Courage

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Courage (also called bravery or valour) is the choice and willingness to confront agony, pain, danger, uncertainty, or intimidation. Physical courage is bravery in the face of physical pain, hardship, even death or threat of death, while moral courage is the ability to act rightly in the face of popular opposition,[1] shame, scandal, discouragement, or personal loss.

The classical virtue of fortitude (andreia, fortitudo) is also translated "courage", but includes the aspects of perseverance and patience.[2]

In the Western tradition, notable thoughts on courage have come from philosophers, Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, and Kierkegaard; as well as Christian beliefs and texts.

In the Hindu tradition, mythology has given many examples of bravery, valour and courage with examples of both physical and moral courage exemplified. According to the Hindu religion, bravery and courage are in the blood of all Indians.

In the Eastern tradition, some thoughts on courage were offered by the Tao Te Ching.

Characteristics of Courage[edit]

Daniel Putman, a professor at the University of Wisconsin - Fox Valley, wrote an article titled "The Emotions of Courage". Using a text from Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics as the basis for his article, he discusses the relationship between fear and confidence in the emotion of courage.[3]

He states that "courage involves deliberate choice in the face of painful or fearful circumstances for the sake of a worthy goal".[4] With this realization, Putman concludes that "there is a close connection between fear and confidence".[5]

Fear & Confidence in Relation to Courage[edit]

Fear and confidence in relation to courage can determine the success of a courageous act or goal.[6] They can be seen as the independent variables in courage, and their relationship can affect how we respond to fear.[7] In addition, the confidence that is being discussed here is self-confidence; Confidence in knowing one's skills and abilities and being able to determine when to fight fear or when to flight it.[8] Putman states that:

The ideal in courage is not just a rigid control of fear, nor is it a denial of the emotion. The ideal is to judge a situation, accept the emotion as part of human nature and, we hope, use well-developed habits to confront the fear and allow reason to guide our behavior toward a worthwhile goal.[8]

When trying to understand how fear and confidence play into courage, we need to look back at Aristotle's quote. According to Putman, Aristotle is referring to an appropriate level of fear and confidence in courage.[8] "Fear, although it might vary from person to person, is not completely relative and is only appropriate if it "matches the danger of the situation".[8] The same goes for confidence in that there are two aspects to self-confidence in a dangerous situation.

  1. "a realistic confidence in the worth of a cause that motivates positive action."[8]
  2. "knowing our own skills and abilities. A second meaning of appropriate confidence then is a form of self-knowledge."[8]

Without an appropriate balance between fear and confidence when facing a threat, one cannot have the courage to overcome it. Putman states "if the two emotions are distinct, then excesses or deficiencies in either fear or confidence can distort courage."[9]

Possible Distortions of Courage[edit]

As noted above, an "excess or deficiency of either fear or confidence, can distort courage".[9] According to Putman, there are four possibilities:[9]

  1. "Higher level of fear than a situation calls for, low level of confidence". Someone like this would be perceived as a coward;
  2. "Excessively low level of fear when real fear is an appropriate, excessively high level of confidence." Someone like this would be perceived as foolhardy;
  3. "Excessively high level of fear, yet the confidence is also excessively high." The third possibility can occur if someone experienced a traumatic experience that brought about great anxiety for much of their life. Then the fear that they experience would often be inappropriate and excessive. Yet as a defensive mechanism, the person would show excessive levels of confidence as a way to confront their irrational fear and "prove" something to oneself or other". So this distortions could be seen as a coping method for their fear.
  4. "Excessively low level of fear and low level of confidence." For the last possibility, it can be seen as hopelessness. Putman says this is similar to "a person on a sinking ship". "This example is of a person who has low confidence and possibly low self-regard who suddenly loses all fear". The distortion of low fear and low confidence can occur in a situation where an individual accepts what is going to happen to them. In regards to this example, they lose all fear because they know death is unavoidable and the reason it is unavoidable is that they do not have the ability to handle or overcome the situation.

Thus, Daniel Putman identifies fear and courage as being deeply intertwined and that they rely on distinct perceptions:[9]

  1. "the danger of the situation"
  2. "the worthiness of the cause"
  3. "and the perception of one's ability."

Historical theories[edit]

Ancient Greece[edit]

The early Greek philosopher Plato (c. 428–348 BCE)[10] laid the groundwork for how courage would be viewed to future philosophers. Plato's early writings found in Laches show a discussion on courage, but they fail to come to a satisfactory conclusion on what courage is.[11]

During the debate between three leaders, including Socrates, many definitions of courage are mentioned.[12]

"…a man willing to remain at his post and to defend himself against the enemy without running away…"[12]

"…a sort of endurance of the soul…"[12]

"…knowledge of the grounds of fear and hope..."[13]

While many definitions are given in Plato's Laches, all are refuted, giving the reader a sense of Plato's argument style. Laches is an early writing of Plato's, which may be a reason he does not come to a clear conclusion. In this early writing, Plato is still developing his ideas and shows influence from his teachers like Socrates.[12]

In one of his later writings, The Republic, Plato gives more concrete ideas of what he believes courage to be. Civic courage is described as a sort of perseverance – "preservation of the belief that has been inculcated by the law through education about what things and sorts of things are to be feared".[14] Ideas of courage being perseverance also are seen in Laches. Plato further explains this perseverance as being able to persevere through all emotions, like suffering, pleasure, and fear.[15]

As a desirable quality, courage is discussed broadly in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics,[16] where its vice of shortage is cowardice and its vice of excess is recklessness.[17]

Thucydides, a 5th Greek historian said; “The bravest are surely those who have the clearest vision of what is before them, glory and danger alike, and yet notwithstanding, go out to meet it.”

Ancient Rome[edit]

In the Roman Empire, courage formed part of the universal virtue of virtus.[18] Roman philosopher and statesman Cicero (106–43 BCE) lists the cardinal virtues does not name them such:

Virtue may be defined as a habit of mind (animi) in harmony with reason and the order of nature. It has four parts: wisdom (prudentiam), justice, courage, temperance.[19][20]

Medieval philosophy[edit]

In medieval virtue ethics, championed by Averroes and Thomas Aquinas and still important to Roman Catholicism, courage is referred to as "Fortitude".[21][22]

According to Thomas Aquinas:[23]

Among the cardinal virtues, prudence ranks first, justice second, fortitude third, temperance fourth, and after these the other virtues.

Part of his justification for this hierarchy is that:

Fortitude without justice is an occasion of injustice; since the stronger a man is the more ready is he to oppress the weaker.

On fortitude's general and special nature, Aquinas says:[23]

The term "fortitude" can be taken in two ways. First, as simply denoting a certain firmness of mind, and in this sense it is a general virtue, or rather a condition of every virtue, since as the Philosopher states,[24] it is requisite for every virtue to act firmly and immovably. Secondly, fortitude may be taken to denote firmness only in bearing and withstanding those things wherein it is most difficult to be firm, namely in certain grave dangers. Therefore Tully says,[25] that "fortitude is deliberate facing of dangers and bearing of toils." On this sense fortitude is reckoned a special virtue, because it has a special matter.

Aquinas holds fortitude or courage as being primarily about endurance, not attack:[23]

As stated above (Article 3), and according to the Philosopher,[26] "fortitude is more concerned to allay fear, than to moderate daring." For it is more difficult to allay fear than to moderate daring, since the danger which is the object of daring and fear, tends by its very nature to check daring to increase fear. Now to attack belongs to fortitude in so far as the latter moderates daring, whereas to endure follows the repression of fear. Therefore the principal act of fortitude is endurance, that is to stand immovable in the midst of dangers rather than to attack them.

Western traditions[edit]

In both Catholicism and Anglicanism, courage is also one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit. For Thomas Aquinas, Fortitude is the virtue to remove any obstacle that keeps the will from following reason.[21] Thomas Aquinas argues that Courage is a virtue which, along with the Christian virtues in the Summa Theologica, can only be exemplified with the presence of the Christian virtues: faith, hope, and mercy. In order to understand true courage in Christianity it takes someone who displays the virtues of faith, hope, and mercy.[21] Courage is a natural virtue which Saint Augustine did not consider a virtue for Christians. Thomas Aquinas considers courage a virtue through the Christian virtue of mercy.[27] Only through mercy and charity can we call the natural virtue of courage a Christian virtue. Unlike Aristotle, Aquinas’ courage is about endurance, not bravery in battle.[28]

The expressions of how to be living human as Christ did, taking Christ as our forbearance with Christian living, Paul had suggested these living virtues as three pairs; “For the rest, brothers, whatever is true, whatever is honorable, whatever is righteous, whatever is pure, whatever is lovely, whatever is well-spoken of.…” "To be righteous is to be right without; to be pure is to be single in our intention and motive within. We must be right without and pure within." A proper Christian life of following in the spirit of Christ with forbearance, Christian living is to not dissent with others, will always rejoice, will always forbear, and will have no anxiety (Philippians 4:6). This kind of life enjoys the peace of God (Philippians 4:7)."[29]

Witness Lee explains the connection of honor through His grace; "A virtue mentioned in Philippians 4:8 is “honorable.” Honor means dignity. With God in His divinity, it is a matter of His glory, but with us in our humanity, it is a matter of honor or dignity."[30]

Eastern traditions[edit]

The Tao Te Ching contends that courage is derived from love (") translated as: "One of courage, with audacity, will die. One of courage, but gentle, spares death. From these two kinds of courage arise harm and benefit."[31][32]

Lao Tzu stated in regards to the Tao and the question of love:

Embracing Tao, you become embraced. Supple, breathing gently, you become reborn. Clearing your vision, you become clear. Nurturing your beloved, you become impartial. Opening your heart, you become accepted. Accepting the World, you embrace Tao. Bearing and nurturing, Creating but not owning, Giving without demanding, Controlling without authority, This is love.

Lao Tzu suggested having love makes a person courageous, and love is powerful, courage is higher when one has depth to their love; "Being deeply loved by someone gives you strength, while loving someone deeply gives you courage."

In Hindu tradition, Courage (shauriya) / Bravery (dhairya), and Patience (taamasa) appear as the first two of ten characteristics (lakshana) of dharma in the Hindu Manusmṛti, alongside forgiveness (kshama), tolerance (dama), honesty (asthaya), physical restraint (indriya nigraha), cleanliness (shouchya), perceptiveness (dhi), knowledge (vidhya), truthfulness (satya), and control of anger (akrodha).

Islamic beliefs also present courage and self-control as a key factor in facing the Devil (both internally and externally); many believe this because of the courage the Prophets of the past displayed (through peace and patience) against those who despised them for their beliefs.

Modern[edit]

Pre-19th century[edit]

Thomas Hobbes lists virtues into the categories of moral virtues and virtues of men in his work Man and Citizen.[33] Hobbes outlines moral virtues as virtues in citizens, that is virtues that without exception are beneficial to society as a whole.[34] These moral virtues are justice (i.e. not violating the law) and charity. Courage as well as prudence and temperance are listed as the virtues of men.[33] By this Hobbes means that these virtues are invested solely in the private good as opposed to the public good of justice and charity. Hobbes describes courage and prudence as a strength of mind as opposed to a goodness of manners. These virtues are always meant to act in the interests of individual while the positive and/or negative effects of society are merely a byproduct. This stems forth from the idea put forth in Leviathan that the state of nature is "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short". According to Hobbes courage is a virtue of the individual in order to ensure a better chance of survival while the moral virtues address Hobbes's social contract which civilized men display (in varying degrees) in order to avoid the state of nature.[35] Hobbes also uses the idea of fortitude as an idea of virtue. Fortitude is "to dare" according to Hobbes, but also to "resist stoutly in present dangers."[36] This a more in depth elaboration of Hobbes's concept of courage that is addressed earlier in Man and Citizen. This idea relates back to Hobbes's idea that self-preservation is the most fundamental aspect of behavior.

David Hume listed virtues into two categories in his work A Treatise of Human Nature as artificial virtues and natural virtues. Hume noted in the Treatise that courage is a natural virtue. In the Treatise's section "Of Pride and Humility, Their Objects and Causes", Hume clearly stated courage is a cause of pride: "Every valuable quality of the mind, whether of the imagination, judgment, memory or disposition; wit, good-sense, learning, courage, justice, integrity; all these are the cause of pride; and their opposites of humility".[37]

Hume also related courage and joy to have positive effects on the soul: "(...) since the soul, when elevated with joy and courage, in a manner seeks opposition, and throws itself with alacrity into any scene of thought or action, where its courage meets with matter to nourish and employ it".[38] Along with courage nourishing and employing, Hume also wrote that courage defends humans in the Treatise: "We easily gain from the liberality of others, but are always in danger of losing by their avarice: Courage defends us, but cowardice lays us open to every attack".[39]

Hume wrote what excessive courage does to a hero's character in the Treatise's section "Of the Other Virtues and Vices": "Accordingly we may observe, that an excessive courage and magnanimity, especially when it displays itself under the frowns of fortune, contributes in a great measure, to the character of a hero, and will render a person the admiration of posterity; at the same time, that it ruins his affairs, and leads him into dangers and difficulties, with which otherwise he would never have been acquainted".[40]

Other understandings of courage that Hume offered can be derived from Hume's views on morals, reason, sentiment, and virtue from his work An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals.

19th century onward[edit]

Søren Kierkegaard opposed courage to angst, while Paul Tillich opposed an existential courage to be with non-being,[41] fundamentally equating it with religion:

Courage is the self-affirmation of being in spite of the fact of non-being. It is the act of the individual self in taking the anxiety of non-being upon itself by affirming itself ... in the anxiety of guilt and condemnation. ... every courage to be has openly or covertly a religious root. For religion is the state of being grasped by the power of being itself.[42]

J.R.R. Tolkien identified in his 1936 lecture "Beowulf: The Monsters and the Critics" a "Northern 'theory of courage'" – the heroic or "virtuous pagan" insistence to do the right thing even in the face of certain defeat without promise of reward or salvation:

It is the strength of the northern mythological imagination that it faced this problem, put the monsters in the centre, gave them victory but no honor, and found a potent and terrible solution in naked will and courage. 'As a working theory absolutely impregnable.' So potent is it, that while the older southern imagination has faded forever into literary ornament, the northern has power, as it were, to revive its spirit even in our own times. It can work, as it did even with the goðlauss Viking, without gods: martial heroism as its own end.[43]

Virtuous pagan heroism or courage in this sense is "trusting in your own strength," as observed by Jacob Grimm in his Teutonic Mythology:

Men who, turning away in utter disgust and doubt from the heathen faith, placed their reliance on their own strength and virtue. Thus in the Sôlar lioð 17 we read of Vêbogi and Râdey â sik þau trûðu, "in themselves they trusted."[44]

Ernest Hemingway famously defined courage as "grace under pressure".[45]

Winston Churchill stated, "Courage is rightly esteemed the first of human qualities because it is the quality that guarantees all others."

According to Maya Angelou, "Courage is the most important of the virtues, because without courage you can't practice any other virtue consistently. You can practice any virtue erratically, but nothing consistently without courage."

In Beyond Good and Evil, Friedrich Nietzsche describes master–slave morality, in which a noble man regards himself as a "determiner of values"; one who does not require approval, but passes judgment. Later, in the same text, he lists man's four virtues as courage, insight, sympathy, and solitude, and goes on to emphasize the importance of courage: "The great epochs of our life are the occasions when we gain the courage to re-baptize our evil qualities as our best qualities."[46]

According to the Swiss psychologist Andreas Dick, courage consists of the following components:[47]

  1. put at risk, risk or repugnance, or sacrifice safety or convenience, which may result in death, bodily harm, social condemnation or emotional deprivation;
  1. a knowledge of wisdom and prudence about what is right and wrong in a given moment;
  2. Hope and confidence in a happy, meaningful outcome;
  3. a free will;
  4. a motive based on love.

Implicit Theories of Courage[edit]

Researchers who want to study the concept and the emotion of courage have continued to come across a certain problem. While there are "numerous definitions of courage",[48] they are unable to set "an operational definition of courage on which to base sound explicit theories".[49] Rate et al. states that because of a lack of an operational definition, the advancement of research in courage is limited.[49] So they conducted studies to try to find "a common structure of courage".[49] Their goal from their research of implicit theories was to find "people's form and content on the idea of courage".[50] Many researchers created studies on implicit theories by creating a questionnaire that would ask "What is courage?".[50] In addition, in order to "develop a measurement scale of courage, ten experts in the field of psychology came together to define courage.[51] They defined it as:

the ability to act for a meaningful (noble, good, or practical) cause, despite experiencing the fear associated with perceived threat exceeding the available resources[51][52]

Also, because courage is a "multi-dimensional construct, it can be "better understood as an exceptional response to specific external conditions or circumstances than as an attribute, disposition, or character trait".[50] Meaning that rather than being a show of character or an attribute, courage is a response to fear.[50]

From their research, they were able to find the "four necessary components of people's notion of courage".[53]They are:

  1. "intentionality/deliberation"[53]
  2. "personal fear"[53]
  3. "noble/good act"[53]
  4. "and personal risk"[53]

With these four components, they were able to define courage as:

a willful, intentional act, executed after mindful deliberation, involving objective substantial risk to the actor, primarily motivated to bring about a noble good or worthy end, despite, perhaps, the presence of the emotion of fear.[53]

To further the discussion of the implicit theories of courage, the researchers stated that future research could consider looking into the concept of courage and fear and how individual's might feel fear, overcome it and act, and act despite of it.[54]

Clinical Courage[edit]

The term Clinical Courage came to light in relation to modern medicine in the 2000s,[55] mostly in relation to the practice of medicine in remote or resource limited settings. The concept has been described as the practice of medicine outside off a clinician's usual scope of practice, or relevant clinical guidelines, in order to provide essential medical care, where no alternative exists.[56] It has been specifically discussed in relation to Rural Generalists,[57] Paramedics,[56] General Practice[58] and rural medicine.[59] The opposing theory is that of Clinical Recklessness, where the actions of a clinician in stepping outside of their competence results in unprofessional behaviour, which exposes patients to risk or indeed harm.

Society and symbolism[edit]

Its accompanying animal is the lion.[60] Often, fortitude is depicted as having tamed the ferocious lion. The Tarot trump called Strength. It is sometimes seen in the Catholic Church as a depiction of Christ's triumph over sin.[61] It also is a symbol in some cultures as a savior of the people who live in a community with sin and corruption.[62]

Awards[edit]

Several awards claim to recognize courageous actions, including:

  • The Victoria Cross is the highest military award that may be received by members of the British Armed Forces and the Armed Forces of other Commonwealth countries for valour "in the face of the enemy", the civilian equivalent being the George Cross. A total of 1,356 VCs have been awarded to individuals, 13 since World War II.
  • The Medal of Honor is the highest military decoration awarded by the United States government. It is bestowed on members of the United States armed forces who distinguish themselves "conspicuously by gallantry and intrepidity at the risk of his life above and beyond the call of duty while engaged in an action against an enemy of the United States".
  • Distinguished Service Cross (United States) is the second highest military decoration that can be awarded to a member of the United States Army, awarded for extreme gallantry and risk of life in actual combat with an armed enemy force.
  • The Carnegie Hero Fund – was established to recognize persons who perform extraordinary acts of heroism in civilian life in the United States and Canada, and to provide financial assistance for those disabled and the dependents of those killed saving or attempting to save others.
  • The Profile in Courage Award is a private award given to displays of courage similar to those John F. Kennedy described in his book Profiles in Courage. It is given to individuals (often elected officials) who, by acting in accord with their conscience, risked their careers or lives by pursuing a larger vision of the national, state or local interest in opposition to popular opinion or pressure from constituents or other local interests.
  • The Civil Courage Prize is a human rights award which is awarded to "steadfast resistance to evil at great personal risk – rather than military valor." It is awarded by the Trustees of The Train Foundation annually and may be awarded posthumously.
  • Courage to Care Award is a plaque with miniature bas-reliefs depicting the backdrop for the rescuers' exceptional deeds during the Nazis' persecution, deportation and murder of millions of Jews.
  • The Ivan Allen Jr. Prize for Social Courage is a prize awarded by Georgia Institute of Technology to individuals who uphold the legacy of former Atlanta Mayor Ivan Allen Jr., whose actions in Atlanta, Georgia and testimony before congress in support of the 1963 Civil Rights Bill legislation set a standard for courage during the turbulent civil rights era of the 1960s.[63]
  • The Param Vir Chakra is the highest military award in India given to those who show the highest degree of valour or self-sacrifice in the presence of the enemy. It can be, and often has been, awarded posthumously.
  • The Military Order of Maria Theresa, the highest order of the Austro-Hungarian Empire, awarded for "successful military acts of essential impact to a campaign that were undertaken on [an officer's] own initiative, and might have been omitted by an honorable officer without reproach".
  • The Edelstam Prize awarded for outstanding contributions and exceptional courage in standing up for one's beliefs in the defense of Human Rights.

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Pianalto, Matthew (2012). "Moral Courage and Facing Others". Philosophical Studies. 20 (2): 165–184. doi:10.1080/09672559.2012.668308. S2CID 143490856.
  2. ^ Rickaby, John (1909). "Fortitude". The Catholic Encyclopedia. 6. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
  3. ^ Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1115b17–19
  4. ^ Putman, Daniel (2001). "The Emotion of Courage". Journal of Social Philosophy. 32 (4): 463–470. doi:10.1111/0047-2786.00107.
  5. ^ Putman 2001, pp. 464.
  6. ^ Putman 2001, pp. 463.
  7. ^ Putman 2001, pp. 466.
  8. ^ a b c d e f Putman 2001, pp. 465.
  9. ^ a b c d Putman 2001, pp. 467.
  10. ^ "Plato Biography by Philosopher, Writer (c. 428–348 BCE)". Biography. Retrieved October 18, 2015.
  11. ^ Walton 1986, p. 5.
  12. ^ a b c d Walton 1986, pp. 56–58.
  13. ^ Plato, Cooper & Hutchinson 1997, pp. 675–86.
  14. ^ Plato, Cooper & Hutchinson 1997, pp. 1061–75.
  15. ^ Plato, Cooper & Hutchinson 1997, pp. 2061–75.
  16. ^ Walton 1986, pp. 59–61.
  17. ^ Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, 1103b15-20, 1104a15-25, 1104b1-10, 1107a30-1107b5, 1108b15-35, 1109a5-15, 1115a5-1117b25, 1129b20-5, 1137a20-5, 144b5-10, 1167a20, 1177a30-b1, 1178a10-5, 1178a30-5, 1178b10-5, in Aristotle, Translation, Introduction, and Commentary, Broadie, Sarah, & Rowe, C., Oxford University Press, 2002.
  18. ^ McDonnell 2006, p. 31.
  19. ^ McDonnell 2006, p. 129.
  20. ^ De Inventione, II, LIII
  21. ^ a b c Walton 1986, pp. 62–63.
  22. ^ "Summa Theologica". Christian Classics Ethereal Library.
  23. ^ a b c "Summa Theologica: Fortitude (Secunda Secundae Partis, Q. 123)". New Advent.
  24. ^ Ethic. ii
  25. ^ Rhet. ii
  26. ^ Ethic. iii, 9
  27. ^ Miller 2000, p. 204.
  28. ^ Miller 2000, pp. 21–22.
  29. ^ Lee, Witness. "The Experience and Growth in Life. Taking Christ as our Forbearance". Ministrysamples.org. Living Stream Ministry. Retrieved 9 May 2019.
  30. ^ Lee, Witness. "The Experience and Growth in Life. Forbearance being the sum total of the human virtues". www.ministrysamples.org. Retrieved 20 May 2019.
  31. ^ Chapter 67 and 73, Tao Te Ching (C. Ganson uses the word "courage", but the Mitchell translation does not.)
  32. ^ "Traditional Chinese Characters". Zhonwen.com. Tao Te Ching with Hanzi translations
  33. ^ a b Hobbes 1972, pp. 68–70.
  34. ^ Hobbes 1972, pp. 17–18.
  35. ^ Hobbes 1972, p. 290.
  36. ^ Hobbes 1972, pp. 150–52.
  37. ^ Hume 1751, p. 434.
  38. ^ Hume 1751, p. 666.
  39. ^ Hume 1751, p. 459.
  40. ^ Hume 1751, p. 900.
  41. ^ Tillich 1952, p. 89.
  42. ^ Tillich 1952, pp. 152–183.
  43. ^ Tolkien, JRR. "Beowulf: The Monsters and the Critics". The Tolkien Estate. p. 25. Archived from the original on 2007-10-15. Retrieved 2008-04-25.
  44. ^ Grimm, Jacob (1835). Deutsche Mythologie (Teutonic Mythology) (in German) (1 ed.). Dieterich: Göttingen.
  45. ^ Carter, Richard (1999). "Celebrating Ernest Hemingway's Century". neh.gov. National Endowment for the Humanities. Archived from the original on 2013-09-30. Retrieved 2009-06-19.
  46. ^ Nietzsche 1989, p. 65.
  47. ^ Dick, Andreas (2010). Mut – Über sich hinauswachsen. Bern: Hans Huber Verlag. ISBN 978-3-456-84835-8.
  48. ^ "Implicit theories of courage". p. 81.
  49. ^ a b c Rate, Clarke & Sternberg 2007, pp. 81.
  50. ^ a b c d Rate, Clarke & Sternberg 2007, pp. 83.
  51. ^ a b Rate, Clarke & Sternberg 2007, pp. 84.
  52. ^ Woodard 2004, pp. 174.
  53. ^ a b c d e f Rate, Clarke & Sternberg 2007, pp. 95.
  54. ^ Rate, Clarke & Sternberg 2007, pp. 96.
  55. ^ Wootton J (2011). "President's message. Clinical courage". Can J Rural Med. 16 (2): 45–6. PMID 21453603.
  56. ^ a b Mallinson, Tom (2020). "Clinical courage". Journal of Paramedic Practice. 12 (11): 429–429. doi:10.12968/jpar.2020.12.11.429. ISSN 1759-1376.
  57. ^ Konkin, Jill; Grave, Laura; Cockburn, Ella; Couper, Ian; Stewart, Ruth Alison; Campbell, David; Walters, Lucie (2020). "Exploration of rural physicians' lived experience of practising outside their usual scope of practice to provide access to essential medical care (clinical courage): an international phenomenological study". BMJ Open. 10 (8): e037705. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2020-037705. ISSN 2044-6055.
  58. ^ Walters, Lucie; Laurence, Caroline O.; Dollard, Joanne; Elliott, Taryn; Eley, Diann S. (2015). "Exploring resilience in rural GP registrars – implications for training". BMC Medical Education. 15 (1). doi:10.1186/s12909-015-0399-x. ISSN 1472-6920.
  59. ^ Fox, Kevin; Corstorphine, Wendy; Frazer, Jenny; Johnstone, Anna; Miller, Alasdair; Shepherd, Neil; Cooper, Paul (2020). "Ten reasons why every junior doctor should spend time working in a remote and rural hospital". Future Healthcare Journal. 7 (1): 12–14. doi:10.7861/fhj.2019-0050. ISSN 2514-6645.
  60. ^ Miller 2000, pp. 101–102.
  61. ^ Revelation 5:5
  62. ^ Walton 1986, pp. 199–202.
  63. ^ "Bio | Ivan Allen Prize". Georgia Institute of Technology. Retrieved 2018-08-20.

References[edit]

  • Bauhn, Per (2003), The Value of Courage, Lund: Nordic Academic Press, ISBN 91-89116-62-3.
  • Jeanmart, G.; Blésin, L. (dir.), Figures du courage politique dans la philosophie moderne et contemporaine, numéro thématique de la revue Dissensus. Revue de philosophie politique de l'Université de Liège (http://popups.ulg.ac.be/dissensus/), n°2, automne 2009.
  • Avramenko, Richard (2011). Courage: The Politics of Life and Limb. University of Notre Dame Press.
  • "Catholic Encyclopedia "Fortitude"". New Advent.
  • "Summa Theologica "Second Part of the Second Part"". New Advent. See Questions 123–140
  • Becker, Ernest (1973). The Denial of Death. New York: The Free Press.
  • Bussey, K. (1992). "Lying and truthfulness: Children's definitions, standards, and evaluative reactions". Child Development. pp. 63, 129–37.
  • Deci, E. L.; Ryan, R. M. (2000). "The 'what' and 'why' of gal pursuits: Human needs and the self-determination of behavior". Psychological Inquiry. pp. 4, 227–68.
  • Eisenberger, R. (1992). "Learned industriousness". Psychological Review. pp. 99, 248–67.
  • Evans, P. D.; White, D. G. (1981). "Towards an empirical definition of courage". Behaviour Research and Therapy. pp. 19, 419–24.
  • Hobbes, Thomas (1972). Bernard Gert (ed.). Man and Citizen (De Homine and De Cive). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-8446-4756-2.
  • Hobbes, Thomas; Tuck, Richard (1991). Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hume, David (2009). A Treatise On Human Nature : Being An Attempt To Introduce The Experimental Method Of Reasoning Into Moral Subjects. The Floating Press.
  • Hume, David (1751). An Enquiry Concerning The Principles Of Morals. Lanham: Start Publishing LLC.
  • Peterson, C.; Seligman M. E. P. (2004). Character Strengths and Virtues: A Handbook and Classification. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 197–289.
  • Putman, Daniel (2001). "The Emotions of Courage". Journal of Social Philosophy. 32 (4): 463–470. doi:10.1111/0047-2786.00107.
  • Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (1989). Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. New York: Vintage. ISBN 978-0-521-77078-1.
  • Rate, Christopher R.; Clarke, Jennifer A.; Sternberg, Lindsay & Robert J. (2007). "Implicit theories of courage". The Journal of Positive Psychology. 2:2 (2): 80–98. doi:10.1080/17439760701228755. S2CID 144404365.
  • Ryan, R. M.; Frederick, C. (1997). "On energy, personality, and health: Subjective vitality as a dynamic reflection of well-being". Journal of Personality. pp. 65, 529–65.
  • McDonnell, Myles (2006). Roman Manliness: "Virtus" and the Roman Republic. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-5218-2788-1.
  • Miller, William Ian (2000). The Mystery of Courage. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-00826-7.
  • Osho (1999). Courage: The Joy of Living Dangerously. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-312-20517-1.
  • Palmquist, Stephen (2000). "Angst and the Paradox of Courage". The Tree of Philosophy. Hong Kong: Philopsychy Press.
  • Plato; Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. ISBN 978-0-87220-349-5.
  • Tillich, Paul (1952). The Courage To Be. Connecticut: Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0-300-08471-9.
  • Walton, Douglas N. (1986). Courage: A Philosophical Investigation. Los Angeles: University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-05443-1.
  • Woodard, C.R. (2004). "Hardiness and the concept of courage". Consulting Psychology Journal: Practice and Research. pp. 56, 173–185.
  • Zimmerman, Barry J. (1995). Self-regulation involves more than meta cognition: A social cognitive perspective. Educational Psychologist. pp. 30, 217–21.
  • Deutsch, M. (1961). "Courage as a concept in social psychology". The Journal of Positive Psychology. 55:1 (1): 49–58. doi:10.1080/00224545.1961.9922158.
  • KM, Kerfoot (2012). "Courage as a concept in social psychology". Nursing Economics. 30 (3): 176–178.
  • Aultman, Julie (2008). "Moral Courage Through a Collective Voice". The Journal of Positive Psychology. 8:4 (4): 67–69. doi:10.1080/15265160802147140. S2CID 72024672.
  • Cynthia, L. S. Pury; Shane, J. Lopez (2010). "The Psychology of Courage: Modern Research on an Ancient Virtue". Decade of Behavior. American Psychological Association.
  • Andrei G., Zavaliy; Aristidou, Michael (2014). "Courage: A Modern Look at an Ancient Virtue, Journal of Military Ethics". Journal of Military Ethics. 13:2 (2): 174–189. doi:10.1080/15027570.2014.943037. S2CID 143041288.
  • Robert M., Van Sant; Stevens, Margaret Talbolt; Jones, M.W. (1929). "B and O Magazine, Volume 17". B and O Magazine. Baltimore and Ohio Railroad., 1929. 17: 46.
  • John, Ruskin (1886). "The Works of John Ruskin ...: The stones of Venice 4th ed. 1886, John Ruskin". The Works of John Ruski. Allen, 1886. 33: 39–40.
  • Lord, Herbert Gardiner (1918). The Psychology of Courage. Luce, 1918.
  • United States., Army; Pacific Division, Division of the Pacific; Washington Greely, Adolphus (1906). Earthquake in California, April 18, 1906. U.S. Government Printing Office, 1906. p. 19.
  • Pacific, Railroads (1878). Pacific Railroads in Congress, 1877 and 1878: Proceedings Compiled from Official Records. p. 83.
  • Congress, United States.; Committee on Finance, Senate (1962). "Revenue Act of 1962: Hearings Before the Committee on Finance, United States Senate, Eighty-seventh Congress, Second Session, on H.R. 10650, an Act to Amend the Revenue Act of 1954 to Provide a Credit for Investment in Certain Depreciable Property, to Eliminate Certain Defects and Inequities, and for Other Purposes,". 1–4. United States: 1319. Cite journal requires |journal= (help)

External links[edit]