days of the nursery, and who have so neglected Christian teaching from that time on to mature age that they have never corrected the conceptions of those childhood days, are not fit to judge of the dignity of the human attributes alleged to be bestowed by Christians on their God. CONCLUDING CRITICISM OF MONISM. 145 CHAPTER IX. CONCLUDING CRITICISM OF MONISM. But, furthermore, Christians do not bestow human attributes upon God. Rather do they bestow divine attributes upon man. They do not anthropomorphize God, but theomorphize man. For Christianity does not teach that God is like man, but that man is like God ; it de nies that men make God and affirms that God makes men, and that he makes them in his own image. In fact, monism teaches the same thing, only its idea both of God and man is different from that of Christianity. Which is the more worthy idea is a question for each to decide for himself ; and here it is a question, not of the truth of the idea, but merely of its worthiness, raised by the monists themselves. But while Christianity teaches that man is hke God it Real doctrine does not, like monism, teach that man is God, or that and man in man is as like him as the part is Uke the whole. Chris- 'teaching. tianity teaches that man differs from God both in degree and quality. With reference to the difference of degree, Christianity asserts that it is infinite. Such a difference in degree amounts to a difference in kind— the infinite and the finite are two diverse kinds of being. But the difference in quality is not noted in the difference of degree. Love, truth, intelligence, these are of the same quality whatever their degree. In this respect there is no difference in quaUty be tween man and God. This difference shows itself only where man is characterized by qualities altogether wanting in God. For example, man has bodfly parts, God has none ; he is not an old man with a long beard. Here is one difference of quality. Another is seen in the presence in man of moral elements which Christianity denies to God, as hate, maUce, and the like. StiU another pertains to intelli- Further state- ment of tne gence, wisdom, power, and their contraries. Man is both difference. intelligent and ignorant, both wise and unwise, both strong and weak. God is neither ignorant, nor unwise, nor weak. What objection can there be to thinking of God and man as alike when their likeness consists in that which is absolutely noble, and when God is not thought of as having human qualities but man is thought of as having godlike qualities? Does this degrade God? Let 146 Foundations of the Christian Faith. us compare such a conception of God with the conception held by monists. Which is the nobler God : the intelligent or the nonintelU gent, the loving or the nonloving, the righteous or the nonrighteous (that is, the indifferent to righteousness), the favorer of moraUty in men or the one who regards good and bad in morals as alike good, the God who knows what he is about or the one who does not ? In fact, it is monism which holds to a degrading conception of God; for it teaches us that God is the producer of all things — truth and error, moral goodness and moral evil included. This leads us to the third characteristic of monistic theology, namely, its vagueness. This has been made apparent by the preced ing discussion. It may be that it is difficult to make clear an idea of God which has nothing to correspond to it in the entire range of our knowledge. What we really find fault with the monists for under this head is that they attempt to define their idea, since, according to Forel, he cannot be represented.1 Why, then, do they try to repre sent him ? Why do they not take up a consistently agnostic position ? inconsistency We have seen that Strauss identifies God and the uni- ofmonismin . ,. ,,-,¦,.¦„.. , . attempting verse. According to Forel, all original potencies (Urpo- God. tenzen) of organized life, including the potentiality of the soul, are contained in inorganic nature. This amounts to a universal, potential besouling of the world-all, which leads us back to our monistic conception of God."2 Again, "We reverence in deepest humihty the eternal, unfathomable almightiness of the omnipresent God which reveals itself in every atom of the world, the God who is at once the cause of the to us unknown world-aU and the world-all itself." s If this means anything it means that, since God is both the cause of the world-all and the world-aU itseU, God must be the cause of himself. This vagueness does not arise alone from the difficulty of defining the monistic God, but from the nature of that God. A God who is the cause of himself is of necessity vague to aU who mean anything by the law of causality. For it is evident that if God is the cause of Also its ab- himself he must have existed before himseff, since the cause is always prior to the effect. But if such a thing is absurd, why hold to it ? Christianity also beUeves that God reveals himself in every atom of the world, though it does not believe that the atoms have souls. It also believes that God is the cause of the world- all, but not that he is the world-all. There either is or there is not a distinction between God and the world. If he is the world there is no 1 Gehirn und Seele, p. 6. « Ibid., p. 26. 3 n,;,}., p, 30 1. Concluding Criticism of Monism. 147 distinction. If he is the cause of the world there is a distinction. But apparently monism holds both that there is and that there is not a distinction between God and the world, using the words in the same sense in both cases. This may not be contradictory, but it is so vague as to make it impossible of acceptance by one who demands of himself clear thought. But in fact monists themselves give up the monistic idea when they come to practical life ; and with the presentation of the proof of this statement we shall close our discussion of pantheism or Practical monism. In a note in Haeckel's "Confession of Faith" mentofmon- he discourses on the world-substance as follows:' "The ists. relation of the two primitive constituents of the Cosmos, Ether, and Mass, may possibly be made in some measure provisionally clear (anschaulich) in the foUowing comparison (according to one of the many hypotheses) : WORLD (SUBSTANCE COSMOS) NATURE AS KNOWN TO MAN. World-ether (Spirit), movable or active sub- World-mass (Body), inert or passive sub stance — Possibility of Vibration. stance — Possibility of Stability. Principal functions : Electricity, Mag- Principal functions : Gravity, Inertia, netism, Light, Warmth. Chemical Affinity. Structure: dynamic ; continuous, elastic Structure: atomistic; discontinuous, substance, not composed of atoms. inelastic substance, composed of atoms. Theosophically considered : ' Creative Theosophically considered : ' Created God ' (constantly in motion). World ' (formed in rest)." It will be seen at a glance that here is no qualitative, and hence no quantitative or numerical unity. But, more than this, the above scheme provides for a creation and a creator, a body and a spirit. The difference between it and the Christian scheme is that the mon istic idea of God as spirit and creator is identical with the world-ether, whfle Christianity makes God intelligent and personal. It is difficult to see how that homogeneous thing known to science as the ether could affect mass (matter) in the way supposed unless that thing which no sense ever perceived, and which exists only as a inadequacy of means of helping our inert, passive matter, is also intelli- of monism. gent. In any event there is duaUty instead of unity, and the dual ism of monism is not as adequate to the explanation of the facts as the dualism of Christianity. When we make an hypothesis simply for the explanation of results it ought to be made adequate to their 1 Der Monismus, p. 42. 148 Foundations of the Christian Faith. production. It is impossible to see that the hypothesis of the ether without intelligence is adequate. Another element of vagueness arises from the fact that whfle he makes the ether equal to spirit — that is, identical with spirit — he has also given to every atom a soul. We could wish to know whether this spirit is of the same kind with the soul which is in the atom, and Are this ether- whether it is also the same kind of a somewhat that we tSer atonv duahsts call spirit. As his atom-soul and his brain-soul s anie1!1!! differ so essentially from the soul of duahsm we sus- kind? peet that the spirit he here speaks of differs from the spirit posited by dualists. If so we are left entirely in the dark with reference to the nature of this spirit. It may be very clear to Haeckel, but the teacher of a new reUgion ought to be considerate of the mental unpreparedness of those to whom he addresses himself. We have a suspicion that the reason why he gave us no clearer conception of all this is that it is lacking in himself ; that, as is so often the case with him, he dogmatizes on the subject without taking the trouble to think it through. Monistic theology, as monistic psychology, is a dismal failure. JJEISM versus Eeligion. 149 SECTION IY.-DEISM. CHAPTER I. DEISM VERSUS RELIGION. In some of its aspects deism is the very antipodes of pantheism. According to the latter God and the world are identical ; according to the former they exist apart, very much as a machine exists apart from the man who made it. Deism makes God a necessity to the beginning but not to the continuance and progress of the world. It thinks of God as the Creator, but only indirectly as the Preserver of creation; as having, at the creation, bestowed upon the Deism, pan- theism, and world such forces and laws that the world's history is Christianity. their natural and necessary result. God did his work once for aU. Thenceforth he left it to itself. In some respects this system is not mimical to Christianity. It, in common with Christianity, regards God as one and personal, as well as Creator. But it is evident that in the relation which it gives God to the world lies hidden a vast realm in which it must antagonize Christianity. If God be excluded by his own act, or in any other way, from participation in the affairs of the world, then providence, prayer, revelation, sin, and redemption, in any Christian sense of these terms, fall away. The majority of readers will think of deism as a standpoint de fended and overcome chiefly in the preceding century. But deistic thought pervades much of the scientific literature of our day, and especiaUy do many theologians who attempt a reconciliation between science and Christianity rest satisfied with deistic conceptions of the relation of God to the world. For example, Andresen 1 says that for men to deny the intervention of God as cause would be the same as to assert that our sense of causaUty could be perfectly satisfied with out including in it the infinite. But whfle this appears, as it is in tended, as an argument for the doctrine that God inter- Deism in mod- venes in the affairs of the world it does in fact faU short ern oug of that. For deism admits the need of God as first cause, and that is 1 Die Entwickelung der Menschen im Lichte christlieh-rationaler Weltanschauung, Hamburg, 1892, p. 43. Compare the criticism of Andresen on this point by Steude, in his Christenthum und Naturwissenschaft, Giitersloh, 1895. 12 150 Foundations of the Christian Faith. reaUy all that Andresen here proves. But that his standpoint is un consciously that of deism is stfll more plain from the fact that he says:1 " For practical purposes it is indifferent to us just when God exerted a causal influence." If this declaration be true then deism is as satisfactory for practical purposes as theism. This Andresen by no means holds to be the case ; but nevertheless much of his argu ment is valid rather against atheism than against deism. Many of the deistic positions can be better dealt with under other heads than deism. But so far as deism has a place in modern thought it wiU be necessary to treat it here. And we begin by show ing that the deistic theory is incapable of satisfying om- religious needs. To him who denies the validity of the religious nature in man this argument wfll have but little weight. But the majority, even of scientific men, are not of the class just mentioned ; and to their thought any doctrine of God which fails to meet the demands of the reUgious nature would have to be replaced by one which an swered that purpose better. One of the most striking evidences of a deistic tendency in modern apologetic literature is that the place of miracle is denied either as Evidence of possible or as actual. Schweizer affirms that in the in- deistic tend- ency m terest of religion itself it is necessary to deny every apologetic ° J J J literature. supernatural intervention.2 Wagner in his excellent Uttle work entitled Christen glaube im Bunde mit der Naturwissen- schaft (Christian Faith in League with Natural Science) 3, touches the subject of miracles very gently, and throws doubt upon them in a most amazing manner. The whole trend of these, and scores of similar writings, is to minify or banish the miraculous from Christian faith and to reduce it to the acceptance of the purely me chanical view of the world, in which God has no part ; at least none by which he can alleviate our misfortunes or commune with our souls. The drift of all such thought is to place the world, at its very beginning, at a distance from God, and to bring him near to it only in the human spirit through the power of the idea of God.4 Now, all this directly contradicts the teaching of Jesus, and robs us of what we need in our relation to God. Of what use is it that God is per sonal if when we call on him he is unable to answer us? Even though we do not need miracles to convince us of the presence of a 1 Die Entwickelung der Menschen, p. 48. a Die Zukunft der Religion, Leipzig, 1878, p. 25. " Braunschweig, 1891. See, for example, pp. 17 f.. 48 f. « Comp. Frohschammer's Das Chrlstenthum und die moderne Wissenschaft, Vienna,. 1868, p. 307. Deism versus Eeligion. 151 divine power in the world, stiU, for answer to prayer, God must have access to the working forces of nature and abflity to direct them as he wfll. The child of God does not go in prayer to one whom he thinks unable to do for him everything needful at the moment. Efleetistod Were that the prevaihng conception of God prayer stroy prayer. would be no longer offered. For whatever the reflex benefits of prayer may be, and they are doubtless very great, if they were be heved to be the only benefits possible men would cease to pray. It is unreasonable to pray to a God who is unable, but it is reasonable to pray to a God who, though able, may often decUne to answer. Hence, to a prayerful life, the belief in God's access to and power over the forces of nature is a necessity ; and all schemes which rob him of these are not only deistic but destructive of religion in any true sense of the word. Thus deism, even when the attempt is made to couple it with ^Christian elements, is ruinous to the devotional life. But it is equally dangerous to the ethical side of religion. One of the most recent at tempts, by an anonymous author, to reconcile the Chris- Equally dan- tian faith and natural science asserts 1 that the perfection the ethical sid6 of rfili- of God consists in the fact (?) that all his later counsels gion. (volitions) are the necessary consequences of his first volition, all his later operations the inevitable results of his original creative wfll. This makes prayer answerable by provision having been made both for the prayer and the answer to prayer in the origi nal outfit of the world. The offerer of the prayer did not freely choose to pray, though he thought himself free in that act. He prayed because the time had come and the circumstances conspired which God had foreordained from the beginning of the world. And as he had planned for the prayer, which was inevitably offered in just the way and just the spirit prearranged, so the answer had been planned; or, if the petition was denied, this was planned also. In other words, God has deliberately planned to deceive us into thinking we are praying and that he can answer, and into the belief that when he answers it is because we pray, and when he dechnes our petitions it is because his wisdom discerns in it that which our minds fail to grasp. Were this generally believed prayer would cease, and so would respect for the moral character of God be at an end. But, more than this, aU real moral endeavor would be impossible. The doctrine in question is even more fatal to the ethical life than the materialistic theory. For it makes God himself a deceiver, as well 1 Der christliche Glaube und die Naturnotwendigkeit aller Dinge, Berlin, 1891, p. 27. 152 Foundations of the Christian Faith. as the author of aU our sin. That we are not drawing, from the doc trine of the book, conclusions not accepted by the author himself is evident from its utterances relative to the freedom of the wfll. "From the impossibflity of our being conscious of the natural laws which operate upon us arises for us the capacity of free choice." "The freedom of the wfll consists in the unconsciousness of its lack of freedom." " We ourselves make the laws which manifest themselves in our lives, since we make our decisions by free choice on the basis of causes which do not appear in our consciousness." ¦ That is, we are free because we do not know that we are not free. This is word- juggling and thought-juggling combined. The upshot of it is that we think we are free, but we are not ; and even our deceptive conscious ness of freedom is the result of the original creative act of God. So we are deceived and God is the deceiver. If this idea, consistently acted upon in everyday life, would not result in a cessation of all moral endeavor then no idea could possibly affect conduct. But we are taught by these modern deists that our relations to God are not ideal when we seek to have him. interfere in his works on our behalf. Frohschammer * teaches us that the true natural providence of God consists in the fact that God has given us the physical and mental power to know and to control the forces of nature for our own good ; and that when this power is not adequate man should bow in Frohscham- resignation to God's wfll as manifested in what is, and trfneSofCres- not caU upon him to change miraculously his orderly igna ion. purposes according to our desire. For not in the wish to have God adapt himself to us, but in humble acquiescence in God's wfll and the unchangeable course of his creation does real religious sentiment display itself. And Frohschammer further says that Jesus in the garden of Gethsemane performed the most truly and perfectly religious act which the history of man offers, displaying the true na ture of the religious faith and life by submitting himself, in spite of his deep sorrow, to the divine counsel and the natural course of events, without claiming the miraculous protection of God. To this Steude replies s that, while the act of Jesus was an humble acquiescence in the divine will, it was not acquiescence Steude's reply. . ^ in the natural course of events ; least of all was it resigna tion as a result of the conviction that the divine power does not affect 1 Der Christliche Glaube und die Naturnotwendigkelt aller Dinge, pp. 38, 39, 43. Comp. Steude's Christenthum und Naturwlssenschaft, p. 68 ff. 2 Das Christenthum und die moderne Naturwlssenschaft, p. 295. Comp. Steude, as above, p. 57 f. 8 Christenthum und Naturwlssenchaf t, p. 67 f . Deism versus Religion. 153 directly, but only indirectly, the welfare of man. For had this been his conviction the prayer that the cup might pass from him would be inexplicable. Accordingly the words " If it be possible, " and ' ' Thy wfll be done," do not relate to the natural unchangeable course of things ordained by God, but solely to the question whether his suffering and death were founded in the saving counsels of the Father. As Steude weU says, humility can be a truly ethical and religious act only when it is achieved and practiced in the face of the conviction that God could guide us otherwise, and that he could, if he would, miracu lously help and save us. On the contrary conviction resignation is a necessity, to refuse to submit foolishness, humflity a mere matter of the understanding — the result of mental reflection and not a religious act. In none of these ways, then, does modern deism satisfy the con ditions of true piety. 154 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. THE CHRISTIAN AND DEISTIC CONCEPTIONS OF GOD'S RELATION TO THE WORLD. It is sometimes claimed that the relation of God and world as con ceived by this modern deism is more exalted than that which is supposed by Christianity. Says Wallace, the colaborer of Darwin in establishing the theory of natural selection : ' "I beUeve that the uni verse is so constituted as to be self -regulating. ... As a matter of feeling and religion, I hold this to be a far higher conception of the Creator and the universe than that which may be called ' the con tinual interference ' hypothesis. " " The world is so constituted that by the action of general laws there is produced the greatest possible variety of surface and of climate ; and, by the action of laws equaUy gen eral, the greatest possible variety of organisms has been produced, adapted to the varied conditions of every part of the earth. The object or would probably himself admit that the varied surface of the earth Wallace on *s *ne result of general laws acting and reacting during character of countless ageS) and that the Creator does not appear to conception guide and control the action of these laws— here deter- of God. mining the height of a mountain, there altering the chan nel of a river. ... If , then, a ' contriving mind ' is not necessary at every step of the process of change eternaUy going on in the inorganic world, why are we required to beUeve in the continued action of such a mind in the region of organic nature ? . . . Why should we suppose the machine too compUcated to have been designed by the Creator so complete that it would necessarily work out harmonious results? The theory of ' continual interference ' is a limitation of the Creator's power. It assumes that he could not work by pure law in the organic as he has done in the inorganic world ; it assumes that he could not foresee the consequences of the laws of matter and mind combined. ... If we could not conceive the world of nature to be self-adjusting, and capable of endless development, it would even then be an un worthy idea of a Creator to impute the capacity of our minds to him; but, when many human minds can conceive, and even trace out in de- 1 Natural Selection and Tropical Nature; Essays ou Descriptive and Theoretical Biology, London and New York, 1891, pp. 144, 151, 152. CONCEPTIONS OF VjtOD'S ItELATION TO THE WoRLD. 155 tail, some of the adaptations in nature as the necessary results of unvarying law, it seems strange that, in the interests of religion, any one should seek to prove that the system of nature, instead of being above, is far below our highest conceptions of it." Did we ascribe to God our human incapacity it would indeed be a degradation of our conception of him. But we deny that the theory of constant intervention limits the power of the Creator, and that it involves the doctrine that he could not have controlled the world by natural law without his intervention, or that he had not the ability to foresee the results which would be worked out by the complex laws of matter and spirit. We do not assert, as WaUace in- Wallace's as- scrtions dG- timates, that such a machine as this world, on the sup- nied. position that it is capable of guiding itself, is so complicated that God could not have produced it. The assertion that God is limited is made by those who deny the possibflity of his intervention. Theists do not say, in this connection, what God could or could not have done. True to their scientific instinct, they ask simply what the facts indi cate that he does do. They leave it to scientists, so called, to specu late as to what God can and cannot do. Did deists never raise that question, theists would never discuss it; but when they deny the possibility or actuaUty of divine control of this world and interven tion in its affairs we submit the facts in proof of the contrary. Indeed, Wallace himself admits that, with reference to man, there is a class of phenomena which indicates "that a superior intelligence has guided the development of man in a definite direction and for a special purpose, just as man guides the development of many animal and vegetable forms." 1 True, he wfll not admit that this superior in teUigence is the one Supreme Intelligence whose wfll or power he con ceives to have given origin to universal forces and laws. But he dis tinctly admits throughout his entire section on The His own j^. Limits of Natural Selection as Applied to Man, covering misslons- twenty-eight pages, that these natural forces and laws are not suffi cient to account for all the facts of man's physical and moral being. Whether there is any reason for supposing that some inteUigence higher than man and lower than God, as Wallace supposes, rather than God himself, " guided thedevelopment of man in a definite direc tion and for a special purpose," we shall not discuss further than to say that the only apparent reason for such an hypothesis is to get the advantage of a needed higher intelligence without admitting that God had anything to do with the world except to start it on its way. i Natural Selection and Tropical Nature, p. 204. 156 Foundations of the Christian Faith. The question is before us in the form of the more worthy concep tion of the relation of God to the world. We assert that the theistic conception is far more worthy than the deistic. If the fact be once admitted that God created the world aU that nonsense about his abso luteness and incommunicableness, in the transcendent meaning of those terms, is at once done away with. By the hypothesis God can be God and yet be interested in something. So far, then, theists and deists would seem to agree. But once this fact is conceded, that God was interested enough in the world to create it, we can in no way ac count for his immediate loss of interest in it. Such a change in his mind is exactly what we find in the frailest of human beings, but not in the strongest. Yet to attribute it to God is supposed not to be de- Deism makes grading, while to affirm that his interest in his creation w ith°nthne is perpetual is declared to be degrading. Perhaps, how- worid. ever, it may be said that the modern deist does not deny that God is interested in his creation, but merely that he in any way touches it or affects it. He made it to suit him at first, and that is all there was to do. If there were only unintelligent beings on earth ; if it were a mere question of inorganic existence, or even of plant and animal life, this would not be so bad. But, according to deism, God made the world to suit him and it continues to suit him, man included. An exalted idea of God, surely, that man is and has been as God wants him to be ! Can it be that God is satisfied either with our sorrows or our sins ? That all this is just as he would have had it ? If so he is neither as moral nor as merciful as man. But not only must consistent deism attribute to God this self-com placent observation of human sin and misery, but idleness as weU. He is a mere spectator, with nothing to do. Surely, if it be a question of worthiness in the eyes of man, this is a much lower conception of God than that given us by Jesus Christ in those memorable and preg nant words, "My Father worketh hitherto." Idleness, and indiffer ence to the pains and sins of his creatures, are not exactly exalted qualities to attribute to God. But maybe the deist means to say that God is idle, not because he would not be active, but because he cannot, in the nature of the case, do anything for the world. Now, we ask, And gives him why can he not do anything for the world ? Did he make do. it so that he could not? If so, then we must suppose either that it exactly suited him or else that he would make it other wise if he had it to do over again. The latter supposition is the re pentant God of Genesis, and the early books of the Bible, which has caused so much horror to scientists, but which in this case they have CONCEPTIONS OF liOD'S KELATION TO THE WORLD. 157 found to be exactly their God. Christians do not believe in a God that has any need to repent of any of his acts ; though they believe that there were those who had such a conception of God, of whom we have a record in Genesis and elsewhere. But maybe he did not in- tentionaUy make it so that he could not interfere with it. Perhaps it slipped out of his grasp and he could not help himself. Any of these suppositions of the relation of God and the world are possible under deism, and one of them must be true. Whichever one is true it is a degrading idea of God. We can here give to the intrinsic merits or demerits of the deistic notion of the relation of God to the world but little space. But it is worth while to point out that any theory which fairly and honestly admits God as Creator cannot deny his continuous agency and at the same time assert the evolutionary theory of the world. If evolution is God's method of creating he is still at work. Theistic Deism and evolution is possible, but deistic evolution is a contradic- c a°p abTe'of tion in terms. Again, it is all a mere supposition that in thought! God created the world and endowed it with forces which will of necessity work out his wfll. It is impossible for us to say that God put forth energy in the beginning and then ceased. It is, to say the least, as probable that gravitation is a divine force constantly exerted on matter in a certain way as that it is a divine force deposited in matter once for all. In the former case the law or method of proce dure is as divine as the force ; and, whfle we might continue to speak of the laws of nature, we should be persuaded that in reality these are laws of God. We see, further, that the main reason why certain scientists desire to rid themselves of the idea of an immanent God is that they fear the effects of divine intervention upon science. This point we must postpone for discussion until later. But when the proper place has been reached ' we shall show that the interventions alleged by Christianity are not dangerous to science.1 Meantime it is a matter of life and death to religion whether God is able to intervene or not. 1 See division il, section ii, chap. 6. 158 Foundations of the Christian Faith. division n. SCIENTISTS AND THEOLOGIANS DM CONFLICT. SECTION I.-SCIENTIFIC AGNOSTICISM. CHAPTER I. CHRISTIANITY AND SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH. The struggle which Christianity has had with phflosophy has been in good measure carried on with those, who in some degree profess to be its friends, engaged in giving philosophic expression to its prof ounder basal tenets. The beginnings of modern science also were made by open adherents of Christianity ; and although in the recent past many great scientific names have arrayed themselves in antagonism to some or all of the fundamental doctrines of the Christian faith, from the beginning until now some of the greatest of scientists have been Christians. We do not place any reliance, by way of argument as to Vaiueiessness the merits of the question, on the attitude of scientists merit6 "om toward Christianity. Unless it were demonstrated that of6 scientific scientific thought is more exact than other thought, and men- scientific men more free from bias than other men of trained minds, the opinions of scientists as to the truth of the Christian system could be of no special value. But these things are not demon strated, though by the history of science the contradictory of them is.1 But, while it is not true either that scientific testimony to the Christian faith has any special value or that the majority of great scientists have been opposed to Christianity, the tactics of some enemies of the cause we represent compel us to call attention to the facts. That there is, among clergymen especially, a profound fear of the results of modern science there can be no doubt ; nor is this fear cen surable, notwithstanding it is really groundless. There are some men of science who are at the same time bitter antagonists of the Church, if not of Christianity. They seem to take delight in setting forth the alleged facts of science in such a way as completely to destroy reU- 1 See a brief editorial In the Methodist Review, July- August, 1897, pp. 622-624. Christianity and Scientific Research. 159 gious beUef . In so doing they conduct themselves in a manner very unbecoming those who profess to be humble and earnest searchers after the truth, and they have no right, under such circumstances, to the reputation for exactness and impartiality which the designation "scientist" usuaUy bestows. Nevertheless, but few are Tne reiation thoughtful enough to distinguish between the scientist and {j* Gentile the partisan, and to the popular mind even the rankest bought. falsehood, if uttered in the name of science, passes of necessity for truth.1 When the clergy see large portions of the community turning away from the faith given us by Jesus Christ, as a result of the teach ings of men who train professedly under the banner of science, they naturally take alarm, especially as they are thoroughly convinced of the value and necessity of Christianity to the needs of mankind. The spectacle they witness is like that of a man who throws a rope to a drowning man and sees it rejected as a means of salvation. Now, while this is right and commendable, it is absolutely necessary that the clergy should know that, wherever there is a conflict between science and theology, either the science is erroneous or the theology — or both. However protracted the dispute between scientists and the ologians may yet be, between true science and true theology there can be no conflict. It is therefore very much out of place for a Christian to oppose or fear scientific investigation, for it is the principle of Christianity to encourage freedom of thought. In fact, Christianity not only leads men to seek the exact truth but prompts them to ad here to it through all persecutions. Besides, the God of Christianity is the Creator of all things, and true science can, at Christians ° ' should not the worst, but correct our ideas concerning his methods oppose or ' ° fear scientific in creation. The thing to be feared, then, is false science research. and false theology. Nor should we, because an alleged scientific fact contradicts our theological belief , immediately conclude that it can be no real fact, but must be merely an imagined one. The trouble may be with our form of theological belief. This has happened many times in the course of Church history ; some of the darkest pages in the history of Christendom are those which record persecu tion of men for holding scientific opinions contradictory of alleged Christian doctrine.2 The case of Galileo is generally cited, but there 1 Comp. Christenglaube im Bunde mit der Naturwlssenschaft, p. 37. 8 For the long and painful history, considerably exaggerated, however, see White's His tory of the Warfare of Science with Theology in Christendom, in two volumes, New York, 1896. Minify his statements as we may and must, there is still overwhelming evi dence of the folly of ecclesiastics in their dealing with scientists. See also Zockler's Geschichte der Beziehungen zwischen Theologie und Naturwlssenschaft, Giitersloh, 1887, and Bowne's The Christian Revelation, Cincinnati and New York, 1898, p. 95. 160 Foundations of the Christian Faith. are others equaUy striking. Luther opposed the now universally accepted Copernican theory ; and in this he was supported by his co- laborer Melanchthon, by Calvin, and by divines in the English Church. ' When the theory of evolution was first announced by Darwin and his colaborers it was almost universally held by the clergy to be subver sive of the fundamentals of the Christian faith. It is, perhaps, needless to say that few well-informed theologians of to-day so regard evolution. These and similar experiences should teach us, not indeed to accept, as established, every scientific statement, but on the other hand not at once to reject it simply because it seems inimical to some dogma we cherish. It may be that the opposition of the two is apparent rather than real, or it may be that we have surrounded the dogma with accretions not essential to its full value and that the alleged scientific fact is opposed only to them. For a practical reason also we should not be in haste to condemn as unchristian, and therefore false, a sup posed scientific fact. When evolution was publicly declared to be destructive of Christian faith those who felt that evolution was true naturally turned their backs on Christianity, on the word of its official representatives. Besides, it is humiliating to have to retract our hasty condemnations, and tends to decrease the confidence of the thought ful public in our judgment ; and those who are our unrelenting antag onists point to the victories which science has won in its warfare with Christianity, thus strengthening the hold of science as exact True attitude truth on the minds of the masses and weakening ours towaerdles!£ h7 evelT battle we lose. The true attitude of the clergy to ence- science is one of friendliness. That attitude has never done us any harm ; antagonism has. But our friendliness should also be intelligently discriminating, not unduly credulous. Above all, when anything in science appears to contradict important doctrines of our faith, we should remind ourselves and others that in the past no truth of science has failed of adjustment to the truths of Christianity; and that as it has been in the past so it wfll be in the future. Perhaps it is more appropriate for us to acknowledge with all frank ness the faults of theologians in the conflict they have waged with scientists than it would be for us to point out the corresponding errors among scientists. But it will at least not be out of place for us to quote what scientific men themselves have said on this point. Forel, after administering a stern rebuke to theology, turns also upon science, and says : 3 " Proud of her results, science has often forsaken 1 White, History of the Warfare of Science with Theology vol 1 pn i>6 ff 2 Gehirn und Seele, p. 9. Christianity and Scientific Eesearch. . 161 the modest path of true philosophy. She has often forgotten that her alleged laws are not fundamental laws. . . . She has set herself in the place of God, and worshiped materialistic idols „ , c , •¦ , s , . , Scientists' (matter, force, atoms, natural laws) which are no more confession ,,,.,,.., of their own tenable than the religious dogmas which she has com- fauIts- passionately ridiculed." But a greater by far than Forel has spoken to the same effect. " Science, however, like' religion, has but very incompletely fulfiUed its office. As religion has faUen short of its function in so far as it has been irreligious, so has science fallen short of its function in so far as it has been unscientific. ... In its earlier stages science, whfle it began to teach the constant relations of phe nomena, and so discredited the belief in separate personalities as the causes of them, itself substituted the belief in causal agencies which, if not personal, were yet concrete. When certain facts were said to show ' Nature's abhorrence of a vacuum,' when the properties of gold were explained as due to some entity caUed ' aureity,' and when the phenomena of life were attributed to a ' vital principle ' there was set up a mode of interpreting the facts which, while antagonistic to the religious mode, because assigning other agencies, was also un scientific, because it professed to know that about which nothing was known. Having abandoned these metaphysical agencies — having seen that they were not independent existences but merely special combinations of general causes — science has more recently ascribed extensive groups of phenomena to electricity, chemical language of affinity, and other like general powers. But in speaking Mr- sPencer' of these as ultimate and independent entities science has preserved substantially the same attitude as before. Accounting thus for all phenomena, those of life and thought included, it has not only main tained its seeming antagonism to religion by alleging agencies of a radically unlike kind, but in so far as it has tacitly assumed a knowl edge of these agencies it has continued unscientific. ... In each phase of its progress science has thus stopped short with superficial solutions— has unscientifically neglected to ask what was the nature of the agents it so familiarly invoked. . . . And this, which has all along been the unscientific characteristic of science, has aU along been a part cause of its conflict with religion. " ' ' Each (science and religion) has been obliged gradually to relinquish that territory which it wrongly claimed, whfle it gained from the other that to which it had a right. ... A permanent peace will be reached when science becomes fully convinced that its explanations are proximate and relative." ' 1 Spencer, First Principles, pp. 104-107. 162 Foundations of the Christian Faith. The high position of Mr. Spencer in the world of science makes these words doubly weighty. And it is to be wished that men who affect a standing among scientists would always be mindful of them. That the religious impulse and the impulse to search creation through and through, both of them ineradicable, should lead to conflict between the special representatives of the two is due solely to the obstinacy which springs from human pride of opinion. To the Christian it is perfectly evident that there should not be conflict but cooperation. Let us as Christians be so well informed that we can distinguish what is established from what is mere hypothesis, so loyal to truth that we shall welcome it from whatever source it comes, and so completely master of the situation that we can prove, to all honest inquirers whom we meet, the truth of Christianity side by side with all truth of science ; while we are so magnanimous that whenever we hear our scientific brethren telling us that our statement of dogma is wrong, from their point of view, we shaU give their words a fair and impartial consideration. Science does not, like philosophy, set up systems of thought in rivalry of Christianity. Its most determined antagonism is rather incidental than purposed or systematic. This fact will make nec essary a departure from the method of procedure employed in dis cussing the relations between phflosophy and Christianity. We shall not have to do with scientific systems which we must attempt to over throw, but with objections which science brings against Christianity. The conflict thus engendered may be considered under three general heads, which bear upon the methods and objects of theological knowl edge and upon theological theories of the relation of God to creation and providence. Method of Acquiring Theological Knowledge. 163^ CHAPTER II. THE METHOD OF ACQUIRING THEOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE. Before we can estimate correctly the weight of the objections which scientists make to the methods by which theologians profess to acquire theological knowledge a basis of comparison between the methods of science and of theology must be sought. Such a basis is to be found in the respective natures of the two departments of learn ing. At the very outset we are met with questions as to what we mean by science, what it includes, and whether there is anything to which the methods of science are not applicable. Haeckel denies that there is any distinction between the scientific study of matter and the scientific study of mind. ! This is a consistent conclusion from his form of monistic faith, and means much more than at first sight appears. For it will be remembered that he regards the problems of life and mind as simply a special form of the problem of matter and force ; hence the true method of studying mind is to study matter and force. So his monism leads him, of course, to identify the Haeckel's doc- study of theology with the study of substance. In reality scfe n c e' Is his idea of science is, then, the investigation of matter and Physical- force. But he thereby excludes, as having no place in the realm of investigation, every form of psychology except the physiological, and every form of theology except the monistic. In other words, psychology and theology in the Christian sense are ruled out. But this doctrine that there is but one science, that which has to do with matter and force, is a most narrow and partial view of things. Before we take up that point, however, we wish to point out that ac cording to Haeckel himself monism is not demonstrable, but an a? tide of faith.2 However probable monism might appear, therefore, to any mind, it would be unsafe to assume the truth of the doctrine under discussion. But what shall we say of history ? Is it, too, to be regarded as the study of matter and force ? There are The stll(Jy of indeed those who hold to a philosophy of history which tntSJ his would favor that conclusion. But nobody studies history ™w" by studying matter and force exclusively. For purposes of history 1 Der Monismus, p. 10. ' Ibid., pp. 9, 37. See also Romanes's Mind and Motion, and Monism, p. 118. 164 Foundations of the Christian Faith. psychology must be studied in the light of free wfll and the reaUty of the soul. And in fact, so far as monism is a theology, this too must be considered as philosophy rather than science. We may, then, dismiss Haeckel's denial of the distinction between sciences. There is at least a science of mind, as seen in psychology and history, as weU as a science of matter and force. The latter is generally known as science, or natural science, including its various branches of physics, chemistry, biology, and the rest, while the other sciences are known by their specific names. But this does not prove that they are not sciences ; and in this' way it is seen that theology in the Christian sense may be as truly a science as any other branch of learning, though it is generally designated by its specific name. Any sober definition of natural science wfll agree with Du Bois-Reymond, Alexander von Humboldt, Kant, Lotze, Fechner, Liebmann, and oth ers, in limiting it to the physical world,1 thus leaving room for the sciences of psychology, history, and theology. Even on the suppo sition of the truth of monism the last three sciences have to do with Diverse phe- one c^ass °^ attributes, or phenomena, of the one substance maud3, aT an<* natural science with another. The subject-matter, odsof inves- then, of natural science and of theology differs, and the tigation. former should, as a consequence, not find fault with the methods by which the latter arrives at conclusions. Natural sci ence deals with the changes which take place in the physical world;" theology deals primarily with God and the human soul. If this were the whole account of the matter there could be no con flict ; but whfle science looks at the world from one standpoint theol ogy is obliged to look at it from another. Theology does not meddle with science when it declares that God is, and that he made and up holds the world ; nor even when it declares that he intervenes in its affairs. For theology must attempt to define, though it may not be able to explain, the relation of God to the world. All theology, mon istic as well as dualistic, does this. Science, however, does meddle with theology whenever it undertakes to say that there is no God, or, Conflict be- admitting his existence, attempts to define his relation to tweeu the- ology an d the world. That is a task which lies entirely outside the scientists un~ necessary. sphere of science. Now, it is evident that there are two ways of viewing the world : the scientific, which knows, and in the nature of the case can know, nothing about God's relation to creation, and the religious, which asserts such a relation. And it is perfectly 1 Comp. Steude's Christenthum und Naturwlssenschaft, pp. 89 ff. * Du Bois-Reymond, Vortrage, p. 35 f. i-VJ.Ji.inuu UK' ACQUIRING J.HE0L0GICAL KNOWLEDGE. 165 evident, also, that while, as Romanes says,1 " A reUgious explanation of any natural phenomenon is, from the scientific point of view, no explanation at all," it is equally true that a scientific explanation of any natural phenomenon is, from the religious point of view, no ex planation at all. Yet if both of these views are kept unmixed with anything belonging to the other it is impossible there should be any conflict.2 In so far, then, as science and theology occupy diverse realms, or look at the same objects from a different point of view, it is natural to expect that their methods of attaining certainty should differ also. It by no means follows that, because the methods employed by science in the investigation of matter and force afford certainty, these same methods must be pursued in realms apart from matter, and that otherwise certainty cannot be attained. The existence of an invisible spiritual entity cannot be demonstrated by the methods of physical science ; but that does not say there is no method by which such enti ties can be demonstrated. To him who refuses the use of DiVerse meth- methods and powers of observation other than those of °quaiiayvld- the physical sciences there must always be doubt con- uaWe- cerning the existence of anything other than the physical world ; just as men who fail to utilize the faculties and methods necessary to be employed in the study of nature cannot discern what the trained stu dent of nature discerns. But as the scientist in the use of the appro priate methods and faculties becomes ever more certain of his ground, so does the Christian theologian.3 The divergence between the two realms renders it unbecoming in either to dispute the findings of the other. If either encroach upon the domains of the other there is likely to be a conflict, but it wfll not be between scientists and theologians, as such, but between those who, for the time, pose for what they are not. In this respect both scientists and theologians have been guilty. But it would be a mistake to suppose that the methods of theolog ical investigation are wholly diverse from those of natural science. There is, indeed, in this respect, much in the history of theology of which we have reason to be ashamed. Other dogmas have been de duced from accepted dogmas and contended for as though they were as sure as revelation. Such instances are to be found frequently in the records of both the Roman Catholic and the Protestant Churches, 1 Thoughts on Religion, p. 40. s Spencer has an excellent paragraph which should be heeded both by scientists and theologians.— First Principles, p. 21. 3 Comp. W. Schmidt's Christliche Dogmatik, Bonn, 1895. Erster Theil, p. 31. 13 166 Foundations of the Christian jaith. though the cases are less numerous in the latter than in the former. Wrong meth- An iUustration within Romanism is the doctrine of the ods some- . „. ,, ,.,.. . _, .,, . times em- immaculate conception of the virgin Mary: withm the ployed by theologians. Protestant Church we mention the doctrine of the ultra- Lutheran Flacius, that sin is the very essence of fallen human nature.1 Another false method of attaining certainty in theology is that of ac cepting as true the definitions of doctrine promulgated by Church councils, whether they appear true or not, on the basis of the general doctrine that the council cannot err. This, of course, does not prevail in Protestantism, though there is sometimes a submission to authority even there, in the absence of personal conviction, which is quite simi lar to Roman Catholic procedure. Still another false method has been that of insistence upon a given interpretation of the Christian Scrip tures as the only true one. This was done when there had been no at tempt at securing a correct text and without any appeal to the facts of observation, even in cases when these were easily accessible. These are a few of the false methods which theology has employed in securing its conclusions. Many pages might be filled with descrip tions of similarly careless processes. And we do not wonder that sci entists who were conscientious in scrutinizing every phenomenon of nature felt that in comparison theologians were exceedingly credulous. Nor can we plead that scientists were as dereUct in this regard as the ologians ; for theology is far older than modern science, which did not hesitate to reject the science of earher days, while, until very recent times, theology has failed to make similar progress. The only excuses that theologians can offer, and within certain limits they are valid, are that the sacred character of their faith, so different from purely scientific beliefs, led them to extreme conservatism, and that it is dan gerous to break hastily away from doctrines so intimately interwoven with the ethical life of the people. But we repeat that to-day theology is very rapidly becoming mod ernized in its methods, and that its best representatives proceed with as much critical care and breadth of learning as scientists employ. When one considers that theologians are expected to be not only schol ars, but conservators of the moral vigor of the people also, it cannot be denied that progress is fully as swift as ought to be expected. Those who criticise our methods to-day are probably not aware of the variety of tests to which all theological conclusions are subjected by the most 1 Comp. A History of Christian Doctrine, by H. C. Sheldon, Professor in Boston Uni versity, New York, 1886, vol. il, pp. 57, 120. Also M611er's Lehrbuch der Kirchen- schichte, Freiburg 1. B., and Leipzig, 1894, vol. iii, p. 257 f, and Gieseler's A Text-book of Church History, Translated by H. B. Smith, New York, 1862, vol. iv, p. 455. Method of Acquiring Theological Knowledge. 167 thoughtful students before being announced to the world. In the study of the Bible the greatest learning is applied in the effort to se cure the nearest approach to the true and original text. The most diligent research is made into the date, authorship, motives, or objects of the books of the Bible. The history of the canon is made the object of investigation of the most painstaking kind. AU the results of these studies are applied in the interpretation of the Scripture, with a knowledge of the sacred and cognate languages, of the history con temporary with the times of the writers, of the manners and customs of ancient peoples, and, in short, of everything which can Exactness of throw light on the meaning of the written word. Biblical "fog? cai theology employs the results of this critical interpretative methods- care to discover the peculiar contents of each book, or of a group of books by the same author, and of the Old as distinguished from, and then as combined with, the New Testament. Notice is taken of the upward progress of the contents of revelation, the nature of which, as well as of inspiration, is discriminatingly studied, not in the light of dogma, but of the Bible itself. Not all have the same skiU in the ap plication of these methods to Bible study, and no theologian perfectly applies them ; but the ideal is ever before us, and perhaps we succeed as weU in our department as any other class of investigators does in theirs. Nor do theologians confine their researches to the Bible. After they have discovered the real significance of the history and the doctrine of their own sacred books they study, for purposes of com parison, the sacred books of other religions. And it can be truthfully said that the teachings of other religions are estimated with judicial temper side by side with those of Christianity. Furthermore, the Scripture portrayals of human nature are compared with the phenom ena of individual psychology and with history, that storehouse of facts relative to the psychology of the human race. Christian ex perience is studied with scientific care— its states compared with those found apart from loyal devotion to Christ in the same individual at successive periods of time, every safeguard being employed to make sure that the experiences described are real, so that the results may be properly estimated. 168 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. BELIEF IN MIRACLE AS EVIDENCE OF A WRONG METHOD. Some scientists find fault with the methods of theology because of its conclusions. They tell us that as long as we believe in the possi bility or actuaUty of divine intervention in the affairs of the world our methods must be wrong. Such scientists need to be reminded that only as they cease to be scientists can they affirm or deny any thing concerning divine intervention. If science is rightly denned as Scientists the study of changes wrought in the material world by the° rate eof material forces, then, of course, science can see no divine philosophy, intervention. And in this sense of the word no one can deny the legitimacy of science. But when scientists undertake to say that there is nothing which effects changes but material forces they at once become unscientific. This is a matter which lies rather in the realm of philosophy or theology than of science. 1 And when they speak as philosophers or theologians scientists must ex pect to find philosophers and theologians asserting their rights by the methods of philosophy and theology. Unless one is ready to deny the existence of God and his creation of the world it is impossi ble to say that God does not intervene at every moment. As Andre sen says,2 there is no characteristic, essential difference between law and intervention, but the difference Ues in the point of time in which God acts. Since we do not know the laws of God in aU the minutiae of their deep-lying operations we cannot teU whether the cause of an event lies far back in the past or in the immediate past. The former we call causality, the latter intervention. Both are, by hypothesis, God's acts. All the scientist need ask is that, if God intervenes, he shall not contradict his own laws. Says Dahl : 3 " The investigator of nature as such dare not acknowledge miracle. He cannot rest satis fied, when he fails to find the natural cause of an event, with the thought that a miracle has taken place. He must, in fact, strive to wholly eliminate miracle. . . . But it would be an extremely ven- 1 On the relations of philosophy to science see Wundt's Ueberdle Aufgabe der Philoso- phie in der Gegenwart, Leipzig, 1874, p. 9 ; also Kaftan's Das Christenthum und die Phi losophic, Leipzig, 1896, p. 8. a Die Entwlekelung der Menschen, p. 47. 3 Die Nothwendigkeit der Religion, p. 106 f. Belief in Miracle as Evidence of Wrong Method. 169 turesome conclusion to draw, from the universal activity of natural law, that no miracle whatever can take place. What scientist can prove that the world is not created by an Almighty God ? And if it is created the creator can intervene in the regular course of his own creation. . . . But not only are miracles possible, we cannot even know that miracles do not occur daily in our presence. When we see any event we rightly seek to trace it to its causes. We seek and find an explanation. Often we hit the right one ; and often we find later that we are deceived, and that the causes were other than we at first supposed. ... It often occurs that we cannot find the causes even by the most diligent search. We assume in such cases, and with perfect right, that this is owing to our imperfect knowledge of natural law. But who will assure us with certainty that it was not a miracle ? I think that what has been said will suffice to show that the assertion, 'There are and there can be no miracles,' is as hazard ous as that hundreds of miracles occur daily in our immediate presence." Though this is the reasoning of a scientist we do not regard it as altogether satisfactory, for analogy would teach us to suppose that, as most events can be traced to natural causes, aU of them could be did we know nature with sufficient intimacy. StiU, so much remains true that we cannot positively and with absolute assurance of certainty deny either the possibility or actuality of miracles. Hence, if the theologian, after careful sifting of the evidence, still thinks that miracles have occurred, the scientist ought not to find fault with his methods on the mere ground of a supposed erroneous conclusion. The only way to attack the methods in that case would be to show that they were based on some faUacy in argument or investigation. The whole difficulty here seems to lie in the fact that the scientist forgets the widely diverse but not mutuaUy destructive character of the scientific and the religious explanation of an event. The truth probably is that neither explanation is complete, but that both combined give all the facts.1 This question of the validity of theological method is of such funda mental importance that we venture to add a quotation from Pro fessor Bowne's Metaphysics,3 which, though written from the stand point of philosophy, is with sUght modification capable of being applied to the subject in hand. "What, then, is our method? It is plain that every philosophical inquiry assumes a certain trust of 1 Comp. Paulsen's Einleitung in die Philosphie, pp. 244, 247. 2 Metaphysics, pp. 18 ff ., revised edition, pp. 5, 6. 170 Foundations of the Christian j?aith. reason in itself. This is a universal fact of mind, and hence a fact Professor of the system of which we form a part. This self-con- ^ owne quo fidence of reason is not to be groundlessly distrusted, both because such distrust would be irrational and because it would forestall all investigation. In discussing our theory of things we pro pose, therefore, to take everything as it seems to be, and to make only such changes as are necessary to bring our views into harmony with themselves. . . . Such a method does no violence to the natural sense of probability, which can never be needlessly violated with im punity. Such a method, too, allows reason its full rights. It is an act of faith, not of skepticism ; for it makes no changes unless reason calls for them. If we distinguish between appearance and reaUty it is because reason can be harmonized with itseU in no other way. . . . Our only assumption is a provisional trust in reason ; but we by no means assume that inquiry wfll leave our general views unchanged. Nor is our problem any more speculative than are the theoretical problems of physical science, while the method is the same in both cases. Physics, going out from phenomena, asks how we must conceive of the unseen agent, or agents, which produced them. Ac cordingly it posits atoms, ethers, etc., of various kinds and powers. Indeed, theoretical physics is metaphysics, as far as it goes. And the physicist carries himself beyond the phenomena by the sole force of reason. He has no other criterion of truth in this unseen realm than the mind itself. He enters it only by thought, and thought is the only warrant for its existence. We go to work in the same way and appeal to the same standard. We use, therefore, no new method and appeal to no occult authority. . . . Neither science nor philosophy denies anything which the senses give, though both find reason for denying that the senses give as much as uncritical thought assumes. Both make the data of senses their starting point, and on them build up a rational system. But this system is never a matter of the senses, but an inference from their data. Both physics and metaphysics carry us at once into a world of realities whose existence can be assured only by thought. The conclusions of physics concern ing the true nature of things are most startUng, and at first sight seem to outrage aU reason. These theories, which seem so monstrous when tested by the senses, are not to be tested by the senses, but solely by reason. They deny nothing which the senses can give, but are inferred from the data of the senses. Our trust in them, therefore, depends only upon our trust in reason itself, and on the cogency with which they are inferred from the data. . . . The visible heavens J5ELIEF IN 1V1IRACLE AS iiVIDENCE OF WRONG METHOD. 171 are the heavens as they appear to the eye ; the astronomical heavens are the heavens as they appear to the reason. . . . As it is no objec tion to physics and astronomy that the atoms and the ether cannot be seen, or that the heavens seem to contradict Copernicus, so it is no objection to phflosophy that its theories cannot be verified by the senses. They are never matters of eyesight, but of insight." The only additional remark needful is that we do not admit the universal, nor even the general, use of the strictly scientific method by scientists. As we have before pointed out, scientists often claim for their speculations the protection of their own scientific reputa tions. It is unscientific to attempt to make the facts bend to a the ory, as some try to do with facts refractory to theories of science. It is equally unscientific to ignore these refractory facts TT . .... u n S C 1 6 H X 1 1 1 c and yet claim certainty for the theory. Such facts can, procedure ^ *" 'of some sci- at most, be left on one side until further investigations entists. can be made ; and should they exist in any considerable number they must inevitably suggest that the theory needs emendation, if it is not wholly false. Still more objectionable is it to assume that matters otherwise inaccessible may be determined by a theory, as, for ex ample, the existence of an extinct race through which man passed on his way from the pithecoid to his present state. Science stops where the facts of observation stop. Its only business is to interpret these facts into theories consistent with them. Anything further is not science, but speculation, often of the most dogmatic kind. Sober- minded scientists protest against such procedures on the part of their more venturesome brethren.1 But as long as scientists dogmatize and still set themselves up as examples of propriety in method they should not complain of speculative and dogmatic theologians who foUow in their footsteps. 1 Comp., for example, Semper's Der Haeckelismus in der Zoologie, pp. 25-33, and the notes on pp. 34-36, in which Semper quotes also a protest from His. 172 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. the objects of theological knowledge. The criticism of scientists against theology in this respect is inti mately connected with that just discussed. As the methods of the ology are declared to be inadequate, so the objects of theological knowledge are affirmed to be uncertain, and belief in them is branded as superstition. The underlying assumption in such criti cism is that there is nothing but matter and material force. The f oUy of such an assumption is evident upon a moment's reflection; for, even though it were true, scientific research cannot for a moment claim to have established its truth. It is unfortunate that so many scientists should be so proud of their achievements as to forget at False assump- times the apparently inexhaustible stores of surprises held tain scien- °y the world with which to reward human research. The scientist, so far from thinking for a single instant that he has exhausted the knowledge of nature, ought to be surprised at noth ing that may appear. That student of nature who was most skilled in the secrets of the world two centuries ago might just as well have supposed he had exhausted all knowledge of reaUty ; yet what mar velous discoveries have been made since then. In fact, the dreams of alchemy, ridiculed some time since by science, bid fair to be realized in a time when diamonds can be produced by artificial means. And while it is not to be expected that scientific research into the nature of matter wfll ever bring to light the existence of God, yet the modesty proper to science forbids it to say there is no God. But some of those scientists who assert the existence of God talk about the superstitions of Christian theology. The monist wfll posit a soul in every atom and in every living cell, and in the world-all, and he will ' ' bow in deepest humility " to this world soul ; yet he will point the finger of scorn at the Christian, whose belief makes not half so great a draught on credulity. True, the monist says that by soul he means a function of matter, and not an independent reality; and this he thinks guards him against the accusation of superstition. But, as we have seen, the firmest monists do not claim that their behef is more than belief. We ask, therefore, which is the more superstitious act, to " bow in deepest humility " before what we know— or at least 1'he Objects of Theological Knowledge. 173 believe — to be a mere unintelligent function, or to bow before what is believed to be an inteUigent being? But perhaps it will Monism and be said that the superstition consists just in this very [ty raV super- belief of such an intelligent being. Let us remind the stltlon- monist again that his belief is but a belief, even though he may claim that it is a more rational belief than belief in a personal God. At the most it is belief against belief. We insist that it is more superstitious to feel reverence toward an unintelligent thing than toward a personal being. Did the monist openly declare himself a materialist he could be excused from the accusation of superstition ; but the religious mon ist is as superstitious as the Hottentot who worships a fetich. It ill becomes any class of scientists, therefore, to raise the cry of supersti tion against Christians. Aside from this ad hominem argument in justification of Christian beliefs we wish to caU attention to a fact often overlooked by both scientists and theologians. It is that, as far as the objects of his sup posed knowledge are concerned, the theologian is in no worse case than the scientist. The former assumes the existence of spirit, the. latter of matter ; both with good reason. Men of about equal mental caliber and reflective power have assumed or denied one or the other. The scientist ignores the doubt and proceeds with his investigations as though matter were an unquestioned reality. ShaU he blame the theo logian for proceeding in a similar manner? Both act on Assiimptions the discoverable laws, one of matter, the other of spirit, fyttvs°&£& and each in his own realm gets invariable results under sclentlsts- like conditions. Both are equally sure that back of the phenomena there is entity. Yet the scientist cannot explain the ultimate nature of matter nor the theologian of spirit. Both find limits to their in sight and knowledge, and so far as we can see they are alike in bad case— 0r, if it be preferred, each has advantages and disadvantages about equal to the other. This point demands further amplification. The situation is often so represented as to leave the impression that science is a system of facts while theology is a system of speculations.1 We think no candid theo logian who knows the facts can deny that theology has speculated un necessarily. But, just so, no candid and well-informed scientist can deny that many of the conclusions of science are the result of specula tion. Perhaps theology, which, like philosophy, deals much with the unseen, should be excused even if it speculates unduly ; for scientists, though it is not their proper function, cannot resist the temptation to 1 So Buckle, History of Civilization in England, New York, 1864, vol. ii, pp. 453, 458 ff. 174 Foundations of the Christian Faith. speculate the instant they come to the boundaries of the sensuously perceptible. But if both science and theology speculate both also have their facts. Sometimes there is a dispute between theologians and scientists as to the ownership of these facts. Many things in na ture are available for use as indicative of a guiding inteUigence. The theologian does not hesitate to employ them. On the other hand the Dispute be- scientist often claims the whole realm of being and event, ioVg1anstaend in, the physical world and in history, for his own. If ?oeowuer- some scientists had their way they would exclude aU in- ship of facts. vestigators who do not follow with them. But even though the theologian may admit the right of the scientist to attempt the explanation of such facts as the religious sentiment, conscience, the universal belief in God, the existence of sacred books, especially of the Jewish and Christian Scriptures, Jesus Christ and the religion he founded, and Christian experience, he still insists that these are his own facts and that it is his peculiar duty to explain them. And he not only holds that he can explain them more reasonably than can the scientist, but also that where science fails of an explanation of the facts of the natural world theology can lend it some useful hints. It is to be hoped that the time will come when speculation shaU be re duced to a minimum both in theology and science, but it is very sure that at present both have facts and both speculate on them. Closely related to this is another fact. It is often assumed that science is sure of its objects while religion has to take its objects on faith. This may mean several things. So far as it means that science is sure of matter and religion not sure of spirit, it is a false assumption, for both have a degree of certainty concerning them. Perhaps what is really meant is that the propositions of science are demonstrated, Faith em- while those of theology are merely assumed. If this defi- in science nite form of putting the supposed advantage of science oiogy. over theology be taken up for discussion it must be met with an unequivocal denial. That Christians believe in many things they cannot demonstrate is freely admitted; but that these beliefs are mere assumptions is very seldom true, even of the most recondite dogmas. That they appear so to some people only proves that those people have not studied with unprejudiced minds the arguments by which dogmas are upheld, or else that they lack the power to appreciate a certain class of facts. Christian dogmas always have some foundation in fact, though in the history of theology many such dogmas have been very poorly supported. As theology progresses the inadequately supported doctrines are given up. But precisely the The Objects of Theological Knowledge. 175 same thing is going on, and has gone on, in the history of scientific progress ; scarcely more nor less so than in theology. So that here, too, theology appears to as good advantage as science. Why, then, it may be asked, is the impression so general that faith occupies so much the larger place in religion than in science ? We answer, it is the result of nomenclature rather than of fact. Religion speaks of faith, science of knowledge. But science has no more knowledge than religion. In other words, science is a system of faith in every sense in which religion is such. This may appear to be a radical statement, but we assure the reader that it is made in all calmness and that it is capable of abundant illustration. In order that the truth of what we have just asserted may appear let us compare science and religion in their two aspects of practice and theory. Beginning with Christian faith, in the sense of trust in a personal God, or in the efficacy of certain practices, we find that science, in its appUcations t» practical Ufe, offers an almost perfect paraUel. Faith in God as a person of the kind described in the New Testament is always followed by certain definite results affecting parallel be- the happiness of the human mind, the soul's attitude tm^andthe- toward questions of conscience, and the corresponding practical conduct. Careful observation has revealed the fact that procedure. just in proportion as faith in God as revealed by Jesus Christ is un mixed with uncertainty— clear in its comprehension of his nature and firm in its reliance upon him— are the above results weU marked. In other words, faith in this sense, of confidence in a person, always pro duces the desired results, and they cannot be attained when this faith is lacking. This would be admitted even by atheists, though they would affirm that the results of the atheistic faith are as good, or bet ter, though not identical. Now, the same thing is true with reference to the practices of Christianity. The one who performs them expe riences certain well-defined consequences which those do not expe rience who neglect them. Such practices are the studious and devout reading of the Bible, prayer, association for religious purposes with earnest Christians, and the like. These, if performed in the spirit of Christianity— that is, according to the known laws of Christian pro cedure—never fail of their effects. The conscience is enUghtened, the purpose to live unselfishly and helpfuUy is strengthened, and the whole deportment becomes distinguished by a rare combination of cheerfulness, patience, loving-kindness, and moral strength. There may be those who wiU underrate these results as compared with practical science, but no one can deny that for practical purposes 176 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the scientist must proceed in the same way as the Christian. He must trust the powers of nature and their regularity ; he must use the appointed means for accomplishing the desired ends. If he does aU this he gets the results he seeks ; if he fails to do so the results are not obtained. It may be said that the analogy fails because in trusting The parallel in God we take his existence on assumption merely, the"6 """ while in trusting the powers of nature, and their regular action, we act on what we know. But this is a faUacy. We know the powers of nature by their results, and in no other way. And we beUeve in their regular action because they have never disappointed us. Precisely so is it with the Christian's faith in God. Perhaps, however, some one may say that all the results of Christian faith can be explained without the supposition of a God. But this is, at least, undemonstrable ; while the natural scientist, unless he be an atheist, would not assert it. In its proper place we shaU show that it would be as unscientific to deny that these are results of the divine aid as to assert that events in the physical world are not controUed or affected by the action of physical forces.1 But the paraUel does not end here. In the matter of the acceptance of propositions which are unproved, or perhaps incapable of proof, science as much goes on faith as does theology. The popular under standing of the situation is the contrary of this ; but aU capable scien tists know that it is true, and do not hesitate, on occasion, to ac knowledge it. We have had previous occasion to refer to one of the most recent representatives of a purely scientific view of the world, so purely scientific as to be atheistic ; one who denies, in other words, the validity of the religious view altogether. But hi order not to Strecker on break the connection we cite the passage in full: "In t l'ciVs0 olf order to attain a complete system of opinions materiaUsm 1 also finds itself compeUed to fiU out the numerous gaps in the knowledge gained by internal and external experience with articles of faith (Glaubenssatze) which it cannot establish, which therefore wfll be contested by our opponents, and which by no means answer the purpose of explaining the difficulties and problems which present themselves to us in considering the world. . . . The ma terialistic view, then, does not at all rest, as its overzealous adherents sometimes assert, in all respects on the basis of established fact, but must, like all positive views of the world, give faith a large place. Materialism believes in the objective validity of time and space; it believes in atoms ; it relies upon the unchangeable operation of the 1 See division viii, section viii, chap. 2. The Objects of Theological Knowledge. 177 law of causation. MateriaUsm starts from the knowledge gained by experience ; its point of view is the law of causation as deduced from experience; and with the validity of this law it stands or faUs." 1 Before going further it should be noticed that a purely scientific view of the world must " give faith a large place," since it does not always rest on the basis of established facts. But Strecker is by no means the only nor the best known representative of an exclusively scientific view who confesses the place of faith in science. Huxley declares that the great act of faith which every man must perform is to believe that the powers of nature wiU continue to operate in the future as they have operated in the past.2 And Haeckel Also Huxley ,,,.,,,„ ' and Haeck- the self-appomted prophet of the exclusively scientific el- view of the world, in the already oft-quoted because for our purpose important work, says : b " The gaps which the empirical investigation of nature must leave open in the temple of science we can fill up with hypotheses, with more or less probable suppositions. These we can not at present positively prove, although we may be allowed to em ploy them in the explanation of phenomena so far as they do not con tradict a reasoned * knowledge of nature. Such reasoned hypotheses are scientific articles of faith. ... A reasoned hypothesis of fun damental significance is, for example, faith in the unity of matter (the composition of the elements out of original atoms), faith in the origin of the first life from nonUving substance (Urzeugung),6 faith in the unity, in principle, of all natural phenomena." On the same page he says that he regards this last article, faith in the unity in principle and in the genetic connection of organic and inorganic nature, as one of the fundamental doctrines of monism. That is, one of the fundamental articles of monism is not a proved fact but an hypothesis, an article of faith. Again, on pages 39 ff. of the same work, he says : "The law of conservation of substance belongs also, taken strictly, to the articles of faith of natural science." Yet he immediately sets it up as section 1 of the monistic religion. He then proceeds to say that the present day physicists universaUy, and with 1 Strecker, Welt und Menschheit, p. 13 f. 3 " It is quite true that the ground of every one of our actions, and the validity of all our reasonings, rests upon the great act of faith which leads us to take the experience of the past as a safe guide in our dealings with the present and future."— Essays Upon Some Controverted Questions, p. 280. 3 Der Monismus, p. 37. 4 Perhaps some would prefer to translate "reasonable " (vernunftige). 1 The word Urzeugung is difficult to render in English so as to convey the exact Idea of Haeckel. We append a translation of a part of the definition given in Brockhaus' Konversations Lexikon: "Urzeugung or Abiogenesis, the origin without parents, of organic beings from inorganic matter (Stoff)." 178 Foundations of the Christian Faith. right, regard the law of the conservation of energy as the indestructi ble basis of their scientific knowledge of nature, just as chemists hold to the doctrine of the conservation of matter ; but that skeptical phflosophers could raise serious difficulties with these individual laws just as they can with the union of the two in his law of the conserva tion of substance. Perhaps we shall not need further evidence, drawn from the statements of scientists themselves, that science does, in deed, give large space to faith. Yet we add the testimony of Buchner in his Introduction to Strecker's work as above mentioned. He says : l "He (Strecker) emphasizes with perfect justice the undoubted right of the searcher after truth to bridge over the gaps in our knowledge, which perhaps science can never fill, with hypotheses or articles of faith." We think none the less of science because it is obliged to beUeve where it cannot see ; and it is a great wrong to scientists to censure them for making any hypothesis necessary for the explanation of the phenomena of matter and force. But it is an equaUy great wrong to theologians to condemn them for making hypotheses suita ble to the explanation of the facts of the religious life, or to demand that theology should abdicate in favor of physical science.2 1 Welt und Menschheit, p. x. aComp. G. F. Wright, The Logic of Christian Evidences, Andover, 1880, pp. 7-U. -articles of Faith in Theology and Science. 179 CHAPTER V. ARTICLES OF FAITH IN THEOLOGY AND SCIENCE. Perhaps it wiU occur to some one to say that while both science and theology have their articles of faith the former are well founded, the latter fll founded. Haeckel makes this assertion in its strongest possible form, affirming that Church creeds or religious dogmas are either pure fictions (without any empirical proof) or un- Haeckel's reasonable (contrary to the law of causation).1 He gives against 're" no examples and makes no exceptions. That is, these mas. g" creeds are without any facts in their support or, worse than that, contrary to the law of causation. We sincerely regret that he did not give us at least one example of each kind. However, he gives us a hint of what he means in a remark on the same page. " Since both the simple processes of inorganic nature and the more complex phenomena, of organic Ufe are traceable to the same forces of nature ; and since, further, these (the forces of nature) have their common ground in a single primitive principle which fills the universal infinite space of the world, we may consider this last (this primitive principle— the ether) as the all-comprehending Deity and thereon base the proposition that 'faith in God is capable of being united with natural science.' " We have here at least a specimen of what he regards as a scientific article of faith, one which has facts to support it and which does not contradict the law of causality. On the other hand we must suppose, since he rejects the Christian doctrine of God, that he regards it as having no facts in its support or as being contrary to the law of caus ation, or both. As this is not the place to display the facts which the Christian system has to offer in support of its faith in God we refer the reader to the appropriate portions of this volume that he may judge for himself whether it has no facts, and is therefore purely fictitious, and whether it contradicts the law of causation. Here we inquire what facts Haeckel's doctrine of God has for its support. It is evident that he has given, though briefly, his argument for belief in God, and that he has identified for us his deity (the ether).2 The first part of his 1 Der Monismus, p. 37. 3 See also the scheme we have cited from him on p. 147, above, where he attributes crea tion to the ether. 180 Foundations of the Christian Faith. argument is that both the simpler processes of inorganic nature and First part of tne more complex phenomena of organic life are tracea- ment foA"- ^le tothe same forces of nature. But, as we have seen,1 lief in God. y^g ^ according to his own declaration, an article of faith and not an established fact. Should it be replied that though it be an article of faith it is itself supported by fact, we answer that the majority of scientists do not think so.3 Anyone who wfll take the pains to read what scientists have to say with regard to the origin of life will discover that it is really a piece of arrant dogmatism to assert that the processes of inorganic nature and the phenomena of organic life, in which Haeckel includes mental processes, are traceable to the same forces of nature. So, then, the first part of his argument for his deity is an unproved hypothesis, and not an established fact. The next factor in his proof is that the forces of nature have their common ground in a single (unitary) principle (the ether) par . wnjcn g2is fljg universal infinite space. But is this an estabhshed fact ? By no means. The very existence of the ether is an hypothesis ; rendered necessary, as scientists think indeed, by the de mand of facts for explanation, but still an hypothesis; and an hypothesis which has undergone considerable modification in reaching its present form. It is admitted on all hands that the ether is not perceptible by the senses. It is as truly without parts as the God of the Christian is affirmed to be. It is immaterial. It is the condition of all things visi ble and tangible. In fact, it seems to have about the same duties which Christians assign to God, so far as the material world is con cerned. It is declared to be the God of the monist (see above). The only difference between this ether and the God of the Christians is that the latter, with his intelligence, is better fitted for his task than this supposed ether could be. God is not matter, and he cannot be known to the senses ; ether is not matter, and it cannot be known to the senses. Both are held, so far as the facts of observation demand explanation, as hypotheses ; and yet Haeckel would attempt to say that the scientific articles of faith have facts in their support, while the creeds have none. As an hypothesis by which to account for all the facts God is incomparably superior to the ether. But to this Haeckel would reply, probably, that the doctrine of God is unreasonable in that it contradicts the law of causation. Let us 1 Page 177 above. i Comp. Willkomm's Ueber die Grenzen des Pflanzen-und Thierreiches und den Urs- prung dos organischen Lehens auf der Erde, Prague, 1888, pp. 24-31 ; Philipp's Ueber Urs- prung und Lebenserscheinuugen der tierischen Organismen, Leipzig, 1887,p. 19 f ; Du Bois-Reymond's Vortriige, pp. 55 ff. ; 88 and 89 ff . „ _„„„ „, ^heologyand Science. 181 look at this. We shall make no objection to the fact that science knows no cause which is not an effect, and none which does not lie within the realm of matter and force. But how does the doctrine of God as held by Christians contradict the law of causation ? Evidently by supposing that somehow he affects the matter and force already in the world. But does this ether not do exactly the same thing ? Haeckel ascribes to the ether the impartation of motion to matter, and makes it the condition by which atoms can affect each other at a dis tance. ' This is dualism, pure and simple, since the ether is not mat ter, but distinct from it, and yet affects it. Hence it is difficult to see how the Christian doctrine of God is less weU supported by facts or more unreasonable than this "scientific" doctrine.3 Buchner, too, tries to make it appear that the articles of faith of religion and philosophy rest on unproved suppositions and assertions which contradict grossly the facts of science and the rules of logic, while those of science rest on the unimpeachable basis of Btichner on an order of all being which is founded on law and cannot "'[* 0 u°g be changed, a basis brought to light by science itself.3 faith- Not much time may be spent on this. There is not a single doctrine of the Christian religion (though the same cannot be said of some doc trines of professed Christians) which contradicts any established fact of science or which violates any rule of logical thought. These doc trines do not rest on unproved assumptions, nor on assertion. They are, without exception, so far as they are fundamental to Christianity, based on well-established facts ; that is, they are necessary to the ex planation of the facts, and the attempt to explain these facts in any other way does violence to them. If we examine the confessed articles of faith mentioned by Strecker and sanctioned by Buchner we shaU discover that the whole system of science rests, according to them, on faith in the law of causation. This law, though deduced from expe rience, contains in it no assurance that it is universal or unchangeable. This assurance is read into the law by our own judgment. It is a mere matter of opinion, or belief. Hence Strecker truly says that the materialistic, which is given out as the strictly scientific view, trusts in, relies upon, the unchangeable operation of the law of causation. 1 Der Monismus, p. 41. 3 Iu fact the hypothesis of the ether is a kind of scientific confession of ignorance. En tirely justified to science by its usefulness, it becomes utterly absurd when required to explain the dynamic origin of things or when set up as the creative deity. What possi ble notion can be formed of a unity without parts that yet fills all space, an impondera ble, immaterial somewhat that is not spirit, a cause of order and system together with all the phenomena of organic and conscious life, yet devoid of intelligence? 1 In his EinfUhrung to Strecker's Welt und Menschheit, p. xi. 14 182 Foundations of the Christian ±aith. When we believe that this law is universal and unchangeable we do so with good reason. But it is, none the less, belief, not established fact. And the beliefs essential to Christianity are based on equaUy good grounds, although many scientists, especiaUy atheistic and mon istic scientists, seem not to be aware of it. But, again, it is affirmed that Christians talk with assurance con cerning things which in the nature of the case lie beyond the range of actual knowledge. Now, we frankly admit that we are convinced of many things which, in the strictest sense of the word, we cannot know. We talk familiarly of things unseen and intangible. Here, too, we must postpone the justification of this mode of procedure ; but by turning to the proper place in this volume the reader may see that we do not beheve without the best of reasons. In this part of our work we can only point out that we do just what science does in its sphere, and that if it is aUowable in matters of science it surely cannot be con- demnable by scientists in the sphere of reUgion. That science does talk familiarly of things concerning which it can give no consistent account is acknowledged by aU who understand the situation. Herbert Spencer devotes twenty pages of his First Princi ples to an exhibition of the Umitations of scientific knowledge. 1 Among the things which science cannot do or does not at aU understand are, ac cording to Spencer — Space and Time, the Nature of Matter, of Motion, of its Transference, of Force, and how it acts, of Consciousness, of Mind, of Self. Du Bois-Reymond gives us seven Weltrathsel (prob lems or puzzles found in the world), the first of which is the nature Spencer on °£ matter and force, the second the origin of motion, the oTscfentiflc third the origin of life, the fourth the apparently purposed knowledge. and teleological order of nature, the fifth the origin of sense-perception, or consciousness, the sixth reasoned thought and the origin of language, and the seventh the freedom of the wfll. Several of these he regards as not only unsolved but insoluble.3 Even the all- wise Haeckel admits that there is one limit to his knowledge (Jesus ad mitted as much concerning himself), namely, the nature of matter and force, and says that if we knew this we should know aU about the world, including life and consciousness.' Wagner, in his Christenglaube im Bunde mit der Naturwissen- schaft, to which we have made frequent reference, gives eighteen pages to the emphasis of the limits of scientific knowledge of na ture.* Considering the fact that he is fully committed to the mod- 1 Comprising the whole of his chap. 3, on Ultimate Scientific Ideas. 3 Vortrage, pp. 73-112. »DerMonismus,p. 44. * Ibid., pp. 23-41. Articles of ITaith in Theology and Science. 183 era scientific theories of the world, his concessions are the more strik ing. He says : " Nevertheless, we dare not overlook the fact that all our natural laws are founded on hypotheses which we wagner and make concerning the effective forces of nature. Kepler in Kosanes. deducing his planetary laws from the results of many observations came upon certain ideas which when applied to our planetary system led at once to correct conclusions, which harmonized with observation. These laws, however, find their mathematical foundation in the cele brated Newtonian law of gravitation, which, indeed, is called a law, but which, nevertheless, is only an hypothesis, concerning which Rosanes says,1 ' If for the explanation of the motion of the cosmical masses we could discover a simple hypothesis which varied but infinitesimally from that of Newton, we could have no means of discovering which was the correct one.' That is, we could very well think of two diverse fundamental causes for the actual masses and distances and their changes of place, which, nevertheless, if applied to other given masses and distances could lead to quite different movements. Which of the two is right could not be decided ; within the actual limits in which they were to be apphed either one would suffice. Thus all hypotheses and the laws of nature deduced from them are valid and applicable only within certain limits. . . . Whether we have in fact hit the exact truth with our hypothesis is and will remain whoUy uncertain. ... It cannot be denied that from the heaven (of knowledge) into which we were transported by the modern scientific view of the world, we are, so to speak, in turn torn away. ... On every side the insight into the real causes of that which appears and disappears is denied us ; the world now, as before, is inexplicable." " One can, if he wfll, deceive himself into the belief that aU hypotheses which lead us to natural laws, so far as we can judge, correspond to experience and are absolutely correct, or in other words are no longer hypotheses, but certainties, in which case one would indeed proceed very unscientificaUy." These confessions could be multiplied indefinitely. We take no pleasure in them. We think none the less of what science has done because she has found her limits. But when scientists, or those who would be scientists, accuse us of talking familiarly of those things -concerning which, in the ultimate analysis, we know nothing, we feel justified in saying that, while it is all true, we are in no worse case than others. No one feels more painfully than the thoughtful theo logian his lack of knowledge in the strict sense of the word. But we 1 Eosanes, Ueber die neuesten Untersuchungen in betreff unserer Anschauungen vom Raume, Breslau, 1871. 184: Foundations of the Christian Faith. are aU justified in the practice of taking some things for fact in order to have a working theory ; and we need not say at the end of every Articles of sentence that we do not know the facts, but only as- faith justM- ., T , • A. . , ,. , able in sci- sume them. In other words, scientists who take up ence and theology. an agnostic position relative to religion should not forget that theologians would be equaUy justifiable in toking an agnostic po sition relative to science. Scientific agnosticism consists essentially in the assertion that the methods by which we acquire theological knowledge are inadequate and that the objects of theological knowledge are of very uncertain reality. If we have succeeded in defending Christianity against these two very serious imputations we have succeeded in refuting scientific as distinguished from philosophical agnosticism.1 ' On scientific agnosticism see further, Schurman's Agnosticism and Religion, New York, 1896, Part I. vjod and Ureation. 185 SECTION II.-SCIENTIFIC AND THEOLOGICAL THEORIES OF THE RELATION OF COD TO CREATION AND PROVIDENCE. CHAPTER I. GOD AND CREATION. We have had occasion several times to caU attention to the fact that the existence of God as Creator cannot, in the nature of the case, be disproved. In fact, science as such has nothing to do with creation. This is apparent from the definitions of science which are given by the best authorities. As Professor Bowne says: "He (the scientist) views nature as given, and seeks to find the order of its changes and the interaction of its parts." • Creation is reaUy a phflo sophical or theological problem ; and it is not even true that science seeks to discover the method of creation, though in pursuing its pur pose it may shed some Ught on that interesting subject, creation not a How matter came into existence, what were its original science. attributes and how it came by them are questions with which sci ence as such need not concern itself. Concerning the origin of atoms Haeckel says: "This event, if it ever took place, is wholly beyond the range of human knowledge, and can, therefore, never be an object of scientific research." Philipp says: "In what manner the dead fundamental substance originated we can no more con jecture than we can guess the history of the origin of the ele ments of granite." And Virchow teUs us: "I have expressly declared that natural science is not able to solve the problem of creation."2 Science can neither affirm nor deny creation by God ; but it is at liberty and it is its duty to ignore that whole matter. If any scientist sees fit to dabble in such questions we make no objection ; but we do object when he does it in the name of science. Nevertheless, scientists have busied themselves with the problem of creation— the Whence, the Why, the How, and the Whither. Hence it becomes the duty of the apologist to consider what they say. And first we wish to point out that scientists have not by any means unanimously, nor even 1 Metaphysics, p. 102. "These citations are from Steude, Christenthum und Naturwlssenschaft, p. 134. 186 Foundations of the Christian Faith. generally, denied creation by God; while many have asserted it. All monists assert it, though some of them in a very vague and unsat- Scientists do isfactory way. AU deists assert it, though they deny ally deny the any further relation of God to the world. No agnostic God increaf denies it ; for he professedly knows nothing about it. tion. Only atheists are left to deny it ; and they are relatively few in number, while of them many will go no farther than to say they see no reason for believing it. Among scientific men of the first order who have more or less clearly expressed themselves in favor of the idea of God as creator is WaUace, who by the very fact that he argues the more exalted character of creation as an original act of God betrays his belief. And he distinctly says: " Only in reference to the origin of universal forces and laws have I spoken of the will or power of one Supreme InteUigence."1 Further, he takes the posi tion that all force is wiU force, and that as matter is force the whole universe probably is "the will of higher intelligence or of one Supreme Intelligence."2 In a general way these utterances commit WaUace to some form of the doctrine of creation by God, though he insists that it is through law, with notable exceptions. Darwin, too, although he professed to become more and more an agnostic as he advanced in years, leaves us in no doubt that he held to the existence of God and creation by him. "The question . . . Darwin's posi- whether there exists a Creator and Ruler of the uni- 11 on- verse . . . has been answered in the affirmative by some of the highest inteUects that have ever existed."3 "The birth of the species and of the individual are equally parts of that grand sequence of events which our minds refuse to accept as the result of blind chance." 4 " I see no good reason why the views given in this volume should shock the religious feeUng of anyone. ... A cele brated author and divine has written to me that he has graduaUy learnt to see that it is just as noble a conception of Deity to believe that he created a few original forms, capable of self -development into other and needful forms, as to believe that he required a fresh act of creation to supply the voids caused by his laws." B On page 428 of the same work he speaks of " what we know of the laws impressed upon matter by the Creator." On page 429, at the very close of the volume, he says : " There is grandeur in this view of life with its several powers having been originally breathed by the Creator into a few 1 Natural Selection and Tropical Nature, p. 205. a Ibid., pp. 210-212. » The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, new edition, Revised and Augmented, New York, 1895, p. 94. ¦'Ibid., p. 613. » The Origin of Species, By Means of Natural Selection, London, 1872, page 421. God and Creation. 187 forms, or into one ; and that, whilst this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, from so simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful have been and are being evolved." Comparatively late in Ufe he wrote: "In my most extreme fluctuations I have never been an atheist in the sense of deny ing the existence of a God ;" • on the contrary, he thought of himself as an agnostic. In 1876 he wrote of the "impossibility of conceiv ing this immense and wonderful universe, including man with his capacity of looking far backwards and far into futurity, as the result of blind chance or necessity." 3 In 1881 he wrote of "my inward convic tion . . . that the universe is not the result of chance." 3 It is easy to see that there is a growing indeflniteness in his references to God as Creator ; yet we think that from first to the last they show a be lief that the world is not a chance product but the result of the act or acts of an inteUigent God.4 These names are sufficient, though scores of scientific men of highest rank could be added to the Ust. That to some students of science the facts have appeared otherwise is not strange. For it is easy to mistake an argument against design, for example, for an argument against creation by the Deity ; or a refutation of the ordi nary arguments for the existence of God for a denial of his existence. Darwin could not accept the proofs of God's existence as conclusive ; yet he could not escape the conviction that this universe is not the result of chance. This can mean only that it is the product of inteUi gence; and its immensity and its wonderful character must have suggested, though it did not, to his mind, prove, that why they God created it. Another fact which has seemed to many understood to indicate that scientists deny creation to God is that \£e ddfVnie with almost perfect unanimity they deny the creation in asency- the manner described in Genesis. As long as the account of creation there given was held to be literal and exact history scientists denied creation. They refused to go to the Bible for an account of how this world came into being when the world itseU was before them and open to their study. And particularly were they unwiUing to accept the Bible account, since it seemed to them to contradict the records of the world itself. So to those who identified creation with the account of creation given in Genesis it appeared to be denied by scientists. 1 The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, edited by his son, Francis Darwin, in three volumes : London, 1887, vol. i, p. 304. 2 Ibid., p. 312. 3 Ibid., p. 316. 'See the article by Professor B. B. Warfield, on Charles Darwin's Religious Life, in the Presbyterian Review, vol. Ix, pp. 569 ff. 188 Foundations of the Christian Faith. But whfle scientists have not generaUy denied creation by the Deity some have gone so far as this, and especiaUy have some done so who have been rather natural philosophers than natural scientists. Per haps we should not too severely censure those scientists who attempt phflosophy ; for, as Romanes points out, science cannot account for any of its ultimate facts, nor even attempt to do so, without entering the domain of phflosophy. • Nevertheless, we again protest against the attempt to pass off this natural phflosophy for natural science. And we point out that many of the conclusions of the natural phflosophy are unwarranted by science. Says Wagner :' "The more recent in vestigations prove most clearly that man was a product of the latest Conclusions Slaciai period in Europe, and this fact suffices both for of natural natural philosophy and for those who in our day are philosphy * r j •> ra°nteWdaby trame(* m natural science to teach that the Scripture science. account of creation is not to be held as historically cor rect. But whfle the men of science content themselves with this fact the natural philosopher at once rejects any and every divine in fluence in the development of the organic world and sets up his atheistic view instead. The progress of chemistry makes it proper to speak of those infinitesimal, indivisible portions of matter, the atoms, of which bodies are composed, which when united in groups form molecules, and which are separated from one another by certain dis tances. By the supposition of attractive and repulsive forces the various changes which bodies can undergo are explained. This hypothesis has much in its favor, although it leaves much wholly unexplained. But to the natural philosopher the existence and opera tion of these atoms, out of which according to fixed laws the world forms and modifies itself, suffice to render unnecessary the creative energy of God." That the facts in the cases cited by Wagner do not support, nor even suggest, the conclusions drawn by natural philoso phy is evident at a glance. Others have tried to do away with the creative agency of an inteUigent being by positing a soul in each atom, as Haeckel does. The unsatisfactory character of this monistic doctrine has been sufficiently pointed out. We only remind the reader here that it cannot account for the unity of our con sciousness nor for our consciousness of personal unity, and that as long as we feel ourselves to be personal no doctrine of God which diffuses him through the whole universe can hold its place in our thought. 1 Thoughts on Religion, p. 43. » Chrlstenglaube im Bunde mit der Naturwlssenschaft, p. 2 f. LrOD AND CREATION. 189 But the question of the relation between the theories and discoveries of modern science and the biblical account of creation recurs.1 That there is a conflict here is undeniable ; and the dogmatic theologian is bound to take his choice between an attempt to disprove the findings of science and the establishment of the historical verity of the Scrip ture account of creation on the one side, and on the other the admis-' sion that Genesis is not an exact statement of scientific facts. For all efforts at harmonization have fafled, since they either deny what science affirms or do violence to Genesis itseU.2 It is a significant fact that few scientists of first rank who believe in creation and also in the Bible have thought such a harmony possible. However, because we are not dogmaticians but apologists, the alternative mentioned does not present itself to us for decision in this connection. For in this place we are discussing the question whether God created the world, not how he created it. So that we need neither insist that the Bible account of creation is correct nor affirm that it is wrong. If anyone takes the latter position aU that can be de- Can tne teach. manded of Christian evidences is to show that faith in the j".|s science" revelation given in Jesus Christ is not thereby destroyed, si^berecon- It is bad pohcy for the defender of the faith to support the ciIed? correctness of Bible science : for our defenses fail to convince scientific men, and react unfavorably upon their estimate of our ability to see the truth in those matters in which they would not naturally set up their opinions against ours. So that we have no reward for our effort, and have made access to the hearts of scientists more difficult than ever. Men may say as much as they please, that the unreadiness of scientists to accept the science of the Bible results from a wicked heart of unbelief. Scientists repel the imputation, and are alienated from Christianity thereby. Hence, unless the science of the Bible be essential to salva tion, we ask whether it is not wiser for those who accept it on faith to allow those who cannot believe as they do to believe as their judgments dictate. That is a right precious to Protestants, at least, and we should not forbid it to others. The important point is to win men to living faith in Jesus Christ and to activity in his service. If the teachings of the Bible relative to science stand in anyone's way let us not strive to hinder his attempt to destroy the barrier. 1 An excellent discussion of the contents of the first three chapters of Genesis may be found in Professor Samuel Harris's God the Creator and Lord of All, New York, 1896, vol. i, pp.466ff. 3 For conclusive proof of this statment see Steude, » firm believer in God as Creator, Christenthum und Naturwlssenschaft, pp. 19 ff. Comp. also two articles by President Morton in the Bibliotheca Sacra, 1897, pp. 264-292, and 436-468. 190 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. THE SCIENCE OF THE BIBLE. There are several facts which suggest that the utterances of the Bible on scientific questions, whether absolutely true or not, cannot be Are the scien- 0]E fundamental importance. First, it is an unquestioned ances of the fact that the Bible was not given us to teach science, but difme0"™! to show us God's relation to man. The science of the importance? gjDie) therefore, is of secondary importance; it is inci dental. Again, had the inspiring Spirit regarded it as essential we can but beUeve that the language employed would have been so un equivocally scientific, instead of popular, that there could be no ques tion of its inspiration. Instead of this we have a purely popular set ting forth of the facts relative to the universe. There is nothing in the language employed to indicate that there was in the mind of the writer any other than the popular view. When we say that he knew the scientific facts but put them in popular form we can only do so because we believe in the equal inspiration of all parts of the Bible. This brings us face to face with the question whether we must enter tain such a belief in inspiration. This question we shaU not discuss at length. But we recommend anyone who is in doubt to read what is said on that subject in Dr. Henry M. Harman's Introduction to the Study of the Holy Scriptures. ' We quote a few sentences : ' ' But it (the theory of verbal inspiration in every part of the sacred Scriptures) is very in convenient to the biblical interpreter, apart from its being in many cases useless, for it compels him to reconcile every discrepancy, how ever trifling, and to vindicate the grammatical accuracy of every word and sentence in the sacred canon, which, in not a few instances, is a difficult task and rarely satisfies the candid reader." The doc trine is even more fatal in the field of Christian evidences ; for it leads us to attempt a harmony where none is really possible, and thus to an unconsciously dishonest interpretation of the Bible or to un called-for denials of the truth of scientific conclusions. It is better to give our strength to the overthrow of those positions which are really dangerous to faith in Jesus Christ,2 and to the defense of those 1 Fourth edition, New York, 1884, chap. 1, pp. 23-28. a Comp. Professor E. Caird's The Social Philosophy and Religion of Comte, Glasgow, 1885, p. 185. '1'he Science of the Bible. 191 Christian truths the acceptance of which leads consistent men and women straight to his service. A third point is that nobody now holds to the UteraUty of the Gene sis record of creation in aU its parts. The days, with their mornings and evenings, are universally regarded to-day as periods by those who strive to reconcile Genesis with science. That this method of harmonization also is a failure is clear from the fact that, however long these day -periods may be, they represent, in the Bible, periods in which definite portions of the creation were brought to completion, whereas the periods known to science have no such definite contents, but overlap each other. Our purpose here is, not to show that no rec onciliation is possible, but to exhibit the fact that we need not insist on the scientific accuracy of the Biblical account of creation. StiU, we think it unwise so much as even to attempt a reconciliation be tween Genesis and science at present. For, in the first place, such a reconciliation implies that we have an absolutely correct interpreta tion of the Scripture record ; ' and, second, that we have the final word of science as to the method of creation. Had we not better wait with our harmony until science has finished its work ? Most of our difficulties with science have arisen from the fact that we have ad justed our doctrine to scientific teaching, and then, when the latter changed, we were not willing to readjust. Let us as much as pos sible quit such adjustments until scientists can pledge us that they have the final truth in their various departments. Until then, strong in the faith, let us not be anxious about the harmony or disharmony of our doctrine with the teachings of science, but let us be anxious to learn the truth. All this desire for harmony with science implies a relatively feeble faith in the religion we profess. If the essential point in the scriptural account of the creation is not its scientific utterances that point must be sought in its reUgious as pect. This is without doubt the favorable position for Christianity. Many of the most thoroughly orthodox of the Scrip- theologians of the present day so fuUy beUeve this that of creati°n they not only deny that Christianity can experience any in its reii- harm from the admission of the nonhistorical character of the Scripture record of creation, but strongly insist that this should be openly and everywhere taught. Steude, one of the editors of Der Beweis des Glaubens, a standard orthodox periodical of Germany, says : * 1 Comp. Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences, New York, 1869, vol. 1, p. 403. 2 Christenthum und Naturwissenschaft, p. 45 f. Steude is admitted by theologians of all schools in Germany to be strictly orthodox. 192 Foundations of the Christian Faith. "I hold it as one of the duties of apologists who are caUed to the task of establishing peace between natural science and Christianity, and of restoring peace to the hearts of many educated Christians of our day, to declare over and over again, openly and emphaticaUy, that the Biblical account of creation is not an historical but a reUgious record, and its scientific aspects, neither in the Old nor in the New Testament, to be looked upon as binding, or as a dogma of the evangelical Church. And so also I hold it for the duty of the teachers of evangeUcal re Ugion in treating the BibUcal account of creation to bring out and emphasize only the religious truths of Gen. i and ii, and to make known to the more mature pupils the reasons why the Bible story of creation can be granted no historical worth or doctrinal significance on their natural-historical side. For only when this is universaUy done can the collisions between science and Christianity and between the modern view of the world and Christian faith graduaUy cease." We confess that such an utterance as this appears to us extreme- For, even according to so radical an opponent of revelation as Haeckel, there is very important truth in the Mosaic account of creation. He says : 1 " Two great and fundamental ideas, common also to the non- Haeckel's miraculous theory of development, meet us in this Mosaic concession as to the sci- hypothesis of creation with surprising clearness and sim- ence of Gen- .... . , . . . . . . . _. ... , , , esis. plicity — the idea of separation or differentiation and the idea of progressive development or perfecting." In view of this con cession it is no wonder that we find Biot saying : " Either Moses had a more profound instruction in science than that afforded by our century or he was inspired."2 Dutoit-HaUer argues that aU the events in the physical world which took place prior to the appear ance of man must have been revealed if they are found in the Mosaic record to be in accord with the discoveries of natural science.3 This is a vaUd argument unless we are willing to admit that Moses hit on the unquestionably scientific features of his account by accident, or else that the science of his day approached remarkably close to that of ours. In fact, Haeckel denies inspiration to Moses's record of crea tion only on the ground that along with the great truths, which he ad mits the account contains, it also records some fundamental errors.* So, then, we cannot agree that we should teach that the account of creation in Genesis has no historical worth. But, though the lofty • The History of Creation, from the German of Ernst Haeckel, the translation revised by E. Ray Lankaster. In two volumes. New York, 1876, vol. 1, p. 38. 3 Cited from his Tralte elementalre d'astronomie physique by Dutoit-HaUer, in Schop- fung unci Entwicltelung nach Bibel und Naturwlssenschaft, p. 6. 8 SchUpfung und Entwlckelung, p. 6. * The History of Creation, vol. i, p. 39. J. HE SCIENCE OF THE BlBLE. 193 scientific conceptions admittedly belonging to that account indicate inspiration, yet the fact that these are not uniform and complete, but partial in their extent, suggests that the inspiration which Moses had for rehgious purposes aided, though it did not render him infaUible, in the scientific conception also. This inspiration for the purpose of a religious revelation is made very clear when we note the differences between the Mosaic account of creation and the cosmogonies of other ancient people. Comparing the Hebraic and Chaldean cosmogonies Horton says that, while the resem blances are striking and interesting, the differences are far more signifi cant. In the Chaldean account "the gods did not create the world, but rather the world created them. The distinctive note of Gen. i, on the other hand, is that ' in the beginning ' there was God, and he created the whole universe." "The further the comparison with other rehgious systems is carried the more convincing Horton pn the is the conclusion that the whole tenor of this first chapter of Pt h^°Mo^ of Genesis is unique. God is at the beginning. He has mogony.C°s" no equal, no rival." " The whole creation proceeds from his will and the word of his mouth." " This clear and firm conception of God as the creator, and of man as the image of his creator,1 is in itseU sufficiently wonderful, and can leave no doubt on the mind of the stu dent of Comparative Mythology that in this point Ues the essential revelation of this chapter. If the chapter had been composed for the first time to-day — in the schools of Darwin or Haeckel, for example- it would be a revelation ; it would be, not a scientific statement, but the assertion of two consummate truths which science is not able to discover. ... If these truths are not revealed they cannot be known, and yet when they are revealed they become the key to all the science of God, or theology, or to all the science of man, or anthropology." 2 The insistence on the religious character of the revelation in Genesis relieves us of the necessity of adjusting our theology to the changes in scientific views. Whether they remain the same or whether they alter, we have in Genesis, which arose in the midst of surrounding rehgious error, truth which the ages need and have never been able to shake. " No scientific investigation of nature can cause us to weaken in the faith in God as the Almighty Creator of heaven and earth." s If we confine our use of Genesis to its reUgious value we cannot come 1 Notice that even in this very early revelation human attributes are not ascribed to God, but divine likeness to man. God is not made in the image of man, but man in the Image of God. ' Horton, Revelation and the Bible, New York, 1892, pp. 31-37. s Riehm, Christenthum und Naturwlssenschaft, Leipzig, 1896, p. 27. 194 Foundations of the Christian Faith. into conflict with science, and we use it as it must have been originaUy designed, namely, as a revelation of religious truth. Should it be said in reply that the teachings of science are in danger of overturning faith in this religious truth, we answer that such a fear is groundless. This is evident, first, from the fact that these religious truths are en tirely out of the reach of science ; and, second, from experience of the past relations of science and theology. We have mentioned the fear which Christians felt of the Copernican theory, now universaUy held by Christians without the slightest detriment to their faith. It is not generally known, though it is a fact, that Newton's laws of gravita tion were also feared and opposed as unsettling to faith. Even Leib nitz regarded the doctrine of gravitation as destructive of revealed re ligion.1 These, with numbers of similar experiences, ought to teach us that religion is not bound up with any method of creation which men have gathered from the Bible or read into the Bible, nor with any question of natural science, but stands on a foundation of its own; and that it is in no danger of being banished from the world. Such considerations as those which have been presented must, if allowed their due weight, lead the Christian apologist to leave each individual to his own belief in matters of science, and to spend his strength in showing that none of the really established scientific hypotheses can destroy the effect of the argument for Christian be lief. But in making this concession the true limits of science must be ever kept in mind ; for much is set forth for scientific fact which in Necessity of reality is nothing but assumption ; and much also is caUed observing . the true lim- science which really belongs m the realm of phflosophy. ence. ' And, while no established fact can undermine faith in Jesus Christ as the Son of God and Saviour of the world, there are many speculations both in science and philosophy which, if con sistently held, must make such faith impossible. But it needs to be remembered that even if the evolutionary idea of creation came to prevail in the minds of men it would not of necessity destroy faith in Christ ; for many of the truest Christians of the last thirty years have been firm believers in the evolutionary theories ; and their numbers are increasing. This is true even of the evolutionary theory of the origin of man,2 the arguments for which, though not compulsory, are yet so strong that few thoughtful and weU-inf ormed men of to-day can be found who will venture to assert that it is false. And when we 1 Comp. Darwin's Origin of Species, p. 422, and White's History of the Warfare of Science with Theology, vol. I, p. 15 f. a Comp. Tayler Lewis's The Six Days of Creation. KoboD«'ctadv. 1855. p. 246 f. AMIS SCIENCE OF THE BlBLE. 195 look afresh into the Biblical record of creation we find that God formed man out of the dust of the ground, but the steps of the process are no where described. In the days when science accepted the idea of the immediate creation of species by a divine fiat theologians read that notion into the words of Genesis. Now that science has changed its mind is it necessary for us to defend the old science which is not in the Bible at all ? It may be said that it is unworthy of man to believe that he was de veloped from the lower orders of animal life through a being which was partly ape and partly man. We answer that if God did it in that way it is not an unworthy way of doing it. The real question, in other words, is not one of the dignity of the method, which it is The evolution- difficult for man to settle, but one of fact. We certainly of creation have no wish to persuade anyone that man was developed thy. in the manner supposed by evolutionists ; but we also do not wish any one who is convinced of it already to feel that he must therefore reject Jesus Christ. No one who reads Gen. i can fail to note that from the grass, herbs, and fruit trees, through the water animals, fowls of the air, and beasts of the earth, to man, there is an ascending scale. And it is also clear that as God formed man out of the dust (that is, the elements) of the earth, or soil, so he is represented as forming the beasts of the field out of the same.1 The material employed was the same as that which goes to constitute our earth ; and it was the same, according to Genesis, both in man and beast. This science finds to be a fact of observation, and so far the story of Genesis and the discov eries of science agree. When the Bible gives us no word as to the method employed, and science thinks the method was by evolution, why should we try to make it appear that science is wrong ? Genesis does not, as Willkomm asserts,2 teach that all the animals and plants of our earth were created by the word of God complete, as PaUas Athene sprang ready accoutered from the head of Zeus. The language of Genesis is, "And God said, Let the earth bring forth grass, . . . Let the waters bring forth abundantly the moving creature that hath life, . . . Let the earth bring forth the living creature after his kind, cattle, creeping thing, and beast of the earth." However nearly or remotely this may correspond to the scientific conception of the proc ess of creation, it certainly is just as possible to think of it from the standpoint of evolution as of sudden creation ; for no description is given us of the method. The language simply ascribes creation to God without telling us anything of his mode of procedure. Why should 1 Gen. ii, 19. 2 Ueber die Grenzen des Pflanzen-und Thierreiches, p. 24. 196 Foundations of the Christian Faith. theologians read into Genesis a method of creation contrary to that assumed by science ? At the behest of science we once read the sud den creation theory into the Scripture record ; now that science has changed we need not read the new theory in ; but we also need not de clare that science and Genesis conflict.1 The conflict is not between science and Genesis on the question of evolution, but between science as it was and science as it is. The evolutionary method may not be demonstrated, but it must not be overlooked that no other method is demonstrated. Whether by immediate creation or by evolution, man's body is formed of the physical elements of our earth. Then, too, it is a question whether we are consistent in thinking slightingly of any being God has made. No one denies the superiority of man's physical organism, however many points of resemblance may be found between it and the organ isms in lower animal life. These resemblances are facts no less than the differences. Need we find fault with our Creator, or jealously contemn his other creatures, because the differences of bodily organ ism between them and us are not greater ? But if the writer of Gen. ii tells us that man and beast have the same physical origin he also notes a difference which science does not Distinction Pretend to deny. To the statement that the Lord God mVn" and t°rmed man of the dust of the ground he adds that he no6tedSin the " breathed into his nostrils the breath of life."2 How- Bible. ever we may interpret these words they note a some what which God gave to man which it is not said he gave to the ani mals. The whole account in Gen. i and U shows that the author or editor thought God had given man the place of dignity. Of man only is it said that God created him in his own image. And that image is not physical, for God is a spirit. Man is not, then, robbed of his divine image by being regarded as physically the lineal descend ant of lower forms of animal life. Nor can the breathing into man's nostrils the breath of life be taken literaUy. For in that case we should have to think of God as having physical breathing apparatus similar to ours, and the breath of life would mean the ordinary breath necessary to life. But this the lower animals have also. Hence the words " breathed into his nostrils the breath of life ; and man became a living soul," cannot imply that prior to that he was dead matter, nor a living, though not breathing, organism. It must mean that he, like the beasts of the field which God also formed of the dust of the j?round, was alive and breathing, but that God gave him an addi- 1 Lewis, The Six Days of Creation, chaps. 16 and 24. " Gen. 11, 7. J. HE SCIENCE OF THE BlBLE. 197 tional something. The words probably signify the same as making man in his (God's) image. AU this indicates that there is not so much difference between the accounts of man's creation, as given in Genesis and by scientists, as has been sometimes supposed. And it suggests that we should at least not try to make those differences greater than they are. In a general way the Bible doctrine of the origin of man does not differ from that held by evolutionary science. The fact for us to hold fast is that God created man, by whatever method, and that he created him in his own image.1 1 A. Berthoud, a strict conservative of Geneva, asserts the purely religious purpose of the Bible. Apologie du Christianisme, Lausanne, 1898, p. 275 f. 15 198 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. NECESSITY OF MIRACLE TO RELIGION. Providence, in the Christian sense of the word, involves the con stant divine superintendence of man and the at least occasional inter vention of God in man's behalf. The doctrine also includes answer to prayer. The classic expression of the doctrine of providence is con tained in the words of Jesus: "Are not two sparrows sold for a farthing ? and one of them shall not faU on the ground without your Father. But the very hairs of your head are aU numbered. Fear ye not therefore, ye are of more value than many sparrows." 1 Of the many utterances of Jesus relative to answer to prayer we quote but one : " Ask, and it shaU be given you ; seek, and ye shaU find ; knock, and it shall be opened unto you. ... If ye then, being evil, know how to give good gifts unto your children, how much more shall your Father which is in heaven give good things to them that ask him ? " 2 The assault of science, however, is not directed so much against provi dence and answer to prayer as against miracle ; for scientists rightly feel that if miracle is admitted providence and answer to prayer The assault follow. Hence many scientists, some of them professed directed Christians, demand that faith in miracles shaU cease. acie. Buchner, in the name of materiaUsm, describes the true order of the world as one which rests on the necessary and perpet ual operation of natural causes, excluding aU voUtion (or caprice — Willkur) and acts of violence in the phenomena of nature.3 And Strecker* rejects every explanation which admits chance or voU tion (caprice) in the formation of the world and which does not insist on the exclusive action of physical causation. EKeld says : ' "The unfortunate antagonism between the reUgious and the scientific standpoint . . . will continue as long as theology . . . insists on the faith in miracles." Says Haeckel : "Not to that theology does the fu ture belong which conducts a fruitless warfare against . . . evolution but to that which masters, recognizes, and employs it." e 1 Matt, x, 29-31. » Matt, vii, 7, 11. 8 Einf aiming to Strecker's Welt und Menschheit, p. viii. 4 Ibid., p. 27. 8 Die Religion und der Darwinismus, Leipzig, 1882, p. 3. •Die heutlge Entwlckelungslehre im Verhttltnlss zur Gesammtwissenschaft, Stutt gart, 1877, p. 19 f . Necessity of Miracle to Keligion. 199 These references may suffice to reveal the fact that what science demands of Christianity in order to the restoration of peace is the yielding of the faith in the miraculous. In view of this some theo logians have ceased to emphasize the miraculous in the Christian religion, and have practically come to agree with Elfeld's implication in saying that "the world-order is the greatest and most imposing of all wonders."1 This is evident in such expressions as that of Her mann Schultz, that life is, in its final analysis, a riddle and a wonder (or miracle— Wunder).2 Still more clearly does this tendency appear in Lipsius.3 " That many events and phenomena in the world cannot be sufficiently explained by laws valid for a definite circle of phe nomena does not prove that these laws are suspended by a ' higher order' of procedure." "Everything which, from the teleological standpoint, offers itseU as a proof of divine guidance and provi dence is a miracle in the reUgious sense, and as such, indeed, never empirically cognizable." It would be fortunate in some respects if we could accept this idea of a miracle which has a significance for religion but which natural science cannot deny because it cannot discover it. But this is not the Christian doctrine of miracles, as the tages con- , ., , nected with miracles attributed to Jesus and the apostles plainly giving up be- lief in nnrac- show. Besides, whfle we should gain, in that the dis- uious inter ventions. pute with scientists on the subject would cease, there would be several disadvantages connected with this modified view. For let us suppose that we could get on if we gave up the miracles of the New Testament, and admitted that miracles are not necessary to attest a divine revelatory authority, stiU Christian faith cannot get on without belief in miraculous interventions. This is not because we can see no evidence of God's connection with the world except in some unusual events ; for his handiwork is apparent every- where. But we need belief in present-day interventions for at least two very important reasons. First, any doctrine of providence which makes us a part of a chain of cause and effect from which we cannot be extri cated, and from the sins and sorrows of which God cannot redeem us by his intervention, leads to aU the consequences of fatalism. First disad- It represents God as having made the world so that we are van age' sinners by no fault of our own and yet as having given us consciences to torment us for our sins. This is an injustice which must caU forth 'Die Religion und der Darwinismus, p. 2. 2 Grundriss der Christlichen Apologetik, Gattingen, 1894, p. 29. 3Lehrbuch der Evangelisch-Protestantischen Dogmatik, Dritte bedeutend umgear- beitete Auflage, Braunschweig, 1893, pp. 324 ff. 200 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the resentment of aU who do not fear his further wrath. It would be impossible to love such a God. The same remarks would apply to our sorrows. Should it be repUed that we are in just as bad case with a God who can help but wfll not, we answer that in aU cases of sin God does help, and that if all ceased from sin there would be very Uttle sorrow, and the sorrow which remained would wear a new and less oppressive as pect. Further, that while God does not, in some instances, release us from sorrow, he does in others, and a moment's reflection wfll show any thoughtful person that if he is a father he may want us to bear some trials in order to bring out our greatest perfection of character. So that whfle we may sometimes murmur because we are caUed upon to pass through sorrow we may be sustained, under the Christian doc trine, by the sense of the combined wisdom and love of God, who knows what is best and loves us so much that he wfll not aflow any thing to effect our real harm which we do not, by our own fault, bring upon ourselves. Such a God we can love ; and a God so related to us we must love, unless our hearts are ingrate. On the other hand, let it be known that God has so made us and the world that he cannot help us and we cannot help ourselves, and we will not only be unable to love him but it would benumb all our better feelings and lead to inaction. Why strive, if with aU our striving we accomplish nothing ? If we are, through and through, automata, there is no ideal Ufe for us. What the whole mechanism provides for that part of itself which we are, we shaU become ; no more, no less. Thus we lose the sense of di vine companionship and the incentive to high endeavor. Any doc trine of providence, then, which is not to crush within us the most precious possession of life must aUow for interventions whenever God will. Second, any doctrine which makes answer to prayer impossible will sooner or later sflence prayer. That the privilege of prayer has been Second disad- misunderstood, and employed in the hope of securing aU vantage. manner of benefits which men ought to secure with out special interventions, is true. But this does not invaUdate the proper use of prayer nor the certainty of its answer. And while it is a fact that the older and the wiser we grow the less extensive is the range of those things in which we expect a divine intervention, yet is it also a fact that graduaUy we come to the assurance that God does answer, by direct agency, some of our petitions for earthly as well as for spiritual good. And those who think that God cares for our souls, but not for our bodies, forget that God created us with bodily as weU 1NECES8ITY OF MIRACLE TO KeLIGION. 201 as spiritual needs, and consequently that his providence must extend over the one as over the other. For the sake of true reUgion, there fore, we need answer to prayer. But if God cannot answer we must cease to pray ; for under such circumstances prayer would be mockery and self-delusion. This is true even of the so-caUed reflex influence of prayer, the value of which can scarcely be estimated. If it were beUeved that it is the only value which prayer has we should no longer pray. We secure the reflex influence of prayer only when the possibflity that God can intervene is left open. Without behef in providence and answer to prayer in the Christian sense there might be some kind of reUgion, but there could be no Christian reUgion. Hence Christianity feels that here is the very heart of the conflict between itseU and that science which is antichristian. We must therefore with aU care examine the affirmations of those scientists who deny the miraculous in the world's history. In substance they make three points : A There is no need of miracles. B. Miracles make science impossible. C. Miracles are impossible. 202 Foundations of the Christian .paith. CHAPTER IV. THE INADEQUACY OF THE MECHANICAL THEORY. The scientists referred to claim that the mechanical theory of the world is sufficient for the explanation of all phenomena, and that hence the intervention of a spiritual being is uncaUed for. In discuss ing materialism and pantheism or monism we saw the inadequacy of the mechanical theory so far as psychology and theology were con cerned. But there are also many facts, which Ue directly within the realm of science, which the mechanical theory whoUy fails to account for. It is generally agreed that, while the immediate causes of proc esses in the bodies of living plants and animals, when we can see them at all, are the same as those which we find operative everywhere, it is by no means possible to point out the bond that unites the quah ties of matter known to us and all the phenomena of life, as, for ex ample, growth and heredity.1 Now, one such confession shows as Mechanical we^ as one hundred that the mechanical theory is not e'tfua t eato sufficient for the explanation of phenomena known to sci- tfon6 o^phi^ ence. And whfle such a fact does not prove the necessity known" of the intervention of a spiritual being it certainly does science. strongly suggest it ; for to the human mind the power of wfll to help out the forces of physical nature is known. That without such help it is impossible to explain the phenomena of man's nature is argued by A. R. Wallace in his section on the Limits of Natural Selec tion as Applied to Man.2 It is true that he seems to think that the superior inteUigence which guided in the development of man is not the " one Supreme Intelligence," whose will or power gave origin to the universal laws and forces of nature, but some being or beings in termediate between God and man. But still he holds that natural selection is not sufficient for certain facts which he sums up as follows : "Briefly to resume my argument, I have shown that the brain of the lowest savages, and, as far as we yet know, of the prehistoric races, is little inferior in size to that of the highest types of man, and immensely superior to that of the higher animals ; while it is uni- 1 Comp. Strecker's Welt und Menschheit, p. 130. For a full discussion of the diffl- . enltles in the way of the mechanical theory, see Steude's Christenthum und Naturwis- iSenschaft, pp. 134 ff. ' Natural Selection and Tropical Nature, pp. 186-214. The Inadequacy of the Mechanical Theory. 203 versaUy admitted that quantity of brain is one of the most important, and probably the most essential, of the elements which determine mental power. Yet the mental requirements of savages, Summary o£ and the faculties actuaUy exercised by them, are very mVnf'Vy little above those of animals. The higher feelings of pure Wallace. morality and refined emotion, and the powers of abstract reasoning and ideal conception, are useless to them, are rarely if ever manifested, and have no important relations to their habits, wants, desires, or well-being. They possess a mental organ beyond their needs. Nat ural selection could only have endowed savage man with a brain a few degrees superior to that of an ape, whereas he actually possesses one very little inferior to that of a philosopher. "The soft, naked, sensitive skin of man, entirely free from that hairy covering which is so universal among other mammalia, cannot be explained on the theory of natural selection. The habits of savages show that they feel the want of this covering, which is most com pletely absent in man exactly where it is thickest in other animals. We have no reason whatever to beUeve that it would have been hurt ful, or even useless, to primitive man ; and, under these circumstances, its complete abolition, shown by its never reverting in mixed breeds, is a demonstration of the agency of some other power than the law of the survival of the fittest in the development of man from the lower animals. " Other characters show difficulties of a similar kind, though not, perhaps, in an equal degree. The structure of the human foot and hand seem unnecessarily perfect for the needs of savage man, in whom they are as completely and as humanly developed as in the highest races. The structure of the human larynx, giving the power of speech and of producing musical sounds, and especially its extreme development in the female sex, are shown to be beyond the needs of savages, and, from their known habits, impossible to have been ac quired either by sexual selection or by survival of the fittest. "The mind of man offers arguments in the same direction hardly less strong than those derived from his bodily structure. A number of his mental faculties have no relation to his fellow-men or to his ma terial progress. The power of conceiving eternity and infinity, and aU those purely abstract notions of form, number, and harmony which play so large a part in the life of civilized races, are entirely outside of the world of thought of the savage, and have no influence on his individual existence or on that of his tribe. They could not there fore, have been developed by any preservation of useful forms of 204 Foundations of the Christian Faith. thought, yet we find occasional traces of them amidst a low civiliza tion, and at a time when they could have had no practical effect on the success of the individual, the family, or the race; and the de velopment of a moral sense or conscience by similar means is equaUy inconceivable. " But, on the other hand, we find that every one of these character istics is necessary for the fuU development of human nature. The rapid progress of civilization under favorable conditions would not be possible were not the organ of the mind of man prepared in advance, fully developed as regards size, structure, and proportions, and only needing a few generations of use and habit to coordinate its complex functions. The naked and sensitive skin, by necessitating clothing and houses, would lead to the more rapid development of man's in ventive and constructive faculties, and, by leading to a more refined feeling of personal modesty, may have influenced to a considerable extent his moral nature. The erect form of man, by freeing the hands from aU locomotive uses, has been necessary for his inteUectual advancement, and the extreme perfection of his hands has alone ren dered possible that exceUence in the arts of civilization which raises him so far above the savage, and is perhaps but the forerunner of a higher intellectual advancement. The perfection of his vocal organs has first led to the formation of articulate speech and then to the de velopment of those exquisitely toned sounds which are only appre ciated by the higher races, and which are probably destined for more elevated uses and more refined enjoyment in a higher condition than we have yet attained to. So those faculties which enable us to tran scend time and space and to realize the wonderful conceptions of math ematics and philosophy, or which give us an intense yearning for abstract truth (all of which were occasionaUy manifested at such an early period of human history as to be far in advance of any of the few practical appUcations which have since grown out of them), are evidently essential to the perfect development of man as a spiritual being, but are utterly inconceivable as having been produced through the action of a law which looks only, and can look only, to the imme diate material welfare of the individual or the race. "The inference I would draw from this class of phenomena is that a superior intelligence has guided the development of man in a definite direction and for a special purpose, just as man guides the develop ment of many animal and vegetable forms. The laws of evolution alone would, perhaps, never have produced a grain so weU adapted to man's use as wheat and maize, such fruits as the seedless banana and The Inadequacy of the Mechanical Theory. 205 breadfruit, or such animals as the Guernsey milch cow or the Lon don dray horse. Yet these so closely resemble the unaided produc tions of nature that we may well imagine a being who had mastered the laws of development of organic forms through past ages refusing to beUeve that any new power had been concerned in their production, and scornfully rejecting the theory (as my theory will be rejected by many who agree with me on other points) that in these few cases a controlling inteUigence had directed the action of the laws of variation, multiplication, and survival, for his own purposes. We know, how ever, that this has been done, and we must therefore admit the pos sibility that, if we are not the highest intelligences in the universe, some higher intelUgence may have directed the process by which the human race was developed, by means of more subtle agencies than we are acquainted with. At the same time I must confess that this theory has the disadvantage of requiring the interference of some distinct in dividual intelUgence to aid in the production of what we can hardly avoid considering as the ultimate aim and outcome of all organized existence — inteUectual, ever-advancing, spiritual man. It therefore implies that the great laws which govern the material universe were insufficient for his production, unless we consider (as we may fairly do) that the controlling action of such higher inteUigences is a necessary part of those laws, just as the action of all surrounding or ganisms is one of the agencies in organic development. But even if my particular view should not be the true one the difficulties I have put forward remain, and, I think, prove that some more general and fundamental law underhes that of natural selection." 206 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER V. BREAKS IN THE PROGRESS OF MATERIAL DEVELOPMENT. Such an argument as that just quoted from WaUace is in pleasing contrast, in respect both of frankness and abflity, with the statement of Haeckel that the superiority of man to the animals is founded solely in the fortunate combination of the higher development of the larynx, of the brain, and of the extremities; and in his erect posture.1 Wallace regards these also as important to man, but he is not deceived by this fact, nor would he aUow others to be deceived into thinking that the cause of these advantages is thereby explained. Everybody knows that the advantages mentioned are so great as to practicaUy elevate man from the animal into a higher order of being. The ques tion, however, still remains, How did man come by these advantages ? Wallace has shown that by the law of selection, natural or sexual, these peculiarities of man find no explanation. That law worked up to a certain point, then came intervention ; when the intervening in teUigence, working by means unknown to us, had accomplished the differentiation of man from the lower animals, or from the animal next below him, then the law of natural selection began to apply again ; or at least we can see how by its appUcation man might de velop indefinitely. As Schurman says : 2 " Assuming, therefore, Dar winism to be true, I trust I may be permitted to observe that the President 0I"igm 0I species remains almost as much a mystery as the "survival ever- ¦ • • Organisms differentiating themselves continu- of the fittest. ous]y along particular lines for indefinite periods of time must, under the law of the survival of the fittest, infallibly give rise to new species. But pray observe that the survival of the fittest does not account for the arrival of the fittest. That self -evolving organism, on which the entire issue is dependent, is a miracle which no naturalist has as yet transmuted into science. . . . The question then arises by what agency those variations are originated, shaped, and continued so that they are capable of producing those specific forms which, under the sifting of natural selection, actually emerge. Darwin himself was not insensible to the heavy weight of this unexplained mystery. In a letter" to Huxley, written November 25, 1859, he expressed his per- 1 Generelle Morphologle, 1866, vol. U, p. 430. « Agnosticism and Religion, p. 17 f. Breaks in the Progress of Material Development. 207 plexity concisely and aptly, though somewhat profanely, in the fol lowing query : ' What the devil determines each particular variation ? What makes a tuft of feathers come on a cock's head, or moss on a moss rose ? ' " It is impossible for anyone to be insensible to the simplicity and beauty of the principle of a gradual differentiation of form and func tion and an equaUy gradual progress from homogeneity toward com plexity, and thus from the lower to the higher, assumed by science. We can understand that, once this theory has taken possession of the imagination, it is regarded as a rude disturbance of a dehghtful men tal state to suppose that anything can interrupt the steady on-going, even though that something be the power of God. And it is natural that scientists upon whom this idea has seized should prefer to think of God as having made the world capable of this infinite and steady progress. The difficulty is that the theory is demonstrably not in ac cord with the fact. In order to make the theory fit the facts it be comes necessary to ignore some facts and to invent others. For ex ample, Mr. Wallace, in an argument for Creation by Law, says : 1 " Now, this great mass of facts, of which a mere sketch has here been given, are fully accounted for by the ' Law of Variation ' as laid down at the commencement of this paper. Universal variabihty — smaU in amount, but in every direction, ever fluctuating about a mean condition until made to advance in a given direction by selection, natural or artificial — is the simple basis for the indefinite modification of the forms of hfe." Here Wallace overlooks the all-important fact that the variations employed by selection to give a definite direction to the forms of life are not accounted for. Well might Darwin ask what determines the particular variation. What WaUace caUs the simple Evolutionists basis for the indefinite modification of the forms of life is f|°orl'nvent just this tremendous fact of unaccountable variation, ac s" which seems subject to no law but the law of chance. Not only is the fact ignored ; it is first minified. Take away variability and intro duce the reign of universal law, and things would wear a different as pect in this world. So also other alleged facts have to be invented. For example, Haeckel claims that the species of ape to which man is traceable lived in the middle Tertiary period, and disappeared long ago. Out of this species was evolved the man-ape, or anthropoid, and out of them the ape-man, or the speechless man, the progenitor of true or speaking man.2 These two missing links, together with the species ' Natural Selection and Tropical Nature, p. 158. * Elfeld, Die Religion und der Darwinismus, p. 89. 208 Foundations of the Christian Faith. of apes out of which they were evolved, are supposed to have existed on a hypothetical continent between Madagascar and the Island of Sunda. This continent, to which Haeckel has even given a name, Lemuria, sank into the sea and carried with it aU these supposed men- apes and ape-men, so that we need hope for no discovery of them until the sea 3hall give up her dead, when progenitor and progeny shall have the joy of a happy reunion. Now, personally, we have not the slightest objection to being de veloped from or through apes, since it is universaUy agreed that we are not now apes, but men. But we do object to having speculations palmed off upon us as facts. Why should the fact that the missing links have not been discovered be ignored to such an extent as to make possible the invention of supposed facts to take the place of missing real ones ? Why substitute guesses for realities ? It is simply done in order that the beautiful imagination of an uninterrupted prog ress through the smallest possible variations, extended over an un limited period of time, may make unnecessary the reasonable hy pothesis of divine guidance and interest in the world. When we wake up to the real facts we are forced to believe that God never ceased his work upon creation, and that he is engaged upon it still. We agree with WaUace, that "a superior inteUigence has guided the development of man in a definite direction, and for a special purpose ; " which we interpret by the words : " So God created man in his own image, in the image of God created he him ; male and female created he them." No better iUustration of a break in the continuity of progress in nature can be found than the phenomenon of Ufe, the attempt to ex plain which has called forth such strenuous efforts among scientists. Nor have these efforts been altogether unrewarded. They have ehc ited many most interesting facts concerning the nature of Ufe ; and Life a break in have by so much tended to minimize its mystery. And ity* of°devei- ** *s w^tn no sense of triumph over the defeat of a rival opment. theory that we caU attention to the fact that, not withstanding all that has been discovered concerning life, the secret of its origin is stfll wrapped in impenetrable mystery. But, since scientists sometimes speak with such unbounded contempt of those who insist that there are breaks in nature, it may not be amiss to cite a few utterances from those who have a recognized high standing in the scientific world to show that theologians are not alone in claiming that a creator is needed to account for the phe nomena of life. Breaks in the Progress of Material Development. 209 Says Johannes Hanstein,1 speaking of the effort to discover the origin of life: "If the goal can ever be reached by human power it now lies heavily veiled in the incalculable distance." Count Saporta says : " " Instead of attempting, with certain natural philosophers, to find in the operation of purely mechanical forces the key to the secret, we rather confess our complete ignorance as to the origin of organic life." Lorenz Fischer goes stfll further : 3 "If organic life is the result of a special law of nature it can have its ground in the last analysis only in the absolute, the original source of aU finite, conditioned exist ence, as of all natural laws ; for no finite being can give to a thing what it did not from the beginning possess. This conclusion may be caUed mysticism, or God knows what else, but it does not change the facts, and no one can with right dispute the logical sequence from which it proceeds. Without the supposition of an absolute, creative being the final cause of life cannot be explained. . . . This postulate is demanded by logical thought and is contradicted by no fact of obser vation or natural science. " These citations are from Wfllkomm's work, already referred to, as we have not access to the originals. Wfllkomm himself says:4 "Every investigator who is not blinded by human pride must reach the conviction that life is of divine origin." And he declares that to deny his conviction of divine intervention, reached entirely apart from revelation, would be cowardly and unworthy of a man. Du Bois-Reymond admits " that the introduction of life may have been the result of a supernatural act, though he emphatically declares that it might result from a supernaturally imparted motion, and that but one such act could in any event be needed. Such men and such confessions are not to be laughed down, espe ciaUy when it is universally admitted that the origin of life is not ex plained. 6 Life is in itseU so great a variation from the ordinary course of events that we must regard it as a break in the continuity of the world order. The simplest form of life has the powers of assimilation of food, growth, and reproduction : and though life may be defined as the result of matter in motion under certain definite conditions, yet is this power not explained. For the question arises, How did these definite conditions come to exist ? If they arose in the natural course 1 Das Protoplasma als TrKger der pflanzliehen und thierischen Lebensvorrichten, 2. Auflage, Heidelberg, 1887, p. 312. 3 Die Pflanzenwelt vor dem Erscheinen des Menschen. Aus dem Franzosischen fiber- setzt von C. Vogt, Braunschweig, 1881. 3 Ueber das Prinzip der Organization und die Pflanzenseele, Mayence, 1883. * Ueber die Grenzen des Pflanzen-und Thierrelches, p. 31. 6 Vortrage, p. 88. 8 Herbert Spencer has recently said that " in its ultimate nature Life is incomprehensi- ble."-Nature, Oct. 20, 1898, p. 593. 210 Foundations of the Christian Faith. of progress how is it that not aU matter is Uving and possessed of the power to maintain and propagate life ? If the supposed definite con ditions were afforded at a distinct period in the cooling of our earth then all the matter on the earth's surface ought to be alive. Then our problem would be to account for dead matter. If it be said that but a portion of the material of the earth was in condition at any given period, still we must suppose other portions to have reached those con ditions later. If they did not, why did they not 1 Turn it whichever way we will, life is a variation from other phenomena so great as to demand a guiding intelligence which afforded the conditions of the variation at the proper time and place. l It might be legitimate to show that consciousness is a still greater break of continuity ; but we think few readers wfll be inclined to question this fact, so we forbear. These considerations wfll suffice to show that there is need for some thing besides the forces of nature, and that it is exceedingly probable that that something must be an intelUgent being. If there be any being capable of intervening God surely is capable ; for we can scarcely think of God as trusting so important a piece of his creation to any sub ordinate. Wallace's argument that the " grand law of continuity, the last outcome of modern science, which seems absolute throughout the realms of matter, force, and mind, so far as we can explore them, can not surely fail to be true beyond the narrow sphere of our vision, and leave an infinite chasm between man and the Great Mind of the uni verse,"2 is a good scientific argument in favor of the existence of what Christianity has maintained, namely, that there are "angels and archangels, spirits, and demons," but it does not lend any proba bility to the doctrine that these beings, intermediate between man and God, were the ones who ' ' guided the development of man in a definite direction, and for a special purpose." Why should Wallace attribute that guidance to them rather than to him ? Who guided their development ? Presumably each higher guided the development of the one just below. At last we shall come in that way to one whose development was guided by God him self. Was it the purpose of God that the one next below him should 1 Comp. H. W. Conn's The Living World, New York and London, 1891, pp. 46-51. Profes sor F. R. Japp, of Aberdeen, said at the session of the British Association for the Advance ment of Science held at Bristol, England, In September, 1898, " I see no escape from the conclusion that, at the moment when life first arose, a directive force came into play-a force of precisely the same character as that whieh enables the Intelligent operator, by the exercise of his will, to select one crystallized enantiomorph and reject its asymmetric opposite. "-Nature, September 8, 1898, p. 459, col. 1. 2 Natural Selection and Tropical Nature, p. 205, u. Breaks in the Progress of Material Development. 211 guide in the development of the being or order next lower, and so on down to the lowest ? If it were his purpose then why not attribute the work to him ? Is it beneath his dignity ? Surely it w „ , , „ „ „ , „ W di 1 1 a O c o is not less dignified to work than to plan work, except on {fte^ture oi the presuppositions and distinctions of mortals. And if * £nece ™5f^ God designed man and gave this supposed intelhgence, aevilorjment intermediate between God and man, power and authority exammed. to guide in his development, we still have divine interference, though intermediate rather than immediate. If God designed man we may as well add to that concession the truth revealed in Genesis which says that God made man (whether immediately or intermediately) in his own image. So that any clear understanding of WaUace's theory leads directly to divine interference in the affairs of the world as well as to denial of the sufficiency of the world mechanism. If, with our limited knowledge of the facts of nature, we can find so many things inexplicable on mechanical principles, and if the world grows more mysterious the more profoundly we strive to penetrate into its secrets, how can anyone deny that divine interference is necessary ? Nor are we driven by this thought to the conclusion that God must interfere because he could not make a machine capable of doing his will ; but rather are we led to feel that God would not exclude himself from his world, since man was to need his presence for purposes of communion, dependence, and the like. 212 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VI. SCIENCE AND THE MIRACLES OF THE NEW TESTAMENT. We turn to the assertion that miraculous interventions make science impossible. Says Elf eld : • "In fact, we could hardly speak of science if, instead of law, volition of a kind which cannot be prognosticated ruled ; if in the restless change of phenomena nothing fixed and abid ing existed to which the human mind could hold. Not fleeting phe nomena, but the laws which lie at their base form the object of scientific research. Were we to suppose that these laws were subject to change, or even to exceptions, we should thereby remove the foun dation from under the feet of science." This utterance fairly repre sents the general opinion of a certain class of scientists. The first thing to be said about it is that if the supposition of the intervention of a superior being in the phenomena of the universe makes science impossible, the denial of such a possibility makes reUgion impossible. The question would then arise, Which shah give way? The only proper answer to this question must result from a discussion of both science and religion on their merits. After such a discussion were ended opinion would remain divided, just as it is to-day. Another point to which attention needs to be caUed is that the interventions supposed by Christianity are not of the capricious kind indicated in Elfeld's language. But especiaUy is it necessary to state that the miracles of Christianity do not make science impossible, for the reason that they are not, as is often assumed, contrary to natural law, though they are variations from its ordinary operations. They do not require us to deny the exactness and uniformity of the operation of any force in the physical world, though they do require that these forces be manipulated by a Being who understands them far better than do we. In order that these assertions may be confirmed it wfll be necessary to examine the idea of miracle which the Scripture writers had. How did they conceive of miracle in its relation to natural law ? We shall The New Tes- confine ourselves to the New Testament, since its idea of tament Idea . of a miracle, miracle is the same as that of the Old. And one of the first things to be noticed is that in the New Testament the idea of miracle applies only to events in the physical world. For example, 1 Die Religion und der Darwlnlsmus, p. 1 f. Science and the Miracles of the New Testament. 213 the conversion of a soul is nowhere classed as a miracle. In other words, not all divine interventions in human affairs are thought of by the Scripture writers as miracles. Again, it is certain that these writers did not think of miracles as merely natural, though surprising events, adapted to excite astonishment because of their extraordinary character ; they did not think of these miracles as mere tricks or as results brought about by the superior knowledge possessed by Jesus as to methods of doing things. There was a dignity in the deeds he performed which forbids the former supposition, and the latter is ruled out by the fact that his miracles were the expression of love, power, and authority rather than of knowledge, though knowledge was necessary to them. Furthermore, these miracles were regarded as contrary to the ordinary course of events. Had the forces of nature acted in their usual way the sick would not suddenly have be come well, the blind able to see, the deaf to hear, the paralytic to rise up and walk. Again, these miracles were not regarded as the result (at least not in aU cases) of the power of one mind over another mind, and thus mediately over another's body. The healings at a distance, as of the servant of the centurion of Capernaum, and such miracles as the stilling of the storm and the cursing of the barren fig tree, in which instances the subject of the miraculous energy had no mind through which to work, clearly show this. Rather are these last-mentioned instances certain evidence that the New Testament writers attributed to Jesus a direct power over the forces of nature. " What manner of man is this, that even the winds and the sea obey him! " was the nat ural expression of their thought. The essence of their conception of miracle in relation to natural law may be summed up by saying that it exhibited a power or an authority to perform deeds which would not have occurred in the ordinary course of nature, but which that course would have prevented. In this sense of the word miracles are interruptions, or even viola tions, of the laws of nature. But this is not the significance attached to the term "law of nature" when objection is made to Do tne New its interruption or violation. Scientists know that the writers re- ordinary course of nature is not the universal course, f^ asmvk> The ordinary course of nature gives every human t£e '^ws of being a certain number of organs in a reasonably pro- nature? portionate state of development ; but sometimes nature produces a monstrosity. Scientists would not say that in such cases the laws of nature were interrupted or violated. By a law is not meant, then, a 16 214 Foundations of the Christian Faith. perfectly uniform production of results, but the uniform or constant operation of forces. It is a law of nature that on this earth the attrac tion of gravitation always draws bodies toward the center of the earth. It would be a violation or an interruption of that law if the attrac tion of gravitation should occasionaUy draw bodies away from the center of the earth, or should cease to draw them in the direction it does. Now, we assert that, whfle the Scripture writers regarded Jesus as having power over the forces of nature, they did not think of it as a power to unmake gravitation or cohesion, or the like. Menegoz ' and others claim that the IsraeUtes knew how to distinguish between that which corresponded to the laws of nature and that which did not, and that the difference between them and us, in this respect, is simply one of degree. Now, in the sense in which the scientist objects to the in terruption or violation of the laws of nature, there is no reason to be lieve that they knew anything of such laws in any scientific way. They knew that medical treatment might heal the sick, but they could only see divine authority in anyone who could heal without medicine. They knew that one who attempted to walk on the water would, ordinarily, sink. But they knew nothing of the distinction be tween denser and rarer, buoyant or nonbuoyant substances, nor of the nature of gravitation. Hence, to attribute to these writers a pur pose to say that Jesus walked on the water, thereby undoing all these distinctions and laws, is erroneous. The miracles were indeed more than wonders ; but there is no reason to beUeve that they were re garded as the results of a suspension or violation of the forces, but only as a suspension of the ordinary effects of the forces, of nature. Even, this is perhaps going too far ; for it is doubtful whether these writers had any conception corresponding to our idea of a natural force. But it may be said that, even though they did not have such a con ception of the miracles of Jesus, we who have had the advantages of modern education must think of them as having occurred, if they oc curred at aU, in connection with the overturning of those natural forces. If Jesus walked on the water gravitation must be supposed to have ceased to act except so far as it was necessary to hold him to the surface. Now, we need not, and indeed we should not attempt to define altogether the relation of miracle to natural law. AU such attempts lead to unnecessary discriminations as to the probable reality of certain miracles, or otherwise load down the faith in miracles with • La notion biblique du miracle, Paris, 1894, pp. 8 ft. Science and the Miracles of the New Testament. 215 burdens too heavy to be borne. For example, Beyschlag ' makes the attempt, and as a consequence accepts the historicity of the three rais ings from the dead recorded in the gospels and rejects Errors arising the miraculous character of the feeding of the multitudes tempt to de- in the wilderness. In the former he thinks he can see actiy the how Jesus might have raised the dead if they had not each mira- been so long dead as to have lost every spark of life, uraiiaw. But he cannot see how Jesus could have created bread ready baked or fish ready cured ; so he thinks it was not the five loaves and two fishes, but these together with what others in the company furnished, which sufficed to feed so great a multitude. Once we rid ourselves of the feeling that we need explain how a miracle was wrought, and judge of the reliability of a miracle story, not by the criterion of its supposed possibflity or impossibility, but by the historical evidence which it can offer, we shall be on the right road. It may be legitimate to reflect on the manner in which a given miracle was wrought, but it is not legit imate to explain a miracle away simply because we can think of no way in which it could have been wrought, nor even because it con tradicts the ordinary course of nature ; for aU miracles, as weU as aU human interventions, do that. But whfle it is true, as Row says,2 that "we know nothing re specting the modus operandi by which God works a miracle," yet we do know that none of the miracles recorded in the New Testament is there represented as being in violation of natural law, and that it is not necessary for us to assume such violations. There is no reason to suppose that when Jesus walked on the water the law of gravitation was suspended. It continued to operate, but some other law, we know not what, counteracted its ordinary effects. To this it may be ob jected that with the increase of the knowledge of nature Beiation of we might some time reach the point where the miracles of |$gre *J0W£ Christ could aU be explained on scientific grounds, and £™ $^£ then we should have to cease calUng them miracles. This aole- objection to the theory of miracles here maintained is based on the notion that, if the miracles be according to natural law to us unknown, they are not miracles at all. But this is to assume the very point under consideration. Besides, we are so far from such knowledge even now that if we suppose Christ to have had it we must in any event regard him, with Nicodemus, as a "Teacher sent from God." > Leben Jesu, Erster, untersuchender Theil, Drltte Auflage, Halle a. S„ JB93, pp. 296-331. » Manual of Christian Evidences, seventh edition, New York, p. 7. 216 Foundations of the Christian Faith. So that for some of the purposes of the historical miracles we should have, even so, aU that we want. But it must also be said that there is no likelihood of our ever attaining to a perfect knowledge of the laws of nature. There is now a recognized transcendent realm which we do not understand, and which most scientists think we can never understand ; and this realm is more likely with the progress of in vestigation to enlarge in our conception than to diminish. However, were we to suppose that some time our knowledge of na ture would be so comprehensive that the laws of the universe shaU aU be known to us, stfll the miracles according to law would not lose their miraculous character. For it is one thing to know the laws of nature and another to manipulate them. These laws are in a meas ure external to us, while with God they are native. They are expres sions of himself. So that even if we had equal knowledge he would have greater access, and hence could do by means of these laws what we could not do. There is another difference between God's relation to the laws of nature and ours : his knowledge is before, ours is after the fact. But if under such circumstances we can combine nature's forces in a manner different from nature's ordinary course, and thus produce artificial as distinguished from natural effects, how much more can God, who determined what these forces should be. For ex ample, we have reason to beUeve that the law of the refraction of light could be so manipulated, by a being who had perfect access to the powers of nature, as to produce the lengthening of the day in the case of Joshua and the return of the shadow on the dial in the case of Hezekiah. But, whether or not any other being has such access or ever used it, we know that we have no such access to powers of na ture which we nevertheless know to exist. Sometimes the emphasis is laid upon the existence of unknown or Alleged un- higher laws by which the miracles were performed. higher niaws There may or may not be such laws, and they may or toCwhiclh: may not De employed in the performance of miracles. might 'be But when the emphasis is placed here we are in danger per ormed. of iosulg the miracmous m answer to prayer by the fact that so far as they are unknown they may at any time be come known ; for they may lie inside the realm which is not tran scendent. Because they are unknown we know nothing about them and can make any supposition we please, but can gain nothing with those who are unwilling to take our suppositions for facts. As to the supposed higher laws, it is difficult for us to conceive of them. Are there two sets of laws by which this world could be Science and the Miracles of the New Testament. 217 governed? That the course of nature might have been different from what we find it had the forces of nature been differently com bined we can easily conceive. But that God has imposed certain forces upon the world different from, and lower than, those which he sometimes employs simply means that he sometimes acts according to one notion and sometimes according to another. If the laws of na ture are the expression of his will then the idea of a higher law, ex pressive of another and higher will, is a dangerous supposition. For we should then have to ask why this supposed higher law was not made the law of our world for constant instead of occasional use. Be sides, the supposition of a higher law by which miracles are wrought takes it for granted that miracles are suspensions of the laws of na ture. Hence it is better to think of miracles as performed by the employment of the laws of nature regardless of whether they are known or higher. The laws of nature must be accredited with suffi cient capabihty of combination to produce aU effects needful for any event which this world could possibly demand. We should say, there fore, not that miracles are performed by the use of unknown or higher laws, but by the unknown or higher use of laws imposed by God upon the world at creation. This would be analogous to what we our selves do when we combine the laws of nature so as to produce effects which nature, left to herself, would not produce. The main point, how ever, is that we must suppose God to have an access to and control over nature which we do not possess, as we have an access to and con trol over ourselves which others do not possess over us. Thus, without any violation of the laws of nature, we can see how God might perform works out of the ordinary course of events, such as men can never perform, and which are in the truest sense of the words divine works, or miracles. No miracle recorded in the New Testament demands for its explanation, so far as human eyes can see, any other forces than those found in nature, though these forces must have been employed or combined in an unusual way if they wrought the effects described. We cannot, indeed, divine the kind of combi nation of forces which should so change the ordinary course of nature as to produce bread already baked, or fish already cured, as must have been the case in the feeding of the multitude ; and hence there is a tendency on the part of many beUevers to pass lightly over such miracles as being most difficult to explain on natural principles ; while unbelievers emphasize them for the same reason. Both are wrong. While all miracles are explicable on natural principles none of them are explicable without the supposition of God to employ the natural 218 Foundations of the Christian Faith. forces. The miraculous does not consist in the conformity or non conformity to the usual natural order, but in the fact that, though in accordance with law, none but God could do it. Hence, unless we could prove that by no possible combination of the powers of nature could bread already baked or fish already cured be produced, we can not deny the possibility of such a miracle. Manifestly such a proof is not forthcoming. The conclusion of the whole discussion is that there is nothing in the New Testament idea of miracles to render science impossible.1 1 Professor Baden Powell labors under the common delusion that miracle is at variance with natural law. See Essays and Reviews, Edited by F. H. Hedge, Boston, 1861, p. 123. Laws of Nature and Divine Intervention:. 219 CHAPTER VII. LAWS OF NATURE AND DIVINE INTERVENTION. The immediately preceding considerations were not intended to exhibit the possibflity of miracles, but to show that if they are possible at aU they are possible without the violation or suspension of natural law. But, says the class of scientists now in our thought, such manip ulations of the forces of nature by a Superior Being are impossible. To this we answer that men, at least, have a power, within certain limits, of manipulating these forces, and that this power increases with the growth of our knowledge of nature. For some readers it may be useful to mention a few particulars in which man has exercised this power of manipulation, or intervention in the ordinary course of events. Chemistry is one of the sciences which are constantly concerned in such interventions. Nature's own combinations are dissolved, and the primary elements thus secured are sometimes preserved separate, sometimes employed in new combina tions unknown to nature, but useful in assisting nature in counteract ing some of her more baneful evils, or in the arts. Furthermore, man has such access to the laws of nature that he can control, within cer tain limits, the products of the vegetable and the animal world. Vege table foods, cereals, fruits, and flowers of a kind which Human anaio- unaided nature never would have produced are con- f \^se \^l stantly on our tables, or in our fields and gardens, as the ventl0ns- result of man's manipulation of natural law. Bacon said that if men would control nature they must obey her. And just in proportion as men know and obey her laws does she cease to be terrible and become helpful, lending herself pliantly to man's invention. Our domestic animals are a constant reminder of the power of man to do with natural forces what nature herself would never do. The same is true of every labor-saving implement and every machine or construction by which our way is made more easy or pleasant through this world. The steady Ught from the electric lamp, the steam which propels our railway trains, our systems of trolley cars, our telephones, our pho tography, and ten thousand other inventions, aU show that man does what nature would not do. Sometimes our interferences with the regular course of nature are helpful, as when soil otherwise barren is 220 Foundations of the Christian Faith. irrigated or enriched and made productive. Sometimes, as when by denuding our mountains or forest lands of their timber, we bring on, now droughts, now disastrous floods, these human interventions are harmful. But the facility with which nature can be diverted from her natural courses to man's wish is so remarkable as to suggest that God purposely left open the possibility of intervention. That it is left open is very sure, not only from what we see in the way of artificial products, but from the fact that the reign of the law itself, in the sense of regularity of order, does not seem to be universal. Some things appear to be left to chance, not in the sense that they are uncaused, but in the sense that they are not predetermined by the na ture of things or by the divine will in creation. The same laws and forces appear to rule in all the heavenly bodies throughout the uni verse ; from which we infer the unitary original cause of aU things. But, while the same law and the same course of nature appear wherever there is law or order, there appear to be realms where, while chaos is not present, there is no prognosticable order which nature will f oUow. Man has five fingers on each hand ; the number is definite, not con tingent ; but trees have branches in the greatest diversity of number and location. l Where the branches are placed and what form they assume are the result of the operation of many causes, but the variety of form, number, and position, in comparison with the regularity of the limbs of a human being, shows that the tree foUows no law (order) of development as minute as that which produces man. That is, there may enter into the production of a tree a greater variety of combina tions of causes than may be concerned in the production of a man. But that in the production even of men a variety of causes may combine is evident from the fact that not aU men are alike, probably no two are alike. Were the combinations.of causes in the production of men always the same, or, in other words, did law in the sense of exact uniformity reign everywhere, there could be no variety in human Lack of uni- appearance or in human minds. There is a certain irreg- certain de- ularity as weU as regularity in the combination of causes, partmentsof . ,. . , .,.,..„, nature. and. this leaves open the possibility of human determina tion of what those combinations of causes shall be. Enough of them are beyond our reach to prevent us from completely destroying creation; but enough of them are within our reach to make possible their employ ment in its modification. God's providence is not such as to exclude but such as to include man's participation in it. Hence it is that God in his 1 Andresen, Die Entwickelung der Menschen, p. 11. The following discussion was sug gested by Andresen's section on Gesetze und Zufall. Laws of JNature and Divine Intervention. 221 providence cannot always be held responsible for results. He has taken man into partnership with himself in the management of this world's affairs, and while God doeth all things weU man often fails. But this very fact, that man is a colaborer with God in the care of the world, makes it probable that God would have to interfere sometimes to undo the mischief wrought by us. And having left the world open to man's interference it is surely not closed to his own. There is law or prede termined method in every realm in the universe, but law in the sense of predetermined method does not prevail in aU events which take place in every realm. Were it otherwise man could not change the course of nature in any particular. The only way to escape from this conclusion is to suppose that human thought has absolutely no influ ence in what occurs about us, but that we are a part of a great machine which makes us do as we do and think as we think, a part of the gen eral result being that we seem to affect nature when in reaUty we do not; or, in other words, the whole result of this great machine of which we are a part includes our gross illusion of freedom and of influ ence on the world about us. None but the rankest of materialists would assert such a thing. Perhaps some one will say that man can do these things because he has a body by which he is brought into connection with the physical world, but that God, who is a spirit, has no such power over nature just because he is without body or parts. 1 This thought may be based on the doctrine of the conservation of energy, or on the idea that, while body can influence body, spirit cannot. In principle all this has already been traversed ; but as the matter presents itself here under new aspects we take it up for consideration once more. We call attention again to the fact that the doctrine of the conser vation of energy has not been demonstrated universal. Natural selec tion has its limits, and it is just possible that the law of conservation of energy has its limits. We do not know anything about that. But when that doctrine is urged as a proof that God cannot intervene in the affairs of his own creation we must demand that the universality of the law in question be proved. If this cannot be done within the physical realm, where it belongs, how can it doctrine of be proved to be true as between matter and spirit ? There vation of en- is far more probabiUty that we are deceived in thinking possibility of TV} 1VQ plf1 that the law of conservation of energy hinders the mind from influencing the body than in supposing that all the cases of such apparent influence are real. That appearances favor the opinion 1 Comp. Paulsen's Einleitung in die Philosophie, p. 184 ff. 222 Foundations of the Christian Faith. that mind can influence matter no one questions ; for however refined may be the substance of which our brains and nervous systems are composed that substance has all the attributes of matter. So that if our minds do influence our brains, and through them and the motor nerves the muscles of our bodies, then the law of conservation of energy does not hinder spiritual influences upon the material world. Now, the law of conservation of energy, if so construed as to exclude the influ ence of thought and volition, leads straight to the denial of mind, and thus to materialism. And in fact it is as easy to think that we have no spiritual nature as to think that, having such a nature, it can in no wise affect our conduct. But, if the conservation of energy is to be regarded as law for all being, then we ought in all consistency to admit that there is nothing in the universe but matter. We have seen that that form of monism which tends toward mate rialism does not aid us, for while it makes a great boast of finding spirit in everything it gives spirit nothing to do. In fact, monism must, if consistent, deny any function both to what we caU matter and to what we call spirit ; it must even deny the reaUty of both. They are phenomena of a something lying back of both matter and spirit. Thus, in consistent monism, we have phenomena caUed material and phenomena called mental, but no matter and no mind. These phe nomena, of both classes, are effects, not causes ; hence monism makes it impossible for mind to influence matter, and denies the existence of mind just as does materiaUsm. Both monism and materiaUsm make the explanation of the apparent action of mind upon matter impossi ble. There is absolutely no good reason for denying the reaUty of mind and matter. The desire to reduce all reality to the simplest pos sible form is no excuse for such nihilism. If there is any reason to suppose that phenomena have any reaUty behind them, then there is reason to hold that two classes of phenomena so whoUy diverse as the material and mental have two correspondingly diverse kinds of reality behind them. All the knowledge we have of metaphysical reality is deduction from phenomena. Of matter per se we know nothing, and of mind per se the same may be said. But the more energy is studied the more it seems as though it were primarily voli tional. And it is impossible to say, in view of these facts, that, as the result of the law of conservation of energy, mind cannot influ ence matter. If we turn to the other idea, that though we must admit that man's mind can and does influence his brain, and thus mediately even dead matter, God, because he is without body or parts, cannot influence Laws of .Nature and Divine Intervention. 223 matter, we find the argument in favor of it equally inconclusive. If spirit in the form of the human mind can influence matter Can an unem. (brain) the principle that mind and matter are not inac- affect1 Smatr cessible to each other is established, and spirit in the form ter ? of God can influence matter also. We may admit that the universe is not to God what our bodies are to our minds ; but the Christian and philosophic doctrine of the immanence of God makes the possible use or manipulation of the world by God analogous to our use or manipu lation of our bodies. We cannot tell how matter is able to act upon matter nor how mind is able to act upon matter, whether in man or beyond him. The mystery of interaction between being and being is unsolved. It is no greater when supposed to exist between God and the material world than when supposed to exist between the human mind and the human body. The fineness of the quality of the matter of the brain does not help us in the case of man, for, fine as it is, the brain is matter still. We see that somehow mind and brain in man interact; but the "how" we cannot comprehend. Until we know more of the relation of God to the world than we do now we cannot say that there is not something in the world which corresponds to the brain in man. Perhaps it is the ether. This is a guess ; but here aU is guesswork. The one thing which remains sure to all but rank mate riaUsts is that somehow mind and matter can influence each other. The intervention of spirit in the physical world is a fact the denial of which introduces the direst confusion into our thinking. If the his torical evidence in favor of such interventions is as good as that in favor of other alleged facts there is as much reason for belief in the one case as in the other. Whether the historical evidence is of such a character we shaU see. Throughout our discussion of the closely related antichristian phil osophical and scientific positions we have made one great concession to our opponents, for the sake of argument, namely, that the theory of realism is true. Before we leave this branch of our study we think it proper to say that the concession made for the sake of argument does not represent our real opinion. Because of its appropriateness as a conclusion of the discussion which has been carried on at such length, and because it weU sums up our own views, we quote from Bowne's Metaphysics the foUowing forceful words:1 "AUowing the world to be in itself a fact of some kind, two views are possible con- 1 Metaphysics, pp. 459 ff. See also his Theory of Thoughtand Knowledge, part ii, chap. 3. 224 FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. cerning its nature. The realist's position is this : The system of the world is a complex of substantial things which are endowed with vari- Prof. Bowne's ous forces, and which are the real and constant factor in criticism of „ , , ,, . , , „ realism. the changes of phenomena. As such they exist apart from any thought, and when we perceive them we add nothing, but recog nize what they are. This is the view of common sense, and, if analy sis detected no difficulties and inconsistencies in it, it must be allowed to stand. The idealist, on the other hand, thinks as follows : We think under the law of substance and attribute, or of thing and quality. Both thought and language are impossible without nouns as the inde pendent base of the sentence. Accordingly, we tend to give a sub stantive form to every object of thought. So we speak of gravitation, electricity, magnetism, etc., as agents or things ; and it is not until we reflect that we perceive that they are forms of agency only. Indeed, every constant phenomenon tends to be viewed as a thing. Now, the world owes its substantial existence entirely to this tendency. This substantive character is merely the form under which certain objec tive activities of the infinite appear to us. The idealist, then, proposes to replace the nouns of realism by certain constant forms of activity on the part of the infinite. Change in things he views as a change in these forms. Progress he views as a higher form of this activity. There are no fixed points of being in the material world ; but every where there are law and order. The continuity of the system ex presses simply the constancy of the divine action. The uniformity of the system expresses the steadiness of the divine purpose. In short, the world, considered in itself, is an order of divine energizing, which, when viewed under the forms of space and time, of causaUty and sub stance, appears as a world of things. In distinction from subjective idealism this view may be called objective idealism. The former does not allow the world to be an objective fact, but only a series of presen tations in us ; the latter allows it to be an objective fact, but holds that it cannot exist as it appears apart from mind. " The realistic view is, of course, more harmonious with spontane ous thought than the idealistic view, but it properly has no advantage, except for the imagination. It is more easily pictured than idealism, but both views are equally compatible with phenomena and with objec tive science. We have seen that even subjective idealism is compat ible with science, so far as the latter deals with phenomena and eschews metaphysics, while objective idealism allows all the facts even of scientific metaphysics to stand, and seeks only to go deeper. It allows the atom and its laws, and suggests only that the atom, though the Laws of Nature and Divine Intervention. 225 basis of physical science, may itself be phenomenal of some basal fact. Thus all the principles of physical science remain undisturbed, although they may be referred to something behind them and which is the reaUty in them. But, even if the principles of objective science were disturbed, it would not allow that idealism is false, for there is no warrant for making the possibility of physics the final test of truth. The imagination will find more assurance of the uniformity of nature in the hard reality of the physical elements than in the purpose and nature of the infinite ; but, in any case, this is a fancy. We have seen that the finite, of whatever kind, comes into existence, and remains there, only because of the demands of the system. This is as true of the material elements as of anything else. Hence, we have no ontological assurance of the uniformity of nature in any respect. For aU that we know the most unimaginable revolution may take place at any moment and in the most unimaginable way. For knowledge on this point we must have either a revelation from the infinite or a perfect intuition of its nature and tendency. Hence the uniformity of nature can never have any foundation better than the constancy of the purpose and nature of the infinite." 226 Foundations of the Christian Faith. division ni. CHRISTIANITY AND MODERN HISTORICAL SCIENCE. Although so much space has been given to the conflict of Chris tianity with phflosophy and science it would be a great mistake to assume that the weapons of warfare employed by the enemies of our faith are exclusively or even chiefly drawn from the sources already considered. In history, as understood in modern times, we have a science as exacting in its demands for proof as the science of physical nature. This science is rising into favor, and soon this country wfll have its criticaUy trained historians in large numbers who will be im bued with the new ideas and who wfll, at least in some cases, prob ably take sides against us. The apologist needs to know, therefore, the principles of historical science and to be able to estimate their truth or error and to employ or combat them. In a work like this, however, these principles must be tested in connection with concrete instances or phases of their use in opposition to the Christian system. Of these there are three, relating, first, to the miracles ; second, to the biblical record ; and, third, to Christianity as a civilizing force. SECTION I.-THE OPPOSITION TO MIRACLES. CHAPTER I. MODERN EXCLUSION OF THE SUPERNATURAL FROM HISTORY. Our examination of the arguments against miracle drawn from phflosophy and natural science have led us to the conclusion that they are absolutely without force. There is nothing revealed by phfloso phy with reference to the relation of God to the world which forbids miracles, and there is nothing revealed by natural science relative to the laws of nature which casts doubt upon the possibflity of miracles. Hence, when the fact of miracle is asserted, the historian cannot Denial of mir- aUow any prejudices of phflosophy or natural science to em rXstori- binder his belief ; it becomes to him solely a question of evidence. And this is the exact position of at least some who assume to be scientific historians. Hume, ' for example, admits the 1 Philosophical Works, vol. Iv, p. 146 f. Exclusion of the Supernatural from History. 227 possibflity of miracle, though he denies that anymiracles have ever been proved to be facts. Ernest Renan does the same, even more explicitly. He says:* "We do not say 'Miracle is impossible;' we say, 'There has been hitherto no miracle proved.' " After carefully discussing the conditions under which we could beUeve that a miracle has been per formed he declares that these conditions have never been fulfiUed, and adds,3 " Tfll we have new Ught we shaU maintain, therefore, this principle of historical criticism, "that a supernatural revelation cannot be accepted as such." David Friedrich Strauss says:3 "Indeed, no just notion of the true nature of history is possible without a percep tion of the inviolabiUty of the chain of finite causes and of the impos sibility of miracles." Strauss has here very succinctly put the reason why the historian feels himself bound to reject aU miraculous events ; it is because of his belief in the inviolabiUty of the chain of finite causes. As some scientists refuse to beUeve in the intervention of God in the physical world, but insist that nature, by slow degrees and in the course of long-extended periods, evolves all that is ; so in human history some historians fail to see anything but the development of man as he is bound up with physical nature, which sometimes hinders and sometimes helps him. The existence of God is not necessarily denied, but there is nothing for him to do, and he does nothing. Here it is sufficient to point out the atheistic character of all such historical interpretation. The extreme unwiflingness to believe any miraculous event arises in a considerable measure from this atheistic philosophy of history. Nevertheless, those who demand such stringent proof of the occur rence of miracles must not be too severely condemned. They may be atheistic, but they furnish a wholesome check to the unbounded cre- duUty and superstition which many professed Christians seem to regard as an essential part of their faith ; who, because they are persuaded that God can work miracles, are ready to beUeve almost any miracle story related to them. It is one thing to believe that God can give men miraculous aid, and that he has done so at times ; it is another to beUeve that he does so on aU occasions. It ought to be a part of the duty of aU Christians to rescue the miracles of the New Testament from the disgraceful associations in which credulous or designing men have placed them. And perhaps Hume was sincere when he said that his method of reasoning might possibly serve to confound the danger- 1 The Life of Jesus, translated from the Original French by C E. Wilbour. New York, 1886, p. 44. » Ibid., p. 45. » The Life of Jesus Critically Examined, translated from the Fourth German Edition by Marian Evans, New York, 1860, vol. i, p. 55. 228 Foundations of the Christian Faith. ous friends or disguised enemies of the Christian religion." l For that there is an element of superstition in most men is evident ; and when- The excessive ever this is given over to a credulous mind one miracle credulity of many reia- becomes as probable as another, and the miracles of the tive to mir- ... acies. New Testament lose all dignity and value m the eyes of thinking men. Hence it becomes us to put a reasonable restraint upon our tendency to accept alleged miraculous events as realities, rejecting such as appear ill founded and accepting only such as have good evi dence in their favor. The same considerations should prompt us to hear all the difficulties which experts in historical evidence offer against miracles, and to weigh them with candor and impartiaUty of mind. And in giving them this careful consideration it wfll be weU to take up here the more general difficulties which students of history feel, reserving for later treatment the specific difficulties connected with the miracles of the New Testament. We have tried to distin guish these general difficulties and shaU attempt to treat each sepa rately. The first and chief difficulty consists in the aUeged insufficiency of any evidence to establish the fact of a miracle. This is summed up by Hume" as foUows : "No testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle unless the testimony be of such a kind that its falsehood would be more miraculous than the fact which it endeavors to estab lish." It is natural to inquire why such rigorous proof is demanded. Chief difficulty The answer to this query is found also in Hume in relates to evi- .,-,.. dence.Hume's the following words : 3 A miracle is a violation of statement criticised. the laws of nature ; and, as a firm and unalterable ex perience has estabhshed these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is as entire as any argument from expe rience can possibly be imagined." We confess ourselves at a loss to know just what kind of an experience a firm experience is, though perhaps an experience weU established as to its reaUty is meant. We cannot but feel, also, that the word unalterable is faulty in this connection, for though the experience is one which has continued during a considerable length of time it is certainly a presumption to say that it will continue forever. It is, in fact, a begging of the ques tion, for whether the experience of uniformity is unalterable is just the point at issue. Besides, no experience, however uniform, can es tablish a law of nature, except in the sense of that very uniformity itself. What we experience, in other words, is uniformity, and this experience is one of which we have no doubt (or, as Hume would say, • Philosophical Works, vol. iv, p. 149. » Ibid., p. 131. s ibid,, p- m Exclusion of the Supernatural from History. 229 it is firm), and, while we cannot say that it is unalterable, we can say that, so far as it has reached, it is unaltered — it has been invariable. Fire always burns ; ice melts when the thermometer registers a given degree of warmth ; lead sinks and cork floats in water. We should need good evidence to assure us that fire ceased to consume fuel with which it came in contact, ice to melt at a surrounding temperature of thirty-three degrees Fahrenheit maintained for a considerable length of time, and the like. And even if we were sure that any of these things had occurred we should require proof that there was not some natural explanation — that is, that something in the ordinary processes of nature, or introduced into them by man, did not bring it about. For example, we might admit that the wood and the fire came into contact for a sufficient length of time to produce combus tion under ordinary circumstances, but we should be quite certain that, either by excessive moisture or hardness, or by chemical treat ment, the wood had been rendered incombustible. So much the uniformity of experience in these things would require. Did we think otherwise aU action would be rendered uncertain. The farmer could have no expectation of a crop, or of any particular kind of a crop, as the result of the planting of the seed and of aU his husbandry ; the engineer could not trust his steam, nor the navigator the resistance of the water which is necessary for the proper effect of the wheel in propelling the ship, if our experiences in these respects were not uniform. But do not all these illustrations and as many more as we might add show that what we have faith in is this uni formity of nature when left to itself ? In this respect the argument from experience is indeed as strong as can possibly be imagined, not withstanding the fact that we have not experienced all the methods of nature. We can scarcely think of evidence strong enough to con vince us that at any time or place, of its own accord, and as a result of an inherent possibflity of its seU-suspension, gravitation ceased to act in its usual way. But if the witness said that what he saw or was assured of was not the suspension of the law of gravitation by its own failure to act, but the balancing of some other force against gravita tion so that it did not produce its usual effect, we should at once be lieve that it was entirely possible, and, if he were discerning and truthful, entirely probable. Uniform experience leads us to beUeve against aU testimony that the forces of nature, if left to themselves, never change their effects ; but a reasonably wide experience has also led men to believe that there are ways by which any of the forces of nature can be balanced or neutralized in their effects by other forces. Foundations of the Christian Faith. This last belief grows stronger as men become more thoroughly ac quainted with nature, and it has practicaUy led mankind to the feel ing that there is no predicting what men can or cannot do in the manipulation of the forces of the world. Laws of nature certainly do not change themselves ; this it may be said that experience teaches us. And it may be that God has never changed them ; so we beUeve. But the proof from experience goes no further. As we have seen, it is not according to the New Testament to say that a miracle is a violation of the laws of nature. For such a miracle no proof yet given could suffice. But for miracles which are wrought by the combination in new ways of nature's laws or forces good testimony would suffice. We have come to expect such interventions on the part of man. Tes- Testimony suf- timony might lead us to believe that God had manipu- tabiish10 the" lated the forces of the world, or, in other words, miracu- me™tTmir£ lously intervened in away forever impossible to man. posSsibifhtbe Says Hume : ' "It is a miracle that a dead man should come to life, because that has never been observed in any age or country." Very true; it would be impossible to beUeve that one who came to life was ever dead. But it is quite another thing to believe that God could not bring a dead man to Ufe. That we cannot believe ; otherwise we should say that miracles are impossible. The point is, Can any testimony show that he ever did bring a dead man to life ? We assert that such evidence is possible and that it exists, and that only an atheistic construction of history can deny it. Jesus And such tes- Christ is the standing proof that God has interfered in the furnished by affairs of this world." This is felt by the deniers of mira- jesusChrist. ^ g^ nence t^gy strive to explain the miracles he per formed as ordinary events, or the accounts of them as misunderstand ings, misrepresentations, or the like, or else they attempt to make Christ out a deceiver or deceived. The difficulty with the former method is that Jesus undoubtedly thought that he was working miracles. Hence the latter method only is left open. Let us examine it in at least some of its aspects. 1 Philosophical Works, vol. Iv, p. 130. 2 The reader who will attentively consider what we adduce in reference to Jesus as the chief witness to the fact of miracle will see that the difficulties of Professor Baden Powell are overcome. See Essays and Reviews, edited by F. H. Hedge, Boston, 1861, pp. 119-122. Similarly our argument meets the fact of which some have made so much, namely, that the Bible gives us to understand that miracles have been wrought in the interest of false hood. Comp. Supernatural Religion: An Inquiry into the Reality of Divine Revelation, in three volumes, complete edition, London, 1879, vol. i, pp. 11-13. It is not a question what Satanic agency can accomplish, but of whether Jesus is to be credited when he claims to work miracles by divine agency. Thaumaturgic Element in the Miracles of Christ. 231 CHAPTER II. THE ALLEGED THAUMATURGIC ELEMENT IN THE MIRACLES OF CHRIST. Several deniers of real miracle affirm the thaumaturgic element in the reported miracles of Christ. Says Wellhausen : " "If Jesus per formed signs and wonders it is plain from his own utterances that he laid no stress upon them. In the first three gospels he appears as a thaumaturgist, though it is not his purpose to be such." Essentially the same view of at least some of the works of Jesus is taken by Renan, only he regards Jesus as consciously a thaumaturgist, though perhaps contrary to his own will." He speaks of the miracles of healing which Jesus "thought he performed,"3 and says: "Many circumstances, moreover, seem to indicate that Jesus was a thaumatur- Wellhausen, Renan, and gist only at a late period and against his wfll." 4 Strauss Strauss. also seems to think that Jesus was under a sort of necessity of meet ing the expectations of the people concerning the miraculous works of the Messiah, as which he had given himseU out,' though he regards the miracle stories as mythical rather than as accounts of the deeds of a wonder-worker. That thaumaturgy, in the sense of mere wonder-working, is attrib uted to him by Renan and others, is evident from all they say about it. This is implied by Wellhausen when he asserts that Jesus surely did not wish to appear as a thaumaturgist, and by Renan throughout his entire discussion of the subject. We have in aU this two things : First, that Jesus did not wish to work wonders, but was forced to do so by circumstances, partly of his own creation; second, that his miracles were in reality nothing but wonders. Says Renan -." " As to miracles, they were considered, at that time, the indispensable mark of the divine and the sign of the prophetic calling. The legends of Elijah and Elisha were f uU of them. It was the received opinion that the Messiah would perform many. . . . Jesus had therefore to choose between these two alternatives, either to renounce his mission, or to become a wonder-worker." " It is impossible . . . to distinguish the miracles which have been attributed to Jesus by popular opinion from 1 Israelitische und Jttdische Geschichte, Zweite Ausgabe, Berlin, 1895, p. 351. 8 The Life of Jesus, pp. 231, 235, 236. 3 Ibid., p. 232. < Ibid., p. 235. B The Life of Jesus, vol. il, p. 452. 8 The Life of Jesus, p. 230. 232 Foundations of the Christian Faith. those in which he consented to take an active part." 1 " Oftentimes he performed his miracles, not until after solicitation, with a manifest dis inclination, and while reproaching those who asked them for the gross- ness of their understanding. A singularity, apparently inexpUcable, is the care he takes to do his miracles privately, and the injunction which he gives to those whom he heals to tell it to no man." 3 " One would say, at times, that the part of a thaumaturgist is disagreeable to him. . . . We are, then, permitted to believe that his reputation as a miracle-worker was imposed upon him, that he did not resist it very much, but that he did nothing to aid it, and that at aU events he felt the emptiness of pubhc opinion in this regard." 3 These are remarkable statements for one to make who insists on strict adherence to the principles of historical criticism ; for in mak ing them the main principle he has foUowed is the unscientific one of falsifying the record. This he has done in several very important particulars. First, in all that he says or impUes with reference to the disinclination of Christ to perform miracles. Every passage he cites in favor of that idea has to be misinterpreted in order to make it sig nify any such disinclination.4 The first two passages show no disin- Renan's falsi- clination, but note a positive refusal to give a sign. Had record. they come to him with one in affliction he would have ex erted his power ; but when all they wanted was a sign, to gratify their curiosity or to help them in their pretended desire to beUeve on him. he felt no disinclination ; he simply refused. The fourth rebukes the hearers for thinking that he could not or would not provide food mi raculously if it were needful. The third, fifth, and sixth rebuke his disciples for the want of faith which hindered them from performing a miracle requested of them. There is a considerable array of pas sages, but they refer to but three facts, and none of them supports in the slightest degree the aUeged disinclination to work miracles. True it is that he oftentimes did not perform his miracles until after solicitation ; but it is a perversion to make this fact prove an unwill ingness to perform miracles. Renan has conveniently forgotten the fact that Jesus sometimes sought opportunities to perform his miracu lous works, and that he performed them when the influential portion of the witnesses found serious fault with him for his acts. Had he been disinclined to work miracles there were many he need not have performed; but as he would not aUow the hypocritical scribes and 1 The Life of Jesus, p. 232. • Ibid., p. 235. » Ibid., p. 236. 4 The passages are Matt, xii, 39; xvl,4; xvii, 16; Mark viii, 17, seq. ; ix,18; Luke Ix, 41. See the Life of Jesus, p. 235. Thaumaturgic Element in the Miracles of Christ. 233 Pharisees to reduce him to a thaumaturgist, who worked wonders simply to gratify the whims of men and to increase his power over them, so he would not allow them to deter him from performing mir acles of mercy when opportunity offered, even though they had time- honored custom on their side. Second, he has falsified the record in speaking of Jesus as a thau maturgist. He evidently feels this, for he tries to smooth it over by saying that "A mere sorcerer, after the manner of Simon the ma gician, could not have brought about a moral revolution like that which Jesus accomplished. If the miracle-worker had effaced in Jesus the moral and reUgious reformer there would have sprung from him a school of magic, and not Christianity." Also by saying, " Almost down to our day the men who have done most for the good of their kind (the exceUent Vincent de Paul himseUI) have been, whether they wished it or not, thaumaturgists." These are amazing assertions. The last one of them is absolutely false, even in the re ligious world. As to the first one, it implies that there was a com plete divorce between the thaumaturgic element in the The proof that Ufe of Jesus — the unwelcome element, tolerated from ne- notSa Sthau- cessity, imposed upon him— and the moral and religious matul'Sist- reform element, which was that of his own choice. Now, the record can be accounted for only on the supposition that those who wrote it saw in these miracles a part of his moral and religious work. They saw in it no trace of thaumaturgy, sorcery, magic. Had there been any thought of that we should have had as a result of his life both Christianity and a school of magic. These two tendencies would have gone out from him inevitably ; for evidently the works he did made as profound an impression as his words upon those who knew him. But, on the contrary, we have one Jesus, revealed to us in his words and works, harmonious with himself, and producing Christianity only and not a school of magic also. There were thaumaturgists in those days, and they had their followers who were thaumaturgists. That Jesus did not become the founder of a school of thaumaturgy shows that he made upon those who saw his works an impression different from that of the sorcerers of his day. In the gospel of John ¦ we have Jesus reported as saying, "If I had not done among them the works which none other man did, they had not had sin." If our critics will aUow that Jesus uttered these words they will have to admit that he did not think of his works as on a level with those of the thaumaturgists of the time. 1 Chap, xv, 24. 234 Foundations of the Christian Faith. If they refuse the words to Christ, still they must admit that they express the opinion of the Christians of the first century. Hence it is evident that to call Jesus a thaumaturgist is to do violence to the records. But, further, Jesus is reported as claiming that his miracles are not magic, but the result of his union with the Father. The power to heal the sick was also the power to forgive sins.1 The result of his works was that men glorified God. Jesus rebuked the cities wherein most of his mighty works were done because they repented not.3 Had Jesus been an unwilling worker of miracles, or a thaumaturgist, aU such language would have been impossible. Plainly we are obliged by the record to think of Jesus as having wrought his works as the natural result of what he was and of his mission to men ; as the sent of the Father. Third, he falsifies the records in making Jesus enter upon his career as a "wonder-worker" in order to maintain his standing as the Messiah in the eyes of the public. This is to ascribe to Jesus a taint of dishonesty wholly foreign to his character as portrayed in the Renan's the- gospels and epistles of the New Testament. Further, it jeysusadfs- ascribes to him a lack of faith in his mission; for if he had been clear as to his divine commission for the work he had undertaken to do he must have been inwardly sure that, whatever fate befell him, he must succeed without the adventitious aid of works adapted to meet the expectations of the people concern ing the Messiah. Again, had this been his motive he would never have crossed the wishes of the ruling classes by refusing signs when asked for, or by heaUng at times and under circumstances displeasing to them. Besides, throughout the records the impression is left that Jesus wrought his miracles, not because of the reputation they would give him, but for the benefit they would confer upon the subjects and witnesses of them. They were designed to bring healing to the bodies and repentance into the hearts of men. Had his motive been to make the general public accept his Messianic claims he would never have forbidden one who had been healed to publish it abroad. The records teach us that he went about doing good ; that he was moved with compassion ; not that he was seeking to estabUsh a Messianic claim by catering to public expectation. He did expect men to believe on him for his works' sake ; but that is a very different thing from doing them in order to produce belief. He wrought his miracles be cause they were within his power, and because they were part of his mission ; not in order to attest his mission. i Mark II, 1-12. » Matt, xl, 20 and reft. Attempted Degradation of the Miracles of Jesus. 235 CHAPTER III. renan's attempted degradation of the miracles OF JESUS. Renan has sacrificed the character of Jesus to a desire to rid Christianity of the miraculous element. He appears to have labored under the monstrous delusion that if he could make Christ appear as an unwilling thaumaturgist, not as a sincere believer in his pos session of divine power, he could the better recommend The delusion him to the educated classes of to-day. This presupposes of Kenan- that the educated classes would have more respect for one who knew miracles to be impossible, but who wrought works by the methods known to magic, than they would for one who honestly but igno rantly believed in the possibflity of miracles. It is very difficult to make out what Renan was trying to accompUsh, but his perpetual effort to make it appear that Jesus performed his wonders only because he could not do otherwise leaves the impression that the great French romancer wished to screen our Lord from the scorn of the modern world. At any rate he has made him out a de ceiver, though for a noble purpose, weakly yielding to the force of circuinstances. When the strict demands of Jesus for frankness in speech and con duct are considered Renan's view of the motives of Jesus becomes incredible unless we are wflling to think of the professed Messiah as wicked to the heart's core. In the gospels Jesus is represented as condemning any acts of reUgion or mercy performed for the purpose of raising their performers in the estimation of men. AU acts done for such purposes he regarded as essentiaUy hypocritical. Yet Renan does not hesitate to represent this same Jesus as performing his wonders to elevate himself in the eyes of his contemporaries. In the gospels Jesus is represented as recommending the doing of aU good deeds with sole reference to the all-seeing eye of God, whom men were to trust for the reward. In the work of Renan he is affirmed to have taken his reputation into his own hands, thus violating the principle he taught to others. In order to make Jesus out thus doubly hypocritical Renan has had to warp the plain meaning of many individual passages, and generally to falsify the record. Yet he has done all this under the pretense of strict adherence to the principle of 236' Foundations of the Christian Faith. historical criticism— which demands, he teUs us, the rejection of aU Renan's un- supernatural relations — and in the performance of his nistoriC3rl m _ , procedure, duty as an historian, which he asserts to be to in terpret" every supernatural relation and to seek "what portion of truth and what portion of error it may contain." ' Had Renan given out his theory of the miracles of Jesus as purely theory it could be treated with less severity. But foisting it upon the pubUc as he did in the name of historical science it cannot be too severely condemned. It is indeed the business of the historian to seek what portion of truth and what portion of error any relation, whether supernatural or not, may contain. And he has no right to give out as fact anything not fairly deducible from the records to which he has access. Renan has not contented himself with this. simple business of the historian; he has gone beyond, and by mis interpretations of words and deeds of Jesus has read into the records what is not there — in order to read out again as historical fact what he had read in. It is one of the most shameful proceedings known to historical criticism. As an historian he was not obhged to furnish a theory for the explanation of the miracle ; he would have fulfilled aU the historian's duties had he declared it impossible for him to accept the miracles and asserted his inabflity to find any adequate explanation of the facts connected with the record of them. Any thing beyond that was a violation, not a fulfillment, of the duties of the historian. But Renan was not content to degrade the character of Christ, he degraded his work also. He says :' " The four narratives of the Ufe His degrada- or Jesus are unanimous in vaunting his miracles. One character of them, Mark, the interpreter of the apostle Peter, wor k s 'of insists so strongly upon this point that, if the character of Christ were traced exclusively according to his gospel, he would be represented as an exorcist in possession of charms of rare efficacy ; as a very powerful sorcerer who inspires terror, and of whom men are glad to be rid." * An examination of the references to Mark as given in Renan's note shows that six different matters are there mentioned : 1. The stilling of the storm, with the fear of the disciples ; 2. The casting out of the legion of devils, which were per mitted to enter a herd of swine and lead them to their destruction, ' The Life of Jesus, p. 45. " Ibid., p. 237. a We copy his entire note to this remarkable statement: " Mark iv, 40; v, 15, 17, S3, 36; vl, 50 ; X, 32. Comp. Matt, vlll, 27, 34 ; ix, 8 ; xiv, 27 ; xvii, 6-7 ; xxviii, 5, 10 ; Luke iv, 36 ; V, 17 j vlll, 25, 35, 37 ; lx, 34. The Apocryphal Gospel, called that of Thomas the Israelite, carries this character to the most shocking absurdity. Comp. the Miracles of Infancy, in Thilo, Cod. Apocr., N. Y., p. ex, note," Attempted Degradation of the Miracles of Jesus. 237 with the earnest desire of the Gadarenes to get rid of Jesus; 3. The healing of the woman with an issue of blood, who feared, trembled, and told Jesus all; 4. The raising from the dead of the ruler's daughter; 5. The walk upon the sea, and the fear of the disciples before they knew him ; and, 6. The last journey to Jerusalem, Jesus going before— the disciples being afraid. These are the passages which are to prove that the Gospel of Mark represents Christ (1) as an "exorcist" in possession of rare "charms;" (2) as a powerful "sorcerer who inspires terror, and of whom men are glad to be rid." Pray, where does Mark say anything about "exorcism" or "charms" or "sorcery?" Only one who had determined that there is no such thing as historically attested miracle, and who felt it his duty as an historian to read into a record what it did not contain, could write as Renan has written on this matter. Mark does not hint at exorcism, or charms, or sorcery, but wherever he His estimate assigns or hints at any cause for the works which Jesus of the record bv Murk performed he leaves us in no doubt that they were wrought by the power of God in Christ. Nor is there anything in Mark to leave the impression that Jesus inspired terror. The only possible hint which these passages give of such a thing is that con tained in 1, 3, and 6, as noted above. After Jesus had stilled the storm Mark tells us that the disciples " feared exceedingly," and said one to another, " What manner of man is this ? " It is not a necessary interpretation of this passage to make them afraid of Jesus, who had the power to still the storm. It may refer to the fear they had had of the storm. The natural supposition is that the new exhibition of his power would excite wonder, as Matthew teUs us ; 1 but their expecta tion that he could rescue them from their impending danger would seem to forbid fear of him after he had, by any method, done what they desired. But, even if we suppose that this unexpected mani festation of power over nature aroused fear in them, still it would not justify the assertion that, according to Mark, Jesus inspires terror. Nor would so general a statement be warranted if we took the third and sixth cases along with the first ; though it is plain that we dare not do this, because the woman who was healed is not represented as fearing him as a sorcerer but as being naturally timid, since she could bring herself to do no more than surreptitiously touch the hem of his garment; and the disciples who were following Jesus to Jerusalem were not afraid of him, but of the consequences which would attend Upon their arrival in the city. 1 Matt, viii, 27. 238 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Any fear felt in the presence of Jesus was not inspired by him, but by their superstition or by their consciousness of guilt or sinfulness in the presence of one so evidently holy as Mark represents Jesus to be. Furthermore, the passages he cites from Mark do not represent Jesus as one of whom men were glad to be rid. The Gadarenes alone have the distinction of praying Jesus to leave their coasts. So far from his inspiring terror and a desire to be rid of him men sought him, according to Mark, on numerous occasions. They knew the benefi cence of his works. These did not make the impression of being the deeds of a designing exorcist or sorcerer who used charms to ac complish his purpose. Mark does not portray Christ as the unlovely being Renan imagines. The references he adds from Matthew and Luke do not aid Renan's cause, as an examination of them would show. And when the romancer attempts to make the gospel narratives but a less glaring portraiture of works of magic than the gospel of Thomas and the gospel of the Infancy he shows himseU so incapable of dis tinguishing things which are different that we lose aU faith in his historical temper; in spite of his professed historical superiority to those who believe Christ's works were miracles and not the deeds of an exorcist or sorcerer, wrought in the consciousness that he was com- Contrastbe- mitting a fraud, but feeling compelled to do them in miracles t]ft order to appear as the promised Messiah. In the gospels j^hai^nd of Thomas and of the infancy of our Saviour the child cha0noni cat Jesus is represented as capricious, willful, and revengeful. gospels. Boys and men are struc]j. dead at kig word Now he does good and kind deeds, now hurtful and maUcious. Most of his wonders have no moral quaUty whatever, but are performed merely to show what he can do. He makes birds of clay with other boys, but at his command his birds fly. He transforms boys into kids and then back again into boys. An expectant bridegroom had been changed into a mule by witchcraft ; Jesus restored him to manhood. These apocryphal gospels give Jesus no dignity of character, but only superiority of power ; they offer us no teachings, but are made up of acconnts of prodigies performed by Jesus. There is good reason why Joseph's neighbors should ask to have Jesus removed from their midst; for according to these apocryphal coUections of wonders he betrays only a purpose to have his own way, not a pur pose to use his power for the good of others. In these gospels it is presupposed that the power to metamorphose one species into another is as important as the power to raise the dead ; for the standpoint is ATTEMPTED DEGRADATION OF THE MlRACLES OF JeSCS. 239 whoUy that of the wonder-worker. In the canonical gospels the power of Jesus is subordinated to the utilities of Ufe and to the spirit of a boundless love. The apocryphal gospels referred to by Renan are brief, each containing little more matter than a couple of the longer chap ters of the canonical gospels, yet they record, on the one side, several people struck dead by the boy Jesus because they had in some way offended him, of which the canonical gospels give no example, and, on the other side, more raisings from the dead than are recorded in the gospels of the New Testament. In spite of aU these marvelous differences Renan has the effrontery to say to an intelligent pubUc that Mark represents Jesus as "an exorcist in possession of charms of rare efficacy, as a very powerful sorcerer who inspires terror, and of whom men are glad to be rid;" and to add that the gospel of Thomas carries this characteristic of Mark's gospel to the most shocking absurdity.1 The attempt, then, to cast odium upon the excellence either of the character of Christ or of his miracles fails. The documents from which alone a knowledge of the Saviour can be drawn do not repre sent him as a thaumaturgist, exorcist, sorcerer, magician, but as one who in a spirit of gentleness and seU-abnegation went about the world preaching and exemplifying righteousness, forgiveness, helpfulness, and love ; as one whose works were wrought by a divine power resi dent in him — works not designed to display his power, for then the wonders of the gospels of Thomas and of the Infancy would have answered as well as any others, but works exhibitive of a compassion and love which could have sprung only from a nature truly divine. So we come back to the assertion in support of which aU this exami nation of the aUeged thaumaturgic character of the works of Jesus has been conducted — the assertion that there can be testimony suffi cient to substantiate such miracles as those recorded in the New Tes tament, and that the testimony of Jesus does substan- „ Conclusion. tiate them. We cannot think of Jesus as mistaken when he thought he performed miracles by the power of God. If it be estab lished that he thought so it is sufficient evidence to all who are cap able of weighing evidence. When any one confesses, as do Hume and Renan, that miracles may be possible, the testimony of Jesus that he has wrought them is ample. 1 The gospel of Thomas in its two Greek forms, and in its Latin form, and The Arabic gospel of the Infancy of the Saviour, may be found in Apocryphal Gospels and Acts ; Translated by Alexander Walker, Esq., Edinburgh, T. & T. Clark, 1873. 240 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. MIRACLES AS UNUSUAL EVENTS. The second difficulty which students of history feel in connection with the credibiUty of miracles arises from their unusual character. It is a common thing to see human beings die or to sink in water ; but The unusual none of us has ever seen a dead man brought to life, nor oil fLTAPtP V Of the miracles witnessed the spectacle of one walking upon water as as a cause of doubt. upon solid ground. Hence, when such unusual incidents are reported, it is natural for us to question whether there may not be some misunderstanding or, perhaps, intentional misrepresentation. Says Hume:' "Suppose, for instance, that the fact which the testi mony endeavors to establish partakes of the extraordinary and the marvelous ; in that case the evidence resulting from the testimony ad mits of a diminution, greater or less, in proportion as the fact is more or less unusual." It is but an echo of this when Renan says : " " It is not therefore in the name of this or that philosophy, but in the name of constant experience that we banish miracle from history." Now, there can be no doubt but that we do demand better testimony for the establishment of an hitherto unheard-of event than we do for the usual events of life. We are more careful about the evidence that a man has survived an absolute fast of forty days than that he has sur vived a fast of two days. If to this unusual character of the event it is added that it was miraculously wrought we want stfll better testi mony just because the miraculous is the unusual. If in every com munity there were men who performed frequent undeniable miracles we should soon come to regard them as the usual, and our care in sifting the evidence would somewhat relax. Nevertheless, the law of evidence is not correctly stated by Hume Hume's mis- when he says that it admits of a diminution in propor- the law of tion as the alleged fact is unusual. Rather is it the true law of evidence that the more unusual the aUeged fact the better the testimony must be to produce conviction. An alto gether unusual occurrence may be sufficiently attested by the high character of the -witness for sanity, discrimination, and probity. Hume quotes the saying, " I should not beUeve such a story were it 1 Philosophical Works, vol. Iv, p. 128. » The Life of Jesus, p. 44. Miracles as Unusual Events. 241 told me by Cato " — and some stories there are which we could not believe, no matter who told them ; but it must be remembered that such are the stories that truthful and discriminating men do not teU. So that, in fact, if we have reason to trust the intelligence and mo rality of a witness we are ready to give credence to his assertions as soon as we are sure he means his words to be taken in their ordinary sense.1 Jesus's testimony to the divine source of his power and the di vine purpose of his mission is sufficient to settle those facts for all who are capable of appreciating the absolute inteUectual and moral integ rity of the Son of man. Had he come representing himself as from God, as doing God's work, and yet as violating the lawg which God reveals as his wfll, Jesus would thereby have proved himseU either in capable of true discernment or else guilty of deception. But nowhere does he represent his works as being such violations. What he claims is a power to bring about results which nature does not produce with out interference, and that this power is the power of God in him for the fffifiUment of a peculiar mission to men. He affirms himseU to have a unique character, a unique mission, and a unique relation to God. As such it is not incredible that he performed unique deeds. Not only are there some beings on whose testimony we feel compeUed to accept as facts alleged occurrences of the most unusual character, but it is in evidence, and accepted by us all, that there have been events which occurred but once. It is the generaUy accepted opinion of scientists that there was a time when life first appeared ^^H a°d on the earth. We have no difficulty now in believing «nvee°attsu^ that dead matter can be turned into Uving matter. Liv- world. ing matter possesses the power to work such a transformation upon the dead matter which surrounds it. But there was somewhere a first Uving matter. It must have come into existence under conditions en tirely unknown to us at the present time. No one doubts that it is so ; yet it is in the most forceful sense of the word an unusual event, never having occurred, so far as we know, but once. At the time of its oc currence there was nothing analogous to it, nor ever had been. In reality there is nothing analogous to it now. But the testimony of our own senses is that there is life in matter, and we are sure it must have had a beginning under conditions different from the origin of life at the present time. So also there was a first appearance of inteUigence in connection with a brain ; and so there was a time when every spe- 1 For a time it was difficult for men to believe the stories related by Marco Polo ; and there are many whom it is still difficult to convince of the truthfulness of those who de scribe for us, as professed eyewitnesses, the "rope trick "or the "mango trick" of Hindu jugglery. 242 Foundations of the Christian Faith. cies of plant and animal which now is was not. To-day human beings are propagated only by human beings ; but there was a time when one human being, or more than one, came into existence independent of any human ancestry. ' No one denies this, and yet men wfll say that everything is incredible in proportion as it is unusual. Nothing could be more unusual than the things just named, and noth ing could be more wonderful ; yet we beUeve them without difficulty —on the testimony of scientists in whom we can discover no motive for deception and no sign of inabiUty to ascertain the facts, or we be lieve them because they seem to us incapable of any other explana tion. We do not admit that with reference to these stupendous facts Their signifl- there must be some misunderstanding or misrepresenta tion aims tion- But wnen Jesus claims power to restore the dead of Jesus. to lif e unbelievers refuse credence on the ground that the event is one which we do not see in everyday life. In reaUty we know nothing about either death or Ufe. Did we understand them we might see that it is perfectly easy to one with access to the powers of nature to bring back Ufe to the dead at wfll. In fact, then, the question is not chiefly as to the unusual character of the events, but as to the character of the evidence in their support. And there is en tire possibflity of evidence to sustain the truth of events which we never saw performed, and which no man ever saw, and which never occurred but once in the history of the world. To this it may be repUed that the events referred to are natural, while the miracles profess to be supernatural. Who can be sure that the first life, consciousness, and human being were the products of purely (so-caUed) natural forces ? The assertion that they are such rests upon no evidence whatever. Besides, who can distinguish either the usual or the unusual processes of nature from the supernatural ? What is natural, and what supernatural ? No one can answer these questions. Only materialism is under any logical necessity of deny ing the creative power and agency of God. So that it is a mere as sumption that the unique events in the history of creation were the results solely of forces resident and operative in matter ; and, in any event, so far as history is concerned, they forbid us to deny the re ality of the unusual, however unlike the usual it may be. > The argument Is essentially as given by Schmid, Die Darwin'schen Theorlen und ihre Stellung zur Philosophie, Religion und Moral, Barmen, 1876, p. 316 f. Credulity as a Ground for Rejection of Miracles. 243 CHAPTER V. CREDULITY AS A GROUND FOR THE REJECTION OF MIRACLES. A third difficulty which those who are accustomed to the careful sifting of human testimony feel in the acceptance of any record of aUeged miracle is the tendency of mankind to believe in the mar velous. This difficulty has been strongly stated by Hume, and more recent writers have simply adopted his ideas. He says : ' The tendeney " The passion of surprise and wonder, arising from mira- |g the far cies, being an agreeable emotion, gives a sensible tend- JjjJgK ff ency toward the beUef of those events from which it is douM- derived. . . . But if the spirit of religion join itseU to the love of wonder there is an end of common sense ; and human testimony, in these circumstances, loses aU pretensions to authority. A re ligionist may be an enthusiast, and imagine he sees what has no reality ; he may know his narrative to be false, and yet persevere in it, with the best intentions in the world, for the sake of promoting so holy a cause; or, even where this delusion has not place, vanity, excited by so strong a temptation, operates on him more powerfully than on the rest of mankind in any other circumstances ; and self- interest with equal force. His auditors may not have, and commonly have not, sufficient judgment to canvass his evidence; what judg ment they have they renounce by principle, in these sublime and mysterious subjects ; or, if they were ever so willing to employ it, passion and a heated imagination disturb the regularity of its opera tions. Their creduUty increases his impudence ; and his impudence overpowers their credulity." To this Renan adds practicaUy nothing. He puts the case in brief thus :2 "It is, in most cases, the people them selves who, from the undeniable need which they feel of Seeing in great events and great men something divine, create the marvelous legends afterward." What Strauss has to say" on this subject also adds nothing. By the time we are through with Hume we shaU be through with Strauss and Renan. It wfll be readily admitted that men do enjoy hearing and tell ing marvelous tales; and perhaps mankind takes some pleasure in 1 Philosophical Works, vol. iv, p. 133 ff. 2 The Life of Jesus, p. 45. » The Life of Jesus, vol. i, p. 55. 244 Foundations of the Christian Faith. beUeving that some of the tales are true. But that the deUght men feel in such stories leads to the invention of them, contrary to The love oi known facts, is opposed to the innate love of truth. ous checked Much as we enjoy the marvelous we enjoy the truth oYtruth.10ve more. And this is true of aU grades of men. In fact, the very first condition requisite to obtaining pleasure in any pro found degree from accounts of marvels is the beUef in their truth. Men do not invent false marvels for the sake of the pleasure they get out of marvels; for it is only as they appear credible that they afford this pleasure. This may argue a very un critical stage of intellectual development, but it does not make men wholesale self -deceivers for the pleasure they derive from decep tion. Men who invent prodigies do it, not for their own pleasure in believing them, but for the satisfaction they secure in the very exer cise of their inventive genius, or for the sake of gratifying the pas sion of surprise and wonder in others, or for the purpose of securing power over those who accept them as truth. But, according to Hume, if the spirit of religion join itself to the love of wonder there is an end of common sense and of the value of human testimony, and we might add, if Hume is correct, of common honesty. Four attributes appear to have inhered in Hume's conception of the spirit of religion : first, an enthusiasm which blinds its victim to actual fact; second, a strong H u m e's a p- parent con- mclination to the perpetration of pious fraud ; third, an ception of . •*.*,¦, ¦-. ¦• the spirit of overpowering vanity ; fourth, a tremendously forcible religion in applicable sense of seff-interest. It would be futile to deny that even if true. aU these attributes have attended some manifestations of religion, and even some professed manifestations of Christianity. To them we owe in a large measure the ill repute of reUgion with a certain class of men. We may also admit that these attributes of hu man nature account in a large degree for the vast bulk, though not for all, of the miracle stories connected with religions. Further, we aUow that these attributes — enthusiasm, fraud, vanity, and self-interest — may form an essential part of some religions. But we deny that they are consistent with Christianity, which, in its records as in its Founder, betrays none of them. Hume was assaulting miracles in general, but it is not our purpose to defend them in general. We have to do here almost exclusively with the miracles of Christ. Aside from what the apostles and early disciples believed, Jesus professed to believe that he wrought miracles. Will Hume say that Jesus imagined what had no reality; that he perpetrated Credulity as a Ground for Rejection of Miracles. 245 pious frauds for the estabUshment of the kingdom of heaven ; that vanity induced him to profess a power he did not possess ; or that seU-interest acted so powerfuUy on him as to make him deceive himself or others? We think not. If Hume was not himseU a hypocrite he must have been a beUever in the miracles of Jesus, for he compares the human evidence for the miracles of the Abbe Paris with the evidence for those "of our Saviour," saying: "As if the testimony of men could ever be put in the balance with that of God himseU, who conducted the pen of the inspired writers."1 The question therefore is as to the character of the Person who pro fessed to work the most of the miracles of the New Testament. Who ever else may have been deceived or a deceiver it must be admitted that Jesus was neither. Were we to assert that Jesus was either one or the other we should do so in spite of the records from which we draw aU our knowledge of him. In other words, our concep tion of Jesus would be the product of our prejudices, and not of a study of the records ; which, if they give us any portraiture of him at all, give us that of a clear- visioned, honest, humble, self-sacrificing, rather than of a fanatical, dishonest, vain, and seU-seeking man. So then, whether or not Hume intended the words we have quoted from him to apply to the miracles of the New Testament, they can only apply if we regard Jesus as the degraded being that Hume has in mind ' when he describes one in whom the spirit of religion is joined to that of wonder. Such a being Jesus was not. But the latter part of his argument touches not so much the pro fessed relator of miracles as those who accept them on his word. When Jesus professed to work miracles did his disciples have suffi cient judgment to canvass his evidence ? In answering this query it wfll not be necessary to enter upon the question of the authorship of the canonical gospels. It is generally agreed that these gospels were put into their present form during the first century of our era ; and that the synoptics were substantiaUy in the form in which we have them soon after the destruction of Jerusalem. So that they correspond to conditions existing in the first three quarters of the first Christian century. Now, we find in the gospels evidence of an unwillingness to believe in miracle which shows that the early disciples exercised what judgment they had, and had neither renounced on principle the 1 Philosophical Works, vol. iv, p. 142. See also pp. 149, 150, where he seems to teach that, though the miracles of the New Testament are not capable of establishment by human reason, they are to be accepted on faith. 18 246 Foundations of the Christian Faith. use of judgment in these matters nor, as a result of passion or a heated imagination, lost the power to . employ it. It cannot be said of the early disciples that their creduUty increased the "impudence" of Jesus, or that his "impudence " overpowered their creduUty. This language of Hume does not apply in the case of Jesus and his disci ples. Even if the writers of the gospels were credulous Tthecawr?ters they describe the witnesses of the resurrection of Jesus peith1nBac- as being incredulous, at least in a reasonable degree, co'unts^f though not so incredulous as to disbelieve when they miracles. ^^ ^.^ ^^ Qwn eyeg They did not ttlinki indeeol, that all miracles imply creduUty or imposture, but neither did they feel themselves bound to beUeve aU that was told them. In Matthew and Mark we have the record of the testimony upon which the women beheved in the resurrection, and there is no evidence of incredulity in their cases but rather of creduUty. We have no hint in those gospels of the testimony upon which the apostles beheved l unless we find it in Matt, xxvui, 17, where it is said of the disciples that when they saw him they worshiped him. However, in the same verse, we are told that "some doubted." It was not easy to convince some of the eleven that there was no deception being practiced upon them. In Luke,5 however, we have some account of the steps which led them to beUeve that Jesus was really risen. In the first place, it is to be noted that the testimony of the women seemed to the apostles as idle tales, and they beUeved them not (verse 11). Perhaps they would have been more ready to believe what the women said had these not professed to have seen the vision of angels who said that Jesus was aUve (verse 23). Angel visions were too insusceptible of verification for ready acceptance. The apostles therefore discounted their whole story. Still they went to the sepulchre and saw the vision of angels for themselves (verse 24), or at any rate found the tomb empty ; but, failing to see the risen Lord, they declined to accept the story of his resurrection. FinaUy he appeared to Simon (Peter) and upon this testimony they believed (verse 34). The two on the way to Emmaus beUeved only when they saw him for themselves. But that the doubts of the eleven were still somewhat active is evident from the story found in verses 36-41. For when he appeared in the midst of them they thought it must be a spirit instead of flesh and bones. They were far more ready to be lieve that a spirit could be rendered visible than that the dead body 1 Comp. Matt, xxviii with Mark xvi. The reader will remember that verses 9-20 of the last chapter of Mark are regarded by critics as a late addition. ' Chap. xxiv. Credulity as a Ground for Rejection of Miracles. 247 of Jesus should be revivified and stand before them. In fact, Luke gives us abundant reason to believe that in spite of some remaining superstitions these disciples were not ready to give up their right to judge for themselves even in the apparent presence of their Master and Lord. The twentieth chapter of John gives us equal reasons for supposing that the apostles were slow to beUeve. They were not to be deceived by the apparition of anyone bearing the closest resem blance to Jesus, in face, form, voice, or manner. There was but one absolutely sure way to identify Jesus ; that was by the prints of the nails and of the spear. Not Thomas alone, but aU the apostles de manded this proof; for it was granted to aU. Paul,1 writing in the fifties, spoke of the many infalUble proofs of our Lord's resurrection, mentioned in Acts i, 3. Now, we may be met by the suggestion that the proofs mentioned in the records are no proofs ; but we must answer that if they were not there is no proof of anything. And it is not the question here whether the resurrection of our Lord is proved, but whether the early disciples knew how to test the reaUty of a phenomenon and whether they applied the tests. If we may judge from the record they were quite as careful as a man of science would be to-day. Such a trained observer could demand nothing more than was demanded by these simple disciples, and no criticism of the record can destroy the fact that such precautions were taken against deception. For even if the wit nesses of the resurrection of the Lord be supposed to have had nothing to do with the matters related in the gospels, stiU those gospels prove that in the early part of the first Christian century those who had to do with the propagation of the Christian faith knew what evidence was demanded for the establishment of the resurrection ; they furnish the proof that the early Christians had the judgment necessary to can vass the evidence for a miracle, and, if the record can be trusted, they did not renounce but employed their judgment in testing the reality of miracle. We are at liberty to infer also that they were duly cautious in ref erence to other miracles than that of the resurrection, nor are we altogether without documentary evidence in support of that inference. Acts i, 3, speaks of "many infaUible proofs " of the resurrection; and Acts iii, 10, declares that the people recognized the lame man, as, ac cording to iv, 14, did also the religious authorities, whfle iv, 16, makes them declare that they cannot deny the miracle. Furthermore, these discipl es were questioned as to the power by which they had wrought the 1 1 Cor. xv, 5-8. 248 Foundations of the Christian Faith. miracle (iv, 7), as though they feared some sorcerer's trick. Verse 13 shows, whatever else it may mean, that the Jews saw in them no sign of wide reading, whether in books on magic or any other. Then we see evidence of caution against deception from those who pretended to be moved by the Spirit of God, in the words: " BeUeve not every spirit, but try the spirits, whether they are of God." 1 True, the test proposed is a doctrinal one ; but the doctrine was one of which they had assured themselves by actual experience. ' Whatever may be the date and authorship of 2 Peter, that document is early enough to fairly represent the earUest period of Christianity, and in i, 16, the author denies having foUowed ' ' cunningly devised fables. " The early disciples constantly referred to their utterances as matters of which they were eyewitnesses.3 And there was no motive of self-interest, for they lost aU earthly good in adhering to Christ. Hence we must con clude that, though there have been deceivers who have palmed off -tricks for miracles, Jesus was not such ; and that, though there have been men ready to beUeve any tale of marvel, the early Christians were not such. They apparently received miracle only on the best of evidence. ¦Uohnlv, 1. * Ibid., 1, 1-3. • See, for example, Acts iv, 20. The Prevalence of Miracle Stories. 249 CHAPTER VI. THE PREVALENCE OF MIRACLE STORIES. Still another difficulty is put by Hume in its strongest form. ' "It forms a strong presumption against aU supernatural and miraculous relations that are observed chiefly to abound among ig- Doubts arising norant and barbarous nations; or, if a civilized people leged ign<> has ever given admission to any of them, that people wfll barbaiismof be found to have received them from ignorant and bar- among whom barous ancestors who transmitted them with that invio- sa'ui "to have lable sanction and authority which always attend received occurie • opinions. When we peruse the first histories of all nations we are apt to imagine ourselves transported into some new world, where the whole frame of nature is disjointed and every element performs its operations in a different manner from what it does at present. Bat tles, revolutions, pestilence, famine, and death are never the effect of those natural causes which we experience. Prodigies, omens, oracles, judgments quite obscure the few natural events that are intermingled with them." In none of their aspects or parts do these words describe the mira cles of the New Testament, taken as a whole. They did not arise in an ignorant and barbarous nation ; nor did the civilized nation in which they appeared receive them from ignorant and barbarous ancestors. In reading the New Testament everything goes on as we see it go on, except when, occasionally, Jesus or one of his disciples is represented as interfering for the time. There are early histories of nations which leave the impression described by Hume, but the New Testament is not among them, though we admit, of course, that to the denier of miracle it would appear to correspond in some degree to Hume's description. But it may be said that, though the New Testament miracles did not originate in an ignorant and barbarous nation, they arose among the more ignorant classes of the Jews. This must be acknowledged to be the fact. There were not many noble, or wise, or learned even among the later generations of the early disciples. The primitive apostles were men of much natural vigor of mind, at least in some instances, 1 Philosophical Works, vol. iv, p. 135. 250 Foundations of the Christian Faith. though they certainly did lack the training of the schools. But as these miracle stories were circulated, if not penned, by the unschooled Because the apostles the phenomena they present cannot be accounted ries of the for on any other supposition than that of their truth. ment were From such untutored men we should not expect such unschooled y miracle stories as these. Any one who will take the must be re^ pains to compare these miracle stories with those of the (M ' 1 V 1 M J MS true. apocryphal gospels wfll see at a glance how superior in point of sobriety are those of the New Testament. The apocryphal gospels give us legendary miracles without doubt ; if the miracles of the New Testament are legendary, also, why are they so different ? Hume's description of early miracles, quoted above, exactly fits the apocryphal gospels, why not the accounts of the New Testament also ? We affirm that it is a psychological impossibility for the uneducated early Christians to have given birth to such miracle stories as those of the New Testament had they not witnessed the events there described. No one man, however gifted, nor any four, could have produced them in aU their simplicity and self -consistency. And to suppose that they grew up as myths or legends grow, and yet took the form they actu- aUy wear, is to suppose that in that place and age and instance human minds operated in a manner different from anywhere else. If edu cated, talented men wrote those accounts then they believed them or were hypocrites. If they beUeved them then we must not say they were not first properly tested, and in any case the odium of having origi nated among ignorant people is removed by the supposition. If igno rant men first related or afterward penned them then we are sure they must have occurred as described ; and if as described it matters not that they were given out by ignorant men. But again Hume's irremediable skepticism rises from defeat to base an objection to miracles on the ground that they are found in aU re- Argument hgions. He says : ' " But, should this miracle be ascribed from the . .... presence of to any new system of religion, men, in all ages, have been miracle sto- „ . , , . , . , ™o ' ries in all re- so imposed on by ridiculous stories of that kind that this hgions. very circumstance would be a full proof of a cheat, and sufficient with all men of sense not only to make them reject the fact, but even reject it without further examination. " There is more of the same kind on the same page, and we must consider it, but now we comment on the above quotation. It teaches that the very fact that a miracle is connected with religion renders it impossible of belief, or even of consideration, by men of sense; such a circumstance is "full 1 Philosophical Works, vol. Iv, p. 148, The Prevalence of Miracle Stories. 251 proof of a cheat." When we consider how much credulity, and perhaps fraud, has been practiced in the name of religion by deluded or design ing men we can scarcely censure Hume's evident heat ; for the words quoted are those of passion, not of calm judgment. But just because they are the expression of indignation, however righteous, we must discount them. It is not a true principle that in a great stack of sheaves of wheat we must expect no grain because we find the bulk of straw and chaff so largely preponderant. It may be that anyone who wiU thrash out and properly sift this great mass of religious mir acle will find some valuable truth. Many men of sense have taken this trouble and have found it so ; and it is not a mark of good sense to reject all religious miracles because they are so often unfounded. But he proceeds : ' ' Though the Being to whom the miracle is ascribed be in this case almighty it does not, on that account, become a whit more probable, since it is impossible for us to know the attributes or actions of such a Being otherwise than from the experience which we have of his productions in the usual course of nature." Here we have a dogmatic denial of the possibflity of miraculous revelation in order to support the improbability of any other form of miracle. Hume asserts what thousands as able as himself deny. We cannot here take up the proofs in favor of a supernatural or miraculous revelation, but Hume and his followers would be largely outvoted on this question in an assemblage of his inteUectual peers in any recent Christian age. Besides, any sufficient proof that God is the author of the usual course of nature is also sufficient proof that he is the author of those unusual events in nature to which reference was made on page 241 and follow ing. So that we must gather our ideas of God from his unusual as well as his usual productions ; and the fact that any of his works are unusual opens the way for belief in other properly attested cases of his unusual action. To this it may be replied that the introduction of life on the earth was accomplished once for all, and that thereafter life was left to develop without his interference. Now, for the sake of the argument, we may admit this. But we also affirm that, so far as the Christian miracles are concerned, they too introduced a CMstian^mir- new order in the world as truly as did the introduction of duced a new life. Christian miracles are chiefly ascribed to Jesus and the world. the disciples of his time. As science claims that life was introduced but once upon the earth, so miracles have their place at the beginning of Christianity. With that beginning the new spiritual Ufe was intro duced into the history of man, and miracles have not been necessary. The miracles recorded in the Old and New Testaments, confined as they 252 Foundations of the Christian Faith. are almost exclusively to turning points in the reUgious history of man, furnish a striking paraUel to God's usual way of doing unusual things in nature as revealed by scientific research. So that we have here no argument against the Christian miracles, but rather one in their favor. Further, he says: "This [that is, God's production in the usual course of nature] still reduces us to past observation, and obUges us to compare the instances of the violation of truth in the testimony of men with those violations of the laws of nature by miracles, in order to judge which of them is most Ukely and probable." We remark again that the New Testament miracles do not represent themselves as violations of the laws of nature, but as variations from the usual Argument course of nature. But suppose they were represented as quent'vioit violations of natural laws ; Hume assumes that as such truth Sc on- violations are less numerous than violations of truth we sidered. must refuse to beUeve aU records of miracle. This would be the case only were the motives for violations of natural law as numerous as the motives for lying. It is a strange argument, indeed, that because violations of natural law are few and violations of truth numerous we must not accept any instances of the former. This could be of any force only if the number of the former were reduced to zero ; but in that case there would be no basis of comparison. If he means to say that there are no miracles, but there are many cases of falsehood, he simply begs the question at issue. If he aUows that there are any miracles then he aUows the point in dispute, and it is siUy to argue that we cannot beUeve them on human testimony. Our business in that case becomes one of sifting the evidence for any aUeged miracle. FinaUy, he says: "As the violations of truth are more common in the testimony concerning religious miracles than in that concerning And m nartic- an^ 0*ker natter of fact, this must diminish very much uiar its ap- the authority of the former testimony, and make us form testimony a general resolution never to lend any attention to it, concerning _ J religious with whatever specious pretense it may be covered." Hume seems very sure that the probability of falsehood in human testimony is much greater than the probability of miracle. And we do not question the fact, which assuredly does diminish the au thority of testimony for miracle. What we contend for is that there is testimony which cannot be impeached that miracles were wrought by Jesus Christ ; and Jesus is himself the chief witness upon whom we rely. The only way to escape this is to deny that Jesus ever pro- The Prevalence of Miracle Stories. 253 fessed to work any miracles, and to make the early Christians or the writers of the New Testament, or both, attribute to him the miracles which he never thought of. This we shall consider in due time. * But if it be aUowed that Jesus professed to work miracles, then we have testimony for miracle which would convince any impartial jury any where. Only the man who is determined to rid the world of the mi raculous at all hazards can disaUow the testimony of Jesus ; and to form a general resolution never to lend any attention to miracle sto ries is not to act the part of an historian, but to neglect one of his greatest duties. It will not be necessary to discuss the statement of Hume that the miracles of different religions contradict each other.3 He appeared to see for himseU that the argument drawn from the alleged fact was "oversubtle and refined," though he tries to bolster it up by a com parison with the reasoning of a judge on the testimony of an equal number of opposing witnesses. A judge does not measure witnesses by the cord, but by their character, inteUigence, and opportunity for knowing the facts. If aU religions presented the same quaUty of tes timony for their miracles there would be something in his compari son, but such is not the case. Nor need we more than refer to the argument mentioned by Hume, that it is extremely difficult to ascer tain the truth or falsehood of the commonest matters. No one would be disposed to question his statement ; but the difficulty with it as an argument against miracles is that it proves too much. For it really means that, as we cannot detect the truth or falsehood of the com monest report, we cannot detect the truth or falsehood of a reported miracle. This lands us in universal skepticism in history— as Hume's other reasoning leads to universal skepticism in philosophy. If truth and falsehood cannot be distinguished we are at Uberty to believe what we please. We admit the difficulty, but deny the impossibility of ascertaining the facts, in large numbers of cases, whether of com mon matters or of miracle. i See division ill, section ii, chap. i. a Philosophical Works, vol. iv, p. 138. 254 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER VII. CHRISTIAN AND SKEPTICAL REQUISITES TO FAITH IN MIRACLES. Throughout the above consideration of the difficulties which pro fessed scientific historians find in the way of miracle as historical fact the purpose has not been so much to demonstrate the reaUty of the miracles of the New Testament as to overthrow the arguments against them presumably derived from the laws of historical evi dence. In pursuance of our purpose we take up for special consider ation the question whether the demands in the way of evidence for the reaUty of miracle made by some modern historians are such as commend themselves to impartial thought. Perhaps no one has fixed Renan's req- more rigid conditions than Renan for the acceptance of the belief of the claims of a "thaumaturgist." We quote him at 'i!l'"i' length.1 "Let a thaumaturgist present himseU to-mor row with testimony sufficiently important to merit our attention ; let him announce that he is able, I will suppose, to raise the dead ; what would be done ? A commission composed of physiologists, physicians, chemists, persons experienced in historical criticism, would be ap pointed. This commission would choose the corpse, make certain that death was real, designate the hall in which the experiment should be made, and regulate the whole system of precautions necessary to leave no room for doubt. If, under such conditions, the resurrection should be performed a probability almost equal to certainty would be attained. However, as an experiment ought always be capable of be ing repeated, as one ought to be capable of doing again what one has once done, and as in the matter of miracles there can be no question of easy or difficult, the thaumaturgist would be invited to reproduce his marvelous act under other circumstances, upon other bodies, in an other medium. If the miracle succeeds each time two things would be proven : first, that supernatural acts do come to pass in the world ; second, that the power to perform them belongs or is delegated to cer tain persons. But who does not see that no miracle was ever per formed under such conditions ; that always hitherto the thaumatur gist has chosen the subject of the experiment, chosen the means, chosen the public 1 " 1 The Life of Jesus, p. 44 f. Requisites to Faith in Miracles. 255 These, then, are the conditions declared requisite and adequate for the proof ' ' that supernatural acts do come to pass in the world, and that the power to perform them belongs or is delegated to cer- These requi sites not as tain persons." It is necessary to note that in the quota- rigid as ...,.,,.,, „ , those de- tion miracle is used, not m the sense of a mere wonder, manded by the Chris- something unaccountable, but of a supernatural act. Now, Man. we have to assert in contradiction to the above that aU the safeguards mentioned by Renan would not suffice to prove to one of us noncriti- cal believers in miracle that the raisings from the dead were super natural acts. If the one who professed to be able to raise the dead should succeed in every instance chosen by the supposed commission until those who composed it were perfectly sure they could not baffle him, all that would be proved is that the person possessed the power he claimed, namely, the power to raise the dead. There would be no proof that the power was supernatural. The power could not be de nied, but the nature of the power, its source, whether resident in man or supernaturally delegated to man, would be left undetermined. For the determination of this question a new set of experiments would be required. Furthermore, if, in addition to the one person supposed who had proved himseU able to raise to life any dead body brought to him, there should appear another possessing the same power the effect would be not to suggest recourse to a supernatural endowment, but to a natural one. The oftener one raised the dead, and the more there were who proved themselves possessed of that power, the more inclined would that "commission composed of physiologists, physi cians, chemists, persons experienced in historical criticism" be to doubt the supernatural character of the power and to regard it as an unusual natural endowment, for which the said commission would immediately proceed to search. In other words, the frequency of the occurrence, so far from proving the supernatural origin of the power by which it was performed, would tend to make men regard it as natural. It is indeed strange that a historian so professedly critical as Renan should have overlooked these two very essential facts : first, that there would be nothing in a raising from the dead to prove that the act was the result of a supernatural power ; and, second, that the frequency of its repetition would be sure to argue the other way. But it may be asked, If the supernatural character of the act could not be proved by the method which Renan proposes what can prove it ? Several things would be needful in addition to what Renan de mands. First, the " thaumaturgist "' would have to claim that he did his acts by divine power ; second, he would have to prove himself 256 Foundations of the Christian Faith. honest in aU his representations in matters which could be tested ; third, he would have to be possessed of a oUscrijninating mind ; Points which fourth, he would have to prove by an unselfish hfe that theChristian ,.•,¦,. would add to he was not actuated in his representations by any desire Renan's re-.,. , quirements. of self -aggrandizement. So much must be demanded of the man who performed the acts or no sufficiently cautious commis sion would feel any assurance that his power was more than an un usual natural power. But this is not all. The commission itseU would have to be composed of men who beUeve in, or at least do not deny, the existence of an order which, as compared with the natural, is supernatural. Should they, a priori, deny the supernatural, no acts one could perform would have the effect of proving that the performer wrought by supernatural means. Further, this commission would have to be composed of men who believe that an honest, discrimina ting, unselfish, and beneficent man, claiming supernatural power as the means by which he performs his works, knows whereof he speaks, and speaks the truth. Did they believe beforehand, as Renan does, that a supernatural relation "always implies credulity or impos ture " ¦ nothing one could do or say would prove to them " that super natural acts do come to pass in the world." But when aU the conditions we have added are fulfilled we have essentially the conditions which existed between Jesus Christ and his early disciples. True it is the disciples were not a commission com posed of " physiologists, physicians, chemists, persons experienced in historical criticism," but they were men who were not inclined to be imposed upon; and if we may judge of the discrimination of "per sons experienced in historical criticism " by the inadequacy of Renan's requirements by way of proof they had more of the true historical req uisites for membership in such a commission than those proposed by Renan. We suggest that the next who attempts to cast doubt on the mira cles of Jesus should reverse all that has hitherto been held by skeptics concerning the ability of the early Christians to determine the char acter and value of historical evidence, and, instead of denying this ability, assert it. A strong case could be made out for all those who believe that violations of truth are particularly common in testimony concerning religious miracles, including Christian testimony. It could be made to appear that these early disciples had reduced the produc tion of miracle stories to a science and an art. They knew they dare not have too many miracles of one kind, or else men would suspect 1 The Life of Jesus, p. 45. Requisites to Faith in Miracles. 257 that there was a natural law governing them, hence they restrained themselves and gave us but three raisings from the dead. So, also, they knew that he who would prove his supernatural power by mira cles must claim that he wrought them by such power ; hence they made Christ claim this. They knew, also, that a man making such a claim must be worthy of confidence ; hence they painted him as pos sessing all negative and positive virtues, and also a remarkably clear and discrhninating mind. The men who understood the laws of his torical evidence so perfectly — so much more perfectly than our pro fessed historical critics of the nineteenth century— were not simple tons ; they were deliberate, crafty, far-seeing deceivers, who because they were so cunning left no trace of their cunning. It is true that such a handling of the testimony of the gospels would, if universally appUed, destroy all faith in humanity and make history writing im possible ; but who cares what else be overthrown if we can only over throw miracles ! Indeed, Renan and his commission are but the modern representa tives of the carping Jews who came to Jesus demanding the kind of a sign which they claimed would convince them, and to whom Jesus replied that no sign should be given them. WeU did he know that since the miracles he had already wrought had failed to convince them that his claims of power from heaven were weU founded, no miracle he could work would succeed in convincing them. Besides, Jesus had his own plans, and he could not allow aU the cavilers who came to him to interrupt him in their execution. Upon but one occasion 1 is Jesus represented as working a miracle for the purpose of proving his possession of supernatural power, and that he is re ported to have had that motive is the most suspicious fact about the incident. He performed miracles as acts of mercy, not that people might believe in him ; though he thought that if they would believe for no other reason they should at least beUeve him for the very work's sake.2 Furthermore, Renan's critical and historical ability suffers when we take into consideration the statements he makes in the last sentence of the quotation under discussion. There are numerous cases on record of wonders of many kinds in which the " commission " prac tically selected "the subject, the means, and the public." If Renan was not acquainted with them he should not have written as he did. Indeed, the cases in question are so remarkable that were it not for the criteria we have added to those proposed by Renan we should be 1 Matt, ix, 6, and ref. » John xiv, 11. 258 Foundations of the Christian Faith. obliged to beUeve that the miracles of Jesus were Uttle more super natural than the wonders of the Indian jugglers, who do not claim the supernatural in their performances and whose character would not lend them credence if they did.1 1 The Rev. E. Cobham Brewer, LL.D., gives accounts of wonders of human hibernation and simulated death which many think supported by unimpeachable testimony, and which, but for the claim of the supernatural made by Jesus, might lead us to class his raisings from the dead and his own resurrection alongside of them Dictionary of Mira cles, Philadelphia, 1884, p. 88. Comp. also an article on " The Wonders of Hindu Magic," by Henrich Heinsoldt, Ph.D., in the Arena, December, 1893, pp. 46-60. Bishop J. M. Thoburn, however, declares his inability to find good evidence for the hibernations men tioned. See his India and Malaysia: Cincinnati and New York, 1892, pp. 135 ff. Biblical and Nonbiblical Miracles. 259 CHAPTER VIH. BIBLICAL AND N0NBD3LICAL MIRACLES. This suggests another difficulty which many students of history feel when brought face to face with the miracles of the New Testa ment. Why, it is asked, should we accept the miracles of the New Testament and reject those of non-Christian origin ? Are we not guilty of historical partiality if we do so ? That is, if we do so, is it not be cause we are limited by our own religious community ? So Strauss argues ; 1 and he reminds us that the Mohammedan is guilty of the same partiality in judging of the contents of the Koran. The question of the credibility of the Gospel history so closely interwoven with the beUef in miracles we shah take up in due time.2 Here we hold our selves firmly to a comparison of the miracles of the New Testament with those outside of it. Such a comparison wfll be altogether favor able to the claims of the New Testament miracles — so thoroughly as to reUeve any historian from the charge of partisanship should he admit the reality of them while denying the credibility of all others. We desire to caU attention to the fact, however, that Christian evidences do not demand of us the assertion that all the miracle stories in the New Testament are authentic ; nor that no real miracles were ever performed except such as are recorded in the New Testament. As we are practically sure that some verses of the New Testa- Limit3 M t0 ment found their way into the text subsequently to the <*« e ^C£D£ composition of the documents,3 so we cannot say that no eaIeinecthe miracle is reported which never took place. Indeed, such New Testa- a case is pointed out. It is John v, 4, the omission of which in the Revised Version, in accordance with the approved princi ples of textual criticism, destroys the miraculous elements of the story as far as the pool is concerned. Whether, in the transmission of the text of the New Testament by written copies, or by other means, miracle stories may be given in the gospels which have no foundation in fact we need not here inquire, since it is clear that the great mass of the 1 The Life of Jesus, vol. I, pp. 47 ff. It will be noted, however, that Strauss so far ad mits a distinction between the Biblical and the extrabiblical records of miracle as to fur nish a possibility for the truth of the former which does not exist for the latter. 1 Division Hi, section ii, chap. 3. • For example, Mark xvi, 9-20 ; John viii, 1-11. 260 FODNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. Gospel miracles were a constituent part of the testimony concerning the deeds of Jesus by those who knew him best. So also the Chris tian accepts the miraculous in the Old Testament and has no a priori inclination to deny the possibflity that God granted miraculous power to Christians in later times, or even to non-Jewish and non-Christian religionists. The apostle Paul believed that God had not left himseU without a witness in any nation,1 and it may be that some of the wit nesses he referred to wrought true miracles. What is here contended for, then, is that the BibUcal miracles, par ticularly those of the New Testament, are as a whole more worthy of credence than aU other miracle stories whatever ; and so much more worthy of credence as to place them, for historical purposes, in a cat egory by themselves. We make the comparison first on the basis of their dignity. Any one who wfll take the pains to compare will at once discover that, The superior taken as a whole, any group of non-Christian miracles the New contains large numbers which are grotesque or otherwise miracles. undignified, while almost nothing — perhaps a sound judgment would aver that absolutely nothing — of this kind appears in the New Testament. In the work by Brewer, mentioned above, any one who desires can find the materials for such a comparison ready at his command. However, we prefer to take cases which have been cited to show that ecclesiastical and other miracles are no less well es tablished than those of the New Testament. Matthew Arnold com pares two miracles of the Acts with two from ecclesiastical sources, and declares concerning them that it is impossible to find any criterion by which one of the incidents may establish its claim to a sohdity which we refuse to the others.2 He compares the promartyr, Stephen, looking up into heaven, seeing the glory of God and Jesus standing on the right hand of God,8 with the record that Babylas and Myg- done, Christian servants of a Roman governor, saw St. Fructuosus, the martyr, and his deacon, Eulogius, carried up on high with crowns on their heads. Now, aside from any question of the antecedent probability of such visions derived from the character of those who were said to have seen them or from the degree of evidence in support of the aUeged vis ions, it is surely evident that the story of Stephen, merely as a story, has in it elements of dignity and subUmity not found in the other. The Biblical story would afford a far finer subject for poetical, musical, or pictorial treatment than the ecclesiastical. This would at once be 1 Acts xiv, 16, 17. a Literature and Dogma, Boston, 1874, p. 126. a Acts vii, 55, 56. Biblical and Nonbiblioal Miracles. 261 admitted by one who beUeved both accounts to be true. Again, Arnold compares St. Paul, who on the way to Damascus hears the voice of Jesus saying, "Saul, Saul, why persecutestthoume?" with St. Thomas Aquinas, who, whfle praying, heard a voice from the crucifix saying, "Thou hast written well of me, Thomas ; what recompense dost thou desire?" It really seems incredible that Arnold should have fafled to see any difference in kind here. The scene on the Damascus road x represents Saul as having heard the voice from Jesus out of heaven, whfle that in the monastery of St. Dominic at Naples makes the voice come from the crucifix. The superiority of the former conception is evident. But in making the comparison Arnold failed to state a fact essential to the proper estimate of the two alleged occurrences : while the voice that spoke to Saul of Tarsus made him the unwearying dis ciple of Christ and apostle to the Gentiles, the voice from the crucifix served to lend favor to the side of Thomas and the Dominicans as against Duns Scotus and the Franciscans in their heated and unedfly- ing dispute concerning the questions at issue between the Nominalists and Reahsts." No one would pretend to say that mere superiority in dignity wfll demonstrate the supernatural reaUty of the Biblical accounts, and in the cases discussed above the difference in this respect, whfle great, is not immense. In fact, it is not by the careful selection of instances favorable to the one side or the other that the question of superior dignity can be determined. It is only when we read rapidly first through the gospels and then rapidly through any other professed his tory or biography containing miracle stories that we note the vast in feriority of the latter. Then it wfll be seen, when the whole effect is felt, that the Christian miracles are as superior in dignity to any other miracle collection as Greek art is superior to Egyptian. The best of the nonbiblical can scarcely match the poorest of the Biblical accounts ; and below the best the stories range down to the absolutely coarse and trivial, which indeed constitute the bulk of the nonscriptural coUec- tion. We give a few examples. Six or eight workmen were unable to lift a stone prepared for a place in a Benedictine monastery. St. Benedict saw that it was the devil who made it so heavy, Exampies of and making on the stone the sign of the cross he was able tu?a\s liiiral alone to lift it with ease to its place. 3 St. Patrick floated cles- to Ireland on an altar stone.* Whfle St. Francis Hieronimus (A. D. • Acts ix, 1-9, reff. 2 See Brewer's Dictionary of Miracles, p. 499. For the story of St. Fructuosus, ibid, p. 7. 0 Brewer, Dictionary of Miracles, p. 160. 4 Ibid., p. 164. 19 262 Foundations of the Christian Faith. 1643-1716) was preaching one day a gentleman was being driven by in his carriage. The preacher, holding out a crucifix, cried aloud, "0 holy Jesus, if these infidels have no respect for thee, let their horses teach them better." As he spoke the horses feU on their knees and continued so until the sermon was over. ' St. Bernardin (1380-1444), St. Francis of Paula (1416-1507), St. Isidore's wife, and St. Raymund of Pennaf ord, all sailed over considerable stretches of water on their cloaks, the second having on board also his six disciples, the latter sailing one hundred and sixty miles.2 St Vincent Ferrier received a sUp of paper from heaven while he was preaching, dropped by a dying man to whom he had some time before given absolution ; and the same saint received a letter from the Holy Trinity.3 St. Eligius was shoeing a horse which would not stand still. He took off the animal's leg, shod the foot, and restored the limb, the horse being none the worse for the procedure.* A man in anger cut off his wfle's long hair which had been her pride. The Saviour told St. Antony of Padua about it. He gathered aU the brothers of the convent together, and after they had prayed her hair was instantly restored.8 Saints Angadrema, Enimia, and Isberga, having vowed their chastity to Christ, did not wish to marry, and yet did not wish to disobey their parents, who desired them to marry. In answer to prayer they became leprous, and so escaped the sin of mat rimony. The last named recovered her beauty by eating an eel picked out of a dead body thrown into a ditch, after which she entered a con vent." The three wise men, kings of different countries, were named Melchior, Balthazar, and Gaspar. AU were buried at death in the same vault. When Balthazar was buried the body of Melchior moved away to give the place of honor to the newcomer. When Gaspar was buried the first two moved respectively to the right and left to make room in the middle for the last of the three. Two dead bishops per formed a similar act of politeness out of respect for St. John the Alms- giver.7 Jesus is declared to have sent St. Agnes of Pulciano a rose in mid-winter." In an image representing the Virgin and Child, the Child Jesus is declared to have left the arms of the Virgin to associate with some boys ; and an image of the Virgin Mary, as a token of her favor, to have taken an apple offered it by a boy on his way from school." These examples of ecclesiastical miracles of a trivial kind are taken at random from Brewer's coUection. It would be easy to multiply 1 Brewer, Dictionary of Miracles, p. 177. » Ibid., p. 64 f. *Ibid p 436 « Ibid., p. 228. » Ibid., p. 228. «Ibid.,pp. 388-390. 'Ibid., p. 439. 'Ibid., p. 448. • Ibid. p. 497. ±5iblical and JMonbiblioal Miracles. 263 their number many times. BUnd must be he who does not discover how almost infinitely below the dignity of the New Testament mira cles they fall. And the cases we have cited, together with others more dignified, illustrate another point in which comparison should be made between them and the miracles of the gospels, namely, the mo tives which prompted the works. There is hardly a mir- Superior mo- r r , tives of the acle of Jesus which did not have for its immediate end New Testa ment mira- the relief of human suffering in some of its forms, or the cies. illustration of some important spiritual truth. He walked on the water, not because he wished to show himself independent of boat men,1 but because he would comfort his disciples in the storm which endangered them. It is a beautiful acted parable. After cursing and withering the fig tree he made his deed an object lesson on the power of faith. We mention these miracles because they fairly represent that class of his works which are most open to criticism as lacking in adequate motive. But let anyone study the motives here side by side with the motives in the nonbiblical miracles and he will see that" in the former they are as much higher than in the latter as the dignity of the former exceeds that of the latter. But not only so ; the eccle siastical miracles are evident imitations of the Biblical ; so that whether we consider them from the standpoint of dignity, adequacy of motive, or originaUty, the advantage in favor of the New Testament is im mense. To this we add what is most important of aU, namely, that the Biblical miracles, especiaUy those of the New Testament, are well, while aU others are ill attested. As we have before pointed Also their su- out, the fact that Jesus professed to work miracles is the tation. best evidence in their favor. The fuU force of this cannot be felt until we have portrayed the Christ of the gospels. But we remind the reader of the failure of Renan's attempt to detract from the power of Jesus's testimony, and of the fact that all other attempts in the same direction have equally fafled. Nowhere in human history has there appeared a man so manifestly superior to all who have preceded and foUowed him, in point of honesty, insight, and beneficence. His testi mony to a supernatural power by which he did his works is as strong as it is possible to make testimony for any fact whatever. Any ordi nary human testimony dwindles into insignificance in comparison with it, whatever may be the point in dispute. The man who can deny that Jesus wrought miracles, in the face of Jesus's own prof ession that he did work them, thereby proves himself incapable of appreciat- 1 As in the case of some of those who sailed on their cloaks. 264 Foundations of the Christian Faith. ing the character of Jesus. But even if one were disposed to dissent from that proposition he could not dissent from this one, that mira cles attested by Jesus Christ are better attested than by any other per son whatsoever. So, then, there is a criterion by which we may as cribe to the miracles of the gospels a warrant not possessed by any others. It is the fourfold warrant of higher dignity, higher motiva tion, higher originaUty, and higher attestation. And these criteria exist in a degree so eminent that none but a determined denier of the miraculous, in spite of any testimony whatever, can hold out against them. Strauss's Mythical Theory of the Gospel Records. 265 SECTION H.-THE CRITICISM OF THE NEW TESTAMENT RECORDS. In the preceding discussion we have assumed that the gospel records were at least so far trustworthy that when they represent Jesus as professing to work miracles we may accept such repre sentation as fact. We must therefore first defend the trust worthiness of the gospels to this extent, and foUowing our chosen mode we take the question up in connection with a specific attempt to cast doubt on the miracles as an historical fact in the life of Jesus. CHAPTER I. strauss's mythical theory of the gospel records. It may appear to some unnecessary to overthrow this theory, which among theologians of aU schools has so Uttle standing in the present day. But those who are reaUy acquainted with the facts know that some of the most scholarly unbeUef of the present Many who still generation builds upon Strauss. Haeckel and Huxley theory. take their views of the New Testament almost directly from Strauss. As recently as 1894 a book, by one who professes to have struggled through scientific doubts into faith, claims to find in the doctrine of evolution the fulfillment of Christianity.1 The Christianity of the book is that of Strauss. And Strauss himseU, though he pubhshed his first Life of Jesus in 1835, maintained the mythical character of the gospels in his Old and New Faith, pubUshed in the seventh edition as late as 1874. Many other facts might be given, but these wfll suffice to show us that we are not yet done with Strauss.3 The first fact to be noted is that Strauss rejects the possibiUty of the supernatural. "Our modern world . . . after many centuries of tedious research, has attained a conviction that aU things are linked together by a chain of causes and effects which suffers no in terruption." "This conviction is so much a habit of thought with the modern world that, in actual life, the belief in a supernatural 1 Die Erfullung des Chrlstenthums auf Grundlage der Entwickelungslehre.— Von P. Nordheim, Berlin, 1894. * For example, Strecker says : " The Christian religion has for its founder Christ, per haps a purely mythical personage.— Welt und Menschheit, p. 136. Strecker's book was published in 1892. 266 Foundations of the Christian Faith. manUestation and immediate divine agency is at once attributed to ignorance or imposture." ' These words were a more correct state- Strauss's re- ment of educated opinion some years ago than they are at the° miracu- present. Says Harnack: " Much which was at one time toiVncon- hastily rejected has been confirmed by more thorough investigation and more comprehensive experience. For example, who, to-day, would dare deal with the miraculous healings of the gospel history as earlier scholars did ? "' But the words of Strauss never did state the facts. For there were always men abundantly capable of judging who did not regard beUef in super natural mamf estations as a sign of ignorance or imposture. We have ever with us an arrogant few who consider any variation from their opinions a token of ignorance. The discussion thus far has rendered obvious the fact that there is nothing to hinder the occurrence of supernatural events ; hence the assumption that they are impossible is a gross violation of propriety on the part of an historian. Whether or not they occur is a simple question of evidence. In fact, Strauss seems to have seen this, and also that if Jesus pro fessed to work miracles we must admit the reaUty of them, and so spent his strength hi attempting to prove that Jesus did not profess to work them. Before we proceed to show this, however, it is needful to consider the presuppositions of Strauss a Uttle more nearly. "Alone with the interaction of finite forces does history have to do. Its first law is that of causaUty, in consequence of which the cause of every effect we see is looked upon as involved inextricably with other forces of nature. The intervention in this complex of a foreign supernatural cause would break the causal connection and make history impossible." a This is the atheistic view of history, which we have so often met before, and we have seen that it is entirely false. In fact, the real conflict here, as everywhere, is whether we shall accept a Christian or a non-Christian view of the world. All who have foUowed these pages with care from the beginning will, we think, be convinced that we cannot accept any non-Christian view yet proposed. All history -writing proceeds upon the basis of certain pre suppositions. Strauss has chosen the atheistic, or at least those which come to the same thing as far as history is concerned. Hence he rejects miracle, and must find some way by which to get rid of the testimony of Jesus in its favor. 1 The Life of Jesus, vol. I, p. 59. a Das Christenthum und die Geschlchte, Leipzig, 1895, p. 18. ¦ Leben Jesu fur das deutsche Volk, s. 4, 5, cited by Beyschlag, Leben Jesu, vol. 1, p. 20 f. Strauss's Mythical Theory of the Gospel Records. 267 It is to be noted, however, that Strauss will not say positively that Jesus wrought no miracles. "It is possible that Jesus may have wrought numerous miracles." "That Jesus censures the seeking for miracles (John iv, 48) and refuses to comply with any one of the demands for a sign does not in itseU prove that he might not have voluntarily worked miracles in other cases when they appeared to him to be more seasonable." ' Nevertheless, after discussing the question, he reaches the conclusion "Jesus would appear to have here repudi ated the working of miracle in general,"2 and adds: "This is not very consistent with the numerous narratives of miracles in the gospels, but it accords fuUy with the fact that in the preaching and epistles of the apostles, a couple of general notices excepted (Acts U, 22 ; x, 38 ff.), the miracles of Jesus appear to be unknown, and every thing is built on his resurrection." His entire treatment of the miracles attributed to Jesus consists in an attempt to show that the records of miracle have practically no foundation in fact, but that they are the result of the tendency to myth found in the thinking of aU nations. Although the main purpose in quoting the above was to show that Strauss means to deny a profession of miracle-working to Jesus, we must look at it from another point of view also. Why did the apostles not make more of the miracles of Jesus U he whythemira- wrought so many? Perhaps no one will ever be able Sei0eJnot to give a sure answer to that question. But their ™u°enttyrai- comparative sflence does not prove that the miracles Apostolic were unknown to them. At most it proves that they andateach? were not regarded as essential in the propagation of ing' Gospel truths. And this is exactly the position of Jesus. He un doubtedly wished men to believe on him for what he was rather than for what he could do for them, or for the wonders he could perform in their presence. It would have been easy to have degraded the Gospel to a mere message of healing for bodily flls, or worse yet to a display of power to work wonders. The miracles of Jesus were so wrought as to leave the impression upon the disciples that he was greater than his miracles, and that to possess him was more than any temporal benefit he could bestow on them. And yet, whfle they did not emphasize the miracles of Jesus in their preaching, they believed in the reaUty of the miracle of his resurrection and preached it every where. Besides, they professed to work miracles, and this they would surely not have done had they not known that their Master 1 The Life of Jesus, vol. ii, p. 453. s Ibid. 268 Foundations of the Christian Faith. performed them. So that we may, nay, we must, assume that the apostles knew of the miracles of Jesus. How then does Strauss account for the miracle stories in the gos pels U Jesus did not profess to have wrought them ? It is to be noted here that he professedly rejects aU methods of accounting for them which attribute fraud to Jesus or the writers of the gospels. The myth grew ; it was not invented. In so far we must accord to Strauss a more profound insight into the character of Jesus and the apostles and early disciples than many of his predecessors and successors.1 A few citations wfll tell the story of his actual mode of procedure. "The expectation of a Messiah had grown up among the Israelitish people long before the time of Jesus, and just then had ripened to full maturity. And from its beginning this expectation was not indefinite, but determined, and characterized by many important The mythical particulars. Moses was said to have promised his people theory stated. a pr0phet iike ^to himself (Deut. xviii, 15), and this passage was in the time of Jesus applied to the Messiah (Acts Ui, 22 ; vii, 37). " "In the old national legends the prophets were made illus trious by the most wonderful actions and destiny. How could less be expected of the Messiah ? Was it not necessary beforehand that his Ufe should be adorned with that which was most glorious and impor tant in the Uves of the prophets ? Must not the popular expectation give him a share in the bright portion of their history, as subse quently the sufferings of himseU and his disciples were attributed by Jesus, when he appeared as the Messiah, to a participation in the dark side of the fate of the prophets (Matt, xxiii, 29 ff. ; Luke xiii, 33 ff. ; comp. Matt, v, 12)?" "In general the whole Messianic era was expected to be full of signs and wonders. The eyes of tha blind should be open, the ears of the deaf should unclose, the lame should leap, and the tongue of the dumb praise God (Isa xxxv, 5 f. ; xiii, 7 ; comp. xxxii, 3, 4). These merely figurative expressions soon came to be understood UteraUy (Matt, xi, 5 ; Luke vii, 21 ff.), and thus the idea of the Messiah was continuaUy fined up with new details, even before the appearance of Jesus." "In no case could it be easier for the person who first added any new feature to the de scription of Jesus to beUeve, himself, its genuineness, since his argu ment would be: Such and such things must have happened to the Messiah ; Jesus was the Messiah ; therefore such and such things hap pened to him.'" "Not only was it predetennined in the popular • However, he does not entirely deny conscious Intention of fiction. See Life of Jesus, VOL 1, p. 67. « The Life of Jesus, vol. 1, pp. 65-67. Strauss's Mythical Theory of the Gospel Records. 269 expectation that the Messiah should work miracles in general, the particular kinds of miracles which he was to perform were fixed also in accordance with Old Testament types and declarations. Moses dispensed meat and drink to the people in a supernatural manner (Exod. xvi, 17); the same was expected, as the rabbins expUcitly say, from the Messiah. At the prayer of Elisha eyes were in one case closed, in another opened supernaturaUy (2 Kings vi); the Messiah also was to open the eyes of the blind. By this prophet and his master even the dead had been raised (1 Kings xvn ; 2 Kings iv) ; hence to the Messiah also power over death could not be wanting." 1 "A frequently raised objection remains, for the refutation of which the remarks above made upon the date and the origin of many of the Gospel myths are mainly important, the objection, namely, that the space of about thirty years, from the death of Jesus to the destruc tion of Jerusalem, during which the greater part of the narratives must have been formed — or even the interval extending to the begin ning of the second century, the most distant period which can be aUowed for the origin of even the latest of these Gospel narratives and for the written composition of our gospels — is much too short to admit of the rise of so rich a coUection of myths. But, as we have shown, the greater part of these myths did not arise during that period, for their first foundation was laid in the legends of the Old Testament, before and after the Babylonish exile ; and the transfer ence of these legends, with suitable modifications, to the expected Messiah was made in the course of the centuries which elapsed be tween that exile and the time of Jesus. So for the period between the formation of the first Christian community and the writing of the gospels there remains to be effected only the transference of Mes sianic legends, almost ready formed, to Jesus, with some alterations to adapt them to Christian opinion and to the individual character and circumstances of Jesus, only a very smaU proportion of the myths having to be formed entirely new." 1 The Life of Jesus, vol. ii, pp. 451, 452. 270 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. CRITICISM OF THE MYTHICAL THEORY. The quotations we have made give the substance of the mythical theory and of the arguments in its support. Since miracles cannot be accepted, and it is evident that the early Christians beUeved that Jesus wrought them, there must be some explanation of the origin of the miracle stories ; and Strauss offers us the mythical theory. Let us examine it. In the first place we admit that the Jews in the time of Christ did expect the Messiah to do essentiaUy the works which Jesus did, and that their expectations were based for the most part on the so-caUed types and prophecies of the Old Testament. Of course Strauss rejects prophecy, as belonging to the supernatural; hence he could not make Christ the fulfillment of prophecy. But we who do beUeve in prophecy have just as good a right to take that view of it as Strauss has to take the other ; for he and we agree that Jesus corresponded closely to the Old Testament conception of the Messiah. So that here again the question reduces itseU primarily to that of whether there is miracle in the form of prophecy. Was Jesus the f ulfiUer of prophecy, «... -j ..¦« or was he the creature of those who, knowing what the The identiflca- ° as°IttoJMSe£ Messiah was to be, somehow strove to make the Unpres entable on s*on **ia* Jesus corresponded to the Messiah? If the steahes°ry°f f°rmeri ^ is simple enough ; the Gospel narrators re corded what they saw and heard. If the latter, why should they have selected Jesus ? Did he reaUy perform in their pres ence some of the works of the Messiah ? If so, then Jesus did after aU claim to work miracles, and we have it admitted that this testimony to miracle exists. That is the point we have been contending for. If he did not perform miracles such as they expected of the Messiah his dis ciples must have known that fact. In that case we have absolutely no way of explaining how they came to regard him as the Messiah. Ac cording to Strauss himself the expectation that the Messiah would work certain well-defined kinds of miracles was common. If Jesus did not perform them he could not have been accepted as the Messiah. If he did perform them then the mythical theory is unnecessary to the ex planation of the origin of the miracle stories. Criticism of the Mythical Theory. 271 Strauss himseU sees this dilemma and tries to escape it by talking about the "overwhelming impression which was made upon those around him by the personal character and discourse of Jesus." Yes, Jesus did make an overwhelming impression upon those around him, and he did it by his character and discourse. But his 0ur kn owl- character and discourse are so interwoven with the mir- character' of acles that U we take away the latter we have but a very p/^epeifd- inadequate method of discovering what his character was. the* mUracie And after aU, whatever impression he made, were the stories- disciples such idiots as to be deceived into accepting as the Messiah and suffering in the cause of one who had failed to exhibit the signs which, according to Strauss himself, the Messiah must show ? How ever low down in the scale of intelUgence they may have been the early Christians had not reached that depth. And in fact it takes some thought to transfer from the expected Messiah to any given individual the Messianic signs with the modifications requisite to adapt them to the individual chosen for that purpose. As they thought how these signs fitted the character and circumstances of Jesus they must have at least raised the question whether Jesus had, after aU, done the works the Messiah was to do. If he did not, they must have pro ceeded violently, and in contradiction to the known facts, to attribute miracles to Jesus. So that on that hypothesis we get back to the theory that the early Christians perpetrated a known fraud by pro claiming Christ to be what they knew he was not. Thus the more completely the expectation of the people corresponded to what the early Christians asserted of Jesus the more sure we are either that Jesus did perform the miracles expected, or else that the reporters or their informants were willful deceivers. Strauss does not think that conscious fiction played any very important part in the reports of the doings of Christ. But it Jesus did perform the miracles ascribed to him he was what he is declared to have been, and his testimony to the reality of miracles is valid and incontestable. These considerations render unnecessary any other investigations of the mythical theory of Strauss. StiU, it may not be amiss to point out some defects not noticed above. First, how is it that, Further diffl- with the expectations of the Jews so definitely fixed con- nected with cerning the works the Messiah was to perform, Jesus is theory. reported as having varied so much from the model ? For example, Moses gave the Israelites bread from heaven and Jesus multipUed the loaves and fishes. Anyone who wfll compare the two accounts wiU see that they differ in every particular. Again, Elisha raised the 272 Foundations of the Christian Faith. dead and so did Jesus ; but in how different a manner 1 How are we to account for these variations from the type, and for the form they actually took ? The result of conscious fiction they were not, or else the mythical theory was wrought out in vain. But for acts so whoUy different from the expected type to develop in the minds of the masses, and become current without contradictions in so short a time, is psychologicaUy impossible. The stories as to the feeding of the thousands, for example, i£ developed as myths in the popular mind would have been distinguished, not by the minor difficulties now ap parent, but by their more or less near approach to the type of the Mosaic manna. Second, it is impossible for us to suppose that so en- Ughtened a theory of religion and ethics could have sprung from the myth-making followers of Jesus. They were Jews ; why did they not make Jesus the Messiah of the Jews instead of the principal object of their reUgion ? " All these things can be accounted for only on the supposition that the records contain, in the main, what the eyewit nesses among the early Christians related concerning the words and deeds and character of Jesus. But, third, the theory of Strauss does not at aU account for the subsequent history of Christianity. Can it be possible that a myth would inspire such tremendous enthusiasm of a moral and reUgious kind ? How did it happen that this myth hit upon such profound psychological truths that, for aU ages, action ac cording to them can suffice to transform character, sustain the great est self-sacrifice, and uplift aU civilization ? Men do not gather grapes of thorns, nor figs of thistles." 1 This Strauss admits him to have been.— Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 48. 5 For an excellent criticism of the mythical theory see Nast's The Gospel Records: Their Genuineness, Authenticity, Historic Verity, and Inspiration, Cincinnati and New York, 1866, pp. 179-196. Trustworthiness of the Gospel Records. 273 CHAPTER III. TRUSTWORTHINESS OF THE GOSPEL RECORDS. While the mythical theory is thus seen to be untenable there are other difficulties in the way of the acceptance of the Gospel records. The first of these has to do with the date of their composition. In the seventh edition of his Old and New Faith, published in 1873, Strauss used these words : "Among those who can be reckoned as scientific no theologian can be found who holds any of our four gospels as the work of the author to whom it is attributed, nor of any apostle or companion of an apostle. The first three, together with the Acts of the Apostles, are held to be tendency compilations of the beginning of the second century, whfle the fourth, since the epoch-making in vestigations of Baur, is regarded as a dogmatic composition of the middle of the second century after Christ." 1 These words did not correspond to the facts at the time they were written, much less do they now ; for during the last twenty-five years theological thought has, with respect to the authorship and date of the New Testament documents, undergone an enormous revolution. As to the authorship of the gospels in their present form, it is now admitted that whether they were written by Matthew, Mark, Luke, and John is an unim portant question ; for New Testament criticism has pretty weU estab lished the doctrine that our present synoptic gospels are based on earlier sources ; so that the authors, U not eyewitnesses, wrote from the testimony of eyewitnesses. The situation at the present day is, therefore, weU summed up by Professor Harnack in these words: " There is, in the whole New Testament, probably but one document (2 Pet.) which, in the strictest sense of the word, can be designated as pseudonymous." * As to the date of the gospels, Harnack gives for Mark, 65-70 A. D. ; Matthew, 70-75; Luke and Acts, 78-93; John, 80-110. s If we take the earliest of these dates in each case, and Har nack regards them as entirely possible, our latest gospel was written by the year 80 A. D. If we take the latest dates our latest gospel is forty years earher than Strauss held it to be twenty-five years ago. 1 Der alte und derneue Glaube, p. 41. 2 Die Chronologie der altchristlichen Litteratur bis Eusebius, Erster Band, Leipzig, 1897, p. viii. 3 Ibid., p. 718 f. 274 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Harnack even ventures to predict several things with reference to future theological opinion on these points. He says: "In the Harnack on criticism of the sources of the earhest Christianity we are, Tes8tament.W without question, in the midst of a movement backward records. ^Q tradition." "A time will come, and it is already ap proaching, in which Uttle interest wfll be felt in the solution of the hterary and historical problems in the domain of primitive Christian ity, because that which is to be discovered will have attained gen eral recognition — namely, the essential correctness of tradition with a few significant exceptions. It will be recognized that in part even before the destruction of Jerusalem, in part by the time of Trajan, all fundamental forms of the Christian tradition, doctrine, preaching, and even of church order — with the exception of the New Testament as a collection — Uad become essentiaUy complete, and that it is neces sary to conceive of them within these limits." 1 Turning from Harnack to other authorities we find JuUcher giving the date of Mark as not earlier than 70, of Matthew not earUer than 80, of Luke not earUer than 80. 2 On the whole he is inclined to dates later than those of Harnack, though it is plain that he does not agree Dates given with Strauss as quoted above. Weiss 3 gives the date for by Jiilicher and Weiss. Mark at the end of the sixth decade of the first century, Matthew soon after the destruction of Jerusalem, Luke not later than 80 A. D. These earlier dates ¦ are in close correspondence with those given by Harnack. Zahn, a strict conservative, thinks that Matthew wrote his gospel in Aramaic in 62. Mark he places at 64, Luke at 75, our present Greek Matthew at 85, and John at 80-90. * GeneraUy speaking, then, it is now agreed among the critics that the gospels were composed during the latter half, or, more exactly, the last third, of the first century. But it is also conceded that, if not written by those whose names they bear, they are based upon tradi- Hamack on tions and writings of eyewitnesses.6 It is not our pur- it yCofdthe Pose nere to S° afresh into these questions of date, au- gospeis. thorship, and credibility, but to give the consensus of present-day opinion among those who have bestowed the most care and study upon these subjects. With regard, then, to the credibility Harnack again may be held to state well the present situation. He 1 Die Chronologle der altchrlstllchen Lltteratur, p. x f. 2 Elnleltuug in das Neue Testament, Freiburg, 1. B. und Leipzig 1S94, pp. 192, 199, 206. a Lehrbuch der Einleltung in das Neue Testament, Zweite verbesserte Auflage, 1889, pp. 518 f„ 537, 655. ' Theodor Zahn's Einleltung in das Neuo Testament, Leipzig, 1899. Zweiter Band, pp, 642, 043. 6 Comp. Jillicher's Eluleltimg, p. 232. Trustworthiness of the Gospel Records. 275 says: ' "There was a time — the great public stiU Uves in it — in which it was supposed necessary to regard the oldest Christian literature, in cluding the New Testament, as a mesh of deceptions and forgeries. That time is past. It was an episode in which science learned much and after which science must forget much. . . . The oldest Uterature of the Church is, in the principal points and in the most of the partic ulars, viewed from the standpoint of Uterature and history, truthful and credible." " The number of documents which, Uke the Pastoral Letters, were interpolated in the second century, is very smaU, and a portion of the interpolations is as harmless as the interpolations in our song books and catechisms." If there is an expert judge in matters of historical research, particu larly in the department of early Christian literature, Harnack is one. He is a Uterary critic, as aU historians must be, but he is more than a critic. The historian must ask himself, when his work of criticism is completed, whether what is left is sufficient to account for the effects which foUowed the movement whose records he has been picking to pieces. If not, then he has a tolerably sure proof of the fact that his criticism has been conducted on erroneous principles, and that his conclusions are incorrect. For example, there must be so much left of the real history of Jesus and the disciples after criticism has done its worst with reference to the Gospel records as wfll suffice to ex plain or account for the tremendous results which followed. Hence the mere Uterary critic may give full rein to his critical spirit, whfle the historian must view the events professedly described in the docu ments as part of a chain of historical cause and effect. This fact in a large measure explains the divergences between crit ics. Those who have reference to a historical purpose are obhged to be less destructive than those who keep in mind merely the work of criticism, or perhaps, in addition, a dogmatic purpose. Strauss was principally a critic, although at first he had in mind a dogmatic recon struction of the life of Jesus. And though he wrote two so-called lives of Jesus he never was, in any sense of the word, an historian. Later his critical spirit, divorced from the historical, led him to deny that the gospels give us any clear and consistent portrait of Jesus, and that hence they do not present him as having any positive value for the reUgious life, but only as a problem." There are not wanting to-day men who, lacking the historical but controlled by the critical spirit, affirm that no true portrait of Jesus 1 Die Chronologie der altchristlichen Litteratur, p. viii, » Der alte und der neue Glaube, pp. 76-79. 276 Foundations of the Christian Faith. can be obtained from the gospels. * To their minds it is worse than useless to attempt a Ufe of Jesus. Nevertheless they beUeve in him, Difference be- and affirm that for a personal faith in him aU that is criticism of needed is the Christ of dogma. This may be ; but the critic ami historian, who has to consider Jesus as the starting point historian. of a religious movement such as the world never witnessed elsewhere, must find in him the adequate cause. And since that move ment was weU under way before there was any generaUy accepted dogmatic conception of him the records must one way and another be made to yield the features necessary to constitute him a cause. So that the historian must somewhere put a stop to criticism. Criticism finds its end in itseU. History looks at criticism merely as a means. Therefore we find such men as Harnack condemning unbridled criti cism. Harnack has some respect for the method of Baur, who saw in the writings of the New Testament one uniform principle— that of the supposed strife between the Jewish and the heathen Christians — but he cannot endure the mere critic. He says : * " The presuppositions of the school of Baur are now, one may almost say, universally given up ; but there remains in the criticism of the early Christian writings an undefined mistrust, a method of procedure such as we see employed by an ill-natured states attorney, or at any rate the method of a would-be master (kleinm eisterUche methode), which observes chiefly aU manner of particulars and seeks to construct from them the clear and decisive elements. Instead of a tendency in the principle, the attempt is made to detect aU sorts of tendencies and to prove large numbers of interpolations; or the critic is governed by a skepticism which places the probable and the improbable on the same level." Anyone who is f amfliar with the methods of the average New Testa ment critic must see at a glance that Harnack has here described them exactly. He does not even except Holtzmann ; and we must add to his name those of Weiss, Weizsacker, and about all the rest, although there is a difference in the degree of their assumed infaUibflity. Har nack gives JflUcher a better name than Holtzmann, and deservedly, though JiUicher leaves also the impression that he thinks he can "hear the very grass grow." It wiU be interesting and profitable to hear what JiUicher, in spite of aU he finds of inadequacy and contradiction in the New Testament, 1 For example, Martin Kilhler. See his Der sogenannte historlsche Jesus und der geschichtllche, biblische Chrlstus, Leipzig, 1896. ' Die Chronologic der altchrlstlichen Litteratur, p. Ix. Trustworthiness of the Gospel Records. 277 has to say with reference to the trustworthiness of the synoptic gos pels. "As the synoptics make Jesus speak, as they make him arouse the masses out of their slumber, and comfort them and _ , . ,_ ' Julicher on subject themselves to him in love, unfold to the disciples tne }J,U st- 0 r worthiness the deepest thoughts of the message of the kingdom of of tp Qyo- heaven, fiercely struggle with his enemies among the Pels- Pharisees or Sadducees, and overcome them, so must he have spoken U we are to comprehend the power of his brief activity to transform the world." " It is indifferent how many of the miracle stories are given up, whether he opened the eyes of one or of three who were blind, in how many cases and under what circumstances he conducted his victo rious struggle, not only with sin, but with the misery, sickness, distress, and death which are bound up with it ; the principal point which is to be illustrated by means of the more or less embellished stories, namely, that he acted as one who had power, that he wrought miracles in the manner described in Mark i, 32 ff., can be contradicted only by a pov erty-stricken rationaUsm. . . . Stories such as that of the talitha cumi (Mark v, 41) were not invented, and the idealizing fantasy of no be- Uever whatever produced the Messiah who in the night, in prayer, in the garden of Gethsemane, with heart depressed almost to the point of death, received power to withstand a fearful death in spite of the dullness of his disciples and the degraded character of his enemies." " And U the whole portrait of Jesus which we have in the synoptists unfolds the entire charm which belongs to reality this is not the result of the Uterary skill of the evangeUsts (rather is it the result of their lack of it), nor of the purely imaginative, poetical-creative energy of their source of information, but of the fact that, modestly keeping themselves in the background, they portray Jesus as they found him in the congregation of the believers, and that in turn this source of in formation corresponded weU to the original. As the highest art, so also has the simplest faith ... a marvelously fine sense of that which is pecuUar to its hero." * If to aU this we add the judgment of such men as Hase, Weiss, Beyschlag, Keim, and Edersheim, who, though they do not agree in all the particulars, yet assert, and by their biographies of Jesus illus trate, the essential adequacy of our Gospel records as sources of a rea sonably full portrait of the Ufe and character of Jesus, we shaU see that the trustworthiness of our canonical gospels is reckoned high by the best critical historians of our day. 1 Einleltung, pp. 230-232. Comp. also the weighty words of Harnack in Das Christen thum und die Geschichte, pp. 15-19. 20 278 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION III.-CHRISTIANITY AS A FACTOR IN HUMAN PROGRESS. This is a subject which we cannot, for lack of space, treat with the fullness it deserves. However, as the science of history has to do with it, it cannot be passed over in this' connection. Not infrequently do we read that unbelievers have announced as decaying the power of Christianity to lead the active forces of the world. It is asserted that The growth of science and practical interests now absorb the attention Christianity . . .... in numbers, of men, to the exclusion of the rehgious point of view, and that they are also the prime forces which control in human affairs. That there is in many quarters an alarming estrangement from the Church is undeniable by the careful observer. And it is f oUy to deny that this state of things is in a good measure due to a mistaken pohcy on the part of the Church, which has been the professed representa tive of the Christian reUgion. StiU, U anyone labors under the impres sion that as a whole the Church is losing its grip upon society he needs but study the statistics to see that never did it make such rapid strides numerically as it has been making during the century just coming to a close. In the year 1500 A. D. there were, approximately, one hundred millions of professed Christians in the world. In two centuries the num ber was increased by fifty-five millions ; whfle in the one century from 1700 to 1800 the gain was forty-five millions — nearly as much as in the two centuries preceding. From 1800 to 1880 the Christian population of the earth increased 210,900,000, and from 1880 to 1890 the gain was 82,865,000 ; making a total Christian population in 1890 of 492,865,000— a gain in ninety years of 292, 865, 000.1 At this rate the Church is not likely to disappear from the face of the earth in the immediate future. But aside from the growth of church membership, and in spite of the unideal lives of Christians, the influence of Christianity was never And in its in- so prevalent in the ethical Ufe of the world as it is to- nuence upon public opin- day. There are some facts which have become so ap ion and pri- vate life. parent that they may be regarded as commonplaces ; for example, that there is no labor question in countries not influenced by Christianity, for the reason that only Christianity can inspire in the masses the desire for better conditions. That on the one side the masses take a too material view of the improved conditions to which 1 See Dorchester's Problem of Religious Progress, revised edition, New York, 1895. Christianity as a Factor in Human Progress. 279 they aspire, and that, on the other side, too few are willing to grant justice, not to say love, to the classes which have been so long op pressed is no fault of Christianity. So far as it does not spring from the impossibility of immediately changing the status quo it arises from the anti-christian selfishness and materiaUsm which Christ has done so much already to banish — a work which the enemies of Christianity have in aU ages hindered from rapid completion. Another common place is that U these great wrongs under which the world groans are ever to be righted it must be by the banishment of selfishness and sin and by the introduction of the law of love — both of which are essen tial elements of the Christian scheme. The laboring classes every where recognize this, and however they may hiss at the mention of the Church they wfll applaud the name of Christ, and, whether they are right or wrong in their estimate of the facts, they hate the Church just in proportion as they think it does not represent the spirit of Christ. It can never be said that Christianity is no longer able to lead the world's progress while the highest conceptions of progress are all found, germinaUy or expUcitly, in the teachings of the Nazarene. It is very easy to find fault with the Church and with Christianity considered simply in its historical manifestations. On .the other hand, it is difficult to show that Christianity is in anywise to blame for the perversions of it which have been such a scandal to all right-minded persons. In judging of these perversions, however, we must always remember that the critics of Christianity compare the great wrongs of Christian history with the teachings of Christ as the standard. Remove from history every trace of Christian principle, and let the same men judge of the same deeds by the non-Christian standard, and they would not appear to the critic so grossly wrong. This is an evidence that the standard of right has very greatly changed under the influence of Christianity. We shaU take up the relation of Chris tianity to ethical Ufe a few pages further along in a more thorough manner. Here it is sufficient to point out and to emphasize the fact, admitted even by enemies of our faith, that it is not the teachings of Christ that are at fault, but the use or abuse of them by professed foUowers of Jesus. And it ought also to be said that it is not alone a hypocritical difficulty with which we have here to deal. Relatively, very few professed Christians have been, or are, hypocrites, at least fundamentally. Only occasionaUy does one meet a human being so depraved that he pretends to be a foUower of Christ when he knows he is not, though it must be confessed that large numbers fall short of the strict conscientiousness required by the gospels. 280 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Many there are, however, who do not so much profess to be foUow ers of Jesus as desirous, though aU too weakly desirous, of Uving ac cording to the teachings of Christ. Their inward propensities to evfl, Why Chris- or their outward temptations, are too strong in compari- tianity has ... . , , m, -, not been son with their purpose to do right. They do wrong, and more effect- , , , , ivein trans- they know it; yet, not because they would be hypo- worid. crites, but because they will not cut themselves off from the good influences of the Church, they remain members of it, to its disgrace, feeling that in the Church there is some hope of improve ment, whfle out of it there is none. The Church, on the other hand, hesitates to discipline to the last extreme of excommunication (the word is not used with its Roman Catholic implications), thinking of itself rather as a family which must strive as long as possible for the betterment of all its adherents. Another reason why Christianity has not been more effective is that it has not been understood, and hence not appUed in aU its purity and strength to Ufe. This is scarcely astonishing when one considers the exalted nature of the teaching of Jesus and the inteUectual and moral dullness of men. The Gospel of Jesus Christ of necessity came to men who were fll prepared for its comprehension. Its point of view was whoUy different from their own. When, for one reason or another, they became Christians by choice, it was impossible that they should comprehend aU the significance of what they had done. Like any other new scheme of thought and conduct, it could at first impress itself but partiaUy upon men. Finally such a mass of heathen phflosophy came in this way to be mingled in the thinking of those who sincerely desired to be true representatives of Christ that the Christian elements were not by any means the decisive ones. Chris tianity was looked upon too much from the standpoint of doctrine, and the doctrines were defined with reference to prevailing heresy, and then the stress of necessity held the thought of the Church to this point of view for centuries. Heathen elements also entered into the Ufe of the Church, and Christianity was by so much overlaid with error. All this is a direct result of the failure to apprehend, in its full extent and richness, the real Gospel. As the ages went by Chris tianity was so grossly misunderstood that it was believed men could be converted by the sword, and it was held to be a mercy to employ this method when peaceful means failed. In all these aspects it is a sad history, but they are not the only aspects, and, besides, during all this time the world was becoming at least nominally Christian and was receiving some of the blessings of the Gospel, while the way was Christianity as a Factor in Human Progress. 281 also being prepared for a better understanding and application of its real nature. Here it becomes necessary to mention another serious obstacle to the spread of the blessings of the Christianity of Christ. We refer to the opposition it has met from unbeUevers. This took two forms almost from the very beginning, and they have contin- Effect of unbe- ued without interruption down to the present day. The ing/the upl first is that in which would-be teachers of the Gospel nueiufe of were at heart unbelievers, though they knew it not. ls 'am y' They were constantly striving to put the new wine into old vessels ; to crowd the divine manifestation of the new religion into the narrow forms of human thought. Fearful of anything which lay outside of or which extended beyond the philosophy or science of the day they have as much as possible denied the supernatural, and kept up such a storm against the superstitions of those who believe in miracle as to guide large numbers into a course which leads directly away from the power of God unto salvation. The other form is represented by the conscious unbeUevers of aU grades. They have always rejected the claims of Christianity, often, whether intentionaUy or not, misrepresented it, everywhere ridiculed it, and done their best to prevent its doing its divinely appointed work. When they have succeeded in some measure they have pointed to the faflure of Christianity to do the very work they have endeavored to the utmost to prevent. Those who have done this have not always, nor indeed generaUy, been the foremost in their communities in respect of inteUect or good morals ; but by an almost diabolical diUgence in promulgating their objections to Christianity, by selecting the worst types of church members or of acts done in the name of the Gospel, and by appealing to the natural desire of a wicked heart to find release from the stern demands of the moral law, they have, not indeed won large numbers of youth to their views, but alienated them from the influence of genuine Christianity as completely as though they lived in a heathen land. Then they have turned about and declared that none but women and children cared for the Gospel. And aU these considerations have to do with the faults which his tory reveals in the relation of the Church toward science and material progress. In so far as the Church has ever been inimical to them it has been owing either to an exaggeration of their importance by those who specially favored them, or to a one-sided conception of the Gospel itseU. But, taking the history of Christianity as a whole, it 282 Foundations of the Christian Faith. has not been unfavorable to science nor to material development. On the contrary, wherever Christianity has gone these have at once sprung up in her path. In spite of those who, whether within or without the Church, have misrepresented the truth of Christ, his religion favors freedom of investigation and teaching, though it also favors such use and only such use of freedom as wfll not result in History shows destroying the roots of aU virtue, without which science tianity has could not flourish and material wealth and comfort science and would be a curse. Hence the Church has rightly asked progress. the scientists, from whom it has received aU of science which it has embodied in its creeds, to give good reasons for a change, and to prove the new views before they are generaUy promulgated. She has refused to overturn at the behest of the science of one age what the science of a preceding age demanded she should beUeve; and especiaUy has she been jealous of the encroachments of any so-called science which comes professing to overthrow Christianity itseU. This is the real truth of the relation between the Church and scien tific progress, although there have been times and individuals that have unnecessarily placed obstacles in the path of research. For such folly the cause we love suffers even now ; for our enemies make the most of it. But, we repeat, taken as a whole, the Church has, even in its Roman Catholic form, been favorable to the progress of science and to the rational enjoyment of wealth and refined civiliza tion. And as for the Christianity of Christ there is absolutely noth ing in it to interfere with them. Impartial history wfll discriminate between Christianity and the perversions of it which have passed for genuine under its name ; it wfll point out the blamelessness of true Christianity and its adaptability to aU true progress ; it will discern the faults of the Church, but it will not overlook its immense services to the world. At the hands of impartial history Christianity wfll receive nothing but praise ; and it wfll not be censured for the faflure of men to submit to its high demands, to understand and properly apply it, nor for the hindrances placed in its way by unbeUevers. Atheistic Egoism. 283 DIVISION IV. THE STRUGGLE OF CHRISTIANITY OTTH ANTICHEISTIAN ETHICS. Under this head it will be necessary to consider : 1. Proposed Sub stitutes for Christian Ethics ; 2. Fundamental Objections to Christian Ethics ; 3. Incidental Objections. However, it must not be expected that non-Christian ethics shaU be treated systematicaUy. All that is here proposed is a consideration of the more important of those ethi cal systems which are opposed, and only in so far as they are opposed, to Christianity. SECTION I.-PROPOSED SUBSTITUTES FOR CHRISTIAN ETHICS. CHAPTER I. ATHEISTIC EGOISM. This is the extreme form of the atheistic ethic. It is represented most brutally by Max Stirner,1 who, not content with Feuerbach's a representation of the idea of God as an illusion, condemned even the somewhat altruistic elements of Feuerbach's theory.3 But as few atheistic ethicists are wholly in sympathy with the extreme position of Stirner we shaU choose as the representative of atheistic egoism Wflhelm Strecker,* who has the express sanction of such a man as Buchner and whose work, published as late as 1892, may therefore be regarded as belonging to the present day. Strecker recognizes the existence of a moral law, unwritten, but nevertheless known to us, and asks how we come to this knowledge, what is the content of the law, whence it came, who gave it, in what the good consists, and why we should do the good. In answer he says this is not inborn, since it 1 Pseudonym for Caspar Schmidt. See his Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum, Leipzig, 1845. > See his Wesen des Christenthums, Leipzig, 1841. 8 Comp. Nippold's Handbuch. der neuesten Kirchengeschichte, Dritte umgearbeitete Auflage, Dritter Band, Erste Abtheilung, Berlin, 1890, p. 195. * Welt und Menschheit, already frequently referred to. Our references to his work in this connection will, unless otherwise stated, be found on pages 95-112. One is forcibly reminded, by the conclusions of the writers referred to, of Weygoldt's prophecy as to the outcome of religlonless ethics. See his Darwlnismus, Religion, Sittlichkeit, Leiden, 1878, pp. 137-153. 284 Foundations of the Christian Faith. is so diverse in different ages and races. Whoever does not beUeve in the existence of God cannot beUeve that he gave any determi nation to our lives. The final purpose of aU our conduct is happi ness, which consists in the effects of certain definite agreeable feelings Strecker's and in the absence of others which are disagreeable. statement of . „ , , . ,, , . , , „ this ethics. The securing of agreeable and the banishment ot pain ful feelings is the purpose of our impulses and passions, in whose perfect satisfaction our happiness consists. It often occurs that the attainment of a pleasurable emotion or the prevention of a painful one is possible only by denying ourselves of some other pleasure. These are the cases in which the moral law comes into play. When there is no conflict of pleasurable feelings then gratification is eth- icaUy indifferent. The ethicaUy good may be designated as those sentiments and actions which, a choice being possible between several feelings, are directed toward that pleasure which in our judgment is most permanent. It is the appUcation of the precepts of prudence and wisdom in the securing of the highest and most enduring pleas ures where several pleasures are possible. The purpose of all our efforts or sufferings for the common good is always our own happi ness. This rightly, since the community has its only justification in what it can do for the individual more than he could do for himseU were he in a condition of segregation. Many acts of friendship are performed chiefly in the expectation that we shaU receive an ade quate return from those whom we serve. In other cases we perform such services, not for a like service in return, but because of the recog nition, gratitude, love, respect, or reverence the beneficiaries wfll show us. In noble souls even this is not needful, since they are satis fied with self -approval. In stfll other cases we act because we have a passionate inclination toward it which can be gratified only by action. Virtue is the disposition to perform ethicaUy good acts and pre supposes strength of wiU to choose the higher and permanent rather than the lower and temporary pleasures. The estimate in which we hold a virtuous action is not dependent on the freedom of the wfll ; for we admire and honor strength of wfll in matters of ethics no more than we do beauty of form, skill, or talents, which are in no way dependent upon the wfll. We revere artists, inventors, and poets without reference to their ethical qualities. This, then, is one of the forms, and a principal one, which atheis tic ethics takes. It is a not very refined selfishness. SeU is first of aU to be considered. One is virtuous in proportion as he acquires a strong and steadfast purpose, not to do right, but to secure bis highest and Atheistic Egoism. 285 most lasting satisfaction at the expense of his lower and more tem porary gratification. And this ethics expressly reserves the right of each one to be his own judge of what pleasures will afford Its practical him the highest and most enduring satisfaction. ' ' LUe is e"ect short," says one, " and there is no future. Sensual pleasures afford me a deUght which is at least more intense than any others which I, with my tastes, can possibly reach in so brief a period. And as virtue consists in choosing those pleasures which in my judgment are high est and most enduring I wfll be virtuous by choosing sensuality." "LUe is short," says another, "and there is no future; but I desire and can secure the respect of the community in which I hve, and I can secure this only on condition that I restrain certain of my pas sions and devote myself to the welfare of others. I can get most hap piness in this way, and so in this way I will be' virtuous." Now, according to the doctrine of atheistic egoism both are equaUy virtuous, for both have the strength of will to do that which is most pleasing to the actor. This is not taking unfair ad van- Strecker not tage of Strecker's words; it is taking them exactly at stood ner 1)1 i S I' ('¦ TJiTG- what they expUcitly say. Not even the conscience is sented. made a test of virtue in this system ; for it distinctly emphasizes the fact that what one man's conscience forbids another's allows. If one's conscience does not hinder his happiness in a given course it is per fectly virtuous to practice it, no matter what it is. We need not mind what others wish; for "a moral law which required us, regardless of our own good, to care always for the good of others would be per verted and senseless.'' If our own good is not advanced by society's demands upon us we are under no obligation to meet those demands. Such an attempt would be ' ' perverted " and ' ' senseless ! " And as I am to be the judge of what pleasures are most valuable to me, and need give up no pleasures for the good of others unless I think I Relation of shaU get a higher pleasure by so doing, I must be the thefsdciaior* judge as to whether I shaU aUow society to control me or ganlsm- not. Any laws which would forbid my choosing what I regard as my own highest satisfaction would be laws which, in the nature of the case, would forbid my being virtuous, since virtue consists in the strength of will necessary to do what most gratifies myself. It is, perhaps, needless to say that, with such a definition of virtue and the ethicaUy good, society would soon become an impossibility. Indeed, one can hardly believe that Strecker means what he says. Yet it is there in unequivocal language ; and it is, apparently, written in cold blood. Very certain it is that he regards himself as occupying a 286 Foundations of the Christian Faith. scientific as compared with the alleged nonscientific Christian stand point. Egoism is bad enough when the actor is required to beUeve that an other (as, say, God, or the general consensus of opinion) sets the standard of what wfll secure him the greatest happiness. But when virtue — the ethically good — is made to consist in the strong determi nation to live in such a way that the individual so Uving shaU obtain his highest happiness, and then the individual is aUowed to be his own judge of how he can secure the highest happiness, the case is doubly serious. All our ordinary ideas of virtue are subverted by such a theory. AU actions are made equaUy virtuous if they only tend, in the judgment of their performers, to secure their highest happiness. Is it replied, That is not what Strecker meant ? Then we ask in re turn, What did he mean ? The same thought runs through the entire section comprised in the eighteen pages in which he treats this sub ject. It recurs and recurs again. No one has a right to say he meant something different from what he expUcitly said. We have no right to take a single passage out of its connections — or for that matter in its connections, especiaUy U elsewhere the author in question modi fies the thought by other utterances— and make it stand for an author's whole thought. But we have not done this. We have taken his whole section devoted to this subject and it teaches the doctrine stated in our analysis of it. Our only resource is to accept so lengthy and explicit a discussion as representing his own thoughts ; and we are at liberty therefore to refute it by showing consequences of the doctrine which he either did not foresee, or which, U he foresaw them, did not shake his faith in his position. There is this further remark to be made. Since this atheistic egois tic system professes to be much superior to the Christian system, TcompTreed wbich Strecker severely criticises, we feel that it is only reaching"! fair for the reader to examine Strecker's teachings for Jesus. himself, or, U that is impossible, to read our analysis of them, often UteraUy translated from his pages, and compare them with such utterances of Jesus as are found in Luke vi, 34, 35, and Matt. vi, 1-3, where we are exhorted to do our acts of benevolence benevo lently, and not with reference to what we can get out of them, though we are assured that acts so done are certain of their reward. The German Ethical Culturists. 287 CHAPTER II. THE GERMAN ETHICAL CULTURISTS. The so-called Ethical Culture movement had its origin in America, where it has some strong books to show as the products of its thinkers. We wish to use these, however, in another connection, and hence we confine ourselves here to the Germans. These are not, indeed, all of one pattern, but we choose as their spokesman the late (Berlin) Pro fessor Georg von Gizycki. We give an analysis of his ethics. ' We call those things good which tend to produce an agreeable, or to do away with a disagreeable, condition of consciousness. We call those things bad, on the other hand, which tend toward the opposite result. Hence we do not look to things, but to the spirit, Gizycki's when we wish to know whether anything is good or bad ; the ethics of and to different spirits the same things may be moraUy ture. different." But things produce, in some cases, both pleasure and pain, in which case the surplus determines the good or the bad char acter of the thing. If there is more pleasure than pain the thing is good, and the greater the excess of pleasure over pain the better it is. If, on the contrary, the pain exceeds the pleasure, it is bad, and that in proportion as the pain is greater than the pleasure.3 It is of great importance to remember that the ideas "good for the individual" and " good for the community " are not always identical. When we govern our conduct by the purpose to serve to the best of our ability the welfare of humanity we are moraUy satisfied with ourselves ; we have a good conscience. The good man wiU give up for the common weUare every form of personal happiness except that of satisfying his own conscience.'1 But there is a distinction between good and bad outside of our consciences ; the highest standard of ethical conduct is the general weUare. All the virtues tend toward the production of happiness and the prevention of misery. All the vices have a tend ency precisely the reverse.6 But why should we act for the common weal ? Because such action is right and reasonable, demanded both by conscience and reason. In proportion as a man is weU disposed is 1 As found in his Moralphilosophie gemeinverstandlich dargestellt, Leipzig, 1888. 2 Ibid., p. 11 f. Comp. also p. 17. 3 Ibid., p. 15 f. 4 Ibid., pp. 17-19. 6 Ibid., p. 21 f. 288 Foundations of the Christian Faith. he moved by the purpose to do that which is right and good. There are fewer morally blind or deaf than phy sicaUy. * What distinguishes the moral from the nonmoral man is that in the former the idea of duty, of the right and good, awakens strong feelings of pain or pleasure, according as he thinks of doing wrong or right, whfle in the latter that idea awakens no such feelings, or but very weak ones.2 While the ethical rule or form is found in the common weal, the ethical purpose is not to advance this weal but to do that which is right, the right being determined by the tendency to advance the common weal. If it were not so our consciences would condemn us when we fail in our best endeavors for our fellow-men. s The feeling of obligation arises not from any authority external to ourselves. No command which does not appeal to our sense of duty- is morally binding.4 In the earliest state of man, as in the childhood of each individual, we find no distinction made between that which is commanded and that which is right, on the one side, nor between that which is forbidden and that which is wrong, on the other ; obedi ence was regarded as virtue, disobedience as vice. Man begins to be a moral being when he begins to judge of the ethical quality of that which is required or forbidden, and to act, not only from fear of punishment, but from the consciousness of the lightness or wrongness of the deed.1 Obligation, command, duty, law, express something which is not left to our personal inclination for decision. This is true for the autonymic as well as for the heteronymic significance of the words ; but in the former case it is our own moral feeling which obliges us ; in the latter the wfll of another. The moral penalty is not any bodfly pain, but the condemnation of our own conscience.6 Duties are requirements which have some kind of a penal sanction, but the real sanction of moral duty is self -censure, seU-condemna- tion.7 The moral law is not a law which another lays upon us. It is the distinctive feature of the moral law that it is seU-imposed. The voice of conscience is man's highest authority and judge concerning good. and bad. There is no appeal to a higher court. One can only appeal from the badly instructed to the better instructed conscience.8 The vast superiority of this system over that of the atheistic ego ists is evident. Atheistic it is indeed, and it is in some measure true that pleasure is the criterion of conduct ; but it is not chiefly the pleasure of the actor, but that of those he affects by his actions. It is 1 Moralphllosophle gemeinverstiindllch dargestellt, p. 27 f. a Ibid., p. 96. • Ibid., pp. 112-121. « Ibid., p. 122. » Ibid., p, 141 f. •Ibid., p. 143 f. ' Ibid., p. 148. » Ibid., p. 150 f. The German Ethical Culturists. 289 an altruistic, not an egoistic system ; and yet it is not altruistic in the objectionably exclusive sense, for it makes the great end of moral action right doing, though the criterion of right doing is the general weUare. We have not mentioned his views as to free will, nor shall we dis cuss them, since to do so would lead us too far. Suffice it to say that he suffers aU the iUs which arise in ethics from the assertion that our acts are such as, under the circumstances, could not have been other wise ; though he sets this doctrine in as reasonable a light as possible. The principal fault we find with his ethics is in reference to what it denies rather than to what it asserts ; and its chief denial is the necessity and value of an ethical authority external to our con sciences.1 It is not true that our actions are moral only It . . when we begin to reflect on their moral quality and not ^"f4 lHe^' upon the fact of a command. True it might be U moral vaJue 0,£ an action were differently defined. But, when the common thority. welfare is made the criterion of the good or bad character of an act, to deny moral quaUty where this criterion is not appUed is erroneous. As Gizycki tells us, our consciences demand that we shaU do right. This is in fact the sole function of conscience, properly speaking. For the deterniination of what is right we are suppUed with the gen eral faculty of judgment, which becomes specificaUy moral judgment when it estimates the ethical quality of any act, past or prospective, performed by ourselves or another. In the performance of its func tion of monitor the conscience is always satisfied in proportion to the profoundness of the conviction of the moral judgment. In other words, conscience sanctions us when we act according to our moral judgment, and disapproves us when we act contrary to it. One of the factors by which the judgment determines its decision is the common weal. But it is not the exclusive factor nor even the chief, in such an estimate. The vast majority of man- The impracti. kind are incapable of estimating the common weal. What the common they can and do estimate is the effect of their acts on the JJJeans of de^ happiness of the few or the one with whom they are in w'h'at1" "i! immediate association. Should most men stop to ask rlght themselves whether their conduct was in the interest of the common good they would find the question so difficult of satisfactory answer, in numberless cases, that they would not act at all. In fact, such a definition of morality would, if the attempt were made to apply it 1 On the compatibility of Autonomy and Theonomy, see G. H. Graue, Die selbstandigo Stellung der Sittlichkeit zur Religion, Braunschweig, 1892, p. 156 f. 290 Foundations of the Christian Faith. universally, aU but paralyze human activity. ChUdren, and indeed practicaUy all adults also, must have some simpler criterion of judg ment. Custom is a valuable guide for the well disposed, since it is the expression of the best thought of the general pubUc on questions of morals. Another such guide is parental authority, or the authority of our teachers, legislators, and civil officers. It is true that we dare not submit ourselves without question to their dictation tf we wish to maintain ourselves in our God-given capacity of moral agents, but, on the other hand, the individual dare not defy either custom or ex ternal authority unless he wishes to render the pubUc unhappy— thus violating one of the strongest instincts of a good heart. It is moral to do that which we believe to be right, whatever may have been the factors which determined that belief. And he must be seU-conceited indeed who never gives up his own judgment as to the right, nor adopts that of any external authority whatever. And this suggests another defect in Gizycki's view. He claims that it is just the distinction of the moral law that it is seU-imposed. But is it so ? What is obedience to the moral law ? It is nothing more or The sole con- less than the doing of that which is right and the avoid- tent of the „ , , . 7 . ™, ^ ¦ . , . moral law ance of that which is wrong. What is right or wrong, not self-im- . posed. and why it is right or wrong, are questions which the moral law does not answer. The moral law does not consist of a given num ber of precepts for the guidance of conduct, whether seU-imposed or otherwise, but of just one precept : Do right. Now, whence does this precept come? To say that man imposes it upon himseU, unless by man is meant mankind, is evidently erroneous ; for each individual finds this precept within his own breast long before he could have made it the one imperative demand of his Ufe. Many a man has tried to rid himself of it, though in vain. It adheres to each of us as long as consciousness lasts. Our opinions of specific acts may change ; but, whatever our judgments of right may be or become, conscience insists ever and always on the same thing : Do right. Whether it is the voice of God within us, or whether conscience be the product of the forces of nature, only those who deny the existence and the creative power of God can deny that conscience is of God.1 So, then, neither as to our moral judgments nor as to our conscience are we independent of external authority. We do not care to foUow this atheistic altruism further here. Certain aspects of it wfll come before us again for fuller consideration. 1 On the relation between the moral law and religious faith, see Traub's Die Sittliche Weltordnung, Freiburg 1, B., 1892, pp. 66-93. The Ethics of Monism. 291 CHAPTER III. THE ETHICS OF MONISM. The high claims of monism in reference to ethics would warrant us in anticipating here something almost, U not quite, unobjectionable. In order to give the monists every advantage we pass by the left wing entirely and choose Hoffding as representative-in-chief of the monistic ethics.1 It is necessary here, however, to repeat the fact that mon ists refuse to be classed theoreticaUy with atheists. Whether their ethics are atheistic remains to be seen from the analysis and discus sion which follow. The distinctive feature of monistic ethics as given by Hoffding is found in his discussion of authority in relation to conduct. First of all he emphasizes the profound significance historicaUy Harming ad- of external authority in the development of the human f o'und 111s- race. Entirely without authority would be only such as, nificance of according to the ancient myths, grew up out of the earth, thority. The authority of the family is the most primitive. Following this the authority of civil society. The king, the nobility, and the clergy (priesthood), by means of their physical and mental authority have made human development possible in rude and wild periods. In the confidence and gratitude which the protecting powers awaken is found the germ of the ethical character of authority. As soon as man arrived at the beginnings of associated Ufe he began to feel that he was related, not only to the ruling authorities in the family, tribe, or state, but also to a higher authority which transcends and furnishes the supports for those human societies; namely, the religious authority. Here, for the first, authority can become absolute. A trace of the moral rela tion is found even in fetichism, as for example, in the case of the Negro, who covers his fetich when he is about to perform some act of which he is ashamed. At first only the evil powers are worshiped ; the good powers need no attention, since it is their nature to be good. This, however, is not an ethical idea, but purely selfish. A higher step is reached when the good powers also are worshiped with grat itude. There was a time when it was thought necessary by ethi- cists to declaim perpetually against authority. Now about aUof them 1 In his Grundlage der humanen Ethik, Aus dem DSnlschen, Bonn, 1880. 292 Foundations of the Christian Faith. recognize its great historical mission for the past, present, and future, and there is a tendency to regard its enforcement as a proof of its fun damental position in ethics. But while the importance of authority is thus recognized he raises the question whether the ideas of law and of authority are necessarily bound up together. If I submit myself to the law because it is the ex pression of the will of the authority my motive does not spring from the idea of the law and its contents but from the relation which I sus tain to the author of the law, whether that relation be one of fear, loyalty, or reverence. I attain to the recognition of the law itself only But denies that in a roundabout way. Had another given it I might not piete f oundiv have obeyed it ; had my authority given me an entirely ion o e ics. con^Ta;ry. comman(i I would have obeyed it. The great significance of authority must be recognized ; but it must be denied that the principle of authority is the complete foundation of ethics. It is the educating force in the history of man ; but it is the true purpose of the educator to make the pupil independent of his preceptor. Only that authority is ethically justifiable which recognizes its own relativ ity. Such an authority is that which represents the tradition which one generation passes on to another as its necessary support until it can stand on its own feet. Fear and seU-interest are banished by the consideration that what is to be realized is not human wishes and feel ings, but a definite, fixed order of things in which man forms a van ishing quantity. As long as the feeling stfll continues in man that he is but a member of a great whole, out of which he has sprung and upon which he is dependent, ethics and reUgion wfll, under various forms, make their influence felt. We stand in the presence of a fact which has its ground in the condition and in the nature of man, and which does not stand or faU with the commandments of an external power. The system of ethics whose principles we have now set forth is as much in advance of the system of the ethical culturists as theirs is in advance of the atheistic egoist. So far as the form is concerned mon istic ethics, as portrayed by Hoffding, strikes about the true propor tion of altruism and egoism. Furthermore, it is an ethics which may be designated as for the race and of the race, rather than for the indi vidual and of the individual. The individual has ever to think of himself as a part of a solidaric unit. The high significance of exter nal authority also receives at least some recognition. But it is in the limitations which monistic ethics places upon this external authority that we find its chief source of weakness. In order to avoid repetition we refer the reader to the defense of the Christian view of ethics and The Ethics of Monism. 293 ethical authority for that part of this discussion which relates to the idea that law and authority are not necessarily bound up together. For the present we content ourselves with pointing out the fact that the monistic ethics is also based on external authority, and that that authority is inadequate. That monistic ethics is based on authority is evident from the ex plicit utterances of its best representative, Hoffding. He says : " Law presupposes an authority to which man submits."1 "Only The monistic 6 tlllCS 3i 1 S 0 those authorities are ethicaUy justifiable which recognize based on ex- t < ' T 11 i 1 I M LI- their relative significance." a He speaks of the individual thority. as a member of his race, as finding himself " caUed" to perform his duties ; of his consciousness of being a colaborer in the great task of advancing the progress of human society ; of this consciousness of be ing one with the feeling of obligation, with the cognition of a higher law. 3 But not only is monistic ethics based on authority, it is based on external authority. The individual finds himself "called;" by whom? Not by himseU, as the ethical altruists would affirm, but by the race of which he is a part. To one who sees himself a part of a world-order that order would not appear as physical, but as ethical. "In our deep sense of dependence upon nature we feel gratitude and reverence in the presence of that great connection of things which has secured for us the ripened fruit of the mental life." 4 In aU this it is plain that the attempt is to sanction our sense of obligation, our call to action, by the order of nature as a whole. These things do not arise from ourselves, but from that which is all about us. As Hoff ding says, "Ethics and religion exist in close and exact union." 6 This is the Darwinian ethics based upon the pantheistic philosophy. And the pantheists or monists affirm emphatically the necessity of a world- view, and hence of religion, as the basis of ethics.6 So, then, monism and Christianity agree in giving to ethics a basis of external authority. Now, the authority posited by monism is inadequate ; first of all, because it is too general and vague. Its function is to give the indi vidual the law of his Ufe. But when an inteUigent being But its au- thority is in- submits himseU to an authority the first thing he demands adequate. of it, i£ the submission is to have any ethical value, is that it shall be intelligent. But the God of monism — the all — has neither personality nor inteUigence. There may be cosmic emotion, but design is denied. The lawgiver has no purpose. The world-order may be ethical, but it is altogether uncertain whether it is so. Remove every trace of a 1 Grundlage der humanen Ethik, p. 47. * Ibid., p. 55. s Ibid., p. 56. 4 Ibid., p. 60 f. » Ibid., p. 61. • Haeckel, Der Monismus, p. 45. 21 294 Foundations of the Christian Faith. personal God, which the monist seldom does in his thinking, though he does so by profession, and it is doubtful whether anyone would see in the world the slightest trace of ethical requirement. For U there is no personal God there is no sin ; what we theists call sin is a part of the manifestation of the all. Hence aU the misery which the theists attribute to sin the monist is logicaUy compeUed, even as the materi alist, to attribute to the world-order. We may feel ourselves a part of a whole as much as we wfll ; if that whole of which we are a part affords us so much suffering, while at the same time we are a mere vanishing quantity, we can but regard ourselves as an unwelcome part. We could, under such circumstances, feel grateful only in the sentimental significance of the word, and our gratitude would be mixed with resentment that our lot is so sorrowful here and is without hope for the future. In other words, monistic ethics fails to give us a clear view either of the inteUigence or the moraUty of the present order of things. Without such a view the authority of the order is a totally inadequate basis for the ethics of a being who is inteUigent and would like to be moral U the untoward order of which he is a part did not hinder him. The tendency of an authority less inteUigent and moral than man himseU is to discourage aspiration. We should nec essarily feel ourselves dependent upon a power, not ourselves, which makes, not for righteousness, but unrighteousness ; or at any rate which demands of us a course of conduct for which it sets no example. But another defect of monistic as of Darwinian ethics consists in the very point which Hoffding exalts as a virtue, namely, its relativity. The world-order is a relative authority, therefore it is entitled to be called ethical. If it were absolute it would lose this title. What does he here mean by relative and absolute authority ? A careful study leads us to the conclusion that by relative authority he means one which wfll cease to command when it has done its work and which w h at does does not claim ideality for its requirements. Accordingly, mean by ret on the one side, the time may come when man wfll be a ative au thority? law unto himseU ; and, on the other, man is now under a law which is but partially perfect. Now, it might at first seem as though the former part of this idea of relative authority is just what we may expect to occur in connection with the Christian authority, which ceases to command those who are in Christ and in proportion as they are in Christ. And as for the second part, it seems to corre spond with the idea of a progressive revelation in the Christian Scrip tures. The first point we dismiss; but we call attention to the error in the supposed correspondence between the unideal requirements of The Ethics of Monism. 295 monism and the unideal requirements of the earlier Christian Scrip tures. The unideal requirements of monism result from an imperfect state of human development. The forces at work upon man's moral progress Ue in the nature of things ; and they are forces, not ideals. At every moment each individual has done the best he could. He is a product, not a creator. There is no goal before him ; at every in stant he is at the goal. If this seems to anyone to be an incorrect representation of monism we beg of such a one to eliminate from monism all theistic elements and then judge afresh of what we have said. The unideal character of the Old Testament gave the individual a definite goal which was beyond him. He was caUed on to strive. He was not taught that his wfll and his action were bound by forces without him— that he had always done the best he could. If the Old Testament requirements were not the highest God would some time expect of men, they were at least far in advance of what man had at tained. He was not merely pushing man from behind, he was calling him from before. This difference between the monistic and the Chris tian ethics shows the inadequacy of the authority posited by the former. It is an authority which fails to utilize the best which is in man for his own advancement in the ethical Ufe. Monists will, of course, deny that they have no ideals, but, we repeat, whenever they aUow any ethical ideals they abandon their own chosen position, namely, that the world-order is the authority in ethics. What the world-order is now is the only standard, but it is evident that the world is up to that standard or else the world-order would not be what it is. And, looked at from the purely monistic standpoint, those indi viduals who seem to be morally in advance of others cannot be taken as models ; for there is no fixed standard by which to judge whether their seeming superiority is more than seeming. Only that ethics which allows an absolute standard can legitimately make any use of ideals. 296 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. criticism of antichristian ethical systems. To the above brief consideration of various systems of ethics op posed to Christianity it is needful to add some remarks of a more gen eral kind. Our purpose here is to point out certain dangerous features which are common to aU antichristian ethical systems ; features in herent in those systems, though not always openly avowed, and some times denied. The first of these characteristics is their fataUsm. However this may be denied or explained away the fact remains that U we cannot, The fatalism m any given act, do otherwise than we do our acts are tfan Systems necessitated. No matter though I may do differently of ethics. under Uke external circumstances in the future, because of the smitings of the conscience, what I do at any given time is the only thing I can do at that time. While we have nothing but con demnation to express toward Strecker's ethical system, yet we must once more credit him with a logical consistency and a courage of con viction worthy those who shrink from his conclusions. He says : l "The man of honor and the criminal are made of the same stuff ; and it is not free wfll, but the force of circumstances which has made them what they are. . . . EspeciaUy is it opportunity and temptation to given acts which determine the character and destiny of men." It is difficult to see, under such circumstances, why anyone should feel re morse. Indeed, Strecker * and Gizycki 3 leave no place for retribution, and make the only object of remorse, censure, or penalty the introduc tion of a subjective element into the mind of the criminal or wrong doer which will become a motive for resistance in future temptations, or at most a protection of society against the deeds of the breaker of the law." Now, as to remorse, it must be said that this is a state which springs up in the individual often without a word of censure from without ; and when there is no remorse for an evfl deed we look upon the remorseless as particularly hardened. In fact, he is no more 1 Welt und Menschheit, p. 92 f. « ibid., p. 91. 8 Moralphilosophie. Slebenter Abschnltt. 4 Comp. Martineau's able criticism of Darwin's theory of remorse, in Types of Ethical Theory, second edition, Oxford and New York, 1886, vol. 11, pp.419 ff. Criticism of Antichristian Ethical Systems. 297 to be blamed for his remorselessness than for his deed if he is alto gether the product of forces over which he has no control. Only in case he is a free agent can we censure him for anything. • The second characteristic is the almost complete obliteration of the distinction between good and bad in actions. Logically and intrinsi cally there can be no distinction at all. Here it is in the Obliteration of the distinc- writings of the monists, who professedly bufld so much tion between good and better than the atheists, that we find the most exphcit evil. utterances on the relativity of the ideas "good" and "bad." Says Forel:" "The concepts 'good' and 'bad' are entirely secondary and relative to man ; they have no existence in and for themselves, but only as relative antitheses. ... In fact, in itself there is nothing good and nothing bad in the world, and when we assume these we do it only because behind all these remain our human interests and rela tive concepts, or we must confess that we simply do not know the purpose and nature of the things in question. " Hoffding says : 3 " Hu man ethics, for which the Golden Age, Paradise, is not a lost good, but a goal which, as far as it is possible under human conditions, is to be attained by the efforts of our race, cannot look upon sin or moral evil as anything absolute. It knows a ' not yet,' but no 'no longer.' " By this he simply means that man is not fallen, and hence we cannot speak of him as " no longer " what he was, but as ' ' not yet " having reached his highest moral possibilities. Now, we believe that man has not reached those possibilities, and also that he had not be fore the f aU. But positive or absolute wrong must be asserted by aU who wfll assert any wrong whatever of a moral kind. The opposite doctrine springs from making right and wrong to consist wholly in their bearing on human happiness. As a matter of fact the right tends to make men happy by Uf ting them above the iUs of life and by providing them the joy of realized moral, inteUectual, social, and re ligious ideals ; but things are not right merely because they contribute to the happiness of man.4 This leads us to the position of the Ethical Culturists as represented by Gizycki. He frankly says : s " If we would know what is good and what is bad we must look at last not to the things (acts, etc.) them selves, but to the mind ; and, according as the mind is, the same 1 Benjamin Vetter admits this. Die moderne Weltanschauung und der Mensch, p. 107. a Gehirn und Seele, p. 7. Comp. also Vetter, as above, p. 107. * Grundlage der humanen Ethik, p. 104 f . He uses the word " human " to distinguish his system from theological ethics. 4 Comp. Balfour's The Foundations of Belief, New York, 1895, p. 16 f. 11 Moralphilosophie, p. 12. 298 FODNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH. things may be good or bad." That is, any act, as say, lying, is in and of itseU neither wrong nor right, neither good nor bad, but is good or bad according as the act bears upon the welfare of the world of hu manity. There might arise, according to such a doctrine, circum stances in which lying would appear to anyone not only excusable, but which would make it appear wrong not to Ue. This is the inevi table consequence of the doctrine that there is no absolute standard with regard to human actions, but that each act is to be estimated by itself, and by each individual according to his own mental constitu tion and best judgment as to the effect upon human welfare of doing or omitting it. Here again Strecker does not hesitate to deduce and defend the logical consequences of the hedonistic ethics. Hear him : "So much at least is plain, that the content of the moral law is not continuaUy and everywhere the same, . . . that even people of equal education differ as to what is good and bad, useful or injurious, right and wrong. . . . We ought to regard the property rights of others ; but does the poor mother do wrong when she steals bread to keep her child from starvation ? We ought not to Ue. . . . Dare this command not be violated in the interest of a higher purpose ? ... Is the Ue under no external pressure allowable or justifiable ? . . . Can a phy sician always avoid falsehood when he wishes to comfort a patient, awaken his hope, etc ? ... In the frequent cases in which the tra ditional moral precepts come into conflict with each other no other guide remains to us than our own feelings and opinions. . . . The moral law is different for each different man." ' Now, the ruin which such a doctrine would work in the moral world must be evident to aU who have not blinded their own moral vision by antichristian prejudice. If there are as many different ways of treating truth as there are circumstances in life, then truth is a mere tool, and truthfulness a mere name. But let us suppose that there might be ex treme circumstances when falsehood would be more useful than truth, still this ought to be considered as an evil, not as being equaUy vir tuous with truthfulness ; as an unavoidable compromise arising from the perversity of human hearts, not as admissible by the moral law ; as the choosing of the lesser evfl, not as warranted by righteousness. The right to perpetrate falsehood is evidently very precious to mo- C ar n eri and nistic ethicists, for they aU appear to defend it. Carneri, istsoii truth- m urging truthfulness as the beginning and end of aU fulness. ethics, says : " " The point is not that one shall never speak an untruth, but if one tells an untruth it should be such a case as 1 Welt und Menschheit, pp. 109-111. ' Der moderne Mensch, p. 108. Criticism of Antichristian Ethical Systems. 299 would be justified by every high-minded man. His conduct must be such that all the world will see that truth is sacred to him. ... If he is sometimes compelled to dissimulate nothing can compel him to play the hypocrite." Surely that is a strange conception of the sacredness of truth which could tolerate falsehood. But it is to be remembered that according to monist ethics everything is done for the common good, presumably even lying. On this ground it wfll be difficult to convict the Jesuits of immoraUty when in the interests of the Church, which is to them the source of all good, they practice mental reserva tions. But Vetter also, whose monistic orthodoxy is vouched for by Haeckel himseU, seems to think that absolute truthfulness is whoUy impracticable. He teUs us once more the story of the young man who made a wager that he would utter no falsehood for a whole day, and who won, though at night he had lost his betrothed, his means of earning a Uvelihood, his best friends, and the inheritance his uncle had expected to leave him.1 The fact is that any system of ethics which makes the standard of conduct dependent upon the individual's esti mate of the effect of his deeds upon the happiness of men must faU a prey to all the evil consequences of this defense of falsehood, which would render society impossible and degrade the individual, and pre vent his development of his godlike personality. This whole system of ethics based upon the doctrine of evolution is, or U made the principle of conduct by the individual would be, dan gerous in the extreme to good morals. Its natural effects are hindered only by the Christian training of its adherents. Says Vetter : "In brief that appears here as fact which we before mentioned hypothet- icaUy as the consequence of the process by which man has been de veloped, that every period and every smaller or larger human society has recognized that as good or bad which by its whole tendency was useful or hurtful to the common weal." And in speaking of the fact that Christianity holds up a flxed ideal standard he un- Advantages of dertakes to say that evolutionary ethics offers something standard. better in that it has no stable norm. "The various spheres in Ufe to which the individual man belongs — family and business caUing, com munity and state, society and humanity — embody in themselves the ethical views of very different stages of development. " 2 Except to one who is convinced that the doctrine of evolution overthrows Christian ity and is better than that which it overthrows, it would be difficult to make plain the superiority of an ever-changing standard over one that is flxed, provided that the latter were the highest conceivable. i Die moderne Weltanschanung und der Mensch, pi 111. * Ibid., p. 112. 300 Foundations of the Christian Faith. The changing standard makes men contented with themselves ; the fixed, perfect standard spurs or allures men to endeavor. Besides, there is of necessity confusion as to what is right and wrong as long as there is no rule by which each can judge his conduct. Another difficulty with the evolutionary ethics, whether egoistic or altruistic, atheistic or monistic, is that it degrades morahty to a means instead of setting it up as the goal. The end is human happiness, the Morality a means right conduct. When conduct is just what it goal, in evo- ought to be aU men wfll be perfectly happy.1 In this ethics. natural and theological ethics agree. But with the for mer conduct and happiness are related as means and end, whfle in the latter the end is ethical conditions subjective and objective, and hap piness is the result. Christianity does not despise but prizes human happiness, and is perfectly sure that there can be no happiness of a true and lasting kind where ethical conditions are not perfect and uni versal. It taught this eighteen hundred years before our modern apostles of evolutionary ethics were born. But much as it prizes hu man happiness it regards moral perfection as infinitely superior. In present conditions our best endeavors often fail to bring our fellow- men the happiness we desire, and not infrequently the only happiness the good man secures as the result of aU his labors is that which springs from an approving conscience. This is, indeed, a sufficient reward, but it is not that, or at least not aU of that, which evolution ary ethicists set for the goal. Hence there must be disappointment and perhaps discouragement. With human perfection rather than human happiness as the end of all our moral endeavor we are always sure that no effort fails to accomplish its due proportion of the great task before us. We may have secured no better external conditions for ourselves or others, owing to the neutralizing effects of the conduct of evfl men, but we have, for ourselves at least, approached our goal by every restraint of evfl passion and by every unselfish performance of duty ; while at the same time we have done as much for the ad vancement of human happiness as though we had aimed directly at that, since all agree that happiness depends upon good morals. Another and most serious difficulty with aU non-Christian systems Inconsistent or ethics is that they are partly inconsistent and partly q u ate" mo- inadequate in their proffer of motives for moral progress. Christian In aU good logic nontheistic evolution ought to disre gard motives altogether. Things, like Topsy in Uncle Tom's Cabin, have no bringing up, they just grow up. They are pushed 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, New York, 1883, chap. 8, and especially pp. 134, 137, 138. Criticism of Antichristian Ethical Systems. 301 from behind ; never attracted from before. The morals of the world have grown up as unconsciously to men as they did to our animal an cestors, or as the weeds grow up in the fields ; they grow because it is in the nature of things that they should. Nevertheless, however inconsistently, all moralists speak of motives. But further inconsistency is manifested in that adherents of natural ethics condemn Christianity for sanctioning good morals by rewards and by threatening evildoers with penalty. Yet, what else is this hedonistic basis of ethics but a system of rewards and punishments ? Christianity caUs men to righteousness for its own sake, and promises happiness in addition. Egoistic natural ethics bluntly tells us that the reward is what it is after, the strong intimation being that if hap piness depended upon bad morals its adherents would be bad. But even in systems nobler than the egoistic the chief thing is the reward or the penalty. Right is to be performed, not because it is right, but because it tends to make men happy — to further the common weal. In this Gizycki J is an exception as far as his declaration goes ; but consistently he cannot demand that men shall do right because it is right and at the same time emphasize the reward of happiness as he does, particularly when he condemns Christianity for the same course.1 But, worse than this, the motives possible in naturalistic ethics are inadequate, chiefly because of the anthropology with which they are connected. Many of these ethicists are apparently fuUy persuaded that man is simply a higher animal, with a morality which differs only in degree from that of the lower animals from which he sprang. This is so firm a conviction with some that they even deny any moral sense in man. Carneri says : " Man is, through and through, a vicious animal (von Haus aus ein bosartiges Thier) in whom resides no moral sense."3 In the same connection he goes on to show that any demands upon man which conflict with his nature (as a vicious animal without a moral sense, we suppose) can never be realized. This is a most depressing view to take of man. In comparison with it the most depraved form of the doctrine of total depravity was ele vated and inspiring. Not many, however, would go so far as the doc trine stated by Carneri suggests. Yet the mildest form of this modern anthropology would crush hope were it to become prevalent. " The time is past," says Hoffding, "in which one can console himself with 1 See his section on Das Bewusstsein recht zu thun als der sittliche Endzweck, Moral- philosophie, pp. 112 ff. ' Moralphilosophie, p. 338, where, however, he misrepresents Christianity. > Der moderne Mensch, p. 22. 302 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the supposition that man is the center of the world's Ufe and that everything exists for his sake. The more thought penetrates into the secrets of nature and learns her laws, the more man by the aid of this knowledge can employ the powers of nature for his own benefit, the more does he at the same time perceive that human Ufe is but a van ishing element in proportion to the great whole." J Hoffding thinks this doctrine tends to deprive men of an egoistic view of life, and even to attract attention away from man and his wishes and to make him submit cheerfully to what nature offers him and to devote himseU to the reaUzation of nature's purposes. But as a matter of fact there is nothing in such a view of man to produce the results he expects, but everything to bring about the contrary. If nature's purposes were those of an intelligent being man might be willing to sacrifice himseU in their interest ; but when the fixed order is unintelUgent and unfeel ing, and when tha,t order has brought man into the world only to mock him for his insignificance, there is nothing to arouse either grat itude or hope in the human breast, and without these there would be Uttle activity or devotion. Let it be generaUy understood that man is very insignificant in point of importance, and that he does not even have so much consideration bestowed upon him as to give him more than a span of days, and the effect must inevitably be pessimistic gloom. Men will not submit themselves cheerfully to such a natural order. If they submit at aU it will be despairingly. They may assist each other under such cir cumstances, but it wfll be not as sharers of a larger hope, but as part ners in a common distress.3 It is evident that, whatever we may think of the metaphysical ¦questions supposed to be settled by monism, the system has as yet, so far as its chief living representatives are concerned, not dis engaged itseU from the toils of the materiaUstic ethics. What is needed is freedom from the depressing influence of the evolution ary idea of the basis of moral action, according to which that action is right which is approved by the community; which there- „ , , fore affords no higher standard by which to measure our Conclusion. J conduct and no ideal toward which we should strive. The supposed fact that the processes of evolution will some time bring in the perfect morality for the race may be unquestionable ; but the difficulty with it is that we shall have no way of knowing when we 1 Grundlage der humanen Ethik, p. 60. 3 Comp. Bowne's The Principles of Ethics, New York„1892, pp. 194 ff. j and Balfour's The Foundations of Belief, pp. 26 ff. Criticism of Antichristian Ethical Systems. 303 have attained. By almost whoUy ignoring the fact that effort can change our individual conduct from bad to good naturaUstic ethics loses tha immense advantage which accrues to morals from earnest endeavor. Ancestry and environment are not, whatever non-Chris tian moralists may say to the contrary, the determining elements in the morals of the individual, and need not be, therefore, in the morals of the race. It is entirely possible to hasten the reign of righteous ness. But U men are to strive for this goal they must not be taught that they amount to nothing here and that there is no hereafter. Every system of non-Christian ethics renders high morality logicaUy impossible by ignoring the value of the ideal, and by robbing human nature of its lofty significance. Only in the light of the Christian doctrines of God and of the divine image and immortaUty in man can we find any sufficient reason why the individual should be just, or honest, or benevolent. Under the influence of the great truths of Christianity human lUe becomes incalculably sacred, every moral in stinct finds its fuU justification, and the inspiration to high endeavor is supplied ; whfle at the same time, in the Christian law of love the rule is supplied for the correct appUcation of our moral judg ments.1 1 Comp. Bowne's The Principles of Ethics, pp. 160 ff. 304 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION II.-OBJECTIONS TO CHRISTIAN ETHICS. CHAPTER I. christian ethics and external authority. Before going further it ought to be said that in almost every instance of objection to Christian ethics the objector has taken either a shaUow or an erroneous view of the Christian idea. This arises generaUy from the habit of taking the words of some supposed representative of the ethical views of Christianity as those of a real representative. The Christian reUgion, which includes Christian ethics, is portrayed authoritatively in the New Testament, particu larly in the four gospels, and U anyone wfll give to those records of the teachings of Jesus an unbiased and careful study he wfll see that most of his objections both to the Christian reUgion and to Christian ethics (if we may distinguish between them) are baseless. The ob jections not thus removed are a fair subject of debate between our selves and our opponents. There are four fundamental objections which non-Christian ethicists lodge against Christian ethics. First, that it is based on external au thority. Here again we must turn to Hoffding for the strongest putting of the opposition. He even goes so far as to say that the one who acts because a higher authority commands him to act would obey a reverse command if the same authority ordered it. • He seems to think that the principle of external authority in matters of conduct robs him who submits to the authority of all right to exercise judgment for himself. This is not true of Christian submission, which is purely voluntary with him who submits ; that is, all ought to subject themselves to the authority of God, but those who do so do it voluntarily. Hence a degree of intelligence is presupposed, and this inteUigence leads men to feel that submission to the will of God as revealed in Jesus Christ is certain to secure the best results for all mankind. As it is a volun tary relation it presupposes reflection on Christian requirement after as before submission. Should one conscientiously think that the law of Christ is not the best law there is nothing to hinder his severing the relation voluntarily entered into ; although he who remains outside 1 Grumilage der humanen Ethlk, p. 48. Christian Ethics and External Authority. 305 of or departs from this relation takes upon himseU aU the natural consequences to himseU and others. Now, the law of Christ is not a set of specific rules, but rather a principle. Christ was the end of the law for righteousness to aU that believe in him ; that is, its compulsory force is not felt by the genuine Christian. The true disciple has never found in the precepts which Jesus indorsed any ill to mankind, but benefit only. His ex perience in this regard leads him to think that whenever a question of conduct is involved he need only determine as nearly as possible what Jesus would have done under like circumstances and his per plexity will end. He believes Jesus sinless within and nature of without, and as he loves Jesus he loves and longs for sin- thorny BIn lessness. It is his greatest grief that he faUs short. He Cnristtanlty- believes that Jesus revealed the character of God as perfectly holy ; and he desires nothing so much as to become ethicaUy Uke God. In other words, ethical authority in Christianity is not lodged in God as ruler but in God as an ethical standard. There are authorities on etiquette. They do not command, but they tell us what is proper. We do as we please about foUowing their notions. If they represent social custom correctly we gain or lose in social standing by regarding or disregarding them ; but in no case do we think of obedience in the abject sense of the word. So God, who has a right to command, does not put the Christian into the relation of an abject subordinate obey ing commands, but the Christian adopts God as revealed in Christ as his ethical standard or authority. To him what God is and wills is right in the same sense in which that is socially proper to the man of the world which the Four Hundred are and do in social relations. Perhaps no one will misunderstand the comparison, which is only designed to define the words authority, obedience, and the Uke. The Christian does not regard ethics as on the same plane with conven tional etiquette ; and while our etiquette of this conventional sort may change with the caprice of the Four Hundred our Christian standard of authority is unchangeable. We may come to understand it bet ter, but it is as unchangeable as God. So that the Christian would not obey a reverse command, for he would know it came not from God. But Hoffding goes further. The principal command of Christianity is declared to be love ; but upon closer consideration he finds that we are not to love man for his own sake but for God's sake. Love is not the cardinal Christian virtue, but obedience— submission to God's wfll. Obedience is the fundamental relation to an authority. In 306 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Christianity love is subordinated to obedience, for it knows no love not founded on belief in supernatural authority. Christianity knows no distinction of race or social condition, but it estabUshes a more vital antithesis, that between behevers and unbeUevers, saved and un saved Love and faith thus work against each other.1 It is most astounding to find a man of Hoffding's thoughtfulness taking such a view of Christianity, and asserting that the law of love is realized only as a result of the modern principle of tolerance and that Spinoza was the first to show that love is greater than faith. Did he never The relations read the thirteenth chapter of First Corinthians, where f°iithvinathe Paul expressly places love at the summit, distinctly system.4 ia" saying that love is greater than faith? Jesus made much of faith, but he said that the great commandment is love; and his new commandment was to love one another as he had loved them. It requires a charitable spirit to save us from saying that Hoffding was hard pushed when he had to resort to such a position. As to the modern principle of tolerance, Jesus taught it in its most perfect aspects. ' Modern principle indeed ! How fond men are of taking the things that Jesus taught and pretending they discovered them ! As to the antithesis between believers and unbeUevers, saved and unsaved, it exists only as a sad fact for Christians, not as a principle of social exclusion, as in the case of the distinction between nations and classes. And if it did it would be unchristian ; for Jesus was the friend of sinners, and his followers are only Christians so far as they are like him. This may be hard on some Christians, but it sets Chris tianity right. Love and faith do not conflict in Cihristianity, then ; but faith works by love.3 So also all that Hoffding says about obedience as the cardinal virtue in Christianity is baseless. He does not pretend to find his conclu sions in the Christian Scriptures ; they are his own inferences from the nature of authority. But, as we have seen, he wrongly conceives the nature of authority in Christianity, and hence also the nature of the obe- Hoffding's dience to be rendered. In like manner does he misrepre- misconcep- tions of sent Christianity when he says that Christians are not Christian-ity. to love man for his own sake but for God's sake. It is a fact that we are taught to love man for God's sake ; and it is one of the glories of our religion that we are thus taught. Man does not always appear lovable to man, but we are taught that when men ap pear to us unlovable we must still love them because God, our God, loves them ; and that when our hearts are right, we can love unlovable 1 Grundlage der humanen Ethik, p. 48 f . » Matt, v, 43, 44 ; Luke ix, 52-66. s Gal. V, 6. Christian Ethics and External Authority. 307 men. Until we can love them with our hearts we must love them in deed because God loves them. If we cannot love them for their own sake we must love them for his sake, and our love to him is tested by our love to man. • And this shows us that Christianity requires us to love man for his own sake. Besides, the whole Christian system pro ceeds on the theory that God loved man for man's sake. The Christian is expected to be not conformed to this world but to take God's point of view, and so to love man as God loved man. If there is any one thing well grounded in the entire Christian system it is that as Chris tians we are to love man for his own sake. Should any of us ever think in a pessimistic mood and moment that man is unworthy of love we are immediately taught the contrary by the recoUection that Christ loved us and gave himself for us. In fact, the Chris tian is related both to God and man, to one as vitally as to the other, and the first duty to both is love. "Thou shalt love the Lord thy God and thou shalt love thy neighbor," the neighbor being anyone who needs our help.2 FormaUy, however, the Christian is in the relation to God of a voluntary subject in the sense explained above ; while his formal relation to man is that of helpfulness. Unless, then, Hoffding understands Christianity better than its Founder did, love is the cardinal Christian virtue. There, is, however, another phase of this matter which ought to be attended to here. While the Christian, because he is a Christian, looks upon God, not as a ruler, but as a father,3 and does the Father's will, not from compulsion, but because he loves the same things the Father loves, yet God is an ethical authority in the sense in which Hoffding uses the word, though only for non-Christians, or for those who are striving to attain but have not yet attained the mind which was in Christ. Anyone who knows the human heart knows that it needs external restraints. Hoffding himself emphasizes the educative power and function of external authority, whfle affirming that the authority ceases to be such when the subject of it becomes able to dis pense with it. Now, this is exactly what happens to one who is striv ing to be like the Christ in spirit and conduct. When he does not feel a disposition to do the right he does it because he is commanded. After the disposition is produced he does the thing commanded be cause he loves it, and not because it is commanded. Here again Hoff ding learned from Christ and ran off proclaiming the discovery as his own. But we must guard against being misunderstood. There is and 1 1 John iv, 20. 2 Luke x, 29-37. s Gal. iv, 6. 308 Foundations of the Christian Faith. must be external authority in matters of civil society and ethics unless each individual is to be a law unto himself. This necessity arises The necessity from the perversion of the human heart — which aU ac- asPdist\ne- . knowledge, however they may explain the fact. It fol- fronl ethical lows that it is the duty of good men to submit themselves ments.ire" to regulations and restraints and to the performance of acts which they would not need were they the only people in the world, and which would not exist but for the presence in society of evfl men. In other words, in civil society there are positive as dis tinguished from ethical commandments, and it is the ethical duty of every man to submit to them just because they are imposed by exter nal authority, without which society cannot exist. In the same way there may be positive duties connected with our relation to God- duties imposed by the Supreme Ruler in consequence of the unideal state of the vast majority. If there be such commands it is duty to observe them, not because they are founded in our conception of right, but because wisdom has dictated them. That we do not see the rea son for these commands does not release us from the obligation to keep them. He who does keep them performs an ethical act, for he is doing the right in submitting himseU to a revealed will of one who has a right to speak. Only one who denies a personal God and his rulership and revelation can deny the ethical character of such sub mission. It is not true that in Christianity unconditional authority continually thrusts itseU between the actor and what he would do, and that the God of the Christian is jealous lest we should act for some other reason than because he has commanded it ; • though it is true that the Christian's God expects that what he is and wills shaU be the standard for aU men, whether their horizon is wide enough to comprehend his reasons or not. 1 Comp. Hoffding's Grundlage der humanen Ethlk, p. 48. The Asoertainability of God's Will. 309 CHAPTER II. THE ASCERTAINABILITY OF GOD'S WILL. But it is declared that there is no way of ascertaining what the wfll of God is. Here we shaU have to follow the sinuosities of Gizycki's reasoning in order to trace out the faUacy involved in the objection stated. He first points out that it is generaUy conceded by scholars since the time of Hume and Kant that the existence of a personal God cannot be demonstrated.1 In this he errs, except as the deniers of God are accustomed to arrogate to themselves the exclusive right to be termed scientific. But Gizycki conveniently forgot to state that Kant declares that though it cannot be proved it must be beUeved, and hence acted upon. However, he supposes for the sake of argument that there is a personal God and that his wfll is the foundation of morals : now he asks, How are we to determine what his wfll is ? There are two ways — the study of external nature and supernatural revelation. He argues that, to say nothing of the doubts on the part Gizycki on the difficulty of of many believers in God to-day as to the possibflity of a ascertain ing the will supernatural revelation, it is stfll a question which of the of God. professed revelations contains God's wfll." If we take any one of these as a starting point we do not get a universally valid morahty, but one which is adapted to the adherents of the religion which fur nished the revelation. In discussing this point we shaU have to refer the reader to the lat ter part of this book for a full consideration of the possibility of a supernatural revelation, and for the proof that the final revelation is furnished us in Jesus Christ. At present we call attention to the fact that Christian morality is adapted to aU men, and that it is, strictly speaking, capable of being applied among aU nations. It is a univer sal moraUty, as weU suited to the orient in which it originated as to the Occident where it has won its chief victories. But at length Gizycki grants us the superiority of Christian morals, shirking the real consequences of the concession by asking whether we shaU fol low the moraUty of Romanism, of the Greek Church, of the Luther ans, or Reformed, or, in general, which. Gizycki ought to know that as we go to Kant for the Kantian philosophy in its pure form so we go 1 Moralphilosophie, p. 330. a iwd., p. 335. 22 310 Foundations of the Christian Faith. to Christ for the pure form of Christian ethics. In the New Testa ment, contrary to the assertion of Gizycki,1 we have an original and His difficulty complete as weU as thoroughly seU-consistent and easily imaginary, comprehensible moral system. That some differences of opinion exist among theologians as to the genuineness of certain pas sages, or even certain books, of the New Testament does not, as Giz ycki pretends,2 make morality dependent upon textual criticism ; for everything essential to the system of Christian moraUty is unequivo cally taught in many unquestioned passages and books of the New Testament. Again, it is asserted that tf we knew the revelation to be from God we should have no method of determining that the revealed ethics was good unless we had a previous knowledge of good ; and U we had the knowledge of good by which to test a revelation we should not need the revelation.3 But it is not true that we could not test the ex cellence of revealed ethics unless we had a previous and adequate knowledge of the ethicaUy good. Briefly, what we have revealed in the New Testament ethics is the law of love. The originaUty of that law as given by Christ we shall discuss in the next chapter. For the present assuming it to be original, we affirm that it might be per ceived to be good by those who had previously no approach to a cor rect conception either of the good or of love as a law. The conscience, which, however we may explain its origin, prompts every man to do right, by its own action gives each of us to understand that there is a right and a wrong, a good and a bad. This much may be said to be revealed by conscience. But a moral standard, as, for example, the general welfare, by which men may test their actions is the possession of very few, most of us acting according to our instincts rather than understandings. Yet there are few so low down in the scale of intel ligence as to be unable to see at a glance the value of any standard which might be at all adequate to the measurement of character and is the knowl- conduct. The ppwer to perceive this value is not so veaied' im> much conditioned by a previous knowledge of ethics as pVnd'en8! it is by a mental capacity. Were it not for our posses- vious knowl- si°n 0^ sucn a power as this, by which we discern almost etfTicaffy intuitively the value of any new scheme or device pre- g0° ? sented to our thought, we could make no progress, or at most but very slow progress, in knowledge or insight. Some knowledge we must have to test the value of revealed ethics, but not the knowl edge revealed. Progress in ethical knowledge does not differ in this > Moralphllosophle, p. 336. • Ibid., p. 337. • Comp. ibid., p. 331 f. The Ascertainability of God's Will. 311 regard from progress in other knowledge imparted by instruction. The wise teacher prepares the way for the impartation of a great truth, but he does not expect a previous knowledge of that truth in order that it may be understood when imparted. For this purpose a far lower degree of knowledge is adequate. In particular, Gizycki tries to destroy the value of the command ment, "thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself," by saying, along with other things of less moment, that it reduces to the standard of religionless ethics, namely, the weUare of humanity.1 Now, let us suppose that, as he says, we need no revelation to teach us to seek the welfare of mankind, or, in other words, to love our neighbors as our selves; what we are after in morals is not merely knowl- Not mereiy edge, but also motives and impulses to action. We think but°aisodmo^ the attentive and unprejudiced reader has discovered ere tives neeaed- this that there is nothing in religionless ethics to impel men to seek the general weUare. Even U, as some suppose, our earliest instincts are altruistic, contact with Ufe soon develops in most men an over powering egoism, as aU history illustrates. The majority of man kind, sad to say, are Uke Ishmael, with their hands against every man, and every man's hand against them." Considerations of self may lead men who have no love for each other to combine rather than compete ; but this merely mitigates the strife somewhat, and does not overcome the egoism so powerfully active in human hearts. For this purpose there must be something which is of a higher order than the world affords. There must be not only a divine revelation to our minds and hearts, but also a divine transformation of our natures. Conscience must somehow be afforded the cooperation, not alone of the moral judgment, but also of the social feelings. We must be born again before we can reach our best in this regard, and in pro portion as the new nature is complete wfll we be able to execute what our judgments dictate. 1 Moralphilosophle, p. 337. J Gen. xvi, 12. 312 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IH. ORIGINALITY OF CHRIST'S LAW OF LOVE— REWARDS AND PUNISHMENTS. But it is erroneous to suppose that we need no revelation to teach us to love our neighbors as ourselves. It is frequently asserted that the law of love was taught by the Buddha, by Confucius, by the Stoics, and others, prior to or independent of Christ.1 The effort to dispute the originaUty of Jesus is, however, a failure. That he did not bring into the world an ethics or a reUgion for which no prepara tion had been made by previous revelations and providential lead ings is not denied but asserted in the New Testament. It is one of the evidences of the wisdom of the Nazarene Carpenter that he did not come to destroy but to fulfiU. But that he brought something new is only questioned by intense partisans ; and even some of them are fair- Testimony to minded enough to acknowledge his superiority to aU who naiity'^of went before, or who have foUowed after. Says WeU- jesus. hausen:3 "Jewish scholars. . . . would have us beUeve that all he (Jesus) said is found in the Talmud. Yes, aU and much more, nteov i/uov travrSc. The originaUty of Jesus consists in the fact that out of the chaotic desert (of thought) he recognized and with greatest possible emphasis brought to our attention the True and the Eternal." Even more definitely does Vetter admit the originaUty of Jesus. Speaking of the growth of the conception of duty to our fel low-men he says that "the idea of the universal brotherhood and equal rights of aU men was first comprehended by Christ in all its inner truth and fuU depth," and that this idea was made the banner which his first followers carried with aU the enthusiasm of a new view of the world.8 These concessions, great as they are, do not comprehend the whole truth of the matter. In the writings or sayings of all others the ap proaches to the love which Jesus inculcated as the substance and standard of conduct the doctrine of love was but occasional, not fun damental—not the one essential ingredient in ethics. In fact, it was negatively rather than positively put. It was not " love as you would 1 So Strauss, Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 85 f., and generally among antichris tian ethicists. a Israelitlsche und jtldische Geschlchte, 2te Ausgabe, Berlin, 1895, p. 351. 8 Die moderue Weltanschauung und der Mensch, p. 112. Originality of Christ's Law of Love. 313 be loved," but " do nothing you would not have others do to you." It was a considerable advance to have the positive side put, Love as taught "Do unto others as you would that they should do unto aVdby you." The negative would prevent much injustice and otDers- unkindness, but the positive would produce much justice and kind ness. Nevertheless, Jesus did not state his moral code in the Golden Rule. When he summed up the great commandments of the law which he came to fulfill he gave the words, "Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyseU." How, now, does this " love thy neighbor as thyself" differ from the standard of the general weUare, or the welfare of mankind ? If it stood by itseU it would still differ from the Golden Rule in that it requires love rather than action; but at the same time a love which is sure to lead to action. Self-love is not selfishness, for the selfish man does not love himself. True seU-love is thoughtful for our own good, and active in the effort to secure it. It is expected, there fore, of the one who loves his neighbor as himself that he love man kind thoughtfully, not sentimentally nor passionately alone, and that he be active in his endeavors to secure the good of mankind. One might seek the general welfare as a mere matter of duty while lack ing any genuine love for mankind.1 Not such can be the attitude to ward men of one who would fulfill the command of Christ. Such an one must cultivate a spirit of love as a feeling toward all men. This is evident from the "new commandment" which Jesus Nature of. the gave to his disciples, " As I have loved you, that ye also by Christ. love one another."" His love to them was to be the model of their love to one another, and his love was one of feeling leading to seU-de- nying and beneficent action. This does not leave each one to judge for himseU as to the degree of love or activity he is to mamf est toward his neighbor. His love for himself is to be tested by the love of Christ for him before he makes it a standard of his love to others. Under the rule or norm set by Christ it is not merely demanded that we seek to ameliorate sorrowful conditions, whether physical or mental, nor even that we strive for the physical, intellectual, and social perfection of human conditions. AU this is included ; but he who loves God with aU his heart and his neighbor as himseU must strive to induce his neighbor to love God with all his heart and his neighbor as himself. He must not only seek the welfare of mankind, but strive to enlist others in the endeavor to bring in the golden age ; and he must do it 1 1 Cor. xiii, 3. * John xiii, 34. 314 Foundations of the Christian Faith. by making men love the good, the righteous, the holy, the loving God. The law of Jesus, in other words, recognizes the fact that the general welfare cannot be secured while men love only earthly things ; and it recognizes that the human heart demands for the object of its truest and highest love a person possessed of aU lovely attributes ; and that true and intense love to such a being, or to one supposed to be such, has the effect of making the heart warm toward all who are loved by him. In the light of all these things it is absurd to say that others had taught the law of love before or independent of Christ.' So far as This law not tney "taught" at aU they taught a law of love, but not ed by itecrit- the law of love. This was first inculcated by Jesus of lcs- Nazareth. And so far in advance of the world was he that, though many have gotten the idea that love is the true law of the ethical Ufe, our boastful scientists who claim that they needed not Jesus to teach them show by all they say of the Master's words that they are incapable of comprehending them. If they would know the truth they must sit at Jesus's feet. If they will not learn of him they will of necessity remain where they now are, in darkness ! The first to teach the ethics of Jesus was Jesus himseU, and those who will not come to him cannot have the light of lUe. Meantime they not only fail to secure for themselves all the blessings of the truth, but by fol lowing the paths which their own pride marks out they confuse others and hinder the light from dawning upon them also. The second objection of a fundamental kind lodged against Chris tian ethics is that it is sanctioned by a system of rewards and pun ishments, and therefore that Christian moraUty is merely a .kind of selfishness.3 Gizycki gives us page after page to portray the essen tially selfish character of aU ethics having for its motives rewards and punishments. So far as Christianity is concerned he could have spared himself aU such slanderous pains ; for all professed Christians who have gotten their doctrines from Christ, the one source of our Rewards and feith, entirely reject the motive of selfishness ; but they m DChr?st?an a^so assel"t that Jesus did not make rewards and punish- ethics. ments the motives for good conduct. Salter, who is one of the chief representatives of the ethical culture movement in this country, as Gizycki was in Germany during his Ufe, nobly defends Christ against the blasphemous charge of proposing a mercenary 1 Comp. Mark Hopkins's The Law of Love and Love as Law ; or Christian Ethics, re vised edition, New York, 1881, p. 76. ' Comp. the remarks of A. S. Farrar, Critical History of Free Thought, p. 180 f. Originality of Christ's Law of Love. 315 ground for moraUty.1 It is one thing to warn men that evil conduct and wickedness of heart wfll certainly lead them to sorrow and anguish, and it is another to make that fact the reason why they should avoid wickedness. Jesus did not, Uke some of our modern ethicists, shut himseU up in his study to prepare lectures on sys tematic ethics which he might afterward deliver to applauding multi tudes. He knew that there is an absolute right which can be summed up in the one idea of love to God and man; that our consciences prompt us to do the right ; that the law in our own hearts teUs us to do the right, without regard to the consequences for our present or future happiness. But he had what many of our modern ethicists seem to lack, namely, good practical sense, and this led him to offer to men who needed, as the vast majority do, lower motives as aids until the higher motives became strong enough to make the lower un necessary. Besides, whfle Jesus was an altruist, he did not carry his altruism to a dangerous extreme.3 Hence he had a place for seU as weU as for others in his ethical system. Neighbor and self are on an equal footing ; and as one should try to shield his neighbor from a course of conduct which must lead to disaster, so he has a right to stimulate himseU to good deeds and divert himself from evfl conduct by similar considerations. It is not selfishness which prompts us so to do ; it is good common sense. Somehow misery and vice are con nected, and virtue and a reasonable degree and kind of happiness in separable in this world. Many do not know this until they have learned it by experience — then it is often too late. It is merctful to declare the facts before the thoughtless or the uninstructed faU into evfl ways. It is diabolical to demand that the truth shall be withheld from them. It is hypocritical in one who would not demand this to accuse Jesus of grounding his moraUty in selfishness because he warned the wicked of the consequences of their sins. It is dastardly to accuse Christian moraUty of selfishness unless Jesus taught it, no matter who else teaches it. 1 Ethical Religion, Boston, 1889, pp. 179-182. * Professor George Harris says: "The altruism which reduces itself to zero is an act without an actor. It is something out of nothing. It is a verb without a noun. It is a nonentity exercising power. . . . Unless one does make the most of himself he is incom petent for good to others."— Moral Evolution, Boston and New York, 1896, p. 153 f. 316 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. NEED OF DIVINE AID— PRACTICABILITY OF CHRISTIAN ETHICS. The third fundamental objection is that we have no need of God's help to lead good Uves. To say that we are incapable of leading good Uves without divine aid Mr. Stanton Coit regards as " blasphemy against our moral nature." He thinks the abflity to do right as much a part of our being as our power to think, to see, and to eat. To deny Divine ai d this would be the same as to deny that a child can add or riihtd]ivin£ subtract without God's help. * The question of blasphemy we shall not discuss. The real question is whether divine aid is help ful. If it is it is needed. But is it a fact that the power to think, to see, and to eat is a part of our being? To deny to man such powers apparently seems to Mr. Stanton Coit impossible ; and if we do not define the quaUty of the thinking, the correctness of the seeing, or the wisdom of the eating, it must be admitted man does possess the powers mentioned. But i£ the abflity to perform those functions as they ought to be performed is asserted of the untrained infant or young child, or even of many adults, we must be aUowed to note an exception. If Mr. Coit means that in the same blundering manner in which the average uninstructed individual thinks, sees, and eats, or adds or subtracts, men can do right, we agree. But tf he means that men possess within themselves the power to discover the law of righteousness and love, and to execute it, we deny the assertion. Man's inability to discover that law was discussed above ; here we have to do chiefly with the question of abflity to execute it. That man possesses no such power has been confessed by such vast multitudes that the pretense of its possession by anyone is necessarily regarded either as evidence of seU-conceit or else of an inadequate conception of what righteousness and love mean. The individual who really comprehends the demands of righteousness and love enters into the conflict with the temptations of Ufe with modest fear instead of boastful courage. He can but measure himseU at his best as probably unequal to the powers which shall be matched against him. He looks within and finds that even his impulses do not aU tend in the right 1 Quoted by Gizycki, Moralphllosophie, p. 386, from Colt's Ethical Culture as a Re ligion for the People, a work of which we can find no trace except in Gizycki. Need of Divine Aid. 317 direction. His struggle with himself is not yet complete, and he has to defend himseU against foes within and foes without. Whether we trace these evfl impulses to our alleged animal origin or to the Bible doctrine of the faU of our innocent first parents, only a superficial observer of seU and humanity at large can deny their existence and power. And just because the demands of the moral law are so com prehensive and exalted it is impossible for us to say that we have reached the point where all our impulses join with the ideal require ments of righteousness. Any moment may afford us a revelation of duty to which we have hitherto been blind, and in the performance of which our impulses refuse to cooperate. Such has often been the case with conscientious seekers after ethical light, and, in view of all this, it is foolhardy to say that the abflity to do right is an inborn power. It is evident, then, that men need aid in the living of right lives, and that mankind in its present state cannot provide it. Unless one denies the existence of God, or his power and readiness to extend to us the assistance we need, it is almost criminal to teach men that they can do for themselves everything they need in the ethical life. It is not claimed for Christians that they hve ideal lives. This is not be cause the aid available is insufficient, but because perfect appropria tion of that aid, for various reasons, fails. But the his- its benefits ' proved by tory of the Church in aU those periods and localities in history. which it has remained truest to the original character of Christianity proves that the motives and forces imparted to one who becomes a genuine Christian enable him to live on a higher moral level than was possible to him in his pre-Christian condition. With divine as sistance better ethical results are possible than without it. He who has a real enthusiasm for right living, such as the ethical culturists profess, ought not to block the way of success by deceiving men into the false notion that they are of themselves sufficient for all the de mands which the moral law makes upon them. The fourth fundamental objection urged against Christian morals is that it is impracticable. Strecker may be aUowed to speak for aU who are of his opinion. He says : l "In fact, many Christian require ments are incapable of f fulfillment because they are in con- Are thede- flict with the peculiarities of human nature, our social econ- c h "i s t im- omy (Wirtschaftsordnung), or our civilization. One can prac abstain from violence against an enemy ; it is magnanimous to forgive him ; but to love him whfle he does us injury, to bless him while he curses us, is a demand on our disposition which, for natural reasons, 1 Welt und Menschheit, p. 150. 318 Foundations of the Christian Faith. we cannot meet." At this point it may be weU to pause and caU attention to the fact that Christianity does not expect any man to love his enemies unless he first obtain the capacity for such love as a result of a complete renewal of his nature. In this sense of the word it is true that Christian moraUty conflicts with the peculiarities of human nature. But Christianity teaches that those peculiarities are not what they ought to be, and that man should be transformed in such a way as to bring his inner nature into harmony with Christian requirement ; and then it wfll be no longer true that Christian morals make demands upon our dispositions which for natural reasons we cannot meet. Anyone who has even the sUghtest acquaintance with the history of the Christian Church knows that its pages afford us numberless examples of those who, though possessed of the greatest energy, have not only forgiven but have also loved their enemies. That many professed Christians do not so Uve is nothing to the pur pose. We hesitate to discriminate among the many worthy of men tion ; but it wfll not, perhaps, be out of place to aUude to one honored name — that of John Wesley. Strecker proceeds:' " To deprive ourselves of our possessions and goods and distribute the proceeds among the poor is a requirement which cannot justly be made upon anyone, and which if foUowed, ex cept with the addition of other conditions, would produce no benefits equal to the greatness of the sacrifice. " In reply to this it should be said that Christianity does not demand that we impoverish ourselves and give the poor our wealth. Christ's command to the young man of the gospel 3 was for him alone ; and a very Uttle study of his case as a whole suffices to make the reason evident to any inquirer. That not even the community of goods among the early Christians was required iS'manifest.' Christ was too wise to demand poverty as a feature of common Ufe. Well did he know that incriminate giving to the poor is a curse rather than a blessing, and he never recommended it. The apostle Paul, who lived much in the spirit of Jesus, said that if anyone would not work neither should he eat.4 This provision un doubtedly corresponded to the teachings of Jesus. Men must have an earthly calling, and they must pursue it with aU possible vigor. The voluntary poverty of the Christians of the Middle Ages was not in aU cases Christian, though in the interests of what they erroneously re garded Christian progress. There is absolutely nothing in the teach ings of Jesus taken as a whole to interfere with the accumulation of wealth. That extreme altruism which would make everyone as 'Welt und Menschheit, p. 150. » Matt, xix, 21. "Actsv,4. « 2 Thess. lit, 10. Need of Divine Aid. 319 responsible for all others as he is for himseU would result in the direst confusion and degeneration. It is no part of the teaching of Jesus, but of a mawkish sentimentality. The spirit of Jesus, as the spirit of com mon sense, requires that we make every individual responsible for his own weUare. Jesus simply introduces so much of altruistic feeling as serves to hinder our selfish passions from acquiring a preponder ance of influence in our lives, and to bind men together in love. The whole effect of the teachings of Jesus would be to place each individ ual in that position in which he could best develop his own personal ity and thus reach his highest possible enjoyment. These considera tions completely, though briefly, show how unfounded are the criti cisms of Buckle, Strauss, and others to the effect that Christianity is opposed to material progress. ¦ In very much the same strain the attempt has been made to show that the ethical requirements of Christianity are not complete. Says Strecker:3 "Many commands of the moral law, such as diligence, economy, promptness, perseverance, are not contained in Are they in- the Christian ethics." Commenting on this statement comp e ? Steude calls attention to the fact that all four of these virtues are com prised in the one idea of faithfulness, which is inculcated in such pas sages as Matt, xxiv, 45 f. ; xxv, 14 ff. ; Luke xvi, 10-12. 3 Were it true that Jesus had never inculcated any of these virtues it would still be false to say that they are no part of Christian moraUty ; for Jesus taught the essentials of a Christian character, not so much by com mandments, of which he gave very few, as by his own example. He is our ideal. To foUow him, to be his disciple, is to do as he would do were he surrounded by our circumstances. That he was dihgent, prompt, economical, and persevering is unquestionable. But as a mat ter of fact he did teach directly aU the virtues which Strecker says Christian ethics lack. Diligence in one's own affairs is directly com mended in the Parables of the Lost Sheep and Piece of Silver,4 and diligence in the discharge of our duties to others is commended and the absence of it condemned in the Parable of the Ten Talents.6 Promptness is one phase of diligence ; so that one cannot be diligent who is not prompt. As to economy, it is directly required in connec tion with the miraculous feeding of the multitude.6 That Jesus gave this command is evident from the statements of Matt, (xiv, 20) ; Mark (vi, 43) ; and Luke (ix, 17). Perseverance is commended in such pas- 1 See Buckle's History of Civilization, vol. ii, pp. 268, 287 ; and Strauss's Der alte und der neue Glaube. p. 63 f. * Welt und Menschheit, p. 133. 5 See his article on Die monistische Etbik, in Beweis des Glaubens, Sept. 1895, p. 349. 4 Luke xv, 3-9. 6 Matt, xxv, 14 ff. " John vi, 12. 320 Foundations of the Christian Faith. sages as Matt, x, 22; xxiv, 13; Mark xfli, 13. That these passages have a specific appUcation in nowise interferes with the conclusion we have drawn from them ; for the very idea of endurance or persever ance, in Christianity, is that we shall perform the duty devolving upon us whatever may be our fate, and every duty is to the Christian a Christian duty. Blinded by passion, such accusations, as that of Strecker are made in willing ignorance of facts to the contrary. Did infidels devote a tithe of the time and energy to the actual and impar tial study of Christianity in its original sources which they expend in ignorantly criticising it they would be astonished at the perfection of the system which they reject. It has also been said that Jesus had no word to say in favor of in teUectual honesty.1 Here again it may be said that Jesus set the ex ample of searching for the truth and of adhering to his convictions wherever they led him. He taught honor, honesty, and love of truth and right in aU things. These requirements are fundamental in his ethics. To say that he did not teach inteUectual honesty in particular is to trifle with the precepts of Jesus. Again, Jesus is complained of Jesus's method because he did not expressly condemn slavery.' But it tea? honesty" was not ms PurP<>se to effect a mere external revolution. poTiTl cal ^s method was to inspire men's hearts with the princi- economy. pje 0f righteousness and love and to trust to these to ac- compUsh, more rapidly and thoroughly than by direct command, aU reforms needful for the ameUoration of human conditions. This is in perfect accord with his doctrine that conduct springs from the heart.3 But by his doctrine of the equality of aU men before God and of uni versal brotherhood he also made impossible, not only slavery, but aU oppression in every thoroughly Christianized land. Were infidels as anxious to secure the freedom of all men from the wrongs that oppress mankind as they are to overthrow Christianity they would completely change their attitude and strive to make all men Christians in fact as well as in name. It is to their opposition that the prevalence of these wrongs in nominaUy Christian lands is largely due. Again, Salter asserts that Jesus did not meet our demands for a higher conception of poUtics and poUtical ethics ; that he gave us no adequate industrial ethics, and that he solved the social problem only by referring the poor to Providence.* In reply to this it must be said that the ethics of Jesus can be, and by Christians should be, appUed » Comp. Steude's Bewels des Glaubens, Sept., 1895, p. 350, and Salter's, Ethical Reli gion, pp. 202-206. » Salter, Ethical Religion, cited by Steude, as above. 3 Matt. xv. 19. ' Ethical Religion, pp. 206-226. Need of Divine Aid. 321 alike to pubUc and private Ufe ; that the form of government is a matter of choice under Christianity, and that it is a slander to say that Jesus did nothing for the solution of social problems except to incul cate trust in Providence in the hearts of the poor. Jesus gave us the doctrine of universal mutual love, the only solution of all the prob lems pertairting to the relations which human beings can sustain to each other. These are examples of the aUeged excesses and defects of Christian morals. They appear on examination to be purely fictitious. A few other illustrations might be given, but they are needless. AU that have been or could be mentioned serve but to betray the diminutive spirit, the ignorance or the malice of their originators. To any fair and impartial mind, capable of forming a judgment on the complex and enormous mass of facts found in the ethical teachings of Jesus, the fact is clear that neither by way of excess nor of defect can any fault be found with Christian moraUty. 322 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER V. INCIDENTAL OBJECTIONS TO CHRISTIAN MORALS. Besides those objections to Christian ethics which, if valid, would destroy the very foundations of Christianity, there are others which we have designated as incidental. The distinction thus made between fundamental and incidental objections does not, however, destroy the fact that both classes are fatal U capable of being substantiated. It is difficult to escape the impression in reading the writings of those who criticise Christianity that the fault-finders have some pur pose to serve. Most certain it is that in every case they either mis represent the facts of the New Testament, or draw their information concerning Christian teaching from other than New Testament sources, or claim as the result of Christian teachings consequences which experience has proved not to follow in actual practice. With out attempting to explain why our opponents should so pervert the facts, we call attention to the perversion in the hope that aU readers may henceforth take with due aUowance any criticisms either of Christian faith or practice. But we cannot refrain from expressing the wish that hereafter our Christian writers may be more cautious. UnbeUevers are not altogether to blame for misunderstanding the genius of Christianity when they find in powerful leaders of the Church the very representations they criticise. And there is scarcely a fault which has been charged against Christianity which is not declared by some celebrity in the Church to be an essential of Chris tianity. There has been altogether too much effort to make Chris- Necessity tianity square with our philosophy, and not enough to amongChr?£ Place ourselves in a position where, with a fuU knowl- tian writers. edge of the eternal truths which Jesus inculcated, we can calmly wait until the world's philosphy comes into accord with the teachings of Christ. Too often the subordinate has been pro claimed as the essential in our faith and practice ; the letter has been insisted upon without regard to the spirit, sometimes in contradiction to it ; the particular and local has been applied as though it were the universal. Thus it has happened that Christianity has been more thoroughly misrepresented by our friends than by our enemies. In so far, therefore, we hafl every criticism offered by our foes, in the Incidental Objections to Christian Morals. 323 hope that we may learn to be true Christians thereby. Our defense must consist largely in clearing away the misrepresentations of friends and foes and in the attempt to state the facts as they are. That we shaU wholly escape from error we can scarcely hope. There are two classes of incidental objections, those against doc trines, and those against the aUeged influence of certain doctrines on human conduct. Of those against doctrines as such we need mention but one example — the doctrine of vicarious suffering. It is declared immoral to let Christ, the innocent, suffer for man, the guilty sinner.1 The assertion is often made that everyone must suffer, and thus atone, for his own sins. In answer it should be said that, Alleged im- while this would vindicate the justice of God, it would S^Cbris- speak but poorly for his mercy. But in fact the objection tr1ned°af is based on a misunderstanding. Vicarious suffering is atonement. not to be understood as a complete and unconditional release of the sinner from suffering for his sin. Nor was it designed chiefly, U at all, to placate God. Taking the teachings of the New Testament as a whole we are obliged to regard the vicarious sufferings of Christ as a method by which God can maintain the divine standard of justice on the one hand, and of mercy on the other, whfle offering the most exalted and powerful motive to man for holy Uving. To this scrip tural form of the doctrine the above objection does not apply. Of the second class of objections we give several examples.3 (1) It is affirmed that the preaching of forgiveness of sins, whether with or without the blood of Christ, weakens moral endeavor. There can be no doubt that the Romanist doctrine of indulgences does natu rally tend in the direction indicated by the objection. The same may be said also of the doctrine of the so-caUed liberal theologians, that the divine forgiveness has its sufficient ground in the possession of the power to forgive. The true Protestant doctrine i£ disconnected from other doctrines which in the Scripture accompany it is equaUy dangerous. Forgiveness can be safely preached only, as it is pro claimed in the New Testament, where the beUever is assumed to hate sin even more than he dreads its consequences and to love all right- eousnesss as revealed in the perfect Son of God, the Son is forgiveness of sins dan- of man. Under proper limitations the preaching of for- gerous ? giveness is essential to high moraUty. If God never forgave sin, but ever required exact penalty, it would produce defiance of him in 1 Strauss, Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 29. The objection Is very ancient. ' For many suggestions under this head we are indebted to an article by Wllhelm Kambli in Die christllche Welt (No. 1, January, 1897), on Religion und Moral. 324 Foundations of the Christian Faith. many, while the outward righteousness of those who strove to lead virtuous lives would be always the result of fear, not of the free choice of the individual. Pardon granted under proper conditions is more likely than penalty to produce love of the virtue recom mended by the pardoner. Only under a system of pardon can grati tude exercise any influence. Virtuous conduct is thus made not only more sure, it is also founded in free choice, whence alone virtue can spring. So the inner Ufe is made richer and purer, and the out ward Ufe more conformable to the moral law, by pardon than by pen alty. Penalty is a last resort, to be employed, not for vengeance, but as a means of moral improvement either of the one punished or of those who fear his fate ; and it is never to be applied when an appeal to higher motives can be made effective. Besides, only as the be liever in God recognizes that he has the divine favor can he take courage and cherish hope, without which there will be no endeavor for holy living. An unforgiving God would set a bad example and paralyze moral effort in aU who had in them the consciousness of guilt. (2) Prayer also, though in another way, is declared to weaken our moral energies. This objection to a Christian doctrine and prac tice is based on the idea that prayer is intended chiefly to afford us a means of escape from unpleasant duties or burdens which we ought to bear cheerfully in the interests of human wel- ' fare. Any prayer which has such a purpose is un christian, and worthy of all condemnation. But Christian prayer, so far as it leads to a sense of the forgiveness of sin in accordance with the teachings of the Gospel, is, as we have seen, no hindrance, but a help to moral effort. Christian prayer, in so far as it affords us relief from sorrows of lUe which, U borne, would benefit no one but might crush us, can do no harm to our moral nature. Furthermore, as far as prayer aids us in the performance of duty, whether agree able or disagreeable, and makes us more strong and courageous to bear the burdens and inevitable sorrows of Ufe, its moral effect is positively beneficial. (3) The doctrine of divine providence1 has been charged with rob bing its adherents of the virtue of foresight. If God is caring for men why should they care for themselves ? There may be a few who so understood this doctrine, though the writer, in a tolerably wide 1 On the doctrine of destiny or providence as Immoral, see Clifford's Lectures and Essays, p. 265. His "destiny" or "providence," however, is remote from the Christian •conception. Incidental Objections to Christian Morals. 325 experience, never met one. The great majority surely hold the true Christian view, that the very condition of benefiting by divine provi dence is effort on their own part. "To him that hath shaU be given " is not spoken to discourage the needy but to stir them to action. Furthermore, the doctrine of providence encourages us, in periods of apparently unavailing endeavor, to expect that, if we contmue in welldoing, out of all our disappointment will emerge a higher good, whether temporal or spiritual, than that for which we providence have been striving. Thereby we are prompted to labor on even when there appears no natural hope of success. Foresight is therefore not destroyed by beUef in the providence of God, whose laws must be known that they may be employed. The foresight our opponents have in mind, divorced from trust in man and God, results in selfishness and would lead every man to care for himself alone. Such foresight is not wanted in this world. We do need the foresight which is tempered with Christian faith. (4) The declaration is made that the nearer one is to God the farther away he is from his fellow-men. It is not to be denied that nearness to God has been sought too often at the expense of flight from the world and the consequent neglect of duty to man. But wherever this has occurred it has been in contradiction Nearness to of Christianity, which teaches by precept and example nearness "to that the true love of God is always attended by love to men" our fellow-men and is the prime condition of its highest exhibition. No doubt, also, there are those who, because of their supposed relation ship to God, are lifted up with pride ; but they are in so far unchris tian. To reject Christianity, however, on account of these unworthy professors of it would be no more justifiable than to select the worst specimens in any department of art, and then condemn all art on account of them. (5) It is objected that Christianity points the poor and suffering to heaven instead of giving them relief here and now. There is, doubtless, too little practical brotherly love manifested by Christians, and it may be that many have been so absorbed by the thought of heaven that they have not given due importance to the earthly Ufe ; but the facts show that Christianity has introduced the idea of practical helpfulness into the world as a principle of all Christianity conduct, and has fortified it with sufficient motives and suffering impulses; and that whatever aspirations the masses classes. cherish after better material or inteUectual conditions are the attend ants of Christianity in proportion as it is in any country true to the 23, 326 Foundations of the Christian Faith. principles of Christ.1 On the other hand, take away the doctrine of future reward and punishment and this world must appear as the scene of the grossest injustice and inequaUty, as a hopeless chaos of social disorder. Nothing but the doctrine that this world is only a part of each man's Ufe, and that each shaU continue to Uve beyond death a lUe indissolubly connected with that which now is, can ever give a moment's rest to the man whose conscience demands the con junction of happiness with holiness, of misery with sin. Deprive the unfortunate, whose sorrows no earthly ministry, however gentle and helpful, can greatly mitigate, of the expectation of a Ufe free from the sad temporal conditions which afflict them here, and their woes would be intensified — robbed of hope and of the prospect of enjoyment instead of pain hereafter. The Christian doctrine of the future has not hindered Christianity from being, Uke its divine Founder, the minister of good to the temporal as weU as the spiritual needs of men, and it has furnished the key for the solution of some of Uf e's greatest mysteries and saved the sorrowing from despair. 1 For full discussion of details see Gesta Christi ; or, A History of Humane Progress under Christianity, by Charles Loring Brace, second edition, New York, 1883 ; and The Divine Origin of Christianity Indicated by its Historical Effects, by Richard S. Storrs, D.D., LL.D., New York, 1884. Christianity and Opposing Religious Theories. 327 DIVISION V. CHRISTIANITY AND OPPOSING RELIGIOUS THEORIES. To some it may seem that the great non-Christian reUgions should be treated in this work ; but while a comparison of them in some of their aspects with Christianity is necessary, and wfll be afforded in its proper place, it is not needful to refute them here. As a matter of fact those who wfll employ this book are in no danger of accepting any of the religions referred to, instead of Christianity ; nor is any of them, not even Buddhism, seriously offered as a substitute for Chris tianity. The same cannot be said of the four proposed substitutes here treated.1 There may be those who wfll think that by introducing into this work a discussion of such systems as Theosophy and Christian Science its whole tone is lowered. We sympathize with aU such readers as far as sentiment is concerned. But we beUeve importance that aU who have had to deal practically with these such sys- vagaries will welcome the discussion offered. Such wfll Theosophy, realize their subtleness and the difficulty of refuting science, etc. their positions. Besides, these systems are seriously offered as rivals of Christianity for the adherence of mankind ; and they are accepted by considerable numbers who should be Christians, and in a few in stances by men and women of noble character and brilliant intellect. In each case these proposed substitutes emphasize something highly prized by multitudes. Since they are, in some circles, supplanting Christianity, or making the propagation of Christianity in its pure form difficult, there is reason to believe they have an attractive power dangerous, not indeed to Christianity, but to many who ought to be enjoying the more comprehensive benefits and engaged in the more varied and important duties of our faith. If Christianity is to be demonstrated superior to everything else offered for the reUgious acceptance of men, these false or imperfect systems must be refuted. 1 It is not proposed to treat all, but only the principal, of those proposed substitutes which have taken some hold on the thoughtful among English-speaking peoples. Steude gives a somewhat exhaustive discussion of substitutes in Evangelische Apologetlk, Gotha, 1892, pp. 451-487. 328 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Such a task, U undertaken, must be performed, however briefly, with conscientious thoroughness and fairness. It will not answer the pur pose to engage in denunciation. Here, as elsewhere, the law of love must be obeyed. And it must always be remembered that however inadequate, or even foolish, these professed reUgions appear to those who reject them, to their adherents they are sacred and dear. While dealing with them in the most uncompromising spirit, therefore, everything must be avoided which savors of contempt or scorn. Should any reader feel that too much space is given to the form of faith to be refuted, his judgment wfll condemn his feehngs the moment he reflects that in order to refute any system it is necessary to exhibit it to the mind of the person to whom the argument is ad dressed. We recognize indeed that these proposed substitutes for Christianity are not all of equal dignity. We have classed them together, not because we oppose them aU for the same reasons, nor to indicate that they are alike worthy of regard or want of regard ; but because, however they may differ in other aspects, they are aU claim ants for the adherence of those whom Christianity has hitherto won or is seeking to win. SECTION 1.-PR0P0SED SUBSTITUTES FOR CHRISTIANITY. CHAPTER I. POSITIVISM, or the religion of humanity. This strange mixture of the grotesque and the valuable is the product of a mind whose thoughts have attracted wide attention and won many adherents, particularly in the realm of philosophy, beyond which most Positivists refuse to foUow their leader, M. Auguste Comte (born 1798, died 1857). His seU-conceit was equal to the greatness of his intellect. He regarded himself as the modern representative of Aristotle in the sphere of philosophy, and of St. Paul in the influence he was to exert on the future of reUgion.1 Although it is true that "the Positivism which he taught, taken as a whole, is at once a phi losophy, a polity, and a religion,"3 it must be considered here chiefly as a religion, with only so much reference to the philosophy with which it is interwoven and to the science which it absorbs into itseU as is necessary to its proper understanding. 1 See the Catechism of Positive Religion, translated from the French of Auguste Comte by Richard Congreve, London, 1858, p. 19. His religious system may also be found in his SystSme de Politique Positive, but as the general reader will find the Catechism more easily accessible, all our citations are from that work. ' Flint, Antlthelstic Theories, p. 178. Positivism, or the Religion of Humanity. 329 In all Comte's criticisms of Christianity, it must be remembered, he is filled with a profound disUke of Protestantism,1 while Chris tianity and Roman Catholicism are regarded by him as identical. Thus, like all who reject Christianity, he first misunder- Comte.s mig. stands it. An illustration of the manner in which he per- f^got Chris- verts it is found in his assertion that it "so Uttle under- tianity. stands the dignity of labor as to refer its origin to a divine curse." " This can refer but to one passage, namely, Gen. Ui, 17-19, which makes, not labor, but the unproductive nature of the soil the curse pronounced on account of sin. Before the "fall "and the "curse" "the Lord God took Adam and put him into the garden of Eden, to dress it and to keep it." Whfle his objections to Christianity are based upon misunderstandings of it, his suggestions which have any real value for ethics are aU the product of the spirit of the system which he rejects. For example, he says : " A thorough sifting of this important question would perhaps show that a fourth of the popula tion in western Europe would be wise to abstain from having chil dren, and that such a function should be exercised only by those who are properly qualified," 3 that is, by those whose health is such as to afford a reasonable warrant that their offspring shaU not be diseased. This is a view which springs directly from Christian principle, which would go further and demand also that persons disposed to crime or vice should abstain from having children. * On the other hand, aU the faults of his system, whether in the sphere of ethics or of devo tional life, are the direct result of his conceit that he is wiser than Christ and the apostles trained by him. This wfll appear in aU the further portrayal of his proposed reUgion. One of the most strikingly distinctive features of Positivism as com pared with Christianity is that its founder, unlike Christ, left almost nothing to be worked out by his followers. He gave the world a com plete reUgion. It is not designed to be adaptable to varying civiliza tions, but it presupposes that when it shall have completely taken possession of the world aU civilizations wfll be alike. This tendency to bind the inteUect and judgment by externaUy im- Rigidity of posed provisions Comte carried with him from Roman ligion. Catholicism into Positivism, both of which, so far, vary from the spirit of Christ, which was not to give us rules and regulations, but to se cure a disposition of the mind by the free choice of the wfll, and to i Catechism, p. 414. " Ibid., p. 10. » Ibid., p. 321. 4 So his altruism, which he claims as a feature that distinguishes Positivism from Chris tianity, is defined on p. 54 of the Catechism quite in the spirit of Christianity. 330 Foundations of the Christian Faith. trust that disposition to perform its office in the individual and the community. In fact, Comte's system is one of external authority and of caste, as his whole doctrine of the hierarchy shows.1 About the only feature which is to be left to the future for determination is the shape which the edifices shall assume which Positivism shall here after employ for purposes of pubUc worship. Provisionally he pro poses that the old churches shaU be utilized, " in proportion as they fall into disuse." ' StiU, two things are settled : their situation, which "must be in the center of the tombs of the elect,'' and their direc tion — " in aU parts of the earth the temples of humanity must turn toward the general metropolis," which " for a long time, as the result of past history, must be Paris. In this manner Positivism turns to account the idea of which we find the rudiment in the Kebla of Islam- ism. We institute, as the Mahometans did, a common attitude for all true beUevers, and so bring into fuller Ught the touching soU- darity of our free worship." We simply ask, Is that worship free which must concern itseU about attitudes as though they were es sential ? Positivism also makes large provision for the clergy, or priestly class.3 One of the axioms of the reUgion of humanity is that "no society can exist and be developed without a priesthood in some form Positivism and or other."4 In Positivism the clergy requires three suc- the priestly . «=>.< i class. cessive orders : the aspirants, admitted at twenty-eight ; the vicars, or substitutes, at thirty-five ; and the priests proper, at forty -two. The first class have a real spiritual calling, but do not as yet belong to the spiritual power and exercise none of its functions. The vicars are irrevocably members of the priestly body, though lim ited to the functions of teaching and preaching. They must renounce aU property and be married. The priests proper are taken from the number of the vicars, and have full powers of advising, consecrating, and regulating, which are the social characteristics of the Positive clergy. The supreme power is vested in the High Priest of Humanity, whose natural residence will be Paris, as the metropolis of the regen erated West. He is the sole governor of the Positive clergy. He or dains its members, changes their residence, revokes their cornmis- 1 Catechism, pp. 341 ff . The priesthood, however, are to have no power to crush opinions contrary to their own, pp. 340 ff, ¦ Catechism, p. 140. His simplicity is both ludicrous and pitiable. 8 The male sex represents physioal laws, the female sex moral laws, and the priesthood intellectual laws. The priesthood shares the life of both male and female— Catechism, p. 162. One is irresistibly reminded of the celebrated division of the human race into men, women, and clergymen. « Catechism, p. 279. Positivism, or the Religion of Humanity. 331 sion, aU on his own moral responsibflity. To assist him in the dis charge of his functions the supreme head of Western Positivism is to have the aid of four national superiors, who, under his direction, guide their four respective churches — the Italian, the Spanish, the English, and the German. The high priest is the national superior for France, though he need not be a Frenchman. The regular mode of replacing him is by a successor whom he is to name himseU, but with the assent of aU four national superiors. Should they be divided in opinion, then the nomination must meet the wishes of the senior priests of the two thousand presbyteries (that are to be). The aspirant has a salary of $600, the vicar of $1,000, the priest proper of $2,400, the high priest of $12,000, and each national superior of $6,000. * Besides, the priest and high priest are to have an aUowance for certain expenses connected with their duties.''' These salaries are to be paid out of the pubUc treasury as soon as the faith is universally adopted.3 Most candidates for the ministry would be ¦wflling to renounce aU property for the prospect of such salaries. Our only additional remark is that this whole clerical scheme has a most striking resemblance to that of Romanism. Not until we come to the Positivist worship do we reach the real pecuUarities of the system. The purpose of the worship is distin guished from that of the worshipers of God as being self -betterment for the better service of humanity, while that of the worshipers of God consists in adoring him with vain compliments. * This false and maUcious fling at Christian worship we pass by. The object of wor ship is not God, whose existence is either denied or ignored, but Humanity, which is the Great or Supreme Being. The symbol of this being, in statuary or in painting, is a woman of the age of thirty, with her son in her arms." But it would be an error to suppose that aU human beings, or human beings only, compose this The^ supreme Great Being; it includes "those only who are reaUy ca- Positivism. pable of assimilation, in virtue of a real cooperation on their part in furthering the common good."6 There are some "mere digesting machines," who "are no real part of Humanity. You may reject them, and to make up for the loss associate with the new Supreme Being all the animals who lend a noble aid." "To form a right esti mate of this indispensable complement of human existence let us 1 These are as close figures as can well be given. They reckon the English pound sterling at five dollars in United States money. » Catechism, pp. 302-305. s Ibid., p. 301. ' «Ibid., p. 87. » Ibid., p. 142. ' Ibid., p. 74. 332 Foundations of the Christian Faith. imagine ourselves without it. We should then be led without hesi tation to look on many horses, dogs, oxen, etc., as more estimable than certain men." ' But not chiefly is it Uving human beings who constitute this divin ity. "In the composition of our Great Being the dead occupy the first place, then those who are yet to be born." 3 Nor is it aU the dead who compose this Great Being. "Our divinity only incorporates into herseU the dead who are really meritorious." Nor is it composed of the meritorious dead as they ready were in Ufe. " The ideal must be an ameUoration of the real, or it is inadequate for its moral purpose." We have a "tendency to forget the defects of the dead, whilst we only recall their good quaUties." The divinity "puts away from each one (of the meritorious dead) the imperf ections which in aU cases dimmed their objective life." ' This divinity, composed chiefly of dead and unborn men, horses, dogs, oxen, etc. ( " animals who lend a noble aid" — who are to be looked upon "without hesitation " "as more es timable than certain men " ), is a purely subjective one. There are two forms of existence. "The first involves the presence of the body and may be termed objective, to mark more clearly its con trast with the second. The second leaves each one to exist only in the heart and inteUect of others, and deserves the name of sub jective."4 "In the past we see such a Ufe . . . prevail during forty centuries. . . . During this long probation the minds of men habit ually recognized the sway of purely imaginary beings — we see them to be imaginary, their worshipers beUeved in their real and distinct existence."6 "The only essential difference between subjectivity in its later and in its primitive shape is this. In its later shape we must be fully conscious of it. . . . Our predecessors, on the con trary, vainly endeavored to see without them what had no existence but within."1' This last citation demonstrates that Positivism is a strictly atheistic system, notwithstanding it dilates upon the worship of the Supreme Being. It wfll be unnecessary to spend much time on this astonish- Positivism an ing effort to create a divinity. It demands of those who atheistic sys- J tem. create the substitute divinity (and each must in the na ture of the case create it for himself) that they shaU perpetrate upon themselves the conscious fraud of treating as real that which they know to "exist only in the heart and inteUect of others." AU others than Positivists, U they worshiped at aU, worshiped imaginary be- 1 Catechism, pp. 75, 76. » Ibid., p. 89. » Ibid., p. 103. ' Ibid., p. 77. • ibid., p. 91. « ibid., p. 92 f. Positivism, or the Religion of Humanity. 333 ings whom they supposed to be real. The Positivists are to worship that which they know to be unreal as though it was real. If the former were fools the latter are asked to become knaves; for "the only essential difference " between the two is that in Positivism the worshiper is "fully conscious" of the deception, not practiced upon him, but practiced by himself upon himseU. Besides, they deliberately "ameUorate" these "meritorious dead," changing them into what they were not. If "amelioration" be aUowable it is difficult to see why the " mere digesting machines" caUed men might not be included in the divinity, since they would only need a Uttle more " ameUoration " to fit them for incorporation into the divinity. In both respects, therefore, does Positivism prac tice conscious seU-deception ; first, by thinking of the dead as though they have a real existence, whereas they exist only in the hearts and inteUects of others, and, second, by thinking of them as having been moraUy what they were not. And without this seU-deception, at least as far as the element of "amelioration" is concerned, the divinity is "inadequate" for its moral purpose." * It is difficult to see why, as far as our own betterment is concerned, we might not as weU omit the dead, the Uving, or the unborn, whether of men, horses, dogs, or oxen, from our ideal. It is, after all, but an ideal which Positivism requires each to worship — an ideal in each in stance of the individual's own creation. If by the worship of the ideal we improve ourselves in mind and heart it is better that the ideal should have no taint of moral fault. In this respect Chris tianity offers us in Jesus Christ a far higher ideal than any mind can create for itself. And as the mind has to choose its own ideal it could choose Christ as well as any other. For, even though his superiority of J6SUS, 3>S sin metaphysical divinity might be supposed to unfit him for {J}jjjJ|- top*}£ use as an example, it is a plain fact that the man Christ itivism. Jesus is a true example. But why talk of the worship of an ideal? To use such language is to pervert it from its own common significance. Hu manity, including those horses, dogs, oxen, etc., which are more esti mable than certain men, is a generalization having no concrete reaUty. It cannot be worshiped without intellectual self -stultification. When Comte speaks of our worship of mother, wUe, daughter, husband, or son,3 he speaks of that which is at least possible in thought; but his humanity has no existence in the sense in which these exist. Not only is it nonsense to talk about worshiping this abstract generaliza- 1 Catechism, p. 103. Comp. Flint's Anti-Theistic Theories, p. 202 f. a Catechism, pp. 120-122. 334 Foundations of the Christian Faith. tion, it is useless to do it. The purpose of the worship of mother, wife, daughter, is to develop within us respectively veneration, attachment, and kindness.1 But unless worship be the only mode of attaining these quahties worship is useless. That they can be attained without worshiping mother, wfle, and daughter is proved by actual experience in numberless cases. i Catechism, p. 121. Worship in Positivism. 335 CHAPTER II. worship in positivism. Why not worship the Christian's God ? In him are aU perfections. The only reason that can be given is that Comte and Positivists do not believe there is a God. Comte's principal precursor in phflosophy was Hume. l This made him an agnostic, U not an atheist. It led him to believe that causes never can be known, and the search after them, whether as final or efficient, is futile. The only thing we can know is laws ; unvarying relations of succession and resemblance ; the how, not the why, of things.3 Put in his favorite form: "Every theoretical conception passes necessarily through three successive stages. The first is the theological, or fictitious. The second, metaphysical, or abstract. The third, positive, or real. The first is always Comte's ai- ' r * leged three provisional. The second, simply transitional. The third stages of theoretical alone is definitive. . . . There is, at bottom, no other cuf- conceptions. ference between ' the first and second,' in point of theory than this : that the deities recognized by the first are reduced by the second to mere entities, or abstractions. . . . Metaphysics . . . have no other effect in the original evolution, whether of the individual or of so ciety, but to facilitate the gradual passage from theology to Positiv ism." 3 This makes beUef in God an out- worn phase in human devel opment. TheoreticaUy, therefore, this is his reason for rejecting the worship of God. But, according to his own statement, the chief distinction between those who worshiped God, or still worship him, and Positivists is not the reaUty of the objects worshiped, for in both cases he regards them as mere conceptions of the mind, but that the former beUeved in the real existence of the imaginary be ing they worshiped while Comtists worship a being they know to be imaginary.* We shall not attempt what has been so often and so successfuUy accomplished, namely, a refutation of the peculiar notion of the his- 1 Catechism, p. 7. ' Ibid., p. 57. Flint answers Comte briefly, but effectually, in these words: "All the reasonings of the Positivists against causes resolve themselves at last into the single ar gument—we cannot see causality, and therefore we cannot know causes "— Anti-Theistie Theories, p. 195. 8 Catechism, pp. 169 ff . * Ibid., pp. 92 ff . 336 Foundations of the Christian Faith. tory of thought mentioned above.' It has no real place here. We insist, as above, that for the purposes of betterment, even with a view to better service of humanity, an ideal entirely disconnected with Absurdity of dead or unborn men, horses, dogs, oxen, etc., is as good is* object'S as the ideal drawn from them, and better, in that we need worship. not practice upon ourselves any seU-deception in connec tion with its worship. And we also insist that U an ideal is to be wor shiped it is better to worship the ideal we have in Jesus Christ, since it is nobler than any other. If the purpose of the worship of humanity is to induce us to Uve for others, then not the dead, or the unborn, but the Uving should be the humanity worshiped. But it is not nec essary to worship human beings in order to live for them. Positivists have exhibited no preeminence over Christians, even under like cir cumstances, in the matter of Uving for others. And if we take the hard conditions through which Christians have passed in the ages now gone by, in their endeavors to serve their f eUow-men, it must be said that Positivists will never have an opportunity to prove whether they would have done as much or as weU. Christianity has fought down opposition to the spirit of good wfll until, theoretically, at least, that spirit is everywhere encouraged. The conclusion is that Positiv ism is not only ridiculous In proportion as it varies from Christianity, but in aU that is valuable it borrows from the system it rejects. Besides the object we must consider the content of worship in Posi tivism. We pass by its elaborate division of the Positivist year, and take up the vital matter of prayer, the importance of which Positivism emphasizes. It is to be performed in a kneeling posture,3 and — whfle Positivism *ke Prayers are to be read — they must be composed by the and prayer, person offering them.3 The Positivist prays, not for the purpose of receiving anything from the object of his worship, but in order to give expression to his best affections.* "He may also ask, but he asks only for a noble progress, which he insures almost by the very asking. The fervent wish to become more tender, more rever ential, more courageous even, is itseU in some degree a realization of the desired improvement. . . . This holy influence of prayer may extend to the intellect, were it only by urging us to new efforts to improve our thought." " 1 We refer the reader to Flint, Philosophy of History in Europe, vol. 1: Philosophy of History in France and Germany, New York, 1875. See also Flint's Antl-Theistic Theories, pp. 190 ff., and comp. Edward Caird's The Social Philosophy and Religion of Comte, Glas gow, 1885, especially chaps. It and ill. Herbert Spencer also opposes Comte's view, not on this point alone, but on many other points. See his letter in the New Englander for January, 1864. 2 Catechism, p. 121. " Ibid., p. 110. ' Ibid., p. 105 f. 'Ibid., p. 106. Worship in Positivism. 337 Here it is plain that the value of prayer is confined to the reflex in fluence it exerts upon us. This is consistent ; for U the divinity has a purely subjective existence it cannot aid us from without. Such an idea of answer to prayer is the only one possible to the reUgion of humanity. But why call it prayer ? ; Why not call it what it really is, namely, the expression to ourselves of our desire for improvement? Dead or unborn men, horses, dogs, oxen, etc., cannot help us to improve ourselves ; why make any pretense of securing their aid ? They can not hear our oral nor discern the contents of our mental effusions ; why address them to them? We affirm that it is irrational to proceed as the Positivists would have us do. The only explanation that can be given of this strange reUgion of deception is that it is intended mainly for women and proletaries, who, in the opinion of Comte, Tne reugi0I1 could be hoodwinked with ease.3 His Catechism is a "deception. series of conversations between an imaginary woman and an imaginary priest. The woman appears to see many difficulties in the way of the new faith ; but the priest's answers invariably clear them up. Only with such could a man Uke Comte have expected his new religion to find acceptance. Women of discerning minds wfll not be so easily deceived. The limited space which can be given in a work like this to a system with so little merit forbids elaborate treatment. However, the essential features of Positivism, its Great Being and prayer, have been suffici ently exposed. It is not pertinent here to enter upon the Positivist philosophy which professes to underlie the Positivist religion. It is really nothing but agnosticism in a form quite similar to that of Hume and Spencer. But there is one more characteristic of Positivism as a religion to which attention ought to be called. Whoever has read even this brief treatment of the subject must be impressed -with the artifi ciality of Comte's system. It is not a growth, nor did it flow out of his inmost heart Uke the utterances of a prophet. It is a Artificiality of manufactured article, bearing all the marks of device. Posltivism. It was thought out in the study, not wrought out in the conflict of daily Ufe. The only exceptions to these statements are the elements which embody Christian practice or which are imitations of such prac tice or teaching. 8 Besides an artificial divinity, and prayer as an arti- 1 Flint calls attention, also, to Comte's perversion of the word " religion."— Anti-Theistic Theories, p. 198 f. ' Catechism, pp. 31, 33, where he gives his reasons for addressing his reUgion mostly to women. Seep. 114, where we get one of the many hints he gives us of his estimate of the mental weaknesses of women. 3 For example, the offering of the last prayer when in bed, continuing until we fall asleep (p. 124), and the suggestion that the two hours devoted daily to personal improvement by prayer are less than the time usually absorbed by the reading of books of no value, or by useless or even pernicious amusements. 338 Foundations of the Christian Faith. fice, there are several other features worthy of note. " The morning prayer should be, in general, twice as long as the evening. That at midday should be haU as long." "We usuaUy divide the morning prayer mto three parts of equal length." ' The nine so-caUed social sacraments are, presentation, initiation, admission, destination, mar riage, maturity, retirement, transformation, and incorporation.3 Their significance cannot be explained here. Some of them are useful enough, particularly those which are adapted from Christianity. The point to be now illustrated is the artificial periods of time between them. Between the first and second there are fourteen years. Seven years later he receives the third sacrament, which admits him to the service of humanity, whereas he had been previously a mere receiver from humanity. It is a remarkable idea that one cannot serve, though he can be served by, humanity for the first twenty-one years of his Ufe. One would think that a youth of eighteen to twenty-one might "render as noble an aid " as a "horse, a dog, or an ox." Seven years must now pass; he must be twenty-eight before he can be allowed to choose his career— the sacrament of destination. Further development of this point is unnecessary. We mention but one more instance : the clerical aspirants must be twenty-eight, the vicars, thirty-five, and the priests proper forty-two years of age before they can be admitted. All this insistence on definite times, ages, and durations marks the artificiality of the system. It leaves nothing to spontaneity. It overlooks the enormous difference in the rapidity of natural development in different individuals and races. This in itseU is sufficiently serious from a practical point of view, but it is men tioned here solely for the purpose of illustrating the artificial character which pervades the whole of the Positivist reUgion. A reUgion which grows up as the natural product of the desire to meet specific human needs may not be so systematic, and it may not be perfect in all its theories ; but it has in it the breath of life. He who is not content to let a reUgion grow, but would plan it beforehand, must needs be very wise. Even God did not presume to mark out so definitely as Comte the details of human Ufe. He left something to man's discretion and decision, contenting himself with the revelation of the great funda mental principles of conduct. The consequence is that the Christian religion exhibits no marks of artificiality, though it gives evidence of a superhuman wisdom. Comte's artificial reUgion, on the other hand, except where it borrows from Christianity, evinces human folly. > Catechism, p. 125. » Ibid., p. 128. Ethical Culture. 339 CHAPTER III. ETHICAL CULTURE— ITS MISREPRESENTATIONS OF CHRISTIANITY. Not aU the members and adherents of the so-called societies for Ethical Culture would attempt to substitute it for Christianity ; nor would aU of them even go so far as to substitute the societies for the Church. Nevertheless, the majority, U we may judge from the Uterature produced by them, would do both. The Union of the Societies for Ethical Culture aims "to elevate the moral Ufe of its members and that of the community ; and it cordially welcomes to its fellowship aU persons who sympathize with this aim, whatever may be their theological or philosophical opinions."1 The aim of the Union, therefore, is not to displace Christianity, though it does not allow it any rank superior to that granted to atheism. Atheists, materialists, and Christians aU meet on a common level, sinking their differences in the one purpose, "to elevate the moral Ufe." This very breadth, therefore, is destructive of the claim that Christianity furnishes the only firm basis for a true moraUty. Under the specious pretense of breadth it invites Christians to strip off their dearest tenets and help atheists to demonstrate the possibility of high morality without reUgion. But, whfle the Union displaces Christianity only by indirection, there are those in the ranks of the Ethical Cultur- ists, and they are the leaders in the ranks, who openly propose to substitute Ethical Culture for Christianity. The princi- Kelation of pal work of William Mackintire Salter is entitled taretoCb°ri£ Ethical Religion, and aU the suspicions aroused by the Hamty- title are confirmed by the contents of the book. Even the minimum of Christian doctrine which, according to Salter, the Unitarians hold is too much," and hence Unitarianism cannot satisfy him. He can be "satisfied" only when "no confession, Christian or other," limits the freedom of the colaborers for the elevation of the moral Ufe. Mr. Stanton Coit, another leader among the Ethical Culturists, has written a work under the title, Ethical Culture as a Religion for the People,3 to fllustrate the supremacy of ethics and the needlessness of any religious faith. 1 Salter, Ethical Religion, p. 320, n. « Ibid., p. 266. 3 London, 1887. The date and title, as well as the contents, are given by Gizycki. 34:0 Foundations of the Christian Faith. As the standard work on Ethical Culture we choose here Salter's Ethical Religion. It is true that he disclaims any purpose, as his colaborers would deny his right, to speak for others than himseU. Still, he represents very fairly the main principles of the movement, of which he is so ardent a champion, both in this country and in Europe. Besides, there is no mistaking what he means. His lan guage is unequivocal and his utterances are, in the main, seU- consistent. This cannot be said of some other leaders of the Ethical Culture movement in this country. Salter makes the impression of being perfectly honest as well as unhesitating. In many respects, by his solemn earnestness and zeal for righteousness, he reminds the reader of the best of Hebrew prophets. For all these and for many other reasons we have taken him as the strongest and most representative man in the Ethical Culture movement in America, and we shaU dis cuss that movement chiefly in the Ught of his utterances. ¦ It is, how ever, not proposed to condemn the Societies for Ethical Culture for what they are, but to defend Christianity against their assaults and to point out the inadequacy of the movement as a substitute for the religion of Jesus. We consider first the faults Salter finds with Christianity as compared with Ethical Culture. A chief complaint is that Chris tianity holds that love and justice are actually ruling in the world ; Salter's first tnat ** satf8> Th0 ideal does rule, whfle the new reUgion SentottXoi wi11 say> Let it rule.' But Christianity, as one of the old Christianity. religions which Salter rejects, does not say that love and justice— the ideal— do rule. Some theologians have seemed to teach this, but the vast majority of Christian beUevers hold the contrary. The only teaching in the New Testament, which alone is the source from which Christian doctrine can be discovered, approaching the idea that the ideal does actuaUy rule in the world, is the doctrine of God's providence over his people. We are taught that "aU things work together for good to them that love God ;"s but the very state ment impUes that there are evfls in the world, which, however, U we cooperate, God can so overrule that they shaU not harm us but be compelled to contribute to our good. The teaching is not that condi tions are ideal, but that in spite of unideal conditions God's children shall experience no real harm. In spite of all the evfl in the world God • Besides the works already mentioned the reader should consult Felix Adler's Creed and Deed, Now York, 1877 ; also an article by Adler on Modern Skepticism and Ethi cal Culture, In the Forum, October. 1893, and another by J. Smith, Ethical Substitutes for Christianity, in the British and Foreign Evangelical Review, vol. xxxi, p. 439. » Ethical Religion, pp. 12, 13. » Rom. viii, 28. Ethical Culture. 341 is at work upon human hearts striving to hinder its consequences. Just because the standpoint of Christianity is so thoroughly ethical it is possible to teach with truth that the man who loves God, the Good, wfll be able to make the very existence of evfl itseU a means of good; that is, of moral progress. The "old religion," Christianity, has never said that the ideal rules, but that sin and misery are in a world which ought to be, and might be, the scene of righteousness, love, and happiness. On the other hand, this "old religion " has been saying for eighteen hundred years what the advocates of the "new" impudently claim as their exclusive virtue: "Let the ideal, let love and justice rule." Anyone who wfll honestly compare those portions of the world where Christianity prevails, even in its most corrupt form, with the moral conditions which existed among the same peoples prior to the intro duction of Christianity can but come to the conclusion that just in proportion as a nation is Christian is it enlightened and moral — does the ideal, love and justice rule. Were men Uke Salter to cease misrepresenting and maligning Christianity, and to turn their en ergies to making it triumphant, it would not be long until the ideal would rule in a very complete degree. The Ethical Culturists are no doubt honest, but it is amazing that they should, like the enemies of morality, assault the only system which has in it the potency of human ethical improvement, giving aid and comfort to those who in their secret hearts want aU the safeguards of moraUty destroyed. Another serious fault is thus stated by Salter:' "And here is the ignoble side to theology; for not only is the personal Deity of the ology fllusory, but by gathering the divine qualities into a form out side of man it allows us to forget that they are quahties for man, and religion becomes the worship of something already ex- His second isting instead of the sense of a burden and a task. We tation. are to become divine ; we are to make this world a scene of justice. All that men have gathered into the form of God is but the image of our possible selves." Whether "the personal Deity of theology" is illusory is not here in debate. But if there be a being in whom aU divine qualities concur why should we be forbidden to worship him ? It is universally conceded that men tend to become like the gods they worship. Salter seems to object to our becoming righteous by means of worship. Again, it is not true that "all that men have gathered into the 1 Ethical Religion, p. 12. 24 34:2 Foundations of the Christian Faith. form of a God is but the image of our possible selves ;" for they have attributed to God omnipotence, omnipresence, omniscience, none of which is possible to man. Salter, Uke most opponents of Christianity, lacks in power of discrimination. This is why they fail to see the superiority of Christianity. He has failed to discriminate here. What he probably means to say is that aU moral quaUties which men have attributed to God are possible in ourselves— the moral character of God is our possible moral character. Now, these divine qualities of love, mercy, justice, are not gathered by Christian theology into a form outside of man, at least not there alone, but in the man Christ Jesus. And so far from allowing us to forget that these divine quaU ties are qualities for men any Christian theology which deserves the name makes Jesus our example and demands that we shaU strive to become ethically Uke God.1 In this sense of the word Christianity has from the beginning taught that " we are to become divine ; '' that "we are to make this world a scene of justice," and of many good things besides justice. Strange infatuation with seU is that which can make a man take the plainest truths of Christianity and arrogate to himself the credit of having just discovered them without any aid from the system he condemns. But, again, Salter says:3 "The old religions (of course including Christianity) leave us on our knees in rapt contemplation and wor ship : the new wfll summon us to stand erect, and to beUeve that aU men have worshiped, aU that they have dreamed of, aU that has seemed so far above them and beyond them, men and women in the future are to become and to realize." Can it be that Salter ready beUeves that Third misrep- Christianity does not summon man to stand erect, and to resentation. Dei jeye all that he here declares as to the ethical possibil ities in mankind ? With aU purpose to be kind and charitable in judgment we cannot acquit the man who can write such a passage of being either too ignorant to be set up as a teacher of others, or else too prejudiced to admit the good he knows to exist in a system he opposes. Yet not for the sake of condemning Salter, who has doubt less labored honestly, but for the sake of saving men from yielding to his delusion do we point out the absolute unfairness and injustice of what he says and implies. It is surely most unfair to Christendom to represent it as on its knees, in rapt contemplation and worship, while those who oppose the wrongs that are in the world and encour age men to upright living are those who reject Christianity. The Christian religion is indeed "the worship of something already ex- 1 1 Pet. 11, 21-23 ; Matt, v, 43^8. • Ethical Religion, p. 13. Ethical Culture. 343 isting," but it is not that "instead of the sense of a burden and a task," rather is it worship and the sense of a burden and a task. To say or to imply that Christianity is chiefly worship, whfle neglectful of morals, is to utter a base and baseless slander. Many so-caUed Christians may have given themselves chiefly to the devotional side of Christianity ; but they have done so, U at aU, in spite of the ethical teachings of the New Testament, which constitute the bulk of the New Testament writings. Another complaint of Salter against reUgion in general is that it makes sacred aU that it commands,1 and that it has often prompted men to do things that are not right while probably they never once asked themselves any other question than, Will it please my God? and that, U anyone asks himseU what he ought to do, aside from the fear or favor of God, he probably never does altogether wrong.3 Among the iUustrations he gives of men who under the influence of reUgion did things which were wrong he mentions Paul, who, before his conversion, verily thought he ought to do many Fourth mis- representa- things contrary to the name of Jesus of Nazareth. Here tion. is a case in which a reUgionist asked himseU what he ought to do, and yet, according to Salter, did wrong. Now, what do our opposers expect ? That we shall be omniscient, because we are reUgious? Shall other men be excused for falling into error when they follow their moral judgments and reUgionists be condemned under the same circumstances ? That men professing to be followers of Christ have persecuted and done many other wicked things, under the impression that it was right to do so, is too true. But, so far from this having arisen from a purpose to do the will of Jesus, it arose from a neglect of such a purpose in the interests of the current view of right. The savagery and bigotry of the non-Chris tian world had entered into Christendom with the mere outward form of Christianity. Instead of asking themselves, What would Jesus do under our circumstances? men nominally Christians, yet but Uttle CJlmstianized, followed the conception of right they had brought with them into the Christian fold. No man who has respect to the "fear or favor" of the Christian's God, and capable of forming a correct conception of the spirit and content of Christian moraUty, wfll ever do wrong while thinking he is doing right. But U, as so many professed Christians do, he asks himself, irrespective of the 1 Jesus guarded against this danger by requiring men to judge of all acts by other criteria than those of custom or commandment. See, for instance, his words relative to " corban," Mark vii, 7-13. a Ethical Religion, pp. 89-93. 344 Foundations of the Christian Faith. fear or favor of God or man, "What ought I to do?" he will be in danger of going astray. ReUgion does mean, as Salter says, to most persons, the securing of the favor of God. But what sort of a Christian would he be who could expect to get the favor of the Chris tian's God by doing the very things he has forbidden? It is the neglect of the will of God as revealed in Christ, not the effort to follow it, which leads men astray whfle they ask themselves, irre spective of the fear or favor of God, what they ought to do. We cannot resist calUng attention to one peculiar fact. Anyone who wfll read Salter's words on pages 89-93 wfll be impressed with the vigor which he unconsciously admits religion to have lent to its devotees. And this effect of reUgion is exactly what inteUigent Christians insist upon. Salter would rob us of this mighty motive to morality. The truth is that reUgion in the heart — the Christian religion — is the most powerful and steady impulse to the foUowing of conscience which can be conceived. But whfle the Christian reUgion gives us such an impulse it also furnishes us with the principles which in due course of time wfll educate the moral judgment of man kind to a perfect standard. Of both of these tremendous advantages which Christian has over non-Christian moraUty Ethical Culturists of the Salter type would deprive the world. Yet they pose as re formers ! We mention one more fault which Ethical Culturists lodge rather against the Church and the clergy than against Christianity. Says Salter : 1 " Even the Churches, which should inspire us with an ideal view of Ufe, talk of mere morality." "We often hear, and, I am sorry to say, from religious teachers particularly, slighting and con temptuous words about morality." The second quotation probably is Fifth misrepre- to be interpreted in the light of the first. Those who sentation. gpeak of " mere morality » gj.e they who utter « glightjng and contemptuous words about moraUty." No one can object to the term " mere morality " who does not believe that morality is either the highest thing in the universe or else the all of the universe. If there is anything higher or other than morality then it is entirely pos sible to speak of "mere morality" without any thought of sUght or contempt. Morality is a human quality, and it is transcended in dig nity as divine righteousness transcends human. If anyone denies the existence of God there could, of course, in his judgment, be nothing higher than human morality. Of aU human things moraUty is high- 1 Ethical Religion, p. 22 and p. 56. Felix Adler makes a similar complaint in The Forum, Oct., 1893, p. 381. Ethical Culture. 345 est. In a godless system of thought the term " mere moraUty " would be one of disparagement. Not so in a system which acknowl edges God." Besides, Salter should know, and if he dealt with men at as close range as preachers do he would know, that what the major ity of men caU moraUty is the abstinence from doing wrong. In com parison with the demands of Christianity this is to be termed " mere morality." Again, it is a fact that many, so far from being humbled by their deviations even from their relatively low conceptions of righteousness, are filled with pride and self-satisfaction because they are no worse. Theirs is "mere moraUty" to be condemned. UntU they are like God, the Good, who is far higher than morality in their meaning of the word, they are in danger. Salter's is a war of words. If he would take the pains to see what Christian teachers have in mind when they speak what he caUs "sUghting and contemptuous words about morality " he would see that these words never apply to what he means by moraUty and what Christians caU the ethical side of reUgion. 346 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IV. INADEQUACY OF ETHICAL CULTURE TO THE PURPOSES OF A REUGION. We now turn our attention to a criticism of Ethical Culture itseU in which it will be revealed that as human moraUty is not the high est thing in the universe so it is not the only thing needful to hu manity. (1) Ethical Culture is too narrow a scheme to meet all, or even most, of the demands of human lUe. It offers us a gospel of righteousness. In this there is nothing original. The Hebrews had the same concep tion of lUe long ago, and the New Testament is largely made up of it. Both the Old and the New Testament recognize that sin is the prin cipal source of human sorrow, and also the principal enemy to the proper development of human character. Christianity has for its chief aim the destruction of the sinful disposition, the development of righteous character, and the practice of right conduct ; yet, important as it is, righteousness is not the only need of human Ufe. LUe is being, Narrowness of aa weu" aiS conduct. We are, before we can be related to ofPPe1tnicai others, in right or wrong behavior. Christianity says, culture. Be) tliat you may ,j0 Ethical Culture simply says, Do. Thus has Christianity everything that Ethical Culture claims, and it had it before Ethical Culture had it ; and it has far more than Ethical Culture has. There are times when the heart needs the ministry of comfort rather than of exhortation. Ethical Culture has no adequate word for those who long for immortaUty and reunion with the loved and loving dead ; no consolation for those who are the victims of disease or other pain ; no promise that in a world to come there shaU prevail a better state than this because no sin shall enter there, because it wfll be made up of those who have triumphed over sin here. The heart has need of fellowship, of the sense of awe and reverence, and of a thousand things which Ethical Culture with its sole emphasis upon righteousness can not afford. Ethical Culture is perhaps sufficient for those who have plenty of friends and but few sorrows ; but hope must be kept aUve at times when the heart is so filled with a sense of disappointment that its pessimism allows no room for thoughts of duty. It may be said that U all were righteous there would be no such Inadequacy of Ethical Culture. 347 moments. We shall not undertake to dispute the proposition. But the Ethical Culturist has lived so long in the thought of what ought to be that he has forgotten what is. The vast majority are unrighteous ; and no system is adequate which whUe it stimulates to righteousness does not at the same time provide for the amelioration of the sad con sequences of sin. For example, here is an unhappy violator of the laws of righteousness. His conscience smites him, and he is wretched on account of his sins. The sense of the evfl past overwhelms him. He has lost his self-respect. Ethical Culture would exhort him to sin no more. But he needs something beyond that. He must hear the Great Supporter of the moral law say, Thy sins are forgiven thee. Not, as is grossly understood by many, that he may be relieved of the fear of punishment, for this is but a smaU ingredient in his cup of misery ; but that he may feel that he has a friend who, though so high and holy, will still not desert him. (2) The righteousness which Ethical Culture advocates is, compared with that of Christianity, not more exalted, but hard and severe. Could it be practiced in complete isolation from Christian influences it would result in the production of a civilization almost if not wholly devoid of the gentleness and sweetness of genuine Christianity. The reason of this is that Ethical Culture emphasizes righteousness, the outward expression, the result, and places the cause too exclu sively in the will and conscience; whereas Christianity expects righteousness to flow, not only from the operation of the severity of the wfll and conscience, but also from the spirit of love. negss incui- Christianity recognizes that righteousness in conduct ethical cu£ may spring from a sole sense of obligation, and it teaches Ule- that though we bestow all our goods to feed the poor and have not charity it profiteth nothing.1 In other words, Christianity empha sizes love as the source of all righteousness, and at the same time as its most important element. (3) This leads up to another defect of Ethical Culture as a substi tute for Christianity. It claims that righteousness is so attractive that it needs no other support than itself ; U it be Uf ted Attractiveness up it will draw aU men unto it. True it is that when ness. properly presented it is attractive. But it is impossible to present it in its most attractive form in any words or phrases which human thought can devise or human tongues can utter. Righteousness is most attractive when presented in a concrete form ; and hence it is that the righteousness of Jesus is best adapted to attract men to righteousness. 1 1 Cor., xiii, 3. 348 Foundations of the Christian Faith. (4) Again, Ethical Culture is defective in having no authoritative external standard of righteousness. Says Salter : ' "There is an ideal aim for every child of man. It is not in anything outside of ourselves; it is not to please some supernatural being in the skies ; it is not to follow some far away historical figure in the past. It is closer to us than this ; it is in our own heart, it is given to us in our very nature as moral beings." We shall not pause to point out the confusion in the use of terms which makes the passage just quoted unclear. What is probably meant is that the ideal of righteousness is given to every child of man by virtue of his nature as a moral being ; not only is it natural to us to feel promptings to do the right, but the ideal of right need not be sought outside of ourselves. If this were true there could never be any need of instruction as to what is wrong or what is duty. The ideal would be the same in infancy as in manhood, and in all alike. The facts are aU contrary to this. There is, indeed, a powerful impulse in each to do the right, but the ideal of right is chiefly a mat ter of education. It is the defect of naturaUstic systems of ethics that they make this ideal standard dependent upon the concensus of pubUc opinion or upon Lack of an ex- the subjective condition of each individual. Christianity ard of au- gives us a fixed standard outside of ourselves. That "" 'l* standard is Jesus Christ, presumably the "far away his torical figure in the past," who is not needed, according to Salter, because the ideal is closer to us, even in our hearts; a part of our very nature as moral beings. Has Salter never met anyone who had low ideals? Does every man, or any man, have in his heart such an ideal as Jesus Christ except by having it suggested to him from out side himself ? In fact, all men are foUowing a moral ideal which is more the result of revelation either by men or God than of any innate sense of correct ethics. It is notorious that most of what we do, whether good, bad, or indifferent, is the result of voluntary or invol untary imitation. Everyone who is not fiUed with seU-conceit needs some noble example after which he may, though not slavishly, pat tern. The highest actual and the highest conceivable example is just this alleged unnecessary "far away figure in the past." That we have not misunderstood Salter is evident from many pas sages which might be cited. We give but one : " I beUeve a man can be as vigilant over himself as ever God or angel could be. I beUeve he may be as impartial toward himself, as high in Ins demands, and as sure in his condemnations."3 Here he either denies omniscience to ' Ethical Religion, p. 57. a lDld<> p. 1T8. Inadequacy of Ethical Culture. 349 God or attributes it to man, or makes it of no value in determining questions of right and duty. He may have such wisdom that not even an all- wise God could be wiser ; but no one else has. And those of us who feel our profound lack of wisdom in the compUcated questions of human duty are glad to avaU ourselves of the example of that glo rious, though ' ' far away figure in the past, " Jesus Christ. Often have men who did not know what to do asked themselves, What would Jesus do were he in my place ? and after careful restudy of his blame less and perfect teachings and life they have found great light. (5) Ethical Culture does not offer any adequate check to the selfish ness which dominates most human hearts. If this deep-seated evil is to be overcome it must be by the awakening of some Ethical Cui- affection strong enough to counteract it. In some good no adequate degree and in some instances, patriotism, and conjugal human* seif° and parental, as weU as fiUal, affection tend to produce the isnness- desired result. The love of righteousness is impossible while this pro found selfishness continues to exist. Righteousness has no attrac tions for the selfish soul, which is blinded by its selfishness to the beauty of benevolence. Righteousness preached, therefore, is not the antidote to selfishness ; but love incarnate may awaken gratitude, and through love to the benefactor love for his righteousness may be educed. Very certain it is that the enthusiasm for himseU which the person of Jesus has stirred in untold millions of hearts has done more to lead men to forget seU than all other causes combined. It may be said that men ought to love righteousness for its own sake, and not because it is a quality of one who is loved. Such a de mand will, however, be made only by one who knows nothing, or for the time forgets what he knows, of human nature. Many things ought to be which are not, and the question is how to make things as they ought to be. Roundabout methods must often be employed by practical men. The selfish man is self -centered ; to ask him to be righteous is to ask him to act contrary to his strongest f eelings and to be what he is not. By force of wfll he could perform benevolent acts, but he cannot by any volition reach and correct the selfishness of his heart. But if, by any profound emotion, the center of gravity of his feelings can be changed there is hope that selfishness may be ban ished. Even his very sense of self-interest may be employed to destroy his undue love of self. Fear of the consequences of self -grati fication, or love of some good which may be made to appear greater than that which one has been pursuing, may change the center of gravity of the emotions and thus prepare the way for love of right- 350 Foundations of the Christian Faith. eousness. Many means have been found efficient, but the only one which has never failed is the love of Jesus. Just in proportion as men love him do they forget seK and love righteousness. Ethical Culture ignores the fact that " out of the heart are the issues of Ufe." It seeks to get conduct chiefly from the action of will, which, compared with the affections, is powerless. Jesus taught us the true philosophy. Neither in its criticisms of Christianity nor in its own nature is Ethical Culture found worthy of becoming a substitute for the reUgion of Christ. Theosophy — Its Speculative Character. 351 CHAPTER V. THEOSOPHY— EXHIBITION OF ITS SPECULATIVE CHARACTER. Theosophy, says a recognized leader in the theosophical move ment, "is wisdom about God for those who believe that he is aU things and in all, and wisdom about nature for the man who accepts the statement of the Christian Bible that God cannot be measured or discovered, and that darkness is around his pavilion. Although it contains by derivation the name of God, and thus may seem at first to embrace religion alone, it does not neglect science, for it is the science of sciences, and therefore has been caUed the wisdom religion." "By embracing both the scientific and the religious, Theosophy is a scientific religion and a religious science." • In so far as it is scientific we shaU have to let science look after it ; we have to do here only with its religious aspects. If we were to judge from some of the utterances of the advocates of Theosophy we should be compelled to suppose that they feel no sense of difference between Christianity and their doctrine or Relation of system.3 Indeed, so irenic are some of their expressions to^cMsfran^ that one almost wonders what it is that makes Christian- lty- ity unsuitable for their purposes and Theosophy a necessity to them. Further reading, however, reveals the fact that to the mind of the average Theosophist original Christianity was quite theosophic, and that the Christianity of to-day is really therefore not Christianity at all. Though the Theosophist does not regard it as an assault upon original Christianity to say that it was theosophic, yet the Christian feels almost compeUed to defend his Master's religion against the im putation. We gladly recognize the value to Theosophists of aU the Christian truth they possess, but we must demur when Mr. Fullerton a makes Jesus assert or imply one of the essentials of Theosophy, namely, that ' ' man can only exhaust Ufe of its lessons by undergoing lUe in every form ; " that is, makes Jesus teach the theosophic doc trine of reincarnation ; or when Mr. Budd * identifies the method of 1 The Ocean of Theosophy, by W. Q. Judge, third edition, New York, 1896, p. 1. The Supreme Court of Massachusetts has decided (1898) that Theosophy is neither religious nor educational. 2 For instance, the paper by Alexander Fullerton, in Things Common to Christianity and Theosophy, New York, 1894. ' Ibid., p. 10. * Ibid., p. 14. 352 Foundations of the Christian Faith. teaching employed by Jesus and St. Paul with that of Theosophy in its distinction between exoteric and esoteric doctrine and between the masses and the select few. The passages from Jesus and Paul upon which such an identification must be based can only be so interpreted by one who fails to appre hend their true significance. The distinction which Christ made was not between the select few and the masses, but between those who Exoteric and left all and followed him and those who were indifferent 6sot6ricdoctrines. or opposed to him.1 Paul's language about speaking ' ' wisdom among them that are perfect " 3 lends itself much more easily to the interpretation of Mr. Budd. But with him it was not a funda mental distinction, as with the Theosophists, but one founded in a mere pedagogical necessity. Both Jesus and Paul found it necessary to bide their time for the propagation of their doctrines ; but both felt that the very men who to-day were unable to comprehend them might be able to-morrow. The point with them was not that some men could understand by reason of a greater " depth of intellect "or " clearer in tuition"3 than others possessed, but that what truth had already been imparted must first be assimilated before it would be wise to give more. They did not trace this necessity to a faflure in some supposed past incarnations by which they lacked the "purity of life" and the " lofty ideals and aspirations " required in order to be "able to per ceive and grasp the sublimest spiritual truths concerning nature and man." * The truth they taught was not such as to require either high inteUect or purity for its apprehension. It was a truth which the low liest could grasp, and which appealed to the sinner in his sins. It did not require him to be good in order to receive the blessings of the Gos pel ; the blessings of the Gospel were designed to make him good. But the moral and spiritual forces reUed on by Theosophists cannot work except when conditions are favorable. "It would be subversive of the ends they have in view were they (the elder brothers) to make them selves public in the present civilization, which is based almost wholly on money, fame, glory, and personality." " Jesus came to those who were sick. The elder brothers wfll come only to those who are whole. Here is one of the fatal defects of Theosophy, as judged by its chief expounders. It does not save the sinner as such ; it can do its best Plan of tbeo- only for him who, by repeated reincarnations and struggle iSOplW* ' Theosophy — Its Inferiority %o Christianity. 359 founded upon the nature of things lacks exactly the element of brotherliness. The element of voluntary good wiU found in the Christian idea of brotherhood is altogether lacking. We close the discussion of Theosophy as a substitute for Christian ity by giving the reader some idea of the marvels which Theosophists claim their initiates can perform. To anyone who has the least acquaintance with the miracles of Jesus the superiority Tne miraeies of the latter will be immediately apparent; and this theJe|iieged superiority is a symbol of the superiority of Christianity xheosoSphy to Theosophy. We quote from Judge , J "If an initiate comPare(1- can make a sohd object move without contact it is because he under stands the two laws of attraction and repulsion of which "gravita tion ' is but the name for one ; U he is able to precipitate out of the viewless air the carbon which we know is in it, forming the carbon into sentences upon the paper, it is through his knowledge of the occult higher chemistry, and the use of a trained and powerful image- making faculty which every man possesses ; if he reads your thoughts with ease, that results from the use of the inner and only real powers of sight, which require no retina to see the fine-pictured web which the vibrating brain of man weaves about him." 1 Ocean, p. 12. 360 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER "VTI. CHRISTIAN SCIENCE — STATEMENT AND CRITICISM. Were we to accept the reiterated professions, no doubt sincerely made, of the adherents of Christian Science, we should not class this movement as a proposed substitute for Christianity. Christian Scien tists claim to be in fact the true foUowers of Jesus Christ, and by impUcation aU but themselves are mistaken in regarding themselves as true Christians.1 Christian Science may be described as an at tempt to apply the most extreme form of subjective metaphysical ideaUsm to the practical departments of health and soteriology. At first sight it might appear therefore that there need be no rivalry between it and Christianity. When it is considered that it attempts to make Christ sponsor for both the metaphysical doctrines upon which it proceeds and for its appUcation of those doctrines, and that in applying this metaphysics it proposes to speak with authority both concerning some of the presuppositions and some of the plainest doctrines of Christianity, it will be seen that the apologist must at least study it with careful scrutiny. The writer is convinced that Christian Science is subversive of the Christianity of Jesus. One of the first points which must attract the student's attention is the fact that so scant use is made of the teachings and deeds of Jesus. The discoverer of this faith and practice" may be conscious of placing Scant use of Jesus at the center of her doctrine ; but she fails to leave and d£e°drsdof that impression upon the reader of her works. What she Christian teaches and what she has done is far more prominent there than what Jesus teaches and what he has done. The references to the teachings and deeds of Jesus are not only meager, but they appear to be employed as a prop to what she says. The impression is not left that we are attending to an exposition of the life of Jesus, that he is the Spring whence all the teachings of Christian Science flow. The metaphysical doctrines of subjective 1 It should be remembered that Christian history is thickly strewn with the records of parties evidently unchristian which have claimed the Christian name. ' We refer of course to Mrs. Mary Baker G. Eddy. We have taken our references mostly from her cheaper and more accessible writings. Her principal work, Science and Health with Key to the Scriptures, offers nothing essential to the system, not here given. Christian Science — Statement and Criticism. 361 idealism seem to be fundamental ; from them arise aU of the practi cal applications. It is not made clear that this philosophy was the philosophy of Jesus, though the assertion is frequent enough.1 Be sides aU this there would appear to be a misunderstanding in the mind of the founder of Christian Science as to the exact content of the teachings of Jesus. Her mind is so filled with the one thought of the truth of subjective idealism that the utterances of the Scripture aU interpret themselves in the Ught of that philosophy. It is in this spirit that she interprets the saying of Jesus, " Take no thought what ye shaU eat," 3 to mean that mortals need not concern themselves with the chemistry of food ; in other words, that this saying of Jesus supports the thesis that the diet of the invaUd no more than medicine affects the question of his recovery. We think these few statements are sufficient to warrant one in suspecting the Christian source of the new doctrine. But, further, notwithstanding the earnest declaration that Christian Science is not designed chiefly for the healing of bodily disease,8 but that its emphatic purpose is the healing of sin, still the Tne promi- prominence given by Christian Scientists to bodily gives to6bod- healing, taken together with the fact that somehow dy healing. human beings seem to dread sickness more than they do sin, is Uable to leave the impression that the adherents of the new system think the rehef of the former the chief business of Christianity. This may not be a fundamental defect, but one rather of the form in which the doctrine is presented. But it is a notable fact that Jesus so taught that whfle he healed vast numbers of their bodily ailments he left the impression of an ethical and reUgious teacher rather than of a healer of disease. According to Christian Science both sickness and sin are illusions ; but the Christian Scientists would hardly deny that sin is the more hurtful of the two. A system which professes to represent Christianity should see to it that in the minds of its adherents that thought is uppermost to which Jesus gave the principal emphasis. We come next to consider the metaphysical system with which Christian Science is connected; or, rather, the application which Christian Science makes of it. We point out first of its false meta- aU that the founder of Christian Science is not a skflled Physics- metaphysician nor a skflled scientist in the ordinary acceptation of those terms. Yet she speaks on these subjects as one having 1 For example, in No and Yes, p. 30. * Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 23 f. On Mrs. Eddy's exegesis see J. H. Bates's Chris tian Science and its Problems, New York and Cincinnati, 1898, pp. 76-87. ' Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 9. 362 Foundations of the Christian Faith. authority. She quotes from an astronomer in 1891 the commonplace that "color is in us," not "in the rose." ' The statement is not ac cepted almost universaUy by physicists, as her authority makes her beUeve. It is held by scientists that color is something which we at tribute to the rose, but not that the color is in us. She says :3 " The evidence that the earth is motionless, and the sun revolves around our planet, is as sensible and real as the evidence for disease; but science (that is, we suppose, Christian Science, certainly not science in the ordinary use of that word) determines the evidence in both cases to be unreal. To material sense it is plain also that the error of the revolution of the sun is more apparent than the adverse, but true, science of the steUar universe. Copernicus has shown that what appears real, to material sense and feeling, is absolutely un real. Astronomy, optics, acoustics, and hydraulics are aU at war with the testimony, of the physical senses. This fact intimates that the laws of science are mental; and Christian Science demon strates this." Now, idealist metaphysicians do not aUow that the physical senses give any testimony whatever. Their theory is that certain im pressions are produced upon the nervous organism and that the mind within construes these impressions. The ideaUst metaphysics can as weU account for the theory that the sun revolves around the earth as for the other, that the earth revolves around the sun and upon its own axis. In both cases the impressions upon the nervous organism are the same. The difference is in the construction which the mind puts upon the impressions ; not in any supposed "testimony of the physical senses;" any "sensible" evidence as opposed to the mental perception. It is an ungracious task, and one which we reluctantly perform, to point out these glaring defects of metaphysical skill. We should not have done it but for the fact that the founder of Christian Science makes such large use of her metaphysical theory throughout her system of teaching. We now point out the necessity of scrutiniz ing her teachings on aU these subjects, lest her readers be misled by her confidence in her metaphysical reasonings and aver ments. We simply say, Beware. For the rest we shall foUow the metaphysics of the system no further, but only the appUcation of it. 5 1 Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 16. » No and Yes, p. 14 f. 8 The entire metaphysical system is assailable even from the standpoint of its own sub jective idealism. For example, its infinite is so thoroughly comprehensible by man that it can assert that besides Its Infinite there can be nothing else. See Answers to Questions in Christian Science, by Edward A. Kimball, p. 6. Christian Science — Statement and Criticism. 363 According to Christian Science God is all, and there is nothing and nobody in the universe but God. This is reiterated in so many differ ent ways and with such frequency that it cannot be misunderstood. " God must be found AU instead of a part of being." ' "God is AU- in-all." 3 " Mortals do not understand the AU ; hence their inference of some other existence besides God and his true like- citations from ness— of something unlike him." s The same idea comes Mrs- Eddy- out even more fully in the doctrine concerning mind, man, matter, disease, error, evil, and sin. Of mind we read, "God is mind, and there is no other mind." 4 Of man it is said, "he is neither matter, nor a mode of mortal mind, for he is spiritual and eternal, an im mortal mode of the divine Mind."6 "All real being represents God, and is in him." Of matter the teaching is this : ' "All is mind. Ac cording to the Scriptures and Christian Science aU is God, and there is naught beside him." "The five material senses testUy to the ex istence of matter. The spiritual senses afford no such evidence, but deny the testimony of the material senses." "If, as the Scriptures declare, God is All-in-all, then aU must be mind, since God is Mind." Concerning disease we are taught,7 "Disease is a thing of thought mamfested on the body." " The beUef that matter can master mind, and make you ill Scientifically, is an error which truth must de stroy."8 " What seem to be disease, vice, and mortality are illusions of the physical senses." " " Disease is more than imagination ; it is a human error, a constituent part of what comprise the whole of mortal existence, namely, material sensation and mental delusion. But an erring sense of existence, or the error of belief, named disease, never made sickness a stubborn reality."10 Concerning error we have this:11 "In erring mortal thought the reality of truth has an anti- pode — the reaUty of error ; and disease is one of the severe realities of this error. God has no opposite in Science. To truth there is no error. As truth alone is real, then it foUows that to declare error real would be to make it truth." We deem it unnecessary to cite further utterances in proof of the statement with which the preceding paragraph begins. With refer ence to man only is any attempt made to mitigate this conclusion. This is done by adding to the already quoted declarations concerning man, the statement that " Man is not absorbed in Deity ; for he is for ever individual." " Of course man is not absorbed in the Deity U he i No and Yes, p. 21. * Ibid., pp. 24, 32. » Ibid., p. 25. * Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 11. s No and Yes, pp. 34, 35. 6 Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 12. 'Ibid., p. 20. "Ibid., p. 21. ' Ibid., p. 22. 10 No and Yes, p. 12. » Ibid., p. 13. » Ibid., p., 34. 364 Foundations of the Christian Faith. is " an immortal mode " of the Deity ; that is, the divine Mind. WeU may the founder of Christian Science add, "but what this individu- Her anthro- ^7 ^ remains to be learned." In fact, it is inconceiv- poiogy. abie that a mode of the Deity should be an individual dis tinct from the Deity. If as an individual he is not distinct from the Deity he must be a part of the Deity, or the Deity himself in one of his mamf estations. Notwithstanding aU this the founder of Christian Science denies that her system is pantheistic, asserting that pantheism is the beUef that spirit, or soul, exists in matter,1 or, as she states it elsewhere, "Mind in matter is pantheism." a In this sense of the word panthe ism Christian Science does indeed refute it, as its founder claims. " Christian Science shows that matter and mortal mind have neither origin nor existence in the eternal Mind."3 We leave it to our philo sophically trained readers to judge whether she has correctly defined pantheism, and whether or not she can successfully claim immunity from the charge of being a pantheist if judged by her metaphysics instead of by her asseverations. To the present writer it is clear that if her system is not pantheistic there is no system which can be properly so named. We pass on to the Christian Science doctrine of evfl. It is difficult to treat this subject apart from sin, since the system appears to make no clear distinction between them. We give the more important Her doctrine utterances on the subjects in question. "If God knows of evil. evil, even as a false claim, this knowledge would mani fest evfl in him and proceeding from him. Christian Science shows that matter, evfl, sin, sickness, and death are but negations of spirit, truth, and Ufe, which are positives that cannot be gainsaid."* "My system of metaphysics . . . rests on God as One and All, and denies the actual existence of both matter and evil."5 " There was never a moment in which evfl was real. This great fact concerning aU error brings with it another and more glorious truth, that good is supreme. As there is none beside him, and he is aU good, there can be no evil.'"' " AU real being represents God, and is in him. In this Science of being man can no more relax or collapse from perfection than his divine Principle, or Father, can fall out of himself into something below infinitude.'" "Good is great and real. Hence its opposite, named evfl, must be small and unreal."8 " Hence there is no sin, for God's kingdom is everywhere and supreme, and it foUows that the 1 No and Yes, p. 38. ' Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 13. ' No and Yes, p. 24. * Ibid., p. 24 f. »Ibld„ p. 33. • Ibid., p. 33 f. ' Ibid., p. 35. 'Ibid., p. 42. Christian Science — Statement and Criticism. 365 human kingdom is nowhere, and must be unreal."1 " The real Christ was unconscious of matter, of sin, disease, and death, and was con scious only of God, of good, of eternal Ufe, and harmony."3 "Ac cording to the evidence of the so-called physical senses, man is ma terial, fallen, sick, depraved," mortal. Science and spiritual sense contradict this." We recognize the difficulty under which Christian Science labors in the attempt to make clear its tenets and yet escape the danger of mis apprehension. Any metaphysical doctrine suffers from the inade quacy of language to convey its thought, as weU as from the stupidity of the reader. Much more is this the case when, as in Christian Science, there is mixed with the metaphysical a prominent mystical element. Mysticism, however true and valid, is difficult to put into categorical statements. But we think there can be no misunderstand ing of the significance of the foregoing quotations relative to evfl and sin. To show that we apprehend the real meaning which lies underneath the citations we have made we append others setting forth what we may cad the philosophy of the plan of salvation according to Christian Science. We have endeavored to arrange the citations as much as possible in logical order. "The law of Ufe and truth is the law of Christ, destroying aU sense of sin and death. It does more than forgive the false sense named sin, for it pursues and punishes it and wiU not let sin go until it is destroyed — until nothing is left to be forgiven, to suffer, or to be punished. Forgiven thus, sickness and sin have no re- Her pbnoso- lapse. God's law reaches and destroys evil by virtue of j^ ^ **£ the Allness of God."4 " God must be found AU instead of vation- a part of being, and man the reflection of his power and goodness. This Science rebukes sin with its own nothingness, and thus destroys sin quickly and utterly. It makes disease unreal, and thus heals it."5 " Sympathy with sin, sorrow, and sickness would dethrone God as truth, for truth has no sympathy for error. In Science, the cure of the sick demonstrates this grand verity of Christian Science, that you cannot eradicate disease if you admit that God sends or sees it.'"1 "As there is none beside him, and he is all Good, there can be no evil. Simply uttering this great thought is not enough ! We must Uve it, until God becomes the All and Only of our being.'" " Had he (Jesus) been as conscious of these evfls as he was of God, wherein there is no consciousness of human error, Jesus could not have 1 No and Yes, p. 45. * Rudimentary Divine Science, p. 16. a Italics ours. * No and Yes, p. 39. « Ibid., p. 21. « Ibid., p. 40. ' Ibid., p. 34. 366 Foundations of the Christian Faith. resisted them."1 "In him we live, move, and have our being;" consequently it is impossible for the true man — who is a spiritual and individual being, created in the Eternal Science of Being — to be conscious of aught but good." " If mortals could grasp these two words, all and nothing, this mystery of a God who has no knowledge of sin would disappear, and the eternal, infinite harmony would be fathomed."' According to this scheme, since God is AU and God is Good, there can be no sin. To think that there is sin is to depart from the truth, and so to leave ourselves a prey to error. On the other hand, to rec ognize in deed and in truth that God is AU is to recognize that there is no sin ; but not only so, it is to be so fiUed with a sense of God that there is no room for the thought of sin. When there is no thought of sin there is no thought of sinning ; hence no sense of guilt, for when God fills all the thought there can be no sense of having sinned. Thus sin, which never did have any reaUty, is annihilated — cast out even from human thought. 1 No and Yes, p. 46. « Ibid., p. 26. Christian Science Contrasted with Christianity. 367 CHAPTER VIII. CHRISTIAN SCIENCE CONTRASTED WITH CHRISTIANITY. Our first duty must be to point out the divergence of this teaching from that of Jesus. This may be seen, first of aU, in the very forms which the two systems assume ; that of Jesus being sim- First contrast pie, practical, easUy understood, at least as far as is nee- Christianity essary to salvation, and easily appUed ; that of Christian tianscience" Science being, on the contrary, a subtle metaphysical disquisition mixed with misty mysticism, difficult to understand and impossible of appUcation to real Ufe, as we shaU show later on. But, further, it differs from the teaching of Jesus by being less com prehensive. It msists on a certain consciousness of God— and so far it is Christian ; but this God-consciousness is with reference to his being All. It is quantitative, while the teaching of Christ and the apostles was adapted to lead men to be fiUed with a God-consciousness with reference chiefly to his character. Anyone who will compare the writings of the founder of Christian Science with the New Testament will be convinced of this difference. In Christianity the AUness of God is secondary, in Christian Science his character is secondary. The pantheism of the New Testament is figurative ; iii Christian Science it is taken literally. Again, it differs from Christianity in its doctrines. In Christianity there is no question that God is regarded as a person ; in Christian Science his personality is denied in effect, U not in word. * But it is particularly with reference to sin that the difference be- secono: con- tween Christian Science and the New Testament comes trast out most strikingly. In the former it is regarded as unreal, in the latter it is treated as a terrible reality ; and men are exhorted and en treated to forsake it, to repent of it, to seek forgiveness for it, and strength of grace to overcome it. In the New Testament men are not exhorted to beUeve there can be no sin, but, acknowledging its reality, without any metaphysical subtleties, to be filled with the love of God to the exclusion of sin. In Christian Science it is thought which saves, in Christianity it is love. This leads to the mention of another divergence. In Christian Science we hear nothing of faith, in the 1 See No and Yes, pp. 28 ff., and Rudimentary Divine Science, pp. 7-9. 368 Foundations of the Christian Faith. New Testament much. Christian Science does, however, insist on acceptance of a supposed fact. In other words, in Christian Science saving faith may be said to be inteUectual, and to relate to fact. In Christianity the stress is laid on faith in a person. Another very marked difference is in the source of the saving en ergy. In Christian Science it is whoUy in the human being. We must think of God in a certain way. In the New Testament it is the Deity which worketh in us. It might almost be said that in Chris- Third contrast. tian Science one saves himseU, while in Christianity God saves us. This wfll be further seen when we reflect that in Christian Science there is no place for the Holy Spirit. The Trinity is rejected as an absurdity, and the office and work of the Holy Spirit receive no mention. The divine agency in our salvation receives no empha sis. Jesus suffered that he might show " that the way out of the flesh, out of the delusion of aU human error, must be through the baptism of suffering, leading up to health, harmony, and heaven." * In other words, he suffered to illustrate a truth, not to effect our salvation. His death was simply a part of his example. Christian Science leaves no room for the conscience, except in the most incidental way. Repentance is supplanted by the thought of the AUness of God. Christ and the apostles said, " Repent." Chris- Fourth con- tian Science says, ' ' BeUeve that God is AU. " To the man trast- who has been false to a sacred trust, betrayed the inno cent, committed numberless crimes, there is no thunder from Sinai, but only the assertion that sin is unreal; God only is, and God is Good. The sinner finds peace, not in the fact of conscious pardon from God, but in the thought that — no matter what he has done — God only is. We do not say that coupled with the conditions required in Christian Science this is dangerous, but we do say that it is different from the teaching of the New Testament. Such a system as this could not possibly be appUed generaUy to Ufe. It may do for a certain class of people, but its application in matters inappiicabii- of state would result in anarchy. Civil law must act as as a whole, though there is something real besides God ; so must the parent in training his children ; so must the teacher in the conduct of his school. Besides, if it is true that there is nothing but God, hence no sin, no evil, no disease, then it is equaUy true that hunger and cold are unreal ; the demands of our bodies and of our minds, the most ex alted and the most debased, are aU unreal. We are deceived in think ing we suffer for anything. But by the time we have so completely > No and Yes, p. 43. Christian Science Contrasted with Christianity. 369 subverted aU that our dafly experience teaches us and enforces we shaU land in universal skepticism. We might spend much time and space in pointing out other equaUy damaging features ; but we shaU content ourselves with the brief mention of but one more. It is that its ethics, U it can be said to have any, is negative. It saves from sin by the recognition of the supposed fact that there is no reaUty in sin ; but we its negative need something more for moral progress than salva- et ics- tion from sin. We need a moral ideal of a positive kind. It may be said that God, the Good, is this ideal. But we have seen that, in fact, the qualitative conception of God retreats behind the quantitative in Christian Science. Jesus taught, not the AUness of the Father, but the love of the Father ; and the brotherhood of man foUows, the re lation of the brothers being that of love and helpfulness. But even U there were nothing in the fundamental teachings forbidding the for mation of a brotherhood, U the sect were not held together by a theory rather than by a loving interest in one another, stfll, as a matter of fact, the constructive, the social side of ethics is not so presented — in such unmistakable features— as to make much impression. We refrain from any expression of opinion as to the real occasion or cause of the reported healings of the body. ' If any or many have been reUeved of disease, and restored whole to their families and to the world by Christian Science, we rejoice. But we must protest against the inference which Christian Scientists draw from this fact, namely, that they have a divine truth which is the source of their power. There have been so many mind-healers who never heard of Christian Science, who have nevertheless been successful in large numbers of cases, that we cannot say one is divine while the others are not. The four proposed substitutes for the Christian religion now dis cussed have been found utterly incapable of filling the place they would occupy. Above aU human wisdom stands the divine truth and the divine plan offered by Jesus Christ. This we shaU show in detail in due time. Here our principal aim has been to produce the evidences of the inadequacy of the systems which would dethrone the Son of man who was the Son of God. 1 On this subject see Dr. J. M. Buckley's vivacious and able treatment in his Faith Healing, Christian Science. and Kindred Phenomena, New York, 1892, pp. 239-291. 370 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION II.-OBJECTIONS TO CHRISTIANITY DRAWN FROM RE LIGIOUS CONSIDERATIONS. These are of two kinds, the theological and the practical. They relate, 1. To miracles, and, 2. To the relation of the soul to God. 1. The first of the theological objections to miracles may be stated as foUows: " Pantheism and theism unite in declaring that since God made the world it must have been made according to his wfll.1 Hence First theoiogi- miracles are acts contrary to God's own nature as ex- tion. pressed in the world he made." In answer it should be stated again that miracles are not acts contrary to the laws of nature, but events which, though brought about by the employment of these laws, are the result of an unusual use of them. God is a God of order as weU as of power,3 and the scriptural miracles are not the products of capricious interferences on the part of God with his own world, simply in the exercise of his omnipotence, but of wise devia tions from the ordinary course of his providence in the interest of special ends. 2. This brings us to the second theological objection, which is, that Second theo- God did not make nature so helpless, nor bestow upon it logical ob- jection. such unfruitful laws and regulations as to make his inter vention necessary to the accomplishment of his purposes.' This is a deistic difficulty, though it concedes the Christian doctrine that God's creation was very good. But aside from the scriptural doctrine of the intervention of evfl spirits in human affairs, by which the course of human history must have been seriously modified, we have the unquestionable fact of human sin, which has not only wrought spiritual misery, but also confusion in the physical world. Had all spiritual beings been true to God miracles might not have been necessary;4 but the natural order of the world has been dis turbed by sin, and hence divine interventions are no reflection on God's creation, but rather a proof of his goodness, unless we are ready to assert that he ought not to have created spiritual beings. The first of the practical objections of a religious kind is also directed against miracles. It is that offered by Paul Sabatier in his ¦Rewels des Glaubens, July, 1894, p. 270; Farrar, Critical History of Free Thought, pp. 109, 111, 114. • Beweis des Glaubens, July, 1894, p. 271. » Ibid., p. 270. « Ibid., pp. 272 ff. Objections to Christianity. 371 LUe of Francis of Assisi.1 He says : " The equality of all men before God is a teaching of the reUgious conscience; but mira- First practical cle, this good-natured pastime of God, places him on a ODiectlon- level with the capricious tyrants of earth. ... If God reaUy did interpose in so capricious a manner in the destinies of men they could not do otherwise than strive to become his favorites, in the hope of receiving aU benefits from the favor of the ruler." In answer it must be pointed out that Sabatier is arguing against the ecclesias tical as weU as the scriptural miracles. There is indeed no reason to believe that God supernaturally intervenes to produce stigmata,3 and similar phenomena ; nor that his interventions are at all times equally striking. God is represented in the Bible as working miracles chiefly at particular epochs in the world's history. Furthermore, Sabatier thinks of these miracles as violations of the laws of nature. This is an incorrect view. He also thinks of the miracles as evidences of a capricious weakness in favor of some whfle God allows others to receive only the benefits of the regular operation of the natural laws. The correct doctrine is that they are the expression of a love which is universal in its scope, but which, under aU ordinary circumstances, he charges his people to convey to the world. Without the miracles men would never have been stirred to such acts of mercy as Christian ity exhibits. Yet i£ miracles were constant there would be no room for man's activity. So that in a very important sense the New Testament miracles were wrought for the benefit of aU mankind, and not alone for the individuals on whom they were wrought. The second of the practical objections of a reUgious kind against Christianity is that Christ stands in the way of the soul's communion with God ; that Christianity teaches that we must come second practi- to God by him, whereas nothing and nobody ought to be tion. aUowed to intervene between God and the soul.3 This objection ignores the other Christian doctrine, that he that communes with Jesus communes with God. Jesus said, " He that hath seen me hath seen the Father." He is so perfect a revelation of God that we cannot think of God except as we think of Christ. And, so far from his being a bar to our access to God, there is no class of reUgionists who profess such intimate and friendly relations with God as do Chris- 1 Page 256 f. of the German edition. 'The stigmata are probably produced by the constant dwelling in thought on the wounds of Christ. They need no second party to aid, whether divine or human, as the genuine miracles do. 8 Harnack mentions and refutes this difficulty Das Christenthum und die Geschichte, p. 10. 372 Foundations of the Christian Faith. tians. In practice Christ's mediation has precisely the opposite effect from what objectors affirm. A further religious objection to Christianity,1 having both a theo logical and a practical aspect, is that against sin, with its inheritance and its Satanic source. It is said that if men are born in sin they Objections to ought not to be blamed. So they are not ; but they are hJ? f ?I?f tt^3 blamed for the more or less permanent choice of the evfl (IOC 11 111 C OI sin. which they find in themselves and about them. It is said that God must have made the devil. Not so. He made Adam, but not fallen Adam. It is no more impossible to conceive of a fallen angel than a fallen man. Then it is said that God should have kept the devil away from innocent man. But man was, in point of possi bility, the highest of God's creatures. To wrestle successfuUy with Satan is not impossible to man. Those who succeed against him are the nobler for the conflict. No man need be overcome by him. With out temptation, that is, the trial of their wills, men cannot come to their best in morals. The particular form and source of temptation is indifferent. REVIEW OF RESULTS TO THIS POINT. The purpose of the preceding discussion was to show, first, that all antichristian positions, directly or indirectly offered as substitutes Greatvalue of for Christianity, are untenable ; and, second, that the evidences, objections urged by unbelievers against Christianity are either not weU founded or else do not touch the vital elements of the Christian system. The effect of what has been said in the first part of this work will, it is hoped, be to prepare the mind of the reader for the full weight of the argument to foUow. But this is not the only, and perhaps not the most important, effect of the foregoing consideration of antichristian positions and argu ments. We have weighed the principal objections and theories de vised by men in antagonism to the Christian system, and found them wanting. This leaves Christianity in possession of the field, and cre ates a strong presumption in its favor. If all other forms of faith offered as substitutes are false Christianity must be true, unless reU gion is to be rejected. In fact, none but an atheist could propose that we should crush out the religious element in our nature, and but a minute fraction of unbelievers are atheists. While it is thus practi cally acknowledged on all sides that we must and ought to have some 1 Discussed In Strauss, Der alte und der neue Glaube, pp. 20-24. Review of Results to this Point. 373 reUgion, and all the proposed substitutes are found inadequate, the Christian religion alone is left for the acceptance of the inteUigent por tion of mankind ; on the principle of exclusion it must be accepted. Should it be replied that one cannot at will become an adherent of Christianity it must be said in return that, in view of all the preced ing considerations, men should at least make diligent search for the truth of the Christian system. With the presumption so strongly in its favor all who reject it should remind themselves that if they do not see its truth the fault is probably with themselves, and that U they will use the appropriate means and follow the right method they will discover its truth. Thus in an indirect way we have been pre senting the argument for Christianity from the beginning. The bur den of proof has been thrown upon the rejecters of Christianity, and they have been shown unable to bear it. This is a particularly favor able result, inasmuch as it enables Christianity to maintain its position of supremacy. It occupied the spiritual territory ; there were those who undertook to dislodge it ; they have made their assault and have been repelled. Christianity comes forth from the conflict "clear as the sun, fair as the moon, and terrible" to its assailants "as an army with banners." In truth, Christianity need do nothing more than defend itseU against assault, at least in Christian lands. Stfll, since its existence is not that which it holds dearest, it offers reasons for its right to be. It seeks to diffuse its blessings everywhere ; but for this its existence would have no value. Hence it is not enough to prove itself superior to all others. It must show itself the possessor or purveyor of benefits without which man cannot come to his best ; as truth of the most valu able kind. This makes the positive evidences of Christianity a necessity. Never theless, there is danger of misunderstanding at this point. Christian Evidences does not propose a demonstration in the strict sense. Its proofs are not in all cases compulsory of belief. Rather Necessity and does it offer the reasons why adherents of Christianity the* positive choose to beUeve its tenets in preference to others. These evidences' reasons it seeks to present in such a way as to render the truth of the essentials of Christianity so highly probable to the inquiring mind as to lead to the desired practical acceptance of its benefits and duties. In other words, the evidences of Christianity are not designed merely to exhibit truth, but chiefly and primarfly to secure to as many as possible the blessings of the Gospel and to induce all men to cooperate in the great work for which Christianity exists. This practical phase 26 374 Foundations of the Christian Faith. of the task set for Christian Evidences should never be lost sight of. The matter at issue is not chiefly as to which side has the stronger ar gument, although in this respect Christianity has nothing to fear; the real issue is whether men shaU deprive themselves of the benefits of the Gospel and mankind of their aid in diffusing these benefits among others. Hence our contest is not one of dialectics ; our purpose is not to outwit our opponents and put them to inteUectual shame. In such a result Christianity has no interest. Nevertheless, this does not mean that the argument is to be conducted without energy. Our reasons for beUeving as we do must be presented with vigor and strength in the hope that converts and colaborers may be won thereby. Reasons for the Christian Belief. 375 DIVISION VI. THE DOCTRINES CONCERNING MAN. It is not our purpose to consider aU the doctrines of Christian an thropology ; we shall confine our attention to those which, U main tained, furnish aU that is essential to the satisfaction of our religious natures. In this respect dogmatics is much broader than evidences. The former must furnish a complete system of theological thought ; the latter has done all that is required of it when the fundamental facts have been vindicated. Before proceeding to the statement and defense of the anthropolog ical doctrines of Christianity it may be well to explain why these rather than the doctrine of God are first taken up for consideration. Tne question of order reduces itself to one. of convenience ; Tne order 0{ and since the principal reason, aside from revelation, for procedure. beheving in the personality of God is drawn from the nature of man it is evidently better to deal first with the anthropology and afterward with the theology of the subject. Besides, it is plain that, apart from revelation, we know far more about ourselves than we do about God. It is preferable to begin with that portion of our subject knowledge of which is most accessible. There are but four doctrines concerning man which need defensive statement here : I. That man has a spiritual nature. II. That the spiritual nature in man is personal. III. That the spirit of man is immortal. TV. That the spirit of man is sinful. SECTION I.-THE SPIRITUAL NATURE OF MAN. CHAPTER I. REASONS FOR THE CHRISTIAN BELIEF. The caption given to this section is exceedingly general and vague. Too great definiteness is purposely avoided, first of all, because every specific statement would demand proof, the furnishing of which would detract from the simplicity of the argument, and thus from the force 376 Foundations of the Christian Faith. of the impression. Many psychological questions of profound interest have no value for the essentials of Christianity. In a treatise on psy chology they would aU demand discussion ; here we need not commit ourselves to any specific theory. But there is another reason for so general a form of statement. It is that the New Testa- .1 il t* HQ6£L£6r~ © nessof New ment gives us but a meager delineation of the human psychology. govu i Much that has been stoutly defended as Christian in reference to the soul, as, for example, its substantiaUty, is purely speculative, and in no sense a part of Christianity as given us in the New Testament records of Christ and the apostles. Attention should be called in this connection to the further fact that the New Testament attempts no defense of the reaUty of man's spirit ual nature. Indeed, that reality is not even asserted ; rather is it as sumed. It may be caUed the first great Christian postulate, not be cause Christianity admits or suggests anything hypothetical about the existence of the soul, but because it regards the beUef in the soul's reality to be so secure a part of our mental possession that the truth of the beUef may be left without assertion or proof. The Christianity of to-day is equaUy well warranted in such a course. We hold our selves under no intellectual obligation to furnish argument for a fact which has always been and is now so generally beUeved. The logical obligation, the burden of proof, is with those who deny the almost universal belief. Still, where there is no obUgation arising from the conflict of thought, there is one growing out of our Christian faith. However unreasonable or wicked men may be the Christian is not released from the duty of striving to bring them to the Ught and the right. Much Obligations as the denial of the spiritual nature in man may outrage of our faith, the dictates of reason it becomes our duty to set forth the ground upon which we base our beUef . Before we proceed to state the reasons for our faith two addi tional remarks must be made. First we decUne to consider the presentation of these arguments in the light of a conflict of wit be tween the believer and the unbeliever. We are in possession of the field, and have no fear but that through the good sense of the majority of mankind we shall continue to hold it. Our opponents rage in vain. Blinded by passion or pride they do not understand how impotent they are. But by their rejection of what we have ventured to call the first great Christian postulate they not only deprive themselves of 1 Comp. Julius Kostlin's Der Ghiubc uud seine Bedeutung fur Erkentnnlss, Leben und Kirche, Berlin, 1895, p. 18. Reasons for the Christian Belief. 377 the benefits Christianity could confer upon them, but they hinder the ethical development of mankind, which it is one of the chief purposes of Christianity to advance. We covet their aid in this work. Hence, U the statement of our grounds for beUef will save anyone from joining the ranks of our enemies, or confirm the waver ing faith of any behever, or perchance win some of the enemy to our side and secure their cooperation, it is not only duty but pleasure to make such a statement. The second remark is that our reasons for belief are to be taken as such ; not as demonstrations of fact. We are considering a question of beUef, not knowledge, in the strict sense of that word. But here again we must guard against the reiterated assertions of knowledge on the part of scientists. Those scientists who deny the existence of a reality known to Christianity as a soul deny it on the basis of belief, not of knowledge. Whatever scientists may know they do not know that there is nothing in the universe but matter and physical force. With regard to the existence of the soul the scientist is in no better position to judge than any other educated and thought ful man ; and as a matter of fact it is only a smaU portion of the whole number of scientific men of recent times who have made this denial. We repeat, that the question is not one of demonstration on either side, but of their reasons for belief against our reasons for beUef . What, then, are our reasons for belief 1 1. We beUeve in the existence of a soul in man for the reason, first of aU, that aU attempts to explain the phenomena of the mental Ufe on any other hypothesis have utterly fafled. We cannot even re capitulate here the discussion which exhibited the inability of material ism and monism to meet the demands of a theory of mental phenomena. If that discussion is not fresh in the reader's mind we re- The christian quest him to refer back to the sections on those two sub- alone ex- 1 j I £L 1 II S til 6 jects. It can be truthfuUy said that the failure of the phenomena effort to account for human consciousness on any other tai life. theory than that of the existence of a soul is in this particular an almost complete vindication of our faith. Everything that human ingenuity could devise has been tried, and all in vain. The efforts put forth have been not only varied but strenuous. No skfll in argument was spared of which our opponents were capable, and which was necessary to render their positions plausible. Every weapon of de fense has been employed under stress of the feeling that, as between the Christjan and antichristian theories, the struggle was one of Ufe and death. Yet in spite of all this the positions of the opposition have 378 Foundations of the Christian Faith. been confessed, in some cases by their propounders, to be inadequate, and our discussion showed them not only inadequate but untenable, and even absurd. Haeckel, while pronouncing in favor of the monistic view, admits that the truth lies between it and dualism. ' As between monism and duaUsm in psychology we think our discussion made it evident that the advantage is with the latter." Unless we are to turn away, there fore, from the side which has the better argument we shaU be obliged to adhere to the Christian contention that man has a spiritual nature. Even U we were disposed to reject the Christian view we could not; for when everything else fails we can depend only upon it. Should anyone reply to this that we might reject both the antichristian and the Christian view we point out that this would be to deal the deathblow to thought. Where the alternatives appear exhaustive, as in this case, and as Haeckel admits they are, we are obhged to adopt the one that remains, unless we wish to empty our minds of all their contents. But, aside from this, it is unreasonable to reject the only view that is left simply because we do not like it. Only on the supposition that the Christian view failed as ignominiously as all other views could one who is convinced of the untenableness and inadequacy of ma teriaUsm and monism be justified even in considering its abandon ment together with the others. How thoroughly the Christian view accomplishes what the others fail to do for us we shaU see in due time. Here we wish to add a second reason for beUeving the Christian view, which is at the same time a reason why one who is not convinced of its sufficiency should, nevertheless, not renounce it. 2. This second reason for believing in the existence of the soul is the practical universality of that belief. Even if one who is convinced of the failure of the materialistic and monistic hypotheses were com pelled by his investigations to hold that the Christian view also fails in part or wholly, still the universality of the beUef in the reality of spirit in man should hold such a one to the doctrine of Christianity. To this it may be replied that this reason for belief is of force only on the supposition that those who believe do so on good grounds, which Th e uni ver- remains to be proved. We cannot agree to this, however ; beilei In the ^or i* assumes that the few who are not convinced are as soul" likely to be right as the many who are. Majorities are by no means always in the right, but the presumption is always in their favor ; and when anyone confesses that the view held by the minority 1 The Evolution of Man, New York, 1879, vol. 11, p. 453 f. ' Division 1, section ill, chap. 3. Reasons for the Christian Belief. 379 is untenable the opinion of the majority ought to have great weight with him. In other words, where there appear to be equal difficulties pertaining to two opposing views, the fact that a majority of mankind in aU ages have held to one of these views should rouse in the objector the suspicion that the difficulties in the way of the majority opinion are not as great as he has supposed. Particularly is this the case when, as with Christianity, the majority is composed of those who are at least equal to the minority in point of inteUigence and opportunity for attaining knowledge. This is but an other form of the argument employed by Mr. Herbert Spencer to prove ' ' that the diverse forms of reUgious beUef which have existed and which stfll exist have all a basis in some ultimate fact."1 This presumption, according to him, arises in part "from the omnipresence of the be hef s."9 " The universahty of religious ideas, their independent evo lution among primitive races, and their great vitality, unite in show ing that their source must be deep-seated instead of superficial."" Now, if we are to trust Mr. E. B. Tylor's findings, in Primitive Cul ture,4 the belief in the existence of the soul is universal, independent in origin in each race, and possessed of great vitality." It so happens that, according to Tylor, whatever variations of opinion or beUef concerning the same may have existed, all peoples have united in the belief that the soul is a real something ; as real an element in the composition of the human being as a body. If "to suppose that these multUorm (and often contradictory) conceptions (of religion) should be, one and aU, absolutely groundless discredits too profoundly that average human intelUgence from which aU our individual intelligences are inherited,"8 how much more does the supposition that the harmo nious judgment of the race with reference to the reaUty of the soul is absolutely groundless discredit that average human inteUigence in which Spencer puts so much faith. ' First Principles, p. 13. 5 Ibid. a Ibid., p. 14. ' London, 1873, vol. i, chap. 11. B Primitive Culture, vol. I, pp. 428, 429. "Spencer, First Principles, p. 13. For clearness we have added the words in the parentheses. 380 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER H. VALIDITY OF THE CHRISTIAN IDEA OF THE SOUL. To all this it may be objected that it is just to Tylor's own theory of animism that we can trace the groundless character of beUef in the existence of the soul.1 According to Tylor men came to believe in the existence of the soul as an element of the human nature distin guishable from the body by trying to answer two questions : first, " What is it that makes the difference between a Uving body and a dead one— what causes waking, sleep, trance, disease, death ? " and, second, " What are those human shapes which appear in dreams and visions?"" Now U, in the course of time, " ancient savage philoso phers " came to regard the human shapes they saw in dreams and visions as realities, and then as the souls of the human beings to whose bodfly shape they corresponded, have we not a proof that the beUef in the reaUty of the soul, however general, is based entirely upon a deception ? We answer, No. In the first place, it is altogether uncertain whether Tof°r'animism Tyl°r nas given us the true and entire explanation of the examined, belief in the existence of the soul, even among primitive peoples. He supposes that these " ancient savage phflosophers" at tributed to every man a phantom, the image or second seU of the individual, able to appear at a distance from the body, and a Ufe which enabled the body to feel, think, and act.' He admits, by his use of the word "probably," the conjectural character of the func tion of the life as distinguished from the phantom. Why say that they held the life to be that which enabled the body to feel, think, and act ? Is it not just as Ukely that they regarded the Ufe as that which itself felt, thought, and acted ? that the body was the instru ment of the lUe, or, as we now say, the soul ? In fact, several early languages use the same word for both life and soul. "Ancient savage philosophers" who had the discrimination which Tylor attributes to them must have observed what we to-day caU mental phenomena. They must have known that they thought and felt, and that they did not think and feel with their bodies, though they did act with them. 1 So, for example, Clifford. Lectures and Essays, p. 247 f. * Primitive Culture, vol. I, p. 428. » Ibid. Validity of the Christian Idea of the Soul. 381 In other words, they must have distinguished between mental and physical phenomena, though they may have denned the difference very unclearly. If they did notice these differences that fact may have been a part of their reason for believing in the existence of a soul distinguishable from the body — logicaUy and, as they believed, phenomenally distinguishable. We judge it impossible to decide whether a dim logical discrimi nation supported the distinction based upon the idea of a phantom, or whether the latter idea supported the former. Quite evident, how ever, does it seem that, whichever was the first in order of time and strength, both combined very early in sustaining the belief that a dis tinction between soul and body must be made, and that the former is as real as the latter. As to the existence of the soul after death it is probable that the belief in it was based upon the idea of the phan tom. If there be any foundation for our supposition that Capacities of primitive men were as able and likely to distinguish be- men. tween physical and mental phenomena, and to postulate a somewhat as the cause for each of them, as they were to trouble themselves about the causes of waking, sleep, trance, disease, death, and the na ture of the human shapes which appear in dreams land visions, then it is plain that the origin of the belief in the reality of the soul can furnish no argument counter to that which we have drawn from the universaUty of the belief ; for in the case now supposed the beUef had everywhere a fairly respectable origin. But even U the origin of the belief be as Tylor supposes, without the additional cause which we have suggested, stiU that only proves what was the origin of the be lief. No one will assert that the mass of inteUigent believers in the reality of a soul distinguishable from the body hold that belief on the ground of anything seen in dreams or visions. However the belief originated we, to-day, do not believe for the reason adduced by Tylor. Hence, again, the argument drawn from the universaUty of the beUef cannot be met by pointing out the deceptive origin of it. We beUeve in the reaUty of t\e soul, then, because no other theory is tenable, and because it is exceedingly improbable that practically the whole human race, without regard to the degree of inteUi gence, has been deceived, while a Uttle handful of men who can give no clear account of their opposing view, and of whom the more honest confess its inadequacy, are right. But there is a third reason for the belief we hold. It is the fact that the supposition of a soul to do our thinking, feeling, and wflling accounts for the facts of the mental Ufe. There can be no thought without a thinker. Brain can- 382 Foundations of the Christian Faith. not think, nor can matter jn any form think. Hence there must be something immaterial in us or about us which thinks. We have not Thought must spoken of that something as a substance, and U anyone uct of some- insists on using that term in connectiqn with the idea of terial a soul he must distinctively disavow at least the concep tion of material substance. Wundt is entirely correct in claiming that the idea of substance as ordinarily understood in the natural sciences, where the term had its origin, is wholly inappUcable to the idea of soul.1 Professor Bowne, in his chapter on The Subject of the Mental Life,3 well says: "Thoughts and feelings demand a sub ject and have no meaning apart from it. ... If it were clearly seen that thoughts and feelings imply something that thinks and feels, materialism would seldom begin." Again he says :' "How there can be states which are states of nothing, and how consciousness, which is itself a mental state, can also have states, are questions passed over in profound silence" by those who deny a unitary subject of the mental lUe. Says Professor George P. Fisher : * "To talk of thought without a thinker, or beUef without a believer, is to utter words void of meaning." Paulsen admits the contention that wherever there is a feeling there must be some one who feels,1 but he claims that in so arguing we misunderstand our own requirements in the case. According to him we do not need a unitary subject, but simply a recoUection of the fact that a thought or a feeling is never a soUtary mental phenomenon, but is always a part of the entire soul-Ufe. Each thought or feeling is a necessary member of a connected whole. On this theory it is the whole soul-life which feels or thinks or wills. This can mean but one thing ; that is, that that which we call the seU, which we regard as thinking, feeUng, and willing, is a sum total of thoughts, feelings, and volitions, and not a unit. If this be true, then our consciousness of unity is a delusion. There is no unitary seU as the subject of aU these states ; the states are the seU, and this aggregation feels itseU a unit, though it is deceived in this feeling. Now, what reason is there for holding that we are deceived by our consciousness of unity ? When it seems to me I am the same one who ° o"pauisen,n thou£nt> felt' willed, or acted in a certain way yesterday, views. why should I not accept this datum of consciousness? why should I declare that I am not one, but a succession or an aggre- 1 System der Philosophie, pp. 289 ff. 2 Introduction to Psychological Theory, New York, 1886, p. 25. « Ibid., p. 13. « The Grounds of Theistic and Christian Belief, New York, 1891, p. 3. 0 Einleltung in die Philosophie, p. 135. Validity of the Christian Idea of the Soul. 383 gate of mental states ? The only answer is, We must override the testimony of consciousness and conscience in the interests of the ma terialistic or of the monistic philosophy. But those philosophies ought to exist only as explanations of the facts, whereas they are obliged to deny the facts in order to exist. For U we must repudiate the testimony of consciousness, which is so perfectly universal and unUorm, it wiU be impossible for us to know what is fact, i Dualism is probably very hateful to materialists and monists, but, for all that, it alone accounts for both physical and mental phenomena by postu lating a somewhat behind and corresponding to each class of phe nomena. Our theory does not require us to assert thought without a thinker, or else to make God the only reality, as Paulsen appears to do. ' The Christian theory leaves dualism to be explained ; but that is a bugbear raised by materialism and creates no difficulty, for the simple reason that we know nothing whatever of the real nature either of matter or spirit. For aught we know they may differ greatly and yet cooperate perfectly. We decline to contradict the plainest requirements of common sense and consciousness in order to avoid a difficulty for whose existence we have absolutely no proof. All objectors to the Christian doctrine make much of the fact that we cannot define the nature of the soul. But it is no more necessary to define the nature of spirit in order to beUeve that it exists than it is to define the nature of matter in order to believe that it exists. Yet no scientist and no philosopher will attempt to define the Nature of tne nature of matter apart from its activities. We often ^definable read eddying accounts of what matter is not, or of What t^an matter. the phenomena of matter are ; but all admit that every attempt to define matter is a total failure. StiU, we all continue to believe that there is such a thing as matter, because there are material phe nomena. Precisely in the same way it is entirely allowable to be lieve that there is such a thing as spirit because there are mental phenomena, though in the same breath we confess that we do not know what spirit is. It is no more correct to say that spirit is the mere negation of matter than it is to say that matter is the mere negation of spirit. Why should matter be made the standard by which to test reality ? If such a preeminence is to be granted to either spirit or matter it must be accorded to the former. Impossibility of definition proves only our incapacity for comprehending all reaUty, hot the non existence of reality. • Einleitung In die Philosophie, p. 136. 384 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER IH. the personality of man and his superiority to the brutes. Perhaps the most formidable argument of our opponents is that which is professedly drawn from the doctrine of the evolutionary descent of man. Christianity holds that the soul of man, with its . . seU-consciousness, its consciousness of unity, identity, The Christian position. and selfhood, its consciousness of freedom and personal responsibility, is, so far, different in kind from aU other created exist ence known to this earth. Atheists and agnostic evolutionists under take to prove, on the contrary, that man is simply a higher grade of animal. Says Haeckel:1 "Comparative Psychology . . . teaches that this frontier post between man and beast is altogether unten able." Now, how does he proceed to show this? First of aU by the attempt to prove that, physicaUy, man is developed from the lower animals. To this we need give no attention here, since it is not the point in question, although it is proper to add that the difficulties in the way of proving man's physical origin from the beasts by any process known to atheistic or agnostic scientists are constantly demon strating themselves to be increasingly formidable." What we are in terested in is his alleged evidence in favor of the evolution of mind. He says : a " All naturalists, without exception, agree that the central nervous system is the organ of the mental Ufe of animals. ... If the central nervous system is whoUy or partiaUy destroyed, the 'mind/ or the psychical activity of the animal, is wholly or partially annihi lated at the same time. We must, therefore, next inquire what is the character of the mental organ in man . . . Man's mental organ is, in its whole structure and origin, the same as that of all other verte brates. . . . Physiological observation and experiment teaches, more over, that the relation of the ' mind ' to its organ, the brain and spinal marrow, is exactly the same in man as in all other mammals. The former can in no case act without the latter ; the one is connected with the other, as is muscular movement with muscle. Therefore, the mind can develop only in connection with its organ." 1 The Evolution of Man, vol. 11, p. 453. ' Comp. AndresenN Die Entwlckelung der Menschen, p. 35. s The Evolution of Man, p. 450. Personality of Man and his Superiority to Brutes. 385 It will be better to pause here and examine his argument up to this point. The reader wfll recall the discussion of this subject under a somewhat different aspect in the earlier pages of this Haeckel's de- book.1 There it was proved that U the central nervous tinction b'e- system is partially destroyed it does not partiaUy an- ^d "beast nihilate the mind at the same time. Cases were cited in excised. which, with considerable portions of the brain gone, mental power was in no degree decreased, while it is the fact that under such circum stances the brain wearied the sooner. This showed that the brain is the organ of the mind in a far different sense from what Haeckel supposes. Mind and brain are indeed connected in some mysterious way, but the evidence goes to show that a fully developed mind needs the whole of the brain which developed along with it ; not that, if the brain is gone, the mind is gone also. The fact is that Haeckel's argument is based on the supposition of the truth of the materialistic- monistic phflosophy, which regards mind as a function of brain the same as muscular movement is a function of muscle. For a refuta tion of this wholly absurd notion we refer the reader to our treatment of Haeckel's monism in the earUer parts of this book. If, in the nature of the case, mental action cannot be regarded as a function of brain, then, though the mind apparently develops in proportion as the brain develops, this furnishes no proof that there is no mind without brain. Hence his assertion that the "frontier post between man and beast is untenable" fails of adequate support. The testi mony of consciousness that I am not aU matter still holds. His assertion can be proved, if at aU, not by the apparent fact that mind and brain develop simultaneously in man, and in lower animals as weU, but only by a comparison of the mental phenomena as found in man and beast. This brings us to the method employed by Romanes, in the day of his enthraUment to atheism, to prove that there is no distinction in kind between mind in man and mind in beast. In a very elaborate treatise, * which, however, is far more learned and acute than con clusive, he attempts to estabhsh the proposition just mentioned. We cannot undertake here to summarize the argument, which he carries through several hundred pages, nor even his seventeenth chapter, entitled General Summary and Concluding Remarks. We can only point out his methods of procedure and examine briefly the force of his reasoning. It must be said that any one who carefully reads Romanes's work 1 Pages 119 f. * Mental Evolution in Man, New York, 1889. 386 Foundations of the Christian Faith. wiU discover that it is reaUy difficult to get at the exact purpose of the author. The title of the book is, Mental Evolution in Man — Origin of Human Faculty. The second part of the title, compared with the first part, seems to indicate that the whole should be something like Romanes on this: "The Human Mind the Result of the Process of alid beast"1 Evolution." This is probably what the title signifies, U we may judge from certain sentences on page 390 of the work referred to. Now, Christianity gives us no theory as to how the human mind came into existence, and it would not be at all unchris tian to suppose that it came into existence by the process of evolution. It is simply a question of fact, concerning the outcome of which Christians as such need not be troubled, however much they are inter ested. But some sentences in his Preface would seem to indicate that the title of the book, even when its two diverse parts are interpreted into one, does not reveal the author's real purpose. He says •: " Touch ing the present installment,' it is only needful to remark that from a controversial point of view it is, perhaps, the most important. If once the genesis of conceptual thought from nonconceptual ante cedents be rendered apparent, the great majority of competent read ers at the present time would be prepared to allow that the psycho logical barrier between the brute and the man is shown to have been overcome." That to overcome this psychological barrier between brute and man is his real purpose in writing, or at least the real end to which he thought his investigations led him, a careful study of the entire work undoubtedly reveals. And here is where Christianity is obliged to utter a protest. If both the physical and the psychological barriers between man and beast are broken down then man is only one kind of brute, and Christianity is wrong in regarding him as the special object of God's care. Only on the theory that man is different in kind, at least psychologicaUy, from the brute, can Christianity maintain itseU. Man has a mind in a sense in which a brute has none or Christianity is false ; for it assumes a godlike nature of the human mind, in spite of sin, in all its utterances concerning the relation of God to man. We begin by caUing attention to Romanes's statement that by " dU- ference of kind " between brute and human mind he means " difference of origin," claiming that the only real distinction between difference of kind and difference of degree consists in difference of origin.8 Much 1 Page vi. a The book is one of three on the same general subjeot of psychical evolution. •Mental Evolution In Man, p. 3, n. Personality of Man and his Superiority to Brutes. 387 of the error and vagueness of this statement must here be ignored. It is, however, necessary to point out first that sameness of origin may be perfectly compatible with difference of kind. Sameness of iim. • • j if n -j. -j. origin com- The origm of a thing " may mean its source, or it may paflbie with ., ., .. , , . . .. difference in mean its cause, or it may mean the process by which it kind. came into being, or it may mean aU three. The theistic theory of evolution could aUow that as God brought about the gradual advance ment of being physically, so he provided for the addition of mind to physical organization and, finaUy, of a higher kind of mind to a lower kind. However low the grade of consciousness it is different in kind from any material phenomena, even though both were admitted to have had the same origin. In the sense of "source" theists firmly believe the " origin" of both to be the same ; they are not particular as to the process. Atheistic evolution cannot account for the changes and advance ments in physical phenomena, much less for the phenomena of con sciousness even in its lowest form. AU it can do is to trace out the order of those changes and advancements. As soon as it begins to in quire into the why of things it is confronted with insurmountable dif ficulties. Hence consistent atheists, agnostics, and positivists content themselves generaUy with a description of the evolutionary process. As soon as they begin to assume any power at work they are on the road to theism, whither straight thinking is sure to lead them. But the description of a process is not a complete account of the origin of a thing. It is perfectly conceivable that the same process (evolution) might be applied to whoUy diverse materials. So that sameness of origin, whether as to the source or process, or both, is not incompati ble with difference of kind. It is characteristic of the mental confu sion into which atheism leads men that so fundamental a fact should have been overlooked by a really great thinker. And in fact Romanes himseU continually speaks of differences of kind, although at the out set he has notified us that he has in mind differences of origin. This failure to observe that identity of origin (source, cause, process) is not one with identity of kind vitiates Romanes's reasoning, and in no particular more completely than with reference to his H ( s e r ror main contention, that the proof of the genesis of concep- h!sereason- tual thought from nonconceptual antecedents breaks down mg' the psychological barrier between brute and man. Nor need we foUow his elaborate terminology and discrimination of mental states in order to show how his dogmatic assumption that sameness in origin and sameness in kind are identical leads him to confuse as identical in 388 Foundations of the Christian Faith. kind things which his own reasoning and terminology ought to have revealed as diverse. The very words, "evolution of this conceptual from preconceptual self -consciousness," ' are a confession of a differ ence in kind. That which is preconceptual is not yet conceptual, or, in other words, it is nonconceptual. To affirm that self -consciousness is both conceptual and nonconceptual at the same time is to utter sheer nonsense. No one makes the distinction between the two more sharply than Romanes himself. Yet, because he had assumed that sameness in origin was identical with sameness in kind, he was obUged, after having proved to his own satisfaction that the laws of evolution apply to self -consciousness, to assert, or at least imply, that the non- conceptual and the conceptual are the same in kind. That which is conceptual differs from that which is nonconceptual as contradictories differ. If there is no difference in kind between that which is and that which is not possessed of a quality, then there are no differences in kind. The difference may not always be great, but it isa difference in kind, however small or large. The only distinctions in kind of which we know anything are those which are based on observed dif ferences in qualities. If any two things have the same quahties in different degrees they do not differ in kind unless the difference in de gree is infinite. Things which have all quaUties but one in common differ in kind by the greatness or insignificance of that one quality.' 1 Mental Evolution in Man, p. 409. 8 C. L. Morgan, after a careful study of the whole subject, concludes that animals do not reason, and that the anecdotal character of all accounts which seem to Indicate the contrary must restrain us from accepting any conclusions based upon them as to the rea soning powers of animals. See his Introduction to Comparative Psychology, London and New York, 1894, chap, xvi ; also p. 358. Man's Personal Superiority to the Brute — Romanes. 389 CHAPTER IV. MAN'S PERSONAL SUPERIORITY TO THE BRUTE — ROMANES. Following out this same principle we are able to see that man is vastly different as to kind in his psychology from the brute. Ro manes confesses that seU-consciousness exists only in man.1 It de pends on what estimate we fix for self -consciousness e s t i m a t e whether we shall think that man differs in kind from self- con" the brute which has it not. No matter though the little seiousness- child has no self -consciousness, as Haeckel and Romanes are so fond of emphasizing. This proves only that mind evolves in its manifes tation, not that the mind is not there. If the mind of a child and the mind of a brute are the same in kind why is it that the one comes to self -consciousness and the other does not ? If it be said that the dif ference is in the brain only, then the materiaUstic position is thus assumed. Even if we suppose that up to a certain point infant psy chology is but on the same level with the powers of the brute, stfll it is evident that there was at least in the mind of the child what is not found in the "mind" of the brute, namely, the capacity for attain ing to self -consciousness. Nor is this fact invaUdated even U we grant that the faculty of language aided the child in reaching self- consciousness, for it is here not a question of how or by what means the power is developed. Man has seU-consciousness and the brute has it not. The only way by which we can account, on evolutionary principles, for the fact that to man was given the faculty of language is on the supposition that there was latent in the human mind a power or capability not existing in the mind of the brute. Romanes seems to see that if man alone has self -consciousness man must differ in kind from the brute ; for after stating that it exists only in man he tries to show, (1) that in some sense it exists in animals, and also (2) that after all there is no great difference between the be ing which possesses seU-consciousness and the being which possesses it not. Let us examine these two points. As to the first, Romanes's whole discussion of seU-consciousness is confused and contradictory. For example, he says:' "It wfll be granted that self-consciousness consists in paying the same kind of 1 Mental Evolution in Man, p. 406. s Ibid. 27 390 Foundations of the Christian Faith. attention to internal, or psychical processes as is habitually paid to external or physical processes." But this is not granted. SeU-con- Romanes's in- sciousness is not a mere function of introspection. Ro- nition of self- manes grants that the power of introspection does not be- ness. ' long to the brute. J So that the mental phenomena in man would differ in kind from that in the brute by so much even if Romanes's description of seU-consciousness were correct, which it is not. For self -consciousness is a consciousness of seU. And here Romanes seems to apprehend the truth, and to try to make it appear that at a certain " stage of mental evolution the individual, whether animal or infant, so far reaUzes its own individuaUty as to be informed by the logic of recepts that it is one of a kind." Here he evidently means to suggest that U the aiiimal has no consciousness of personaUty it at least has the consciousness of individuaUty in some sense. But there is a vast difference between the consciousness of individuaUty, even U the brute has it, and the consciousness of personaUty.' So that, ac cording to his own reasoning and confessions, there is no true sense in which the brute has seU-consciousness — neither in the sense of the power of introspective thought nor in that of personaUty. The reader of Romanes should note this subtle attempt to rob seU-consciousness of personality, on the one hand, and to give the brute a sense of indi viduaUty approaching personality on the other. This same vicious purpose wfll be apparent when we treat, as we immediately proceed to do, of the second point mentioned above. In order to reduce the differences which distinguish beings possess ing from those not possessing seU-consciousness he uses his distinction of mental faculties as perceptual, receptual, and conceptual. He says:' Perceptual,™- " Pre-conceptual (that is, receptual) seU-consciousness is conceptual exhibited by all children after they have begun to talk, but before they begin to speak of themselves in the first person, or otherwise to give any evidence of realizing their own ex istence as such." This same thing in a brute, or an infant, he calls a "rudimentary or nascent form of seU-consciousness." In estimating this it is necessary to define exactly the issue. If Romanes is trying to show by the language quoted that seU-consciousness dawns grad ually we find no fault. If he is trying to prove that because seU-con- sciousness is preceded by something which is not, but which ap proaches, self -consciousness, we again make no objection. But, while 1 Mental Evolution In Man. p. 406. a See The Evidence of Christian Experience, being the Ely Lectures for 1890, by Lewis French Stearns, New York, 1890, p. 78. s Mental Evolution In Man, p. 407. Man's Personal Superiority to the Brute — Romanes. 391 he is not clear, he seems to be attempting to show that this something which precedes self -consciousness is a kind of seU-consciousness ; for he says : ' "There is a form of self-consciousness which may be termed receptual as well as that which may be termed conceptual." Now, if we take his own description of self -consciousness quoted above, this receptual form of that faculty is not a form of the real thing ; for it does not involve introspection. That it does not involve the idea of personality Romanes would at once admit. Hence he is calling that seU-consciousness which is not, even judged according to his own standard, what he calls it. This is a specimen of his confused and confusing manner of thought and utterance throughout his entire book, and at the same time a refutation of his attempt to make it ap pear that there is not much difference between beings which have and beings which have not self -consciousness. But in order to minify this distinction, which, after all shuffling, he stiU admits exists between man and brute, he offers some subsidiary considerations. We take them up as given in his Summary," treating his second consideration first. It is that ' ' the vast majority of our verbal propositions are made for the practical purposes of communi cation, or without the mind pausing to contemplate the His subsidiary ..,,.,.„,„' . „ t. , . considera- propositions in the hght of seU-consciousness." But in tions. reality this is nothing to the point. We may not always be self-con scious. The point, however, is that we are self-conscious at times; the brute never. With this simple, brief, and obvious criticism we pass to the first of his subsidiary considerations. We quote, s ' 'Although the advance to true self -consciousness from lower grades of mental de velopment is no doubt a very great and important matter, still it is not so great and important, in comparison with what this develop ment is afterward destined to become, as to make us feel that it con stitutes any distinction sui generis— or even, perhaps, the principal distinction — between the man and the brute. For even when seU- consciousness does arrive, and has become fairly weU developed, the powers of the human mind are still in an almost infantile condition. In other words, the first genesis of true self-consciousness marks a comparatively low level in the evolution of the human mind. . . . But, U so, does it not follow that, great as the importance of self -conscious ness afterward proves to be in the development of distinctively human ideation, in itself, or in its past beginning, it does not betoken any very perceptible advance upon those powers of preconceptual ideation which it immediately follows ? " 1 Mental Evolution in Man, p. 410. ' Ibid., p. 412. • Ibid. 392 Foundations of the Christian Faith. To say that such reasoning is amazing is, under the circumstances, a mild form of utterance. The fact that preconceptual ideation pre pared the way, even though causally, for conceptual ideation does not prove that the difference between the two forms of ideation is slight. By Romanes's own use of language it is admitted that the difference is the difference between nonself -consciousness and self -consciousness. The fact that self -consciousness becomes more clear and pronounced as life continues, and that the accompanying mental powers may grow with the growth of self-consciousness has no power to minify seU- consciousness. The beginnings of things are always the most impor tant parts of their history, for upon them aU else depends. The con ception of a child is the most important fact in its Ufe, and the fact that the human embryo at conception has reached but a small degree of its possible development in nowise minifies its significance. It is so significant that it marks the infinite difference between that which is not and that which is. But he carries the argument further, and by so doing brings out the absurdity of his position into stfll more striking reUef. "There is thus shown to be even less reason for regarding the first advent of conceptual seU-consciousness as marking a psychological difference of kind than there would be so to regard the advent of those higher powers of conceptual ideation which subsequently — though as gradu ally — supervene between early childhood and youth. Yet no one has hitherto ventured to suggest that the inteUigence of a child and the inteUigence of a youth display a difference of kind." One who can employ such an argument is indeed hard pressed. According to his own words both the child and the youth have self- He makes the consciousness, the difference being one of degree, and ac- wwien deny™ cording to his own words the child, however young, has ng lt- the capacity for obtaining conceptual seU-consciousness which the brute has not. If his reasoning were followed elsewhere we might have results Uke the following : Two seeds are planted on the same day. One has the power to develop into an apple tree, the other into a peach tree. Yet there is not as much difference in kind between the apple seed and the peach seed as there is between the embryonic peach tree in its seed and the full-grown peach tree. Or, one germ of life has the power to develop into an oyster and another into a horse. Yet there would not be, on Romanes's principles, as much difference in kind between the embryonic oyster and the em bryonic horse as between the latter and the fully-developed racer. If all this were true, difference in kind would be marked by degrees of Man's Personal Superiority to the Brute — Romanes. 393 development, not by tendencies of development. Men who have no case to make out will repudiate such absurdities.1 These considerations, with those in the earlier part of this work, will suffice to show that no argument is sufficient to overthrow man's recognition of his own personaUty, including all that is necessary to constitute one a personal being. The superiority of man in kind as compared with the brute is established by irrefragable argument. Thus far the tenets of Christianity have shown themselves capable of triumphant vindication in the presence of thought, though not in the judgment of prejudice.' i Wundt affirms that there are no existing species or individuals of animals which will ever reach the point of intelligence proper, though he thinks man has reached that point by passing through the stage of association which the child has in common with the brute. Lectures on Human and Animal Psychology, translated from the second German edition by Creighton and Titchener, London and New York, 1894, pp. 365 ff . If he is correct the germinal difference between man and brute is established. 8 We recommend for further perusal, Andresen's Die Entwickelung der Menschen, pp. 10-90. See, also, E. L. Thorndike's Animal Intelligence, Supplement to the Pyschologist, June 8, 1898. 394 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION II.-THE IMMORTALITY OF THE SOUL." CHAPTER I. MAN'S CAPACITY FOR IMMORTALITY. This is a doctrine held by aU Christians, though there are some who affirm the doctrine in a less general form than that in which we have stated it. In other words, some Christians hold what is known as the doctrine of conditional immortality, which may mean several things. In the first place it may mean that only those souls are immortal which have received the principle of eternal Ufe through Jesus Christ. This would leave room for the annihilation of the finaUy impenitent. In this form the doctrine of conditional immortality belongs to the domain of polemics rather than of evidences. But U by conditional im mortality is meant that immortaUty is conditioned upon the continu ous maintenance of the soul in lUe by the divine action aU wfll agree to the doctrine. All created things, human souls included, would van ish into the nothingness from which God caUed them were he to with- The question draw his support.' Whether God will continue exist- of condition al immortal- ence to a soul forever is to be ascertained in this Ufe onlv ity left to ,...„, polemics. by revelation, U at aU. Unfortunately theologians are not in perfect unity as to the question of what revelation says on the sub ject of immortality for all, though the vast majority hold to universal immortality ; that is that, having once brought a soul into being, God wfll not withdraw his support and let it disappear into nothing ness. For this view there are strong reasons. First, the analogy of mat ter, which is held to be indestructible. "We cannot answer the in quiry ' Why preserve matter and motion, and not consciousness and inteUigence ? '—and the idea is nearly irresistible that they may be pre served in states of existence separable from matter and motion." ' However science may view it, from the Christian standpoint the inde structibility of matter depends solely upon the will of God. There is 1 W. T. Harris has written a valuable " survey of the grounds upon which Philosophy bases Its doctrine of human Immortality," entitled The Immortality of the Individual, New York and London, 1885. 2 Andresen, Die Entwlckelung der Menschen. p. 19. 11 Quoted approvingly from an unnamed correspondent of Sir Edwin Arnold In the lat ter's Death— and Afterwards, seventh edition, Loudon, 1889, p. 54 f. Man's Capacity for Immortality. 395 nothing in the New Testament revelation to suggest that matter wfll ever be destroyed. Though it is said that the earth and the heavens shaU pass away, matter itseU is apparently assumed to be indestruc tible. It is not likely that God wfll withdraw his support from spirit while he continues to give his support to matter. Second, there is a dignity attaching even to a sinful soul which renders it probable that God wiU never rob it of existence. ' We recognize that there are diffi culties which can be solved only by the doctrine of annihilation of rebellious souls. But it is doubtful whether they are not offset by the difficulties connected with the doctrine of annihilation. So that, in our opinion, though we do not pretend that the above is an adequate discussion of the case, the weight of argument is in favor of the idea that all souls wiU be maintained in everlasting lUe. We wish to take up the question from a somewhat different point of view and to give some reasons why Christians believe that the soul is immortal. We group the discussion about two heads : (1) the capacity of the soul for immortality, and (2) the probability of the soul's immortaUty. There is no reason to doubt the soul's capacity for immortality un less it be a reason drawn from the soul's intimate connection with the brain. Of course, if the soul is a sum of brain functions in the sense that brain produces thought, it must cease to exist when the brain dissolves." But, as we have repeatedly shown, this and The capability every other materiaUstic and monistic theory of the °or ilnmor- nature of the soul is untenable. The only view which tallty- satisfactorily explains mental phenomena is that which postulates a somewhat, called the soul, capable of being the subject of the mental phenomena in question. The only objection of any force against this view is that it compels us to accept dualism. But duaUsm is a per fectly harmless theory unless men read into it difficulties which they do not know to exist. The fact of the soul's existence being demonstrated as practicaUy certain it is exceedingly unlikely that it dissolves with the body. No one, indeed, ever saw a soul enter or leave the body of a human or any other being. But by hypothesis the soul is invisible ; hence the fact just mentioned proves nothing. Nor is anything contrary to the soul's capacity for outliving the body proved by the fact that with the death of the body aU the dead man's manUestations of mental activ ity cease ; for aU we can say is that they cease to be manifested to 1 Andresen, Die Entwickelung der Menschen, p. 83. ' Comp. James's Human Immortality, pp. 7-30. 396 Foundations of the Christian Faith. us.1 For aught we know the soul's consciousness of itself, which went on unknown to others except as the soul saw fit to reveal it through the body, is as active as ever. This brings us face to face with the old question whether the mind or spirit is in any sense independent of the brain and body. We think there are the best of reasons, whether Mr. MiU wfll grant that they are scientific or not, for holding that the soul- Ufe is in a large measure independent. We adduce some simple and weU-known facts. The same nerves of sensation leading to the same brain produce diverse effects according to the diverse inteUectual content of the matter spoken or seen. If the message brought by a friend be favorable the words by which it is conveyed affect the same nerves as are affected by the words which convey an unfavorable message, but the effect on our f eelings is en tirely different in the two cases. As far as the brain was concerned the operation was the same up to the point at which the content was made clear to consciousness. When the intellectual process was rela tively complete the appropriate feeling was produced. Accompanying these feelings there may have been brain modifications; but these The soui-Hfe could not have produced the feelings. For example, independentof the brain, there was also a modification of the flow of the blood ac companying these feehngs; but the feelings affected the flow of blood, not the flow of blood the feeUngs. Or, the first page of a letter gives us an account of the safe arrival of a friend across the sea, and we are glad ; the second page tells us of his death by disease soon after his arrival, and we are doubly sad because of the contrast with the feelings excited by the first page. Both pages affected the same nerves and the same brain, but produced opposite feelings. The materialistic theory would not only pretend that the brain is capable of distinguishing between two pieces of news alternately, but that disappointment is produced by the reaction of the brain in the second against its condition in the former case. If the reaction ap peared as physical pain we should be led to think that mental phe nomena were caused by brain reactions ; but such not being the case we must conclude that the mind is capable of carrying on activities independent of the brain, at least as far as any causal connection is concerned. This leads up to another fact indicating the same thing. We are clearly capable of distinguishing between bodily and mental 1 J. S. Mill says: " There Is, therefore, in science, no evidence against the immortality of the soul, but that negative evidence which consists in the absence of evidence in its favor. And even the negative is not as strong as negative evidence ofteu is."— Three Essays, p. 201. Man's Capacity for Immortality. 397 pleasure and pain. Unless we are entirely in error when we think ourselves capable of making such a distinction we have here a fact which is almost equivalent to a demonstration that the soul life is, even whfle the body stiU Uves, independent of the body. Closely aUied with this is another class of facts, namely, those con nected with the ethical changes attendant upon religious conversion. That such conversions occur no one who has studied the subject can deny.1 Men of the vilest passions, mental and physical, have, out of curiosity, or similar motives, dropped in at religious services, and in side of an hour have met with some change, whatever it may be caUed, which altered all their moral and spiritual tastes and habits from that time forth to the end of life. Hate has been thus suddenly exchanged for love, malice for tenderness, lust for purity. These things are not uncommon, but of frequent occurrence. Whether we attribute the change to the power of God, or to the influence of man over man, the fact of the change is indisputable. Now, in all such cases of sudden conversion the change must be spiritual ; that is, it pertains to the spiritual nature, not to the physical. Such an enor mous change in the brain in so short a time as one of these sudden con versions would indicate is impossible. Here is indubitable proof that the mind is not determined by the condition of the brain, for the effect of conversion is the same for physical and mental evil passions. Even while the brain is inflamed by the use of alcohol the converted victim of the drink habit feels no impulse to drink, and in some cases conversion is followed by a per manent sense of loathing for intoxicating liquors. Should anyone attribute the result to the change in the center of gravity of the feel ings, to the tremendous force of a new impression, of fear, or hope, or aspiration, or the Uke, still it would not alter the fact that the men tal change was neither caused nor accompanied by a corresponding change in the brain. The force of these facts is such as to make it practically certain that the mind is not dependent upon the brain in any such sense as that it cannot act apart from it. My mind cannot manifest itseU to another without the use of the brain, but it has the power to act in ways for which the brain is wholly unprepared, and even contrary to brain conditions. This being the case it is evident that the soul can go on with its activities when the brain is dead.' 1 Comp. Martineau's A Study of Religion, vol. ii, p. 39. ' For an extended argument see The Relations of Mind and Brain, by Professor H. Calderwood, London, 1879. Comp. also Professor Eucken's Der Kampf um einen Geistigen Lebensinhalt, Leipzig, 1896, pp. 1-19. 398 Foundations of the Christian Faith. The foregoing remarks will suffice to show that the soul is capaci tated to survive the death of the body. There is absolutely no evi dence of the simultaneous death of soul and body, much less is such a catastrophe capable of proof. When Nordheim says that we are unable to discover the time when the soul leaves the body of a dying man" he brings no argument for the beUef that it never leaves and that there is nothing that can leave, the body. AU he shows is, what all confess, that we know soul only in thought, not by means of the physical senses. It is impossible for us to know aU being through the medium of the physical senses. Indeed, had we this medium only we could not know matter. Both matter and spirit are known by thought, and thought alone. Both are known to Weakness of thought alone by their phenomena.' Strictly speaking, Hams™ 6im- we see neither body nor spirit. Hence Nordheim's argu- mortahty. ment is simply a statement of his lack of evidence that the soul exists after the death of the body. And the reason that he lacks evidence is that he searches for it through the channels of the physical senses, which, in the nature of the case, can convey him no such information as he demands. If he wfll attack the problem by thought he wfll see that the first step in the furnishing of evidence for the soul's existence apart from the dead body is given in the proof that the soul is capable of such existence. 1 Die Erf ttllung des Christenthums, p. 286. Haeckel has an absurd passage in which he says that, according to the Christian view, we must suppose that " a little piece of the father's mind accompanied the sperm-cell, a little piece of the mother's mind remained with the egg-cell.— The Evolution of Man, vol. ii, p. 415 f . In answer it is sufficient to say that Christianity has no theory as to the process by which the soul originates. Haeckel can think only in terms of matter, else he would not speak of a " piece" of mind. a Comp. Menzl, Der Materialismus vor dem Richterstuhl der Wissenschaft, part i. Grounds for the Belief in Human Immortality. 399 CHAPTER II. GROUNDS FOR THE BELIEF IN HUMAN IMMORTALITY. In the absence of any evidence against the soul's survival of the death of the body a very slight presumption in favor of such a sur vival would turn the scales of belief in its favor except with those who are controlled by prejudice rather than reason. But the argu ments for immortality are such as to produce a very strong presump tion in its favor. We offer here a few of those arguments, omitting the proof from revelation. Man's rank in creation is such as to render highly probable his con tinued existence after death. (1) However near to the level of the higher animals man's physical structure may be it has been made plain that the human being is vastly different from and superior to the brute in his spiritual nature. Personality, freedom, responsi bility, accountabflity, are terms which can be applied to man alone of aU created beings. Indeed, it is not too much to say that, Man's rank in creation as aside from the word of revelation, man gives evidence of an argument for lmmor- being created in the image of God. In support of this taiity. well-known view we give the substance of the argument on that sub ject by Professor James Orr, D.D.1 First, man bears the rational image of God.' This we know, since man can understand the world God has made. The first condition of success in the attempt to trans late a book from a foreign language is similarity of inteUigence be tween the man who wrote it and the one who attempts to decipher it. If the reason of the former were totally different from the reason of the latter the attempt to understand each other would be hopeless. Precisely the same condition applies to the possibility of our knowl edge of the world. Reason in man and the reason expressed in na ture must be the same in kind, or no relation between them could be established. Second, man bears God's moral image ; not now in the possession of actual righteousness, but in the possession of the inde structible elements of a moral nature, (a) He is a being with the power of moral knowledge. The idea of good, and with it the moral 1 In his The Christian View of the World, being the Kerr Lectures for 1890-91, third edition, New York, 1897, pp. 139 ff. 11 Comp. also W. N. Clark's Outline of Christian Theology, Cambridge, 1894, p. 171. There is a later editiou of this excellent work to which we have not access. 400 Foundations of the Christian Faith. '• ought " or ethical imperative, is part of his constitution. (6) He is a free, spiritual cause, that is, he has moral freedom. At present this freedom is sadly impaired by sin, yet it is one of the constitutive ele ments of his nature. As a free, spiritual, seU-determining cause he is in a very marked sense the image of his Maker. It is this power of wiU and seU- decision in man which most of aU constitutes him a per son. Through it he stands out of and above nature's sequences, and can react on and modify them.1 He is, as some have chosen to regard him, a supernatural cause in the order of nature.' (c) Man is a being with moral affections. Without these he would not be a true image of the God who is love. Thus man has a conscience which reveals moral law, a will which can execute moral purposes, and affections which create a capacity for moral love. Third, man bears the image of God in his deputed sovereignty over the creatures; a sovereignty abundantly testified to by aU man's conquests over material condi tions, his achievements in art and civilization, and his employment of nature's laws and forces for his own ends.3 (2) Man is the highest being that wfll ever dweU upon earth. Even if anyone were disposed to dispute that nature tended toward a goal with which man must be identified, still it is plain from other reasons that no being higher than man wfll ever make this earth his dweUing place. For, on the theory of evolution, the earth has become too old, and its process of cooling off has gone too far, to admit of the advent of a new order with any chance of survival. * We cite in this connection some of the majestic sentences and forci ble deductions of Mr. John Fiske. " " Chief among these agencies, [that is, in the process of development] is natural selection. ... In the desperate struggle for existence no pecuharity, physical or psy chical, however sUght, has been too insignificant for natural selection to seize and enhance. . . . Psychical variations have never been un important. ... At length there came a wonderful moment. . . . 1 So also Andresen, Die Entwlckelung der Menschen, p. 60. 3 Horace BushneU, Nature and the Supernatural, New York, 1867, pp. 23-25. ' On the Image of God In man comp. Laidlaw's Bible Doctrine of Man, Cunningham Lec tures, Edinburgh, 1879, Lecture ill. Dr. J. H. W. Stuckenberg quotes Professor Bastian as saying: " The serious mistake made by Buckle is that he thought what is true of man in his savage state Is also true of him during all the stages of development, namely, that he always remains under the dominion of his environment. The truth, however, is. that man frees himself from his environment in proportion as he rises in civilization, so that instead of being nature's slave he becomes Its master."— Introduction to the Study of Sociology, New York, 1898, p. 227. This recognizes man as nature's master, but not early enough. It would be truer to say that man's progress in civilization Is marked by his increasing mastery over nature. The mastery, in some degree, he had from the begin ning; else he never could have risen at all. * Andresen, Die Entwlckelung der Menschen, p. 40. • The Destiny of Man viewed in the Light of his Origin, Boston, 1885, pp. 26-34. Grounds for the Belief in Human Immortality. 401 Silent and unnoticed . . . there arrived that wonderful moment at which psychical changes began to be of more use than physical changes to the brute ancestor of man. . . . No fact in nature is Jonn Fiske on fraught with deeper meaning than this two-sided fact of eWef of God's the extreme physical similarity and enormous psychical creatures- divergence between man and the group of animals to which he traces his pedigree. It shows that when humanity began to be evolved an entirely new chapter in the history of the universe was opened. Henceforth the Ufe of the nascent soul came to be first in importance, and the bodfly lUe became subordinated to it. . . . Henceforth, in short, the dominant aspect of evolution was to be, not the genesis of species, but the progress of civUization. . . . According to Darwinism the creation of man is stiU the goal toward which nature tended from the beginning. Not the production of any higher creature, but the perfecting of humanity, is to be the glorious consummation of nature's long and tedious work. Thus we suddenly arrive at the conclusion that man seems now, much more clearly than ever, the chief among God's creatures. . . . He who has mastered the Darwinian theory . . . sees that . . . the whole creation has been groaning and travail ing together in order to bring forth that last consummate specimen of God's handiwork, the human soul. . . . The destinies of aU other liv ing things are more and more dependent upon the will of man. It rests with him to determine, to a great degree, what plants and ani mals shall remain on earth and what shaU be swept from its surface. . . . Natural selection itseU wfll by and by occupy a subordinate place in comparison with selection by man." Thus man's position in creation is exhibited to be such as to preclude as unreasonable the supposition that the spiritual life, the goal of all earthly existence, should itseU be as ephemeral as all the precedent existences upon which it, according to the evolution theory, was condi tioned. As before stated, there is no reason to suppose that the soul-Uf e is extinguished with the lUe of the body ; but, if there were, we should certainly have reason to regard all creation as the most Ascription of . folly to the stupendous piece of folly conceivable to God or man. Creator. That so much time and energy and such infinitely varied resources should be expended, resulting in a form of being so exalted as the mind of man, and all be allowed to lavish itself for nothing, is simply incredible. The chfld's pleasure in building his houses of blocks for the pleasure of knocking them down again is a manUestation of highest wisdom compared with the creation of a soul capable of con tinued existence with the understanding that when it is created it shall 4.02 Foundations of the Christian Faith. be immediately destroyed. Were such an outcome possible thought ful men would be compelled to write aU over this seemingly wondrous world of ours one word, with infinite repetitions, FOLLY, FOLLY, FOLLY. Nor can escape be had from this conclusion by the impersonal kind of immortality talked about by some who feel the force of the above reasoning. Carus, it will be remembered,1 says that the parents are immortal in their children, which we answered by pointing to the fact that there are many who never become parents, and who there fore have no immortality. George EUot has a much more real kind of impersonal immortality to offer in her noble poem which begins : O may I join the choir invisible Of those immortal dead who hve again In minds made better by their presence.2 In a very good sense she truly says, "So to live is heaven," and "This George Eliot's is hfe to come." One can but sympathize with her when immortality, she expresses the ardent longing, "May I reach that purest heaven." One is lifted up to such a height of Christian delight in the spirit of helpfulness to others by the reading of the poem that the question of a personal future existence appears insignificant in the comparison. But it appears so only because the great Christian prin ciple of conduct finds such attractive and impressive utterance at the hands of genius as to make us forgetful of other truths and principles. For example, under such an inspiration we forget that it is the beUef in personal immortality — in the lofty dignity and immense signifi cance of the individual human soul — which makes us feel that it is worth while to live for others.3 Says Mr. John Stuart Mill:* "The beneficial influence of such a hope is far from trifling. It makes life and human nature a far greater thing to the feelings, and gives greater strength as well as greater solemnity to aU the sentiments which are awakened in us by our feUow-creatures, and by mankind at large. It allays the sense of that irony of nature which is so painfully felt when we see the exertions and sacrifices of a lUe culminating in the formation of a wise and noble mind only to disappear from the world when the time has just arrived at which the world seems about to begin reaping the benefit of it." Hope is absolutely essentia] to sus tained effort in our own or in another's behalf. Were we sure that we have no personal immortality we might, as companions in a mutual despair, strive to alleviate each other's sufferings as much as possible ; 1 Division I, section Hi, chap. 5. » Jubal and Other Poems, Boston, 1874. 8 Comp. Uhlhorn's Christian Charity in the Ancient Church, New York, 1883, p. 33 f. 1 Three Essays, p. 249. Grounds for the Belief in Human Immortality. 403 but it is unreasonable to suppose that we should expend so much of our own affection and energy upon the development of the minds and hearts of others if we felt that neither we nor they would reap any but the briefest benefits from all our pains. Besides, if we may trust the combined teaching of both science and the Bible, even this impersonal immortality is immortality only in name — a mere fiction set up for the reaUty. For the imm0rtaiity time wiU come when the human race shall disappear only in name. from the face of the earth. If there is no mind left to retain the influ ences of good which we have exerted where wfll be our immortality ? The only hope we can cherish of immortaUty, in the sense in which the word is employed by the gUted authoress, is in the personal im mortaUty of those in whose minds we live again. We repeat that, if man's spirit be not immortal, this world, with aU its intelUgence, is a gigantic monument of imbecility and folly. To suppose that such a being as man came into existence except under the guidance of inteUigence is absurd ; but if man is the product of intelligence he will be too much prized by his Maker for his spiritual destiny to be involved in the dissolution of material combinations like the brain. Very weighty, therefore, is the presumption in favor of hnmortaUty from this point of view. 404 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. presumptions in favor of immortality. From yet another standpoint this presumption is greatly strength ened. The time aUotted to man even in the longest Ufe on earth is in- The argument sufficient for the full development of his mental and moral suf? iciency powers. It is true that the inteUectual and moral progress man™6 de- °^ *ne majority of human beings is much slower than it veiopment. neeri be, and some seem incapable of great progress with or without sufficient time ; but there are large numbers whose physical natures become a clog to their mental powers long before the latter appear to have reached the limit of their possibiUties. Once it is clearly seen that the human mind, while in some measure dependent upon the brain, and indeed upon the entire physical system, is also independent of these material conditions in such a sense that it could carry on aU its operations of seU-consciousness, and the like, were it separate from the body, it becomes evident that there is no telling what the capacities of the mind are. Until the body begins to clog the mind's activities these appear to improve through eight or nine decades of Ufe. It is natural to suppose that were the body as capable of enduring as the mind is, the latter would continue to develop indefinitely. The brain is dependent upon the whole organism for its health, and when the latter becomes diseased it affects the strength of the former. As long as brain and mind are so intimately connected the improve ment of the mind must apparently cease when the brain begins to de teriorate. But there is not the slightest reason for thinking that when the mind is set free from its bodily limitations it cannot proceed to expand to an indefinite degree. Its capability for expansion under right conditions here would seem to indicate that with right condi tions hereafter it wiU continue to expand. And there is nothing to show that those conditions wUl not be afforded. They are provided here to the full extent of the possibilities permitted in a world of mat ter and of sin, why not hereafter ? If the superior opportunities con ceivable hereafter shall be given, the limitless development of the men tal powers so much dreamed of and desired wfll be realized. It is impossible to believe that the Intelligence which produced the mind naturaUy capable of such attainments wUl prevent them by annihilat- Presumptions in Favor of Immortality. 405 ing the mind. Here would be a mark of foUy even greater than the one before mentioned. Only those who are ready to believe with the pessimist, " Vanity of vanities, aU is vanity," can deny that the pre sumption is in favor of the mind's finding further time for reaching its highest possible power. And when it has attained the goal it will be so majestic that the foUy which could annihilate would be as in finite as we now suppose the wisdom of God to be. Furthermore, the moral nature in man is and can be but partially developed in this lUe. Here the facts are much more simple than with reference to mental improvement ; for the very con- The same ap- ditions which hinder inteUectual progress are oftentimes moral nature. exceedingly favorable to the promotion of ethical advancement. Hence moral ripening does not necessarUy cease up to the last moment of Ufe. Yet aU thoughtful people feel that under the best of condi tions no one becomes moraUy, in this life, what he might become were Ufe longer. Now, there are the best of reasons why life should not be unduly prolonged in this world, but there are no reasons that man can conceive why it should not be indefinitely prolonged under other conditions than those which make its brevity desirable here. Why are we possessed of a moral nature and of the capacity for ethical betterment ? Did God, who made us, not give us these capacities ? Were he to cut us off when our moral progress is but fairly begun he would be chargeable, not only with folly, but with contradicting the opinion which the gift of a moral nature has strengthened within us, namely, that he cares for moral beings. The folly and the indiffer ence to high moral attainment attributable to God on the denial of immortality furnish an irresistible presumption in favor of the Chris tian doctrine of life after death. An artist does not spend his lUe be- ginning works of genius only to destroy them before they are haU complete ; and God does not, U we may judge of him by any measure known to ourselves, start his creatures on a career of majestic ethical possibility with the predetermined purpose of preventing its attain ment. Says Mr. John Fiske : " I believe in the immortality of the soul ... as a supreme act of faith in the reasonableness of God's work." Thus, while, as Mr. Mill admits, there is no evidence of weight against the immortality of the soul, there is evidence in favor of the belief sufficient to create a high degree of probability. Unless we are to suppose that the being who, according to both science and the Bible, is fitted to survive, and who, to reach his best, ought to sur vive, is after all to perish with the unfit, we must beUeve in the im mortaUty of the soul. 28 406 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Another fact which creates a strong presumption in favor of Ufe be yond the grave is that it is needed to meet the demands of justice. We all feel that there are, in large numbers, moral heroes who have The argument n°t been adequately rewarded in this lUe. Men and mands6 Iff women die in the midst of then deeds of virtue and love justice. before they have received even so much as the meed of praise which their own consciences would surely have bestowed had they not been so suddenly cut off. On the other hand, there have been many men whose wickedness never caused them a pang of remorse nor any conscious inconvenience whatever. Here are defects of di vine administration if this is our only lUe. But U the soul Uves on, and continues to be conscious of its past, with conscience alive and the ability to recognize and appreciate the approval and disapproval of others which is a characteristic of human nature here, aU this can be remedied, and God can justUy his ways to man. ¦ We do not wish to continue the discussion, as the presumption is absolutely all on the side of immortaUty, and it is at the same time The presump- very powerful. There is, however, one objection which favor of im- should be briefly met. It arises from the firm beUef that, and they are as the mind is always connected with a body here, it can- very power- ful. not exist apart from it hereafter ; that is, that it would be hampered without a bodily organ. The objection springs from the materialism of the day, which makes it impossible for some to con ceive of a purely spiritual existence. But the Christian has no motive for asserting that the spirit wiU be left without a body in the future Ufe. The doctrine of the resurrection assumes that we shall have bodies, though they will be different from our present ones in many ways, when the consummation of all things takes place. It is useless to speculate, and we refrain. But this much must be said : The Chris tian doctrine provides for a body as well as a soul ; and he who insists that the soul cannot Uve without a body simply confirms the Christian view, therefore, that the resurrection is credible and at least probable. Before closing this discussion attention should be again called to the fact that no attempt has been made at a demonstration. AU that can possibly be secured is a high degree of probability. This we believe the considerations adduced will provide for all unprejudiced minds. And when we come to the treatment of the revelation brought by Christ ' Another strong presumption In favor of Immortality we have not thought It necessary to develop. It Is that which arises from the universality of the belief. The declaration of Dr. Richards, that "there seems to be no certain connection between belief and the reality " (The Mystery of Life, New York, 1898, p. 62) Is met by the considerations found on pp. 878, 379 supra. Presumptions in Favor of Immortality. 407 that probability will become a practical certainty. ' Nevertheless, even when it is inteUectually conceded that the doctrine of immortality is so probable that we can but accept it, stfll it must be remembered that for the f uU and effective conviction needful in reference to it some thing more than inteUectual assent, however hearty, is demanded. Says Dr. Clarke, in the excellent work above referred to :' " Only as men know and feel themselves immortal, and are impressed with the deathlessness of their kind, does immortality obtain its rightful power. Hence much of the evidence must be inward, subjective, and more or less indefinable. . . . Men are Uable to doubt immortaUty until they have inwardly learned it. All low, worldly, and unspiritual Ufe tends toward doubt of it, and aU high living tends to beUef in it." In other words, he who has the certainty that he is a child of God through Jesus Christ is certain that he shaU never die. 3 1 Those readers who wish to connect that discussion with this are referred to division viii, section viii, chap. 3. 3 An Outline of Christian Theology, pp. 172, 173. s For a masterly treatment of the doctrine of Immortality from the standpoint of the Bible, see Professor Salmond's The Christian Doctrine of Immortality, Edinburgh, 1895. 408 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION III.-THE ORIGIN OF HUMAN SIN. CHAPTER I. EXAMINATION OF THE NON-CHRISTIAN VIEW. Attention has often been caUed to the fact that Christianity did not place, but found, men in a condition of sin. One of the fundamental and essential characteristics of Christianity is its doctrine concerning the origin and nature of sin. And nowhere is our faith more in dan ger than just at this point. There can be no doubt that the doctrines of sin and salvation are closely linked together hi the Christian sys tem, and that our conception of the latter is inevitably modified by our conception of the former. Any view which makes the interven tion of Christ nonessential, however it may aUow that it is helpful, is antichristian. And while the doctrine of sin in Christianity is not framed to suit the doctrine of Christ's redemptive work, nor the latter framed to suit the former, stfll anything which touches the one affects faith in the other. The Christian doctrine of sin makes man, not God, responsible for the moral evfl which is in the world. In opposition to this view there are Man, not God, two current conceptions of the origin and nature of moral responsible ... . . . ,, . for sin. evil, the existence of which is universaUy admitted. They may be termed the pantheistic-evolutionary, and the atheistic- evolutionary. It wfll be seen that they have the evolutionary idea in common, and it may be added that both practically release man from aU responsibility for the presence of sin in the world, since both re gard his moral condition as the product of forces for the most part be yond his control. They differ in that the former makes God, that is, God as understood by pantheism, responsible for moral evil,1 while the latter, which is atheistic in the sense that it either denies or ignores God's part in evolution, places the origin of sin in the necessities aris ing from the struggle for existence. Both, in effect, deny the abso luteness of the distinction between moral good and evil. Pantheism makes moral evil a part of the divine plan, and regards it as a lesser good, while evolution is constantly tending to substitute for the lesser 1 On the pantheistic versus the Christian doctrine of sin, see Stearns's The Evidence of Christian Experience, p. 93. Examination of the Non-Christian View. 409 the greater good. Atheistic evolution makes moral evfl merely a stage in the progress of Ufe on its road to perfection. It is a part of man's brute inheritance which he is gradually throwing off. Both make the redemption in Christ nonessential, since man would without the intervention of Christ, though perhaps more slowly, attain to free dom from sin. Sin itself is, under both views, maladjustment to envi ronment, not the responsible act or state of a human being. Since both the atheistic and pantheistic theories have been already considered and refuted we may leave these two views of sin to fight out their differences between themselves. But as far as they turn to us a common front we must meet and overthrow them. We take as the spokesman of the non-Christian view Mr. John Fiske, who, though neither a pantheist nor an atheist, holds practically their John Fiske's views of the origin of human sin. One sentence reveals the evoiu- his whole thought: "This original sin (of theology) is gin of sin. neither more nor less than the brute inheritance which every man carries with him." ' To this we add the following, which more fuUy sets forth the evolutionary idea of the origin of moral evfl: "For thousands of generations, and until very recent times, one of the chief occupations of men has been to plunder, bruise, and kill one another. The selfish and ugly passions which are primordial — which have the incalculable strength of inheritance from the time when animal consciousness began — have had but Uttle opportunity to grow weak from disuse. The tender and unselfish feelings which are a later product of evolution have too seldom been allowed to grow strong from exercise.'" "And thus at length we see what human progress means. It means throwing off the brute inheritance— grad ually throwing it off through ages of struggle that are by and by to make struggle needless. Man is slowly passing from a primitive social state in which he was little better than a brute, toward an ulti mate social state in which his character shall have become so trans formed that nothing of the brute can be detected in it. The ape and the tiger in human nature will become extinct." ' There is no niistaking the significance of aU this. Man when he emerged from the brute stage was Uttle better than the brute from which he was evolved. The fundamental passions of propagation of the species and self-preservation he received in all their native strength and unbridled application from his brute ancestor. Man is not respon- 1 The Destiny of Man, p. 103. This exceedingly valuable little book is a condensation of several of Fiske's larger works.— Preface to the Destiny, p. vi. ' Ibid., p. 100 f. a Ibid., p. 103, 410 Foundations of the Christian Faith. sible for his sinful state, though individual men may be for the faflure to check the lower and to cultivate the nobler passions. There are two questions which demand consideration here. First, Did man spring from the brutes ? Second, If he did, was he so slightly different from his ancestors as evolutionists would have us believe ? In reality it is the second question which is chiefly important to Christianity. The first might almost be ignored. Stfll, since it is an swered in the affirmative by evolutionists, and as this answer is the „ . . chief basis for an affirmative answer to the second ques- The doctrine of the brute ^ion. it wiU not be amiss to show the real facts with origin of man ' challenged, reference to it. Our purpose, however, is not to prove that man is a distinct and separate creation for which the brute world was in no sense a preparation ; but that the atheistic theory of man's evolution is unproved and improbable. We examine first into the alleged great antiquity of man as a proof of his brute origin. In fact, this great antiquity is a theory by which it is proposed to account for the aUeged brute origin. The argument is like this : How do we know that man originated so long ago ? By the laws of evolution — which require him to have sprung from ani mals lower than himself and to have differed but very sUghtly from them at the first — we must beUeve that he originated long ages ago. Thus the antiquity of man is supposed to be proved. Turning to the proof for man's brute origin one argument runs thus : How do we know that man sprang from the brutes ? His great antiquity pre supposes it. Thus the antiquity is made to depend upon the brute origin, and the brute origin upon the antiquity for support. More recent investigations and studies are leading thoughtful men to the conclusion that the long periods once affirmed for the age of the world must be given up. Instead of hundreds of millions of years The alleged science now holds to but ten mflUons, or at most twenty ffquity8, of millions.1 So also the antiquity of man is being greatly reduced. Haeckel says :" It is true that, in the present imperfect state of our paleontological and prehistoric knowledge, we cannot solve the problem as to whether the development of Man from the nearest allied Ape-forms took place in the beginning of this Anthropolithic Epoch or as early as the middle or toward the close of the preceding Tertiary Epoch. This much, however, is certain — that the true development of human culture dates only from the Anthro- 1 The latter figure Is given by Lord Kelvin. See Report of President Archibald Geike before the British Association in 1892. The smaller figure is that of Professor Tait, in Recent Advances in Physical Science, p. 167. Comp. Oil's. The Christian View of the World, p. 446. Examination of the Non-Christian View. 411 polithic Epoch, and that this latter constitutes only an msignificantly smaU section of the entire enormous period of time occupied in the de velopment of the organic earth." ' On the same page with the above and on the page foUowing his language indicates that the whole period of man does not amount to one per cent of the entire age of the world. Reckoning this latter at twenty mUlions the whole period of the development of man from the man-apes would be about two hun dred thousand years. Reckoning at ten millions it would be about one hundred thousand years. Large as these figures are they are smafler than those of earher calculations. But stfll more recent cal culations of a thoroughly reliable kind place the close of the glacial epoch not more than ten thousand years ago, which is only one tenth of the smaUest figure we can get from Haeckel's admissions. At any rate it must be said that there is no sufficient proof for the extreme antiquity of man, and so far no evidence for his brute origin.2 Besides, there are no existing remains to support the idea that man sprang from the lower animals. Haeckel, who always Lack of exist- r a ing remains knows more about unknown things than most others are t o prove 0 man's brute wflling to conjecture, admits that " only very uncertain origin. conjectures can be formed as to the time and place of this true ' Crea tion of Man,' " s that is, his development from the ape-men or speech less men. He adds : " It is probable that Primeval Man originated during the Diluvial Epoch, in the torrid zone of the Old World, either on the continent of tropical Asia or Africa or on an earlier continent which has now sunk below the surface of the Indian Ocean." Here is a clear admission of the lack of evidence that man had for his pro genitors a series of man-apes, ape-men, and the like. As the time and place are uncertain conjectures, so is the whole theory that man so originated. It is sometimes said that no stress should be laid upon the fact that the missing Unks have not been found, since but a smaU portion of the earth's surface has been searched and, besides, remains of extinct animals are so easily destroyed. This plea for quarter on the part of our opponents could be heeded were it not always accom panied by the assertion that the evidence surely exists or has existed. It is in reply to this assertion that we insist on the fact that the evi- 1 The Evolution of Man, vol. ii, p. 16. 2 Of course Haeckel is not here credited with allowing the briefer reckonings of world- time. For full discussion see Wright's Man and the Glacial Period, New York, 1892, and a paper read before the Geographical Section of the British Association, August 4, 1892. by Messrs. Kendall and May. Comp. also Orr's, The Christian View of the World, p. 445. Even Haeckel's figures will have to be considerably cut down if, according to him, man originated in the Diluvial Epoch.— The Evolution of Man, vol. Ii, p. 183. s The Evolution of Man, vol. ii, p. 182 f. 412 Foundations of the Christian Faith. dence has not been found, and in accord with Haeckel's surmise that the evidence lies at the bottom of the Indian Ocean, never wfll be found. ' We can imagine Haeckel's scorn should the Christian at tempt to base the facts of the Ufe of Christ upon aUeged documents which had perished in a conjectural fire in a conjectural city at a con jectural period of the Christian era.' 1 Haeckel is reported to have said in a recent address that it is useless to search further for the missing link. "See a brief but valuable statement of the Christian position relative to the brute origin of man and the responsibility of man for his own sin In Max Reischle's Christen thum und Entwickelungsgedanke, Leipzig, 1898, pp. 21 ff. The Fall of Man. 413 CHAPTER II. THE FALL OF MAN. The strongest argument which can be adduced in favor of the evolu tionary theory of the origin of man is the speculative argument from analogy. The analogical argument at its best is never a scien tific proof ; so that the theory can at most be established as probable, and not as fact. This does not, indeed, militate against it in the eyes of thoughtful people, for nearly aU our so-caUed knowledge is nothing more than probability ; but it does rob it of the force which the magic word science is supposed to lend it. It is a scientific theory, not in the sense that it is scientifically established, but in the sense that it is a theory in science. It is obliged, in view of the lack of evidence, to support itself by speculations drawn chiefly from an alogy. How much probability does this argument lend it ? It may be said that it is practically certain that, since the missing links have been found connecting other animals with their past, analogy would de mand credence of the theory that the links are or have The argument been in existence between man and ape. In fact, the is against the analogy here is in the finding or not finding of the links, of man. The greater the number of Unks found in the chain of being elsewhere the more striking becomes the faflure to find them in the case of man and ape. So the argument here is against the brute origin. Analogy demands that these links, if they ever existed, should have been found. Again, it may be said that as aU lUe below man is connected by a series of gradations, so analogy requires us to believe that man, in physical structure so similar 'to the apes, must have descended through them and is thus a part of the ascendmg series ; its crown, if you choose. But there is so much in man that is out of analogy with aU else that analogy demands rather that we should suppose his ori gin to have been out of analogy with the origin of lower forms of lUe. In other words, we place analogy against analogy, thus destroying, or at least neutralizing, our opponent's argument. In view of all this it is clear that the argument from analogy, the only real argument of the atheistic evolutionary theory of the origin of man, lends the theory very little, if any, probability. 414 Foundations of the Christian Faith. We wish now to show that the improbabflity of the brute origin of man is very great. This improbability arises, first, from the practi- Facts showing *ical impossibility that man should be able to sustain probability1" Uimself in the midst of animals so much superior in sprang from capacity for maintaining the struggle for existence. the brutes. physicaUy he was far weaker than many other animals ; he was, to say the least, not more agile than many others ; and the theory of evolution forbids that he should have been so much more intelligent that this could have compensated for his physical deficien cies. [ A second and more convincing source of the above-mentioned improbability is one which Andresen very clearly states as foUows : "Even U those species which originate by crossing were generally capable of propagating themselves, which they are not, stiU the new species must be, not a higher species, but one lying between the two from which it sprang. In order to produce man by crossing both an ape and a creature higher than man would have to unite." ' In this same connection the point made by WaUace already men tioned 3 should be repeated. He shows that the brain of the earUest men of whom we have any trace was nearly as large as the brain of our most advanced races ; whereas, according to the evolutionary theory, the functions it was to perform were such that the brain of the gorilla would have answered every purpose. Now, supposing the theory of very small changes to be true in the progress of animal Ufe, as evolu tion teaches, and that this law holds good until we come to man, where the law fails, as WaUace points out, our faith that man is a part of the same chain of physical being with the lower animals is rudely shaken. These slight changes are essential to the evolutionary the ory. In the chain of evolution there was a break upon the appear ance of man upon the earth. But if evolutionary methods do not hold with reference to man there is reason to beUeve that, however much he may resemble certain animals in physical structure, he is not the mere offspring of those animals. The above arguments against the atheistic form of the doctrine of man's brute origin are intended to show that sin in man is not prob ably a portion of his brute inheritance. If the Creator interfered with the orderly development of the animal world at the point where ¦Some evolutionists go so far as to claim that at first man could not even distin-. guish a human being from a plant. See Wilhelm Mannhardt, in Sammlung gemeln- verstlinclllcher wissenschaftlicher Vortrage, herausgegebeu von Rudolf Virchow und Franz von Holtzendorff, Nr. 239, Berlin, 1876. His language Is quoted by President Warren in his Paradise Found, Boston, 1885, p. 409, where also may be found an excel lent criticism of that position. a Die Entwlckelung der Menschen, p. 35. » See division il, section II, chap. 4. The Fall of Man. 415 man appeared it is exceedingly improbable that man's sin is inherited from the brute. A consideration of the second question mentioned on page 410 wiU shed further Ught on the evolutionary theory of human sin. Intel lectually at least man must have been very far superior to any other animal in existence at the time when men first appeared on earth. President Warren has shown • that evolutionists hold our Tne evidence savage races not to be representatives of the culture of Jsr *m u i ve primitive men. He quotes from Herbert Spencer as f ol- co*"1'11011- , lows : "There are sundry reasons for suspecting that existing men of the lowest types, forming social groups of the simplest kinds, do not exemplify men as they originaUy were. Probably most of them, if not all of them, had ancestors in higher states, and among their beUefs remained some which were evolved during those higher states. . . . There is inadequate warrant for the notion that the lowest savagery has always been as low as it is now. . . . That supplanting of race by race, and thrusting into corners such inferior races as are not ex terminated, which is now going on so actively, and which has been going on from the earliest recorded times, must have been ever going on. And the implication is that remnants of inferior races, taking refuge in inclement, barren, and otherwise unfit regions, have retro graded." ' He cites similar opinions from Darwin,3 Lubbock,4 Tylor," and others. Professor James Orr in his Christian View of the World, in a note on "Alleged Primitive Savagery of Mankind," 6 cites from the Duke of Argyll ' and many others to the same effect. Professor Max Midler says : "We know now that savage and primitive are very far indeed from meaning the same thing."8 As Professor Orr remarks, "The greatest civilizations of antiquity do not show traces of an earlier period of barbarism," " and he quotes Canon RawUnson to show that all authorities agree that, however far we go back, we find in Egypt no rude or uncivilized time out of which civiUzation is developed; and that in Babylon there is not only no sign of early rudeness, but positive evidence of an advanced state of certam arts even in the earliest times. Now, U it be true that the savage lUe still existing in certain parts of the globe is the result of deterioration from a higher primitive 1 Paradise Found, p. 387 f. 2 The quotation is from Spencer's Principles of Sociology, pp. 106-109. s Descent of Man, vol. i, p. 66. 4 The Origin of Civilization, p. 483. • Primitive Culture, vol. i, p. 321. e Page 440 f. ' Unity of Nature, p. 426. 8 Anthropological Religion, London, 1892, p. 150. 9 Christian View, p. 441. 416 Foundations of the Christian Faith. state of culture, it is most likely that the sinfulness of man also is the result of degeneration. In fact, Fiske shows clearly that much of the cruelty and immorahty of the human race result from defective men tal development,1 and says that the fundamental inteUectual differ ence between civilized men and savages Ues in the difference in their power of representing in imagination objects and relations not present to the senses. Fiske apparently beUeves that the savage or, if we may so say, the beastly state was the primitive state of man. But, if his scientific brethren who take the other view be correct, then primitive man had the power which is wanting in our savages. Hence they must have been more moral than our savages. The natural question is, How much more moral? Perhaps some light may be thrown on this question U we take into account some of the conclusions heretofore reached, according to which man is the product of the divine creative agency, whether through the lower animals or not, and, according to which, further, man is even now in several respects an image of God. It is not to be supposed that man ever was or wUl be an exact copy of his Creator in inteUect or morals. But it is exceedingly unUkely that as he came from the hand of God he had a moral nature opposed to that of God who created him. The most probable view is that man was originaUy endowed with con siderable capacity of an intellectual kind, which gave him an advan tage in the struggle for existence, but which needed development in the course of that struggle, and that he was at least sinless in aU his feelings and volitions, though needing positive ethical development. So the Bible represents him, and to this the probabilities in the case, when purely speculative considerations are left out of the account, point. In fact, it is impossible to account for man's present moral condition and sentiments except on the Christian view of sin, which makes it, Man's present not the result of God's method in creation, nor of any moral senti- ments as purely evolutionary process, in which the struggle for fact of a fall, existence produces strongly selfish impulses, but of man's own act. As men become more moral they condemn their sin the more vigorously, whereas, if it were true that with every step in moral progress we are throwing off the brute inheritance, we ought not to condemn ourselves at all but to commend our virtue, won in spite of our origin.' The conscience is so constructed that it makes little, U 1 The Destiny of Man, p, 99. * Somewhere we have read of a witty writer who says: "Evolution says not, 0 wretched man that I am; but, O, progressive creature that I am, who shall help me to evolve myself!" The Fall of Man. 417 any, allowance for the historical origin of sin either in the individual or in the race. It condemns us for sinning and refuses to aUow us comfort from the thought that we inherited our tendencies to evil from our progenitors. This can be explained only on the ground that we are responsible, which we are not U sin is a brute inheritance. Besides, the doctrine of the brute origin of sin fails to account for the fact that, whfle the range of actions regarded as morally wrong has greatly enlarged since human history began, from the first the race, as a whole, has as strongly condemned those acts which it held to be sinful as it does to-day. This fact indicates that man is not naturaUy as depraved as some scientists would have us believe. The original condition of man must have been one in which all his impulses favored righteousness. By virtue of his humanity he has a strong love for the good which no abandonment to sin can quite eradicate. The evolutionary theory of the origin of sin cannot explain this uni form strength of conscience from the earliest to the latest period of human history. Furthermore, this very fact of conscience in man shows that the moral nature of human beings is not a brute inherit ance. A brute wfll sometimes exhibit fear after doing an act disap proved by its master, but of what we know as shame there is no trace. We have not the slightest reason to suspect that brutes have any conception of right and wrong, any conscience which constantly urges to the choice of righteousness, or any sense of ever fading be low the ideal which a noble personality sets for itself. In other words, the brute is a moral neutral, and has no consciousness of sin. But man has this consciousness, which would be impossible were he moraUy the mere lineal descendant of the brute. Between the moral nature of the lower animals (U it be proper to attribute to them any moral nature whatever) and the moral nature of man there is an •enormous and impassable guU. Man may do deeds as vile as those of the beast, but he cannot do them with the impunity of the beast. This is because man is moraUy responsible, while the beast is not. Many object to the story of the faU given in the Book of Genesis, but, even though its details may be discarded, probabihty strongly favors the notion that sin came into the world just as the Bible tells us it did, by the responsibility of a human being ; and as long as the facts upon which we must base our judgment favor that view we shall not give it up simply because there are those who ridicule it. Every man knows that, however he came by his impulses, he feels himself responsible for them ; and the fall is at least so far repeated in every man's life that we are almost compelled to believe in the substance of 418 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the story in Genesis. The Bible theory of the introduction of sin into the world— the theory of a fad of a previously pure being — has a clear advantage over that which assumes that we are the offspring of the brutes and have inherited their brutal tendency to sin. Since it is a question of beUef on both sides, we prefer that side which has' the stronger reason.1 1 On the original moral condition of man and the origin of human sin, comp. Kaftans, Dogmatik, Freiburg, 1. B., Leipzig und Tubingen, 1897, pp. 346-371. Also, The Gospel of Experience, The Boyle Lectures for 1895, by W. C. E. Newboldt, London and New York, 1896, Lect. ii, pp. 26-50. The Doctrines Concerning Cod. 419 DIVISION vn. THE DOCTRINES CONCERNING GOD. In this connection there are but two doctrines which demand our attention. They are the existence and the personality of God. And here, as with reference to the soul, Christianity, as given in the New Testament, offers no proof, at least no direct proof, of the doctrines in question, but everywhere assumes their truth. Hence, so far at least, we might feel ourselves excused from assigning any reasons for be lief. Besides, as aU phflosophy and religious history show, belief in the existence of God, at any rate, is a natural condition, while denial of his existence is unnatural. The burden of proof is, therefore, upon the little handful of those who deny. The hopelessness of their task is plain to all observers, for it is impossible to prove the nonexistence of a spiritual, invisible being. But whfle the Bible does not afford us proofs of the existence and personality of God, and while from the mere standpoint of argument the burden of proof is upon the deniers of God's existence, yet there are the most weighty reasons for belief in the doctrines stated, and Christians are glad to give these reasons to aU sincere inquirers. Nevertheless, here again it is necessary to remind the reader that we are not attempting a demonstration. Science boasts of its knowledge and ignores in large measure the immense amount of mere belief with which it must content itself. Christianity is not only more modest, but more honest. It believes. Still, this does not detract from the degree of certainty with which the weU-informed Christian holds to his tenets. We are certain of many things which we cannot absolutely demonstrate. The reasons for the Christian's belief in the existence and personality of God are such as to afford a certainty which leaves no room for doubt, but we do not claim for them the force of demonstration except in the sense in which the best of evi dence is capable of demonstrating, for example, the guilt or inno cence of anyone accused in a court of law. We repeat, the reasons for the belief in the existence and personality of God are so imperative that no one who gives them due attention can suffer a doubt. 420 Foundations of the Christian Faith. SECTION I.-THE EXISTENCE OF COD. CHAPTER I. NECESSITY, UNIVERSALITY, AND PERSISTENCE OF THE BELIEF. The first reason we offer is similar to the first argument advanced in favor of the reality of the soul, namely, that all other theories fail First reason to account for the facts. Every form of the atheistic i^ttfe'exist- view, together with its agnostic modifications, has been ence of God. prove(j inadequate. Atheism, as also that agnosticism which works into the hands of atheism, fails to meet the demands of thought, ethics, and the reUgious nature. In fact, atheism so far fails as to make necessary the total annihilation of reUgion, which it re gards as superstition. Speaking of religion Mr. Herbert Spencer says : ' "Two suppositions only are open to us : the one that the feel ing which responds to reUgious ideas resulted, along with other hu man faculties, from an act of special creation, the other that it, in common with the rest, arose by a process of evolution. If we adopt Herbert Spen- the first of these alternatives . . . the matter is at once cer quoted. se^ie(j . Taan js directly endowed with the reUgious feel ing by a creator ; and to that creator it designedly responds. If we adopt the second alternative, then we are met by the questions — What are the circumstances to which the genesis of the reUgious feeling is due ? and — What is its office ? We are bound to entertain these ques tions, and we are bound to find answers to them. Considering all faculties, as we must on this supposition, to result from accumulated modifications caused by the intercourse of the organism with its en vironment, we are obUged to admit there exist in the environment certain phenomena or conditions which have determined the growth of the feeling in question ; and so are obliged to admit that it is as normal as any other faculty. Add to which that as, on the hypothe sis of a development of lower forms into higher, the end forward which the progressive changes directly or indirectly tend must be adapta tion to the requirements of existence, we are also forced to infer that this feeling is in some way conducive to human welfare. Thus both alternatives contain the same ultimate implication. We must con- 1 First Principles, p. 15 f. Necessity, Universality, and Persistence of Belief. 421 elude that the religious sentiment is either directly created or is cre ated by the slow action of natural causes ; and whichever of these conclusions we adopt requires us to treat the religious sentiment with respect." This shows how completely atheism must ever faU to meet the re quirements of a theory which shall include and conserve aU the prin cipal phenomena of Ufe. Because it fafls some theory which admits the existence of God must be adopted. By the same course of reason ing it is clear that as not only atheism fafls, but also agnosticism, pan theism (monism), and deism, we are obliged to adopt the theistic view of God. However, this is in advance of what we wish now to show. As a second reason for believing in the existence of God we name the universality of the beUef . There are those who have tried to cast doubt upon this universaUty, but, as Tylor points out, second reason further investigation in every case proves that their re- fortneDelief- searches were incomplete, and therefore the basis for a conclusion incompetent. A similar argument we have already employed with reference to the soul, and hence we may, as in the case of the preced ing argument, give it the less emphasis here. And once more we rely on Mr. Spencer for the form of the argument. In a preliminary way he says : J "In proportion as we love truth more and victory less we shaU become anxious to know what it is which leads our opponents to think as they do. We shaU begin to suspect that the pertinacity of belief exhibited by them must result from a perception of something we have not perceived. And we shad aim to supplement the portion of truth we have found with the portion found by them." He then proceeds to say :' " When duly realized, the general principle above illustrated must lead us to anticipate that the diverse forms of reU gious beUef which have existed and stiU exist have all a basis in some ultimate fact." "To suppose that these multUorm conceptions should be, one and all, absolutely groundless discredits too profoundly that average human inteUigence from which all our individual intelli gences are inherited." " To the presumption that a number of diverse beliefs of the same class have some common foundation in fact must, in this case, be added a further presumption derived from the omni presence of the beliefs." "Their endless variety serves but to strengthen this conclusion, showing as it does a more or less inde pendent genesis." " That these countless different, and yet allied, phe nomena presented by aU reUgions are accidental or factitious is an untenable supposition. A candid examination of the evidence quite ' First Principles, p. 12. » Ibid., pp. 13, 14. 29 422 Foundations of the Christian Faith. negatives the doctrine, maintained by some, that creeds are priestly inventions." This argument is, indeed, originally designed, not to favor the truth of the Christian idea of God, but rather that there is an ultimate Somewhat which aU must acknowledge to exist. But it is applicable to the existence of God, since that is a universal belief. And we con sider it incapable of overthrow. It is so exceedingly improbable that the whole human race should be deceived in this respect that only they whose self-conceit knows no bounds would assert such deception. The argument would amount to but Uttle were it a question of ma jorities merely, and particularly U the majority, which beheves, were composed of ignorant, and the minority, which disbeUeves, of educated and powerful minds. But such is not the case. For beUef is so nearly universal that the unbelievers can scarcely be dignified by the term Moral and in- minority ; and those who believe are, generaUy, the in- periority o f teUectual and moral superiors of those who do not believe neve. in the existence of God. As far as scientists and phfloso phers are concerned but few are atheists. AU pantheists (monists) and deists, and some agnostics, beUeve in the existence of God, though the latter declare that we cannot define him. As the world grows older and human knowledge and thought develop atheism becomes no stronger, but rather has a weaker hold upon the minds of men. Modesty demands of the pitiful few who stfll disbelieve that they ad mit that those who beUeve have a perception of something which un believers have not perceived. The one juror of twelve who con demned the stubbornness and unreasonableness of the eleven who disagreed with him is proverbial. On the basis of the doctrine of evolution the universaUty of the be lief in the existence of God is a striking evidence in favor of its reten tion. It is one of those beliefs which have survived, and the rarity of atheists, in the strict sense of the word, is evidence that even among the most thoughtful of mankind some idea of God is regarded as reasonably well supported. There is at least so much in its favor that few wfll deny it. That the belief has been held in corrupt and unten able forms is no more a reason for rejecting it altogether than the cor rupt and untenable forms which scientific doctrines have assumed are a reason for rejecting them. As President Schurman says : ] "If we cast out our belief in God because it is prescientific the same logic will forbid us to believe in the existence of a seU, or of an objective world." • Belief in God, New York, 1893, p. 133. Necessity, Universality, and Persistence of Belief. 423 This leads naturaUy to the only form of the ontological argument for the existence of God which has any value. ¦ There is something in the idea of God which compels us to believe in a reality The only valu able form of corresponding to that idea. When we strip the idea of the ontoiogi- cal argu- God which is common to aU mankind of the peculiarities ment. which diverse phflosophical or religious creeds have attached to it we find that what remains is essentially that which Hamilton, Mansel, and Spencer call the unknowable, the unconditioned, the absolute, and the like. This idea falls far short of that which we gain through the revelation of Jesus Christ, in point both of dignity and completeness. In the same way it is far less satisfactory than the God which philoso phy demands. It may be called the idea which is given in spontane ous thought. It appears in consciousness as a mystery. It clamors to be clarified and defined ; and the attempt to answer the questions connected with it has led to the development of the various systems of unrevealed reUgious thought. But this mysterious somewhat does not prove its own existence alone by the universal prevalence of its idea. Rather is it the pressure of the idea which makes us so certain that there is a reality behind it. It is one of those ideas of which we cannot rid ourselves. It persists in making itself felt ; for at first it is felt rather than thought. Spencer sums up the facts as they appear at this stage of development (which, however, he regards as final) in the oft-quoted words. : * "Though the Absolute cannot in any manner or degree be known, in the strict sense of knowing, yet we find that its positive existence is a neces sary datum of consciousness ; that so long as consciousness continues we cannot for an instant rid it of this datum; and that thus the beUef which this datum constitutes has a higher warrant than any other whatever." Here the proof is derived solely from the persist ency of the idea. We should be inclined, as above, to emphasize also the pressure of the idea. It is not only persistently but also obtru sively present. Taken in connection with the facts that atheism and all forms of agnosticism aUied therewith fail to explain the world, and that the presence of this idea is universal, the argument here presented from the persistence and force of the idea becomes very- strong. In any other department of practical lffe than religion the sensible man would at once yield to the combined force of the argu ments already adduced. 1 For a review of the different forms ofthe ontological argument see Flint's Theism ; also Fisher's The Grounds of Theistic and Christian Belief, chap, ii; and Stearns's The Evi dence of Christian Experience, pp. 60 ff. Miley also gives a good summary, Systematic Theology, New York and Cincinnati, 1892, vol. i, pp. 73 ff. » First Principles, p. 98. 424 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER II. THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIGN. The ontological argument as just presented is augmented in force by the consideration of the sources from which this persistent and urgent idea springs. Were we convinced that the idea is not intui tive we should stfll, for the sake of simpUcity, not here combat that theory. But passing it by we ask, what are the unquestionable The source of sources from which the idea of God, as described above, augmenting springs ? The first source is undoubtedly that which has cal0 aigu'i generaUy been worked out into the cosmological argu- ment- ment for the existence of God. The kernel of this argu ment is the idea of causation. Not the doctrine of causaUty as known to materiaUstic science, but the general doctrine that every event must have an adequate cause. Starting with this principle we ob serve that the world must be accounted for. Spontaneous thought suggests a being which caused it. It appears to be a product. A producer is postulated by a necessary law of our minds. This pro ducer may be variously conceived, but the one thing in which all agree concerning him is that he is the cause of the world. Although the idea in this form carries with it all the weight which attaches to our fundamental idea of causality, yet there are objections to it which thought in its more advanced stages alone can raise and answer. Admitting the doctrine of causaUty, it may be asked, Why postu late a being who is distinct from the world as the cause of the world, when the very law of causaUty demands that we shall account for the existence of this being? To this the answer is, We must, of course, find somewhere a first cause ; but the first cause cannot be the world, in any phase of its evolution, nor in any or all the powers it possesses. For the farther we trace back the idea of cause the more certain we become that the only cause we know anything about is will. But matter cannot have will. Hence there must be an imma terial somewhat in which the will resides which brings about the material changes observable by us. Thus the law of causation as it is understood in the higher ranges of thought confirms the beUef that there is a being who produced this world, which being men call God. The Argument from Design. 425 To one who believes that aU real causation springs from wfll the argument is irresistible.1 Another source of the all-prevalent, persistent, and obtrusive idea of God is that which is generaUy called the teleological argument, or the argument from design.' It admits of exceedingly simple state ment. When we observe anv product of apparent human The argument " from design skill we at once infer a human mind as the designer of stated. it. We make this inference on the basis of aU we know of our own activities. SoUpsism is impossible. We must suppose other minds when we see products of other hands than our own. Now, assured as we are that there are objects in this world which are not the product of human skill, we naturaUy reach the conclusion that as those objects bear evidence of design they must be the product of a mind other than human. The proof for mind behind any object is just as strong as the reason for holding it to have been designed. If there is the serving of a purpose it is out of all analogy to suppose that it was not designed for that purpose.3 It is in the highest degree ab surd to say : "Eyes were not made for seeing ; but we have eyes, and see in consequence. The propagation of Ufe was never purposed ; but reproductive processes and mechanisms exist and life is propagated." * Unquestionably such considerations have lent impressiveness to the universal idea of God. But evolutionists declare that since the days of Darwin we can no longer trace the wonderful adaptations we see in nature to a design ing mind. All these are affirmed to result naturaUy from the action and reaction of the particles of matter upon each other according to necessary laws." In the struggle for existence those forms which are best adapted to their surroundings survive, and those which cannot adapt themselves perish. Those which survive transmit to their offspring the quaUties by which they themselves survive. Thus the 1 The cosmological argument is the one which is alone relied upon by many, especially such as deny personality to God. Comp., for example, Nordheim.Die Erfttllung des Christenthums, pp. 299 ff. ' Comp. Paul Janet's Final Causes. Translatedby W. Affleck from the second edition of the French. Second edition, 1883. Ebrard discusses the argument from design with great fullness and force in his voluminous work entitled Apologetics ; or, The Scientific Vin dication of Christianity, translated by Stuart and Macpherson, Edinburgh, 1886, vol. i, pp. 164-208. See also Modern Scepticism. A Course of Lectures delivered at the request of the Christian Evidence Society, New York, 1871, pp. 3-31. 3 Hegel's celebrated saying, that though wine be useful to man we must not suppose the cork tree to exist for the purpose of providing stoppers for wine bottles, misses the point. If bottles grew with cork stoppers in their necks we should be compelled to. see design. 4 Comp. Bowne's, Philosophy of Theism, New York, 1887, p. 90. s Comp. A Candid Examination of Theism, by Physicus (Romanes), pp. 52, 63. 426 Foundations of the Christian Faith. weak or unfit are eliminated, and the natural tendency, according to the laws of heredity and environment, is to adapt everything to every thing else. No one has worked out this argument against design more forcibly than Romanes.1 He admits that "arrangement, dis position of facts, subserviency of means to an end, relation of instru ment to a use, implies the presence of intelligence and mind," ' but says that the assumption that mechanism could have no other cause than that of a designing mind is false. He then proceeds to give in stances in which inorganic nature produces certain remarkable results by purely natural laws, where there is certainly no im mediate design, and draws the conclusion that appearances of design in the organic world are no better founded than in the inorganic. Let us examine this. He proposes to prove that no evidence of immediate design is furnished by the organic world on the ground Romanes's that the results of the action of natural forces must be against de- regarded in the same light whether in the organic or ined. inorganic world. He says:' "He (a supposed teleologist) would now find that every one of the adjustments of means to ends which excited his admiration on the seacoast were due to physical causes which are perfectly well understood. The cliffs stood at the opening of the bay because the sea in past ages had encroached upon the coast line until it met with these cliffs, which then opposed its further progress ; * the bay was a depression in the land which hap pened to be there when the sea arrived, and into which the sea conse quently flowed ; 6 the successive occurrence of rocks, shingle, and sand was due to the actions of the waves themselves ; the segregation of seaweeds, shells, pebbles, and different kinds of sand was due to different degrees of specific gravity ; the fresh- water streams ran in channels because they had themselves been the means of excavating them ; and the multitudinous forms of lUe were aU adapted to their several habitats simply because the unsuited forms were not able to live in them." And again : ° "Given the facts of heredity, variation, struggle for existence, and the consequent survival of the fittest, what foUows? Why, that each step in the prolonged and gradual development of the eye was brought about by the elimination of aU the less adapted structures in any given generation, that is, the selec- 1 See some articles prepared prior to 1889 for the Nineteenth Century, but first pub lished in his Thoughts on Religion. J The words are quoted from Paley. » Thoughts on Religion, p. 58 f. ' But were not placed there by a designing mind to prevent the encroachments of the sea. ' And was not hollowed out by the Creator that there might be a bay at that spot. • Thoughts on Religion, p. 62. The Argument from Design. 427 tion of all the better adapted to perpetuate the improvement by heredity. Will the teleologist maintain that this selective process is itself indicative of special design ? If so, it appears to me that he is logically bound to maintain that the long line of seaweed, the sheUs, the stones, and the little heap of garnet sand upon the seacoast are aU equally indicative of special design." We can see no sufficient reason for questioning the idea that the peculiar results arising along the shore of a bay from the action of the waves are not the product of special design. None but an omniscient mind could be able to say what the supposed infinite designer would or would not design to accomplish, nor how, nor in what he would take delight ; while if utility to man be chosen as the criterion of judgment it is certain that the results in question were specially de signed. For they minister, or may minister, to man's sense of the marvelous, the curious, and the beautUul. Even those things in na ture which we caU grotesque are, from this standpoint, as truly the work of the beneficent Artificer as the more sober, for they add to life a constant source of recreation and amusement ; for both of which we are adapted and both of which we need. Romanes has not proved, then, that there may be any other cause than mind for the adaptations we see all about us, but at At most hig most that if they are the product of a mind they are proveVoniy brought about by a process of fixed laws. The argument g yprflCxeesJ from design does not assert the absence of a process, laws- long or short. It merely argues that as we look at adaptations we naturaUy think of them as resulting from design, because man's adaptations are the result of design. Proximately a structure may be due to the operation of physical causes, whfle more remotely the oper ation of those physical causes may be due to an intelligent purpose. There is, therefore, nothing to show that the appearance of design is delusive. Until it can be demonstrated that there is no mind to design the world we shall have to follow the only method of reasoning we pos sess and believe that the world is designed. The more definite and uni form the process involved in the method by which structures are pro duced the more compulsory this reasoning becomes. Nor is there anything in the fact that the designer of the world must be regarded as immanent in it, instead of external to it, as man is external to his products, which can in any degree modify the force of the conclu sion. The point at issue is not whether the designer be immanent or external, but whether there is evidence of thought, purpose, adapta tion, adjustment 428 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. INADEQUACY OF THE PROCESS OF NATURAL SELECTION. We must here point out a fatal flaw in Romanes's reasoning concern- The fatal flaw ing the eye. As quoted above he says : "Each step in the soning con- prolonged and gradual development of the eye was eye.1 brought about by the elimination of all the less adapted structures in any given generation ; that is, the selection of aU the better adapted to perpetuate the improvement by heredity." Now we ask, What determined the direction which things were to take ? How did the environment come to be what it is ? Everything is part of the environment of something else. How does it come that things do not degenerate instead of improve ? There is a total condition of things which tends ever to greater complexity and perfection. Why ? The tendency must determine it; but it is just as conceivable that selection by elimination should have resulted in the survival of the weakest, which would be the fittest for a world constructed on the principle of degeneration rather than progress. Or the world might have been constructed on the principle of the kaleidoscope, so that there would be change but neither permanent degeneration nor progress. If the world is not the product of an infinite mind, but of chance, or U it were the product of a mind bent merely on doing something, no mat ter what, we should expect a kaleidoscope world. The fact that the world tends ever toward progress is the strongest argument for design. Such a scheme is worthy the great designer. So, then, the fact that the eye, which probably began, as scientists teU us with a layer of pigment, changed for the better by the elimination of those features which were less perfect, shows, not that there was no designer, but that he proceeded by a process which must commend itseU to aU who believe in perfection. Furthermore, natural selection works not constructively, but de- Naturai seiec- structively. It does not produce variations, but it is sim- destructive- ply the process of eUminating the unfit. The question is structively. stiU open, how or why the variations appear, and why they tend toward the perfection of the structure. Even if evolution could trace the method, the how, it could not determine whether there was a purpose, a why. That is a matter of judgment with -which Inadequacy of the Process of Natural Selection. 429 science, as such, has nothing to do. Above aU it would be very false reasoning were we to assume, as do those who argue against design from the fact of evolution, that because we can trace the how there is no why. In human affairs we believe in design all the more where a method is apparent. Where method is wanting we suspect madness. In fact, Romanes admits that when we consider the broad area of nature as a whole the argument acquires a weight which, if long and attentively considered, deserves to be regarded as enormous. He says : ' "How is it that aU physical causes conspire, by their united action, to the production of a general order of nature ? It is against aU analogy to suppose that such an end as this can be accomplished, by such means as those, in the way of mere chance or ' the fortuitous concourse of atoms.' We are led by the most fundamental dictates of our reason to conclude that there must be some cause for this coopera tion of causes." So, then, Romanes after all does believe in the argu ment from design, though basing it, not on specific instances of design, but on nature as a whole. But nature as a whole is just the sum total of these specific instances. If the whole is designed the parts are at least so far designed that they work in harmony, or else we should have a chaos and not a cosmos. Anyone not blinded by the sight of second causes to the perception that the law of causation demands a first cause must believe in design when he considers the marvels of the physical world, especially as they appear in the vegetable and animal kingdoms. We advise any one who thinks that these things can be accounted for without the hypothesis of a superintending mind to read such a work as Darwin's Insectivorous Plants, ' and then consider the foUowing points : If we suppose the wonderful organs by which the Sun-dew catches and devours insects which light upon it to operate mechanicaUy, or even instinctively, we have stiU to account for the organs themselves. Natural selection, or adaptation, attempts to say that these organs re sult from the necessity of caring for the hfe in question ; its preserva tion, its nourishment or perhaps pleasure, and its propagation. But who felt the necessity ? the Ufe in question, or a Being who watches over aU life ? Or, if We say that here and there an animal Four points to or plant varied from its original to the possession of an ed. organ or a device adapted to any of the above ends, and that by the union of that animal or plant with another which had varied in the same way a variety was propagated, what have we to suppose ? 1 Thoughts on Religion, p. 67 f. a With Illustrations, New York, 1886. 430 Foundations of the Christian Faith. 1. The accident of the same variation in at least two plants or ani mals. 2. The accident of their finding one another. 3. The accident that their peculiar organ or device was inherited by their offspring, which, considering the known laws of heredity, is highly improbable. 4. Or, if not 2 and 3, then the accident that there was a considerable number which varied in the same way, so as to make 2 and 3 more probable, in which case we have the variety already established to account for the variety itself. So that, in fact, we have a modifica tion of 1 into an accidental variety, instead of an accidental variation in occasional individuals. In fact, we are obliged to think of a natural tendency in things to develop as they do, in which case the tendency is to be accounted for ; or else of a power in environment which has a tendency to force in dividual life into conformity with itself, or into adaptation to itseU, in which case we have another tendency to be accounted for ; or else of a union of both, in which case we have to account for the harmonious working of these two independent tendencies. We are shut up to materiaUsm, with its doctrine of chance as to the origin of aU these wonders, or else we must adopt some form of the doctrine of God.1 The doctrine of natural selection cannot be stated except hi terms of teleology. The necessity for the preservation, nourishment, and prop- impossibii- agation of species of Ufe is itseU teleological. Note, for tne°aoctfine example, the following, taken from a firm beUever in the se /e^Yon doctrine of natural selection : ' " The highest point in this terms Por te- respect is that attained by those seeds which are covered leoiogy. with edible fruit. By their being eaten by animals they receive the widest dispersion. In order that this purpose may be achieved the more perfectly they clothe themselves in a variety of colors and assume a pleasing odor." The very quality of natural selection is that it provides for a definite result. If we are not to be- lie%'e in a purpose on the part of a creator we must believe the pur pose to be part of the whole system. In any event we are compehed to believe in purpose in the order of the world, and of something which has set that purpose. Human beings, as long as they remain true to the only principles upon which they can rightly reason, must believe that that purpose is the deposit of mind. 1 These considerations are Intended to answer all such theories as that of Huxley con cerning the evolution of a watch from a revolving barrel. Huxley, Lay Sermons, pp. 330, 331, cited by Fisher, The Grounds of Theistic and Christian Belief, p. 55 f. 3 Nordheim, Die Erfullung des Chrlstenthums, p. 66. Inadequacy of the Process of Natural Selection. 431 So then, as a source of the admittedly universal belief in God, the natural disposition to see design where there is the appearance of skill is justified. We believe in a God who made the world just as we be lieve in a man who made a watch. The argument for a mind behind the phenomena of the world is parallel with the argument for a mind behind human activity. There is, for human beings, as much reason for beUef in one as in the other. Unless we deny mind everywhere we must admit it as the cause of the world ; for there is more evidence of intelligence in nonhuman products about us than there is in the products of man's hand and brain. We consider the above arguments ample for the establishment of the existence of a creator of the world, and also of the inteUigence of the Creator. Of course they do not exhaust aU possible reasons upon which the belief is based ; but we have not proposed to ourselves an exhaustive, but rather a conclusive, treatment of the subject. Never theless, we find in Professor Bowne's Phflosophy of Theism some re marks which, because of their cogency, we are constrained Citation from D "" Professor to add : ' ' The oversight referred to is the failure to see that Bowne. man and mind are a part and outcome of the universe. The speculator, in curious seU-forgetfulness, fixes his thought on the physical system and ignores himseU. He assumes a monopoly of intellect in the uni verse and forgets that his rare and lonely endowment must still have its roots in the universe. The problem then arises how to deduce the conscious from the unconscious, the inteUigent from the nonintelU gent, the purposive from the nonpurposive, and freedom from neces sity. But psychology shows the hopelessness of such a task. This insight has led to the modern device of a double-faced substance which, whfle stopping short of affirming an independent creative intelligence, does still insist upon intelligence as one of the original factors of the world-ground. . . . But if, on the other hand, we stfll insist on regard ing the world-ground as mechanical, then we reach the same conclu sion by a different road. For if everything is to be mechanically explained then human life, thought, and action must be phases of the aU-embracing necessity. But man can form purposes and determine himseU accordingly. Hence it foUows that in the department of human life, at least, the cosmic mechanism does form purposes and execute them. Here design actually appears as real and controlling. . . . But if it act purposely in the human realm there is no theoretical objection to admitting that it acts purposely in the physical realm U the facts call for it. The only escape from this conclusion is to deny our consciousness that purpose rules at all in our mental life. But as 432 Foundations of the Christian Faith. long as this is allowed the so-caUed cosmic mechanism must be viewed as one which can form plans and determine itseU for their execution ; that is, it must be what we mean by mind." ' "The same argument which discredits mind in nature throws equal doubt upon mind in man. But further reflection shows that U there be no controUing mind in nature there can be no controUing mind in man. For U the basal power is blind and necessary, aU that depends upon it is necessitated also. In that case aU unfolding is driven from behind, and nothing is led from before. Thought and feehng also come within this necessary unfolding. As such they are products, not causes. The basal necessity controls them in every respect, yet without being in any sense determined by them. Thought as thought counts for nothing. . . . Hence any fancy of seU-control we may have must be dismissed as delusive. Human Ufe and history, then, express no mind or purpose, but only the process of the aU-embracing necessity. . . . They (thought and purpose) must be put outside of the dynamic sequence of events, and be made a kind of halo which, as a shadow, attends without affecting the cosmic movement." ' With one more thought we close the discussion of the existence of God. When we consider the general fact that the universe is knowa ble by us, that we reproduce it in thought and formulate the laws of its activities, that consequently there is, as far as we can affix any test, an exact correspondence, even to the minutest particular, between the laws of mental activity and those of nature's processes, the argu ment for an infinite mind as the Creator of the universe seems conclu sive. Given such a mind, we can explain the fact that nature is intel ligible to us • apart from it that fact is, to say the least, inexpUcable. 1 Pages 99-101. * Ibid., p. 107 f. Comp. also Paul Christ's Die sittliche Weltordnung, Leiden, 1894, pp. 132-153. The Personality of God Ascertainable. 433 SECTION II.-THE PERSONALITY OF GOD.1 CHAPTER I. THE PERSONALITY OF GOD ASCERTAINABLE. While fully recognizing that the foregoing reasons for belief in the existence of God do not logically carry with them his unity also, it wfll probably be unnecessary to construct here an argu- Tjnity 0{ Go(j ment for that unity. In effect it is conceded to-day by conoeded- all leading schools of thought that if there be anything corresponding to our idea of God he must be unitary and not plural. That is, the world is a unit, and U it had a creator he must be one, and not many. The agnostics, as far as they allow themselves to speak of a God freely admit this ; as also the deists and the pantheists or monists. Monism is, indeed, not very consistent in its utterances on the subject, though its adherents mean to say that God is one as well as aU. This practically universal concession renders argument in its favor unnec essary, unless for the mere purpose of completeness in logical develop ment. Such completeness would be demanded in a work on theism, but, as it can perform no useful function, may be omitted from a work on Christian Evidences. Nor do we consider ourselves bound formally to defend the trinity in unity. This is to be left, together with much other matter belong ing to systematic theology, for which this work is not designed as a substitute, to the realm of polemics. Here it will suffice Trinity left to to say that, so far from being irrational, the doctrine of theology. the trinity (plurality) seems to be necessary to any proper conception of God as related to the world and man. The notion that trinity and unity in God are contradictory ideas arises from the crude concep tion of God under forms of substance. Any purely spiritual concep tion of God admits the idea of plurality in unity.' With the utmost frankness we admit the probable inadequacy of the formulae we employ to express the entire range of the facts con cerning God. The infinity of God may be apprehended as fact, but no ' The reader will find a strong and enjoyable treatment of this subject in Dr. G. A. Fricke's Ist Gott persenlich? Leipzig, 1896. 2 The argument for the Trinity is well presented in Orr's Christian View of the World Lect. vii. See also Loot's Das Apostolikum, Halle a. S., 1895, pp. 37-39. 434 Foundations of the Christian Faith. finite being would be bold enough to assert that he comprehended the infinite. The limitations of human faculty must be conceded, and the scriptural affirmation that we know but in part sustained. Even Our knowledge the revelation of God in Jesus Christ was such as adapted tiai. itself to our human incapacity. It did not give us the whole knowledge of God — U for no other reason, because we are in capable of receiving it. So that when we say that God is a person we may have the best of reasons for making the assertion, yet we cannot be at all sure that in declaring the personaUty of God we exhaust the entire fact concerning his nature. He is personal, that is, he has the attributes necessary to personality in human beings, but he may be more than personal. What lies beyond the range of our comprehen sion we do not know, and it is futile to conjecture. But, whfle we thus concede the symbolic character of our credal declarations rela tive to God, we claim that this does not invaUdate what knowledge we do possess. Though but in part, we know.1 A further caution must be suggested. When we speak of the per sonality of God we do not signUy thereby any kind of form, corporeal or other. The attributes which in man are supposed to constitute him a person are self -consciousness and seU-direction, or freedom. Rob him of these and he is a thing. SeU-consciousness pertains, not to the physical being and form, but to the unitary subject of the mental lUe which, because it is not material, cannot be thought of as having any of the attributes of matter. So also freedom is not predicated of the body. The physical man may be hindered from the exercise of any freedom of movement while at the same time the spirit feels itseU as free as ever. Self -direction, therefore, whfle etymologicaUy indica tive of the physical, is a purely spiritual attribute. Matter has, and can have, no power of self -direction. Hence it is plain that by per sonaUty, even in man, we do not refer to the physical but to the spirit ual nature. Whether there are good grounds for asserting of God self -consciousness and freedom wiU appear as the dicussion proceeds. We take up first the principal reasons which have stood in the way of belief in God's personality. It is said that, even if God be personal, we cannot know it. This is made out by conceiving of God as the absolute or the infinite, which Treatment of it is declared we cannot positively conceive. " On the the first ob- . J stacie to be- one hand we can conceive neither an absolute whole, lief in God's , ' personality, that is, a whole so great that we cannot also conceive it as a relative part of a still greater whole ; nor an absolute part, that 1 Comp. Herbert's Realistic Assumptions of Modern Science Examined, London, 1879. The Personality of God Ascertainable. 435 is, a part so small that we caimot conceive it as a relative whole divis ible into smaller parts. On the other hand, we cannot positively repre sent, or realize, or construe to the mind (as here understanding and imagination coincide), an infinite whole, for this could only be done by the infinite synthesis in thought of finite wholes, which would itself require infinite time for its accompUshment ; nor, for the same reason, can we follow out in thought an infinite divisibility of parts." . . . " The absolute is conceived merely by a negation of conceivabfl- ity." ¦ The argument appears at first sight to be conclusive. There is no way by which we can conceive an absolute or an infinite whole. Hence our conception of such a whole must be a negation of conceiva- bility. But, if we cannot make the infinite and the absolute a distinct object of thought, how can we attribute to it personality ? Clear as this argument appears it is exceedingly fallacious. All that HamUton says of absolute and infinite wholes is true. But God is not thus to be thought of under physical conditions. By the Christian hypothesis God is a spirit, and does not fill space as though he were material. AU apparent contradictions of this conception Fallacy of of God in the Bible are mere attempts to aid the mind in re asorang getting a vivid idea of his omnipresence. And such con- pointedout. descensions are needful, even in our present stage of inteUectual de velopment, since the vast majority of mankind are incapable of gain ing a purely spiritual conception of God or the human soul. When we remember that God as spirit has no space-filling quality— that he cannot be thought of under terms of number and quantity — all Ham ilton's talk about syntheses of wholes demanding infinite time for their accomplishment is seen to be irrelevant to the question of the con- ceivability of the infinity of God.' Hence the terms absolute and infi nite as applied to God are not the expressions of the negation of con- ceivability, but of a conceivable though not a comprehensible positive reality. Such a God is not unknowable because of his infinity and absoluteness, and hence he can be an object of thought of which we can affirm self -consciousness and freedom. Before leaving this point we wish to give Mr. Herbert-Spencer's crit icism of the position of Hamilton, a position adopted by Mansel. Says Mr. Spencer:3 "In the very denial of our power to learn what the Absolute is there Ues the hidden assumption that it is ; and the mak- 1 Sir William Hamilton, Philosophy of the Unconditioned, in his Discussions on Philos ophy and Literature, New York, 1868, p. 21. aComp. J. H. Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought, the Donnellan Lec tures for 1888-89, London, 1891, p. 274 n. s First Principles, p. 88 f. 436 Foundations of the Christian Faith. ing of this assumption proves that the Absolute has been present to the mind, not as a nothing, but as a something. Similarly with every Spencer's critl- steP m tne reasoning by which this doctrine is upheld. fiton's' ^osi- Tne Noumenon, everywhere named as the antithesis of tlon- the Phenomenon, is throughout necessarily thought of as an actuality. It is rigorously impossible to conceive that our knowl edge is a knowledge of Appearances only, without at the same time conceiving a ReaUty of which they are appearances ; for appearance without reality is unthinkable. Strike out from the argument the terms Unconditioned, Infinite, Absolute, with their equivalents, and in place of them write, 'negation of conceivabflity,' or 'absence of the conditions under which consciousness is possible,' and you find that the argument becomes nonsense. Truly to realize in thought any one of the propositions of which the argument consists, the Uncon ditioned must be represented as positive, not negative. How then can it be a legitimate conclusion, from the argument, that our conscious ness of it is negative ? An argument, the very construction of which assigns to a certain term a certain meaning, but which ends in show ing that this term has no such meaning, is simply an elaborate suicide. Clearly, then, the very demonstration that a definite consciousness of the Absolute is impossible to us unavoidably presupposes an indefinite consciousness of it." Spencer's argument, as far as it attempts to show that we must think of the unconditioned, the absolute, the infinite, as positive, not negative, is valid. But there is nothing in his argument to show that this positive conception must be indefinite rather than definite. In fact, that which can appear in consciousness at aU cannot be whoUy indefinite. Every concept which has reaUty behind it is given by the qualities of the supposed reality as they appear in consciousness ; and were these not in some sense definite there could be no concept. The positive, therefore, must be more or less definite. Mr. Spencer was concerned to prove that there is a positive somewhat, and he gives an elaborate and powerful argument in favor of that proposition. The principal fault we find with his proposition is that it unnecessarily asserts that whfle we know that something is we cannot construe its nature in any degree. In this respect, as our criticism of his agnos ticism shows, his conclusion is unwarranted. Thus far we have found nothing to forbid our believing that God is personal. False Assumptions of Denial. 437 CHAPTER II. FALSE ASSUMPTIONS OF DENIAL. A second difficulty which has stood in the way of beUef in the per sonality of God is strongly stated by Mansel,1 though for the purpose of exhibiting, not the unreliability of our belief in per- Mansel and sonality, but the unreliability of the arguments of natural obstacle. theology in its support. It consists in the aUeged mutual contradictions which arise in connection with the terms First Cause, Absolute and Infinite. "By the First Cause is meant that which produces all things and is itself produced by none. By the Absolute is meant that which exists in and by itself, having no necessary relation to any other Being. By the Infinite is meant that which is free from all possible Umitation; that than which a greater is inconceivable, and which, consequently, can receive no additional attribute or mode of existence which it had not from aU eternity.'' " The metaphysical representa tion of the Deity as absolute and infinite must necessarily, as the profqundest metaphysicians have acknowledged, amount to nothing less than the sum of all reality. ' What kind of an Absolute Being is that,' says Hegel, ' which does not contain in itself aU that is actual, even evU included ? ' We may repudiate the conclusion with indig nation, but the reasoning is unassailable. If the Absolute and Infinite is an object of human conception at all, this, and none other, is the con ception required." There is more of this same kind, but we forbear. Up to this point the argument of Mansel is invalidated by the material conception of the absolute and infinite which he had in mind as he wrote. This is betrayed in the use of terms indicative of number and quantity. He speaks about the sum of all reality, and quotes ap provingly Hegel's language about an absolute being which can con tain all that is actual. We have before pointed out that God cannot be thought of under such terms as these, and hence any criticism of our knowledge of God which proceeds according to them is valueless, and may be ignored. Proceeding now, Mansel says : " A. Cause cannot as such be abso lute ; the Absolute cannot, as such, be a cause. On the other hand, the conception of the Absolute implies a possible existence out of all 1 Limits of Religious Thought, Boston, 1860, pp 75 ff. 30 438 Foundations of the Christian Faith. relation. We attempt to escape from this apparent contradiction by introducing the idea of succession in time. The Absolute exists first by itseU, and afterward becomes a Cause. But here we are checked by the third conception, that of the Infinite. How can the Infinite become that which it was not from the first ? If causation is a possi ble mode of existence that which exists without causing is not infinite ; that which becomes a cause has passed beyond its former limits." If aU these contradictions in our notions of God as First Cause, Absolute and Infinite, are real, we are forced into a dilemma. Either we must admit our inability to think of God consistently, or else we must yield these conceptions of God as invahd. As a matter of fact Mansel plunges us into these contradictions only by so defining the terms that they necessarily lead us to his results. We question the Mansel's er- correctness and adequacy of his definitions. The term initfonSdeof First Casue need not mean that the Being so designated terms. was a cause DUt 0nce ; it may designate him in whom aU things have their ground ; him without whom nothing would have been as it is, not even himself. The absolute need not be conceived as re stricted, but it may be defined as unrestricted ; so also the infinite. It is erroneous, in deaUng with God, to think of him under forms of mate rial existence. Remove the idea of space from the conception of spirit and God can be conceived as the ground— First Cause — of aU things, even of matter. The words cause, absolute, infinite, have an entirely different significance when appUed to matter from that conveyed when the same words are apphed to spirit. In this realm absolute need not mean unrelated ; infinite need not mean that which admits of no other mode of existence ; causation need not mean conjunction in time and space ; and when the terms are used understandingly of God they do not mean the things just mentioned. Should anyone ask what they do signUy we reply that they are to be understood as the nature of spirit demands. He who wfll get a proper concep tion of spirit, or one freed from the notions of number and quantity wfll be able to discover the true application of the terms in ques tion to God. Until one has such a conception of spirit he will think of these terms quantitively and materially, no matter how carefully they are defined. In fact, even the whole conception of matter is crude and inaccurate with the vast majority. What it is we do not know, and yet we are ready to take it as the measure of aU thought. If matter were thought of as an activity of God, not capable of fur ther definition, aU such arguments as Mansel's would be impossible. False Assumptions of Denial. 439 Thus again we see no sufficient reason for aUowing that our knowledge of God is so bound up in contradictions that the ascrip tion of personaUty to him is unfounded. Hold with the theist that the relations of the infinite to the finite are seU-imposed, not necessary, and aU Mansel's formidable array of contradictions would vanish. The two foregoing difficulties in the way of beUef in the personaUty of God were founded on our aUeged inabiUty to know him sufficiently to assert that he is personal. Mansel has, however, gone further, and by an analysis of the conditions of human conscious- The thira 0D_ ness, which is the only consciousness we know anything : u' !l about, asserts that to attribute consciousness to God is to contradict aU we are obUged to hold concerning him. And as consciousness is essential in personaUty we have no foundation upon which to build the doctrine in question. Strangely enough, Mansel, after arguing against the allowability in thought of regarding God as personal, stfll asserts that it is our duty so to regard him.1 Upon what ground, then, does he assert that we are forbidden to attribute consciousness to God? First, consciousness impUes distinction between one object and another. " To be conscious we must be conscious of something; and that something can only be known as that which it is, by being dis tinguished from that which it is not. But distinction is necessarily limitation ; for, U one object is to be distinguished from another, it must possess some form of existence which the other has not, or it must not possess some form which the other has. But it is obvious that the Infinite cannot be distinguished, as such, from the Finite by the absence of any quality which the Finite possesses, for such absence would be a limitation. Nor yet can it be distinguished by the presence of an attribute which the Finite has not ; for, as no finite part can be a constituent of an infinite whole, this differential characteristic must itself be infinite, and must at the same time have nothing in common with the finite. We are thus thrown back upon our former impossibility, for this second infinite will be distinguished from the finite by the absence of qualities which the latter possesses. A con sciousness of the Infinite, as such, thus necessarily involves a self- contradiction." ' It is somewhat difficult to apprehend clearly all the elements in this supposed argument. In this difficulty lies its strength. As one be comes able to analyze it, and thus subject it to detailed examination, ' Limits of Religious Thought, p. 106. J Ibid., p. 93 f. 440 Foundations of the Christian Faith. its weakness is discovered. The first criticism we offer against Mansel is that in the language we have cited he has not so much demonstrated our incapacity to think of God as conscious as he has the impossibility of the coexistence of the finite and infinite. We can think of the infinite and the finite as existing together, but U he has proved anything it is that when we so think we are in error. We ask the reader to go back over Mansel's words and verify this statement for himseU. But any proof that there cannot be a finite lands us in pantheism, which is also, as we have seen, to be rejected. Hence we must regard his argument as nugatory. The second criti cism caUs attention once more to his material way of thinking of the The denial is infinite as made up of parts and consisting of a whole. based on a _. . . . material Given an infinite not defined and conceived in terms of conception . , , . ... of God. number and quantity, and his argument faUs to the ground. The third criticism is that the argument has no bearing whatever on the question of possible consciousness in God. The fourth is that, strictly speaking, we are not conscious of anything ob jective to our own mental states. There is a clear distinction between being aware of the presence of an object and being conscious of an ob ject. I can be conscious of an object, not directly, but only as I have the object in thought. So I may be aware of the existence of God and conscious that he is an object of my thought. When I am aware of the infinite I do not in any sense limit that infinite ; though when I make it an object of thought I limit it. We are not quite sure that Mansel intended the argument we have just criticised as a proof that we cannot attribute consciousness to God. If he did so intend we see that he fafled. If he did not so intend it is impossible to discover what he wished to accomplish. But the second point made by him which we shall mention leaves no room for doubt. " Consciousness is only conceivable as a relation. There must be a conscious subject and an object of which he is conscious. . . . This difficulty, again, may be for the moment evaded by distinguish ing between the absolute as related to another and the absolute as related to itself. The Absolute, it may be said, may possibly be con scious, provided it is only conscious of itself. But this alternative is, in ultimate analysis, no less self -destructive than the other. For the object of consciousness, whether a mode of the subject's existence or not, is either created in and by the act of consciousness or has an existence independent of it. In the former case the object depends upon the subject, and the subject alone is the true absolute. In the latter case the subject depends upon the object, and the latter alone False Assumptions of Denial. 441 is the true absolute. Or, if we attempt a third hypothesis, and main tain that each exists independently of the other, we have no absolute at all, but only a pair of relatives ; for coexistence, whether in con- consciousness or not, is itself a relation."1 We have quoted him at length, but the point is whether the Abso lute may be conscious provided he is conscious only of himseU. For U he is the Creator there was a time when creation was not ; and when, therefore, seU-consciousness could not have arisen or existed in God by reason of the relation of subject and object.' Can self, then, be an object of consciousness ? The Christian doctrine of the Trinity answers in the affirmative. If God be a spirit we get an affirmative answer from this fact also. For a spirit must think by its very Bearing of nature. If it be a free spirit it chooses its thoughts, ofthe Trinity These thoughts are not "created in and by the act of tion. consciousness," but the thinker thinks them. They are not created at aU. They have no existence in the sense in which the thinker exists. They have no true objective reality. Therefore they do not Umit the thinker; rather does the thinker limit the thought. Yet, as having these thoughts, the thinker is conscious. As for self -consciousness, or the consciousness of selfhood, it arises in man by contact with the objects external to him; but once it is awak ened it does not need those external objects for its perpetuation. As we cannot suppose that the vicissitudes of the human mind are in all respects a counterpart of those of the divine we are not at hberty to assume that self -consciousness in God could arise only in connec tion with external objects. Whfle it is perfectly conceivable that God's self -consciousness might need awakening it may have been always existent. Thus from the nature of consciousness and seU- consciousness in men no vaUd argument against the same in God can be drawn. 1 Limits of Rehgious Thought., pp. 77, 78. 2 Herbert Spencer puts the difficulty in this way in an essay on " Religion : a Retrospect and a Prospect," found in The Insuppressible Book—; a Controversy between Herbert Spencer and Frederick Harrison, Boston, 1885, p. 14. 442 Foundations of the Christian Faith. CHAPTER III. ERRONEOUS CONCEPTIONS OF PERSONALITY — THE THEORIES OF SCHOP ENHAUER AND VON HARTMANN. But Mansel goes stfll further and denies our right, in thought, to regard God as personal. He says : " Personality, as we conceive it, is Mansel's d e - essentially a Umitation and a relation. Our own person- r i'gVtf, Tn ality is presented to us as relative and limited ; and it is regard 'God from that presentation that aU our representative notions as personal. Qj personaiity are derived." l Now, admitting the truth of the last sentence, is the first one true? We think not. Person ality is not essentially a Umitation and a relation. Our personality is not presented to us as relative and limited. We do not, nor do the facts demand that we should, think of personaUty under any form of relation or limitation. When I think of my relations to others I am reminded of the fact that I am not the only being ; but there is noth ing in my conception of personaUty to suggest the thought. It arises solely by experience, and subsequent to the concept of myself as per sonal. So my sense of being related springs from contact with others. It is not given in the idea of personality, nor is there any thing in that idea to suggest it. Only by taking my physical form for my person could I entertain the thought that I am essentiaUy related or limited. As for spirits, they cannot be mutually exclusive of each other in any sense in which we know the term. They can be occupied by the same thought without the necessity of josthng one another. Hence, though spirit may know itseU in relations, it cannot know or think of itself as limited by those with whom it is related, nor by anything else which has objective reality. Even our sense of Umitation as to possible mental achievement is accidental. We do not consider it an essential of mind or personality, but only of our finiteness. Nor are we sure, by any process of thought which we can project, that we are not infinite in our capacity rather than finite. On the contrary, there are some facts to suggest that we are infinite in possibility and Umited only in realization.' Very far, then, from the essential notion of per- 1 Limits of Religious Thought, p. 102. ' For Instance, the fact that the limitations of our mental powers are being constantly broken down. Erroneous Conceptions of Personality. 443 sonaUty is the idea that the person is of necessity either related or Umited. With the f oUowing overwhelming language Professor Bowne turns on those who assert that personaUty is a relation and a limitation : ' "OnaU these accounts we regard the objections to the professor personality of the world-ground (God) as resting on a theTib'jec- very superficial psychology. So far as they are not ver- peTsonaf- bal they arise from taking the limitations of human con- 1 y sciousness as essential to consciousness in general. In fact, we must reverse the common speculative dogma on this point, and declare that proper personaUty is possible only to the Absolute. The very objec tions urged against the personaUty of the Absolute show the incom pleteness of human personality. Thus it is said, truly enough, that we are conditioned by something not ourselves. The outer world is an important factor in our mental life. It controls us far more than we do it. But this is a limitation of our personaUty rather than its source. Our personality would be heightened rather than diminished U we were self -determinant in this respect. Again, in our inner Ufe we find similar limitations. We cannot always control our ideas. They often seem to be occurrences in us rather than our own doing. The past vanishes beyond recaU; and often in the present we are more passive than active. But these, also, are limitations of our per sonality. We should be much more truly persons U we were abso lutely determinant of all our states. But we have seen that aU finite things have the ground of their existence, not in themselves, but in the Infinite, and that they owe their peculiar nature to their mutual relations and to the plan of the whole. Hence, in the finite con sciousness, there will always be a foreign element, an external com pulsion, a passivity as weU as activity, a dependence on something not ourselves, and a corresponding subjection. Hence in us per sonality will always be incomplete. The absolute knowledge and seU-possession which are necessary to perfect personality can be found only in the absolute and infinite being upon whom aU things depend." The preceding discussion sufficiently disposes of the objections to belief in divine personality drawn from the doctrine that self -con sciousness and personality are impossible in God, contradictory of the idea of the infinite, and the like. There is, however, a phase of the subject, springing from the philosophy of Schopenhauer and von Hartmann, which demands treatment. 1 Philosophy of Theism, pp. 132-134. 444 Foundations of the Christian Faith. According to Schopenhauer the true nature of things is wfll, uncon scious or blind effort or impulse. This impulse is seen in everything — The positions in the polyp as weU as in man, and even in the inorganic hauer and world. This wUl is all present in every aspect of the uni- mann. verse. The only distinction observable is in what is willed. In the world wUl is prior to intelligence, and hence, though working out intelligent results, pursues its purposes blindly, some what as instinct is supposed to do. Nevertheless, Schopenhauer talks about ends in creation, and about motives, as though this bUnd wfll really knew what it would achieve. He says: " On closely regarding final causation in nature we must not shrink, in expressing its tran scendent essence, from boldly saying, the end is a motive, operating on a being that knows it not. For assuredly .the nests of the Ameri can ant supply the operative motive which has produced the ant- eater's toothless jaw with its long, threadhke, clammy tongue ; the hard shell which imprisons the chick is the motive for the horny tip with which its beak is furnished in order to break through ; after which it is cast off as of no further use. And, in like manner, the laws of reflection and refraction of Ught supply the motive for that extremely complex optical instrument the human eye. . . . But these motives operated before they were apprehended ; so it is, however contradictory it may sound." ] Martineau cites this language, and shows the nonsensical character of this feature of Schopenhauer's phflosophy by the foUowing comment : iur„ ?• „„ ,»= " This contradiction, namely, that a cause can propose to JVL n i 1 1 n 6 fll i 8 criticism. itself an end, and realize it by adapted means, without knowing either end or means — that a future which sleeps unsuspected in the dark can act before it exists, and make preparations for its birth — was too strong for Hartmann, who insists that it is impossi ble to wfll without wflling something, be it this or be it that ; that, tfll there is a determinate object presented, the wiU is a blank, and with out the conditions of action or change ; and that, as it always involves a transition from a present condition to another, it is attended by two representations, namely, of the state immediately felt, and of the state to be realized in its place. Thus, then, the mental element is restored to the will, which is no longer left in the dark, but able to fix its eye on what it wants." We let Martineau complete the statement of Hartmann's view : " Does the will in nature, then, know what it would 1 Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, vol. II, Kap. xxvi, p. 379, cited by Martineau, A Study of Religion, vol. I, p. 267 f. On the metaphysics of von Hartmann, see also Ebrard's Apologetics, vol. il, pp. 116-124. Erroneous Conceptions of Personality. 445 be at ? Does it design and plan and realize preconceived intentions ? Nothing can be further from Hartmann's meaning ; and when he seems on the verge of this admission he flies off from it by an unsus pected turn ; there is indeed a mental representation in the instinc tive wfll, but it is an unconscious one; it Uves in the creature, it directs the organism, it inspires the movement with regulated system, but remains unrecognized and hid." 2 These doctrines may be criticised from two standpoints : (1) as to their own intrinsic absurdity, and (2) as to their relation to the effect upon human freedom and thought. (1) There is but httle difference, in fact, between the position of Schopenhauer and that of Hartmann. In the former the will is blind ; it has no notion of what it is doing, and yet it works to- intrinsic ab- _ surdity of ward ends and is prompted by motives in the shape ot their views. ends to be achieved. In the latter wfll knows what it will accom plish ; it is inteUigent, and yet it is unconscious. It might be denom inated unconscious intelligence, but the term "unconscious intelli gence " is merely an attempt to join two mutually contradictory ideas; for when we are unconscious we are not intelligent. All actions per formed unconsciously are wanting in the very quality of intelligence. From the human standpoint, therefore, nothing can be more obviously erroneous than the theories of the universe proposed by Schopenhauer and Hartmann. We know something of blind impulses which, we may tautologically say, know nothing of what they are about. But we clearly distinguish between these impulses and our wills, which know what they propose. Impulse is blind; wfll is clear sighted. Just because the former works blindly it cannot have a motive, which of necessity implies more or less of intelligence. Impulse achieves, but, left to itself, it is prone to achieve that which intelligence would forbid. But impulse can be subjected to inteUigent control. It can be checked where its results are held to be undesirable ; it can be directed where they are desirable and made the servant of intelligence. In so far, therefore, as we acknowledge the presence of the alleged impulse which resides in all things, and which accomplishes ends approvable by sound judgment, we must suppose, not that it is controlled by mo tives, but that it is subjugated to the wfll of a higher inteUigence, which, working like ours, like ours also controls the impulses which are in the world. (2) But from another standpoint, also, the theories in question are open to criticism. If there is no conscious inteUigence in the world, > A Study of Religion, vol. 1, p. 268 f . 446 Foundations of the Christian Faith. excepting, perhaps, in man, then there is, after aU, no freedom either of choice or of thought hi man. We are reduced to the position Their denial of conscious automata. We are in a condition where of freedom. QUr bought has no bearing upon the outcome of things. And as our thought is thus rendered useless so we are not responsi ble for our choices. The contradiction between these consequences of robbing the world of a presiding conscious inteUigence and what our own consciousness reveals to us is so great, and the conviction that what our consciousness reveals is correct is so powerful, that the sub stitution of unconscious inteUigence must be forbidden. Apart from inteUigence there is no freedom and no wfll, but only blind force. And even this is a mere abstraction from observed activities which we must ultimately refer to a self-conscious intelligence as their ground. We may conclude, therefore, that God is free aud intelUgent, seU- conscious, and seU-directive, and, hence, personal. The Argument for Personality. 447 CHAPTER IV. THE ARGUMENT FOR PERSONALITY. Repeatedly, during the foregoing discussions, have we pointed out that we naturaUy and inevitably think of God as having the attri butes which go to make up personaUty as known to us. Nor by ' ' we " do we mean theists only. For aU men, in those moments when they allow their real thought of God to assert itself, think of him as per sonal. Strauss's demand for reverence for his universe-God can mean nothing else. And those who most firmly adhere in theory to the doctrine that we cannot logicaUy attribute personality to God come around at last to the assertion that we are shut up to the belief in his personality as the better alternative. ¦ This inalienable beUef is worthy of profound respect. Along with the question of the existence of God goes that of his nature. We dare not, with pantheism, think of God and the world as identical, hence by no possibility can we think of him as material. But, as the only modes of being known to us are matter and spirit, if God is not ma terial he must be spiritual. And as the only spiritual being of whose existence we are immediately certain is personal it is nat- Naturalness ural to think of the infinite spirit as personal also. Thus in the per- may be explained in part the universality of the belief in God. God as spiritual and personal. Long before men were able to name the steps in the process by which they reached the conclusion the log ical understanding, which does not depend whoUy upon a knowledge of itself for its correct operation, had worked out the results which the most enlightened minds more intelligently attain to-day. But this is by no means the whole explanation of the naturalness and inevitableness of the belief in the personality of God. The argu ment from design for the existence of God is also an argument for the possession by him of those attributes which fill our idea of personaUty. A designer, whatever the method by which he executes his design, must possess the attributes of inteUigence and free volition. The par ticular method chosen for the accomplishment of his purposes may indicate the wisdom which distinguishes and measures his inteUi gence. So that from an illimitable display of wisdom we should be 1 For example, even Mansel himself. See Limits of Rehgious Thought, pp. 103-105. 448 Foundations of the Christian Faith. compelled to conclude an infinite intelligence, and hence an infinite personality. But for the disclosure of his personaUty we need only the evidence that he is intelligent and free. This the evidence from design supplies. In the physical world we see both adaptation and uniformity of method. The method is such as to result in adaptation among things existing at any one period of time, and yet to provide for progress from lower to higher, and from the simple to the com plex. Here is the sure mark both of inteUigence and free voUtion. Indeed, we can scarcely think of the former without the latter ; but, aside from this fact, the very existence of the actual world-order indi cates a purpose to establish such an order, and thus the rejection of a haphazard method of procedure. The choice of a method furnishes the proof of freedom. In a more or less conscious way these thoughts are inevitable to the human mind. And they help to account for the naturalness of man's belief in the personality of God, even in the earhest stages of human thought. But when the thought of man is enticed from the physical world about him and fixed for a time upon the world of human beings of which he is a part another cause begins to operate whose tendency, also, is to make him believe in personaUty in God. This cause is the perception of the fact that there is a moral order in the world. This moral order is, for our present purposes, nothing more nor less than a special instance of design. An indestructible element in the nature of man is his sense of moral obligation. This sense is twofold in each individual, pertaining primarily to the abstract question or duty of righteousness, and secondarily to the duty of maintaining proper rela tions to other human beings. Could I suppose myself the only human being on earth I should still have the feehng of obhgation to do right. Now, this is a part of the moral world-order. But another feature of the same is that in proportion as individual men give themselves up to this sense of moral obligation are they conscious at once of greater nobility and happiness ; and, at the same time, in proportion as com munities give themselves up to this sense of obligation do they pro gress in all that goes to make life worth living. Here, then, we have the same evidence of adaptation and method which is afforded by the physical world, and the moral world-order appears as designed, thus further accounting for the universaUty of belief in the personality of God, and helping us to see why that beUef is so natural, so apparently spontaneous, in man. ¦ ' Comp. Tyler's Bases of Religious Belief Historic and Ideal, New York and London, 1897, part II, chap. 2, and Frlcke, Ist Gott persOnllch, pp. 52-66. The Argument for Personality. 449 But it might be admitted that it is natural to man to think of God as personal, and that it is natural for the reason that aU the causes named conspire to compel, or at least to produce, that is the belief legitimate belief, yet it might be affirmed that it is not necessarily also? legitimate because it is natural ; in other words, that all the argu ments mentioned merely account for, but do not justify, the behef. The naturalness of the beUef being conceded the question of its legiti macy remains unsettled. In attempting to determine this question it must be remembered that we have gone over all the points involving objection either to the idea of the personaUty of God or to the validity of argu- justifiability ments heretofore adduced in this work in favor of that t a°n e oPuDs idea, and that in every instance the objections have been thinking. answered. This fact itseU legitimizes the belief. Our natural, spon taneous thinking must be rejected only where there are the best of reasons for so doing. Both spontaneous thought and spontaneous action have the right of indulgence unless there are good grounds for their repression. Were this not the case we should soon degenerate into artificial modes of thought and life. Those thoughts and those impulses which arise from the very constitution of our nature must be legitimate, though they may need restraint or guidance lest they become perverted by improper use. And if there is any test of such spontaneity as we have just described it is found in the fact of universality. That all men, or the overwhelming majority, think and feel in a certain way under the same circumstances proves that that way of thinking and feeling is natural. If, therefore, the natural be the legitimate, except in cases where there is good reason for repress ing the natural, the beUef in the personaUty of God must be legiti mate, since there is no good reason for rejecting it ; in other words, since it violates no principle of sound philosophy, science, moraUty, or religion. We might let our case rest here, secure in the feeling that for aU unprejudiced persons it is sufficiently strong. But, inasmuch as Christianity is rich in the reasons for the hope that is within its ad herents, we proceed to add some considerations confirmatory of our position. In the first place, U God is the ground of the world he must be personal because we are personal. This is not, like the facts men tioned in the first part of this chapter, a mere reason for thinking that he is personal. It is compulsory of behef. It is inconceivable that a God should be the ground of the world who is less than any of "the phenomena of which he is the ground. This would be to make 450 Foundations of the Christian Faith. the effect greater or more perfect than the cause. The only alterna tive would be to make God identical with the world, which is impos- Our personal- sible for a variety of reasons already given ; among oth- with it the ers, that man knows himself as personal and therefore as of God. not capable of being identified either with a nonpersonal world-god or with a personal God. The only possible conclusion is that, since man is personal, the world-ground must be personal ; that is, intelligent and self-directive.1 But, again, our religious natures demand a personal God for their gratification and development. Just as our moral natures are acknowl- Our religious edged to be legitimate so must our reUgious natures be. In- mand that deed, there are few to-day bold enough to deny this. The sonal.6 pel" only question which remains here is that which pertains to the form of the religion. Now, there is an inteUectual side to these religious natures of ours, which, as reUgious beings, we may not stul tify. Hence he who is conscious of his own personality cannot at tempt to enter into a truly religious relationship with an impersonal existence. Such an attempt would stamp one as inteUectuaUy un balanced. Not only in its inteUectual aspects, however, does the religious nature demand a personal God, but also in its moral and social aspects. There can be no true morality apart from a person, and hence it is that our moral natures look for their complement, as also for their source, to a personal God who is himself capable of the morahty he has made imperative in us. For this a mere moral world-order does not suffice. If the God who imposed this moral order upon the world is himself incapable of morality the imperative character of moraUty would be immediately and histinctively denied. The God of the moral world must be more than "a power not ourselves which makes for righteousness." What may be called the social relation between the soul and the object of its rehgious worship also demands that God should be personal. We can neither love, reverence, petition, nor commune with an impersonal God ; nor can we receive from such a God the love and care which a personal being needs for the sustenance of his religious life. The doctrine of an impersonal God, carried to its legitimate consequences, would land us in the conclusion that the re ligious nature in man is unmeaning, unworthy of respect and culture, and that its source, so far from being implanted within us by an intel ligent Creator, is bestowed upon us as the result of a blunder such as an impersonal God might be supposed to make, or else that in the l The same line of argument would suffice to demonstrate the moral nature of God. The Argument for Personality. 451 process of evolution there came out a being so constituted that one of the profoundest elements of his nature has no needful function to perform. But in another sense than that mentioned above the intellect de mands that God should be personal. It has been often noted that be tween the laws of the natural world and the laws of So also our in thought there is a correspondence which makes it possi- teliects. ble for us to understand the world. But we understand the world only as we employ the powers we possess in accordance with the laws of correct thinking. Did we violate these laws the world would be unintelligible. In the same way the attempt to attain an intelligible conception of God in the violation of the laws of human thought must always fail. All such attempts have led men into confusion. The utmost ingenuity of pantheists and agnostics has hitherto been un equal to the task of making clear to the human mind what kind of an intelligence that is which is not in some way united with personality. The words "impersonal intelligence " cannot be united in thought. Even that intelligence which is displayed'by animals requires us either to posit a brute personality or else to trace the intelUgence to the world-ground as personal. The only clear thought of an intelligent God is that of a personality ; and this is attained as soon as we f oUow, instead of violating, the laws of our minds.1 Closely connected with the foregoing is another consideration. The only possible way of accounting for the intelligibility of the world is the supposition that it is the product of intelligence. It is impossible for human beings to believe that a rational world should spring from a blind and nonintelUgent cause. This is due to the fact that among human beings the more inteUigent the producer of any- Parallel be- thing, whether in language or in mechanism, the more tive and hu- i ,.,,..,,, - , man intelli- profound, significant, and intelligible the product is, and gence. vice versa. The only exceptions to be noted are such as spring from the inherent difficulty of the subject treated ; and even here the dis cerning discover that, considering the obscurity of the subject, the treatment of it is remarkably simple. If an easy theme is treated in a confused or confusing way we are certain that the thinker is not himself clear or else that he purposely chose to confuse his readers. 1 A good illustration of the absurdity of the results obtained in the violation of the laws of mental action is found in Herbert Spencer's doctrine that God may be higher than personal, and that our inability to conceive of anything higher than personality, so far from being an argument against this higher-than-personal God, is an argument in its favor. That is, as we have before pointed out, it leads him to make the inconceivable the test of the real. See above, p. 95. 452 Foundations of the Christian Faith. But not only are we shut up to the thought of an inteUigent Creator by reason of the mteUigibflity of creation, we are also shut up to the thought that this intelligent Creator must be mteUectuaUy constituted on lines parallel to or identical with our mental nature. For, though we must admit that God's thoughts are higher than our thoughts as the heavens are higher than the earth, yet were his thoughts out of all analogy to ours we could not understand his wof ld. That we can understand it is indubitable evidence that we are created in the image of God, and hence that God is constituted, at least in some respects, like ourselves. It does not follow that U we knew aU about ourselves we should know aU about God, for we have no adequate opportunity of making the entire comparison. But that God's intelUgence is similar to our own is unquestionable. And with this foUows, as before pointed out, the doctrine of his personal nature. The Possibility of a Kevelation. 453 division vin. REVELATION. SECTION I.-THE NATURE AND FACT OF SUPERNATURAL REVE LATION. CHAPTER I. THE POSSIBILITY OF A REVELATION. In the introduction to this work revelation was considered as the impartation of truth by one person to another, and divine revelation as but one species of such communication. Ordinarily, however, when we speak of revelation in this division we have in mind divine or supernatural revelation. It is often said that the object of revelation is God himself.1 But this is not the whole fact. In the Christian revelation God does disclose himseU, but besides he re- God not tne veals man's true relations to God and to his feUow-men, Sf'reve^ia- and also human destiny. It is necessary to scan closely tl0U' the brief statement just made, for the reason that many either fail to give sufficient scope to what is actually revealed or else unduly extend the limits of the supposed revelation afforded us in the Christian Scrip tures. Multitudes mistake form for substance, method for result. When they open their New Testaments and read they And themselves in the midst of angelic appearances and are Uable to the error of sup posing that these and kindred miraculous phenomena are part of reve lation itself, whereas they are rather a part of the method which God employed ; or, U you please, accompaniments of God's communication of needful truth to mankind. So also, many seem to suppose that as far as revelation pertains to God it reveals aU truth concerning him. Nothing in the Old or New Testament warrants such a supposition. He is revealed as the object of our worship, love, and allegiance, but not as to his fuU nature. Even the revelation of God which we have in Christ is presumably not complete ; for the purpose of divine revelation is not theoretical or scientific knowledge even of God himself, but such a knowledge of 1 So Christlieb, Modern Doubt and Christian Belief, New York, 1874, p. 95. 31 454 Foundations of the Christian Faith. him as is necessary to the gratification of our reUgious natures and to our development in the ethical likeness of God. Revelation may be either incidental or purposed. We often reveal ourselves to observant minds when we least intend it. And it is not Revelation improper to beUeve that God has revealed himseU in both propositions of the ways mentioned. But even when God purposed to alone. reveal himself to men, and set about the accomplishment of that end, it is erroneous to suppose that he always put his revela tion into the form of propositions to be mastered by the intellect and that he employed no other method, or this method chiefly.1 Chris tians believe that God is love, not so much because that fact is dis tinctly stated in the New Testament as because he is represented as performing loving deeds. In Uke manner they beUeve in the awfulness of sin, not chiefly because it is declared to be "exceed ingly sinful," but because it is represented in Scripture as having received merited punishment. In other words, historical facts trace able to divine purpose are as available sources of a knowledge of God as definite propositions addressed to our understandings. The diffi culty which might arise in connection with a revelation through facts alone, however, is that it would be left to the faUible interpretation of the human mind to determine their significance. This difficulty is obviated in Christianity by the combination of the method by facts with that by distinct and definite propositions ; or at least by hints which are sufficient to give the observant reader the correct interpre tative clew. Thus it is that the entire Bible, its history, its precepts, and its foundations of reUgious truth constitute one complete whole which, directly or indirectly, completely or partiaUy, perfectly or imperf ectly, reveals to man those things which he ought to know. Strangely enough, it is still necessary to defend the possibility of a revelation, which is doubted by a variety of classes. These doubts center around the two parties to revelation — God and man. It is questioned whether God could reveal himseU and whether man could receive a revelation. God, says the first form of the objection in substance, is absolute, The allegation unrelated, and, as such, cannot reveal himseU. One can npttG°reveai make terms mean anything by depositing within them the significance we wish them to convey. But, unless we are wflling to go back to the deism of the preceding century, it is absurd 1 Comp. C. A. Row's Christian Evidences Viewed in Relation to Modern Thought, Third Edition, London, 1881, pp. 117 ff. ; andC. M. Mead's, Supernatural Revelation, New York, 1889, pp. 80, 84. The Possibility of a Revelation. 455 to speak of God as absolute and unrelated in such a sense that he can-- not reveal himself. For according to all believers in God he is the ground of the world, if not, as the pantheists think, identical with the world. Hence he is related to the world in some way by all who be lieve in him, the deists not excepted, although the latter place his relation to it in the past. When we come to the actual beliefs of those who hold any doctrine of divine existence — when we look away from their words and gather their real faith from their philosophies as a whole — we find nothing in their conception of God to forbid the possibility of his revealing himself. And, in fact, all believers in God do beUeve that he has revealed himself, at least in some degree, though not aU believe that the sacred books of the Christians or of the adherents of other religions contain the record of a special revelation. Their belief in God is founded upon what they take to be the works or manifestations of God. The very doctrines of the relation of God to the world which we find in the various philosophies show that their adherents see something of the nature of God in the world of which we form a part. What they question is, not that God has revealed himself in the world, but that he has ever purposely revealed himself. His works, as the works of any other, betray something of his thought and qualities ; and the principal dispute is as to the extent to which his works as known to us are adequate to a disclosure of his char acter. Among unbelievers in a special revelation there is also a divergence of opinion as to the degree of success men have achieved in reading the language of nature, and hence as to how we must think of God, and as to the accuracy of any inferences we may draw on that subject. But all these things are confessions of the unsatis- factoriness of natural theology rather than the denial of the possibil ity of any revelation whatever. As no doctrine of God implies any fundamental impossibility of his self -manifestation in and through the world, so there is nothing in any of these doctrines to militate against a special reve- Speciaireveia- lation to a single people. As a matter of fact, God is gie people. somewhat differently conceived by different races and tribes of un instructed men. And this is doubtless in some measure due to the particular aspect which nature presents to the observation of men in each general locality. Men must think of God anthropomorphically. And, as nature and man are so interrelated that the former in a good degree molds the latter, it follows that to each particular race of men God reveals himself, if at all, in a special manner and aspect. 456 Foundations of the Christian Faith. Nor is there any falsehood or injustice in this. Each tribe reads as much as possible of God from what its members discover within and without themselves. In any incidental revelation either of ourselves or of God the subjective element must be eliminated if the exact truth is to be ascertained. And no tribe or race of men is warranted in supposing that what they see of the works of God constitutes the whole of what he has done. The error, therefore, is the result of bad logic, not of God's self-manifestation throughout his works, and might have been avoided by greater thoughtfulness on man's part. In the same way there is no injustice in such special revelation unless it is unjust to afford a variety of soil, climate, fertility and products of the surface and bowels of the earth, and of topography and scenery, as well as of stellar grouping and the Uke. There is, then, no difficulty in the doctrine of supposing that God can and does reveal himself through his works, nor in the idea of a special revelation to each particular tribe or race; but for the doc trine of a purposed revelation only that idea of God which regards Doctrine of a ^m as Personal wm suffice. For it is one thing to reveal, languished an<* ** ^s